fbpx
Wikipedia

Social choice theory

Social choice theory or social choice is a branch of economics that analyzes mechanisms and procedures for collective decisions.[1] Social choice incorporates insights from welfare economics, mathematics, and political science to find the best ways to combine individual opinions, preferences, or beliefs into a single coherent measure of well-being.

Whereas decision theory is concerned with individuals making choices based on their preferences, social choice theory is concerned with how to translate the preferences of individuals into the preferences of a group. A non-theoretical example of a collective decision is enacting a law or set of laws under a constitution. Another example is voting, where individual preferences over candidates are collected to elect a person that best represents the group's preferences.[2]

It is methodologically individualistic, in that it aggregates preferences and behaviors of individual members of society. Using elements of formal logic for generality, analysis proceeds from a set of seemingly reasonable axioms of social choice to form a social welfare function (or constitution).[3]

History edit

The earliest work on social choice theory comes from the writings of the Marquis de Condorcet, who formulated several key results including his jury theorem and his example showing the impossibility of majority rule. His work was prefigured by Ramon Llull's 1299 manuscript Ars Electionis (The Art of Elections), which discussed many of the same concepts, but was lost until being rediscovered in the early 21st century.[4]

Kenneth Arrow's book Social Choice and Individual Values is often recognized as inaugurating modern social choice theory.[1] Later work also considers approaches to compensations, fair division, variable populations, strategy-proofing of social-choice mechanisms,[5] natural resources,[1] capabilities and functionings approaches,[6] and measures of welfare.[7][8][9]

Key results edit

Arrow's impossibility theorem edit

Arrow's impossibility theorem is a key result showing that social choice functions based only on ordinal comparisons, rather than cardinal utility, will behave incoherently (unless they are dictatorial or violate Pareto efficiency). Such systems violate independence of irrelevant alternatives, i.e. the system will behave erratically when outcomes are added or removed.

Condorcet cycles edit

Condorcet's example demonstrates that democracy cannot be thought of as being the same as simple majority rule or majoritarianism; otherwise, it will be self-contradictory when 3 or more options are available. Majority rule can create cycles that violate the transitive property: Attempting to use majority rule as a social choice function creates situations where we have A better than B and B better than C, but C is still better than A.

This contrasts with May's theorem, which shows that simple majority is the optimal voting mechanism when there are only 2 outcomes, and only ordinal preferences are allowed.

Harsanyi's theorem edit

Harsanyi's utilitarian theorem shows that if individuals have preferences that are well-behaved under uncertainty (i.e. coherent), the only coherent and Pareto efficient social choice function is the utilitarian rule. This lends some support to the viewpoint expressed of John Stuart Mill, who identified democracy with the ideal of maximizing the common good (or utility) of society as a whole, under an equal consideration of interests.

Manipulation theorems edit

Gibbard's theorem provides limitations on the ability of any voting rule to elicit honest , showing that no voting rule is strategyproof (i.e. does not depend on other voters' choices) for elections with 3 or more outcomes.

The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem proves a stronger result for ranked-choice voting systems, showing that no such voting rule can be sincere (i.e. free of reversed preferences).

Median voter theorem edit

Mechanism design edit

The field of mechanism design, a subset of social choice theory, deals with the identification of rules that preserve while incentivizing agents to honestly reveal their preferences. One particularly important result is the revelation principle, which is almost a reversal of Gibbard's theorem: for any given social choice function, there exists a mechanism that obtains the same results but incentivizes participants to be completely honest.

Because mechanism design drops some of the assumptions made by voting theory, it is possible to design mechanisms for social choice to accomplish "impossible" tasks. For example, by allowing agents to compensate each other for losses with transfers, the Vickrey–Clarke–Groves (VCG) mechanism can achieve the "impossible" according to Gibbard's theorem: the mechanism ensures honest behavior from participants, while still achieving a Pareto efficient outcome. As a result, the VCG mechanism can be considered a "better" way to make decisions than democratic voting when monetary transfers are available.

Others edit

The Campbell-Kelley theorem states that, if there exists a Condorcet winner, then selecting that winner is the unique resolvable, neutral, anonymous, and non-manipulable voting rule.[2][further explanation needed]

Interpersonal utility comparison edit

Social choice theory is the study of theoretical and practical methods to aggregate or combine individual preferences into a collective social welfare function. The field generally assumes that individuals have preferences, and it follows that they can be modeled using utility functions, by the VNM theorem. But much of the research in the field assumes that those utility functions are internal to humans, lack a meaningful unit of measure and cannot be compared across different individuals.[10] Whether this type of interpersonal utility comparison is possible or not significantly alters the available mathematical structures for social welfare functions and social choice theory.

In one perspective, following Jeremy Bentham, utilitarians have argued that preferences and utility functions of individuals are interpersonally comparable and may therefore be added together to arrive at a measure of aggregate utility. Utilitarian ethics call for maximizing this aggregate.

In contrast many twentieth century economists, following Lionel Robbins, questioned whether such measures of utility could be measured, or even considered meaningful. Following arguments similar to those espoused by behaviorists in psychology, Robbins argued concepts of utility were unscientific and unfalsifiable. Consider for instance the law of diminishing marginal utility, according to which utility of an added quantity of a good decreases with the amount of the good that is already in possession of the individual. It has been used to defend transfers of wealth from the "rich" to the "poor" on the premise that the former do not derive as much utility as the latter from an extra unit of income. Robbins (1935, pp. 138–40) argues that this notion is beyond positive science; that is, one cannot measure changes in the utility of someone else, nor is it required by positive theory.

Apologists of the interpersonal comparison of utility have argued that Robbins claimed too much. John Harsanyi agrees that full comparability of mental states such as utility is not practically possible, but believes human beings can make some interpersonal comparisons of utility because they have similar backgrounds, cultural experiences, and psychology. Amartya Sen (1970, p. 99) argues that even if interpersonal comparisons of utility are imperfect, we can still say that (despite being positive for Nero) the Great Fire of Rome had a negative overall value.[citation needed] Harsanyi and Sen thus argue that at least partial comparability of utility is possible, and social choice theory proceeds under that assumption.

Relationship to public choice theory edit

Despite the similar names, "public choice" and "social choice" are two distinct fields, though the two are closely related.The Journal of Economic Literature classification codes place Social Choice under Microeconomics at JEL D71 (with Clubs, Committees, and Associations) whereas most Public Choice subcategories are in JEL D72 (Economic Models of Political Processes: Rent-Seeking, Elections, Legislatures, and Voting Behavior).

Empirical research edit

Since Arrow, social choice theory has been characterized by being predominantly mathematical and theoretical, but some research has aimed at estimating the frequency of various voting paradoxes, such as the Condorcet paradox.[11][12] A summary of 37 individual studies, covering a total of 265 real-world elections, large and small, found 25 instances of a Condorcet paradox for a total likelihood of 9.4%.[12]: 325  While examples of the paradox seem to occur often in small settings like parliaments, very few examples have been found in larger groups (electorates), although some have been identified.[13] However, the frequency of such paradoxes depends heavily on the number of options and other factors.

Rules edit

Let   be a set of possible 'states of the world' or 'alternatives'. Society wishes to choose a single state from  . For example, in a single-winner election,   may represent the set of candidates; in a resource allocation setting,   may represent all possible allocations.

Let   be a finite set, representing a collection of individuals. For each  , let   be a utility function, describing the amount of happiness an individual i derives from each possible state.

A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data   to select some element(s) from   which are 'best' for society. The question of what 'best' means is a common question in social choice theory. The following rules are most common:

Functions edit

A social choice function or a voting rule takes an individual's complete and transitive preferences over a set of outcomes and returns a single chosen outcome (or a set of tied outcomes). We can think of this subset as the winners of an election, and compare different social choice functions based on which axioms or mathematical properties they fulfill.[2]

Arrow's impossibility theorem is what often comes to mind when one thinks about impossibility theorems in voting. There are several famous theorems concerning social choice functions. The Gibbard–Satterthwaite theorem states that all non-dictatorial voting rules that is resolute (it always returns a single winner no matter what the ballots are) and non-imposed (every alternative could be chosen) with more than three alternatives (candidates) is manipulable. That is, a voter can cast a ballot that misrepresents their preferences to obtain a result that is more favorable to them under their sincere preferences. May's theorem states that when there are only two candidates, simple majority vote is the unique neutral, anonymous, and positively responsive voting rule.[14]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c Amartya Sen (2008). "Social Choice,". The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, Abstract & TOC.
  2. ^ a b c Zwicker, William S.; Moulin, Herve (2016), Brandt, Felix; Conitzer, Vincent; Endriss, Ulle; Lang, Jerome (eds.), "Introduction to the Theory of Voting", Handbook of Computational Social Choice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 23–56, doi:10.1017/cbo9781107446984.003, ISBN 978-1-107-44698-4, retrieved 2021-12-24
  3. ^ For example, in Kenneth J. Arrow (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley, ch. II, section 2, A Notation for Preferences and Choice, and ch. III, "The Social Welfare Function".
  4. ^ Colomer, Josep M. (2013-02-01). "Ramon Llull: from 'Ars electionis' to social choice theory". Social Choice and Welfare. 40 (2): 317–328. doi:10.1007/s00355-011-0598-2. ISSN 1432-217X.
  5. ^ Walter Bossert and John A. Weymark (2008). "Social Choice (New Developments)," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition, Abstract & TOC.
  6. ^ Kaushik, Basu; Lòpez-Calva, Luis F. (2011). Functionings and Capabilities. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Vol. 2. pp. 153–187. doi:10.1016/S0169-7218(10)00016-X. ISBN 9780444508942.
  7. ^ d'Aspremont, Claude; Gevers, Louis (2002). Chapter 10 Social welfare functionals and interpersonal comparability. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Vol. 1. pp. 459–541. doi:10.1016/S1574-0110(02)80014-5. ISBN 9780444829146.
  8. ^ Amartya Sen ([1987] 2008). "Justice," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract & TOC.
      Bertil Tungodden (2008). "Justice (New Perspectives)," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract.
      Louis Kaplow (2008). "Pareto Principle and Competing Principles," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd Edition. Abstract.
      Amartya K. Sen (1979 [1984]). Collective Choice and Social Welfare, New York: Elsevier, (description):
        ch. 9, "Equity and Justice," pp. 131-51.
        ch. 9*, "Impersonality and Collective Quasi-Orderings," pp. 152-160.
      Kenneth J. Arrow (1983). Collected Papers, v. 1, Social Choice and Justice, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, Description, contents, and chapter-preview links.
      Charles Blackorby, Walter Bossert, and David Donaldson, 2002. "Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice", in Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, edited by Kenneth J. Arrow, Amartya K. Sen, and Kotaro Suzumura, v. 1, ch. 11, pp. 543–596. Abstract.
  9. ^ Dutta, Bhaskar (2002). Chapter 12 Inequality, poverty and welfare. Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare. Vol. 1. pp. 597–633. doi:10.1016/S1574-0110(02)80016-9. ISBN 9780444829146.
  10. ^ Lionel Robbins (1932, 1935, 2nd ed.). An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science, London: Macmillan. Links for 1932 HTML and 1935 facsimile.
  11. ^ Kurrild-Klitgaard, Peter (2014). "Empirical social choice: An introduction". Public Choice. 158 (3–4): 297–310. doi:10.1007/s11127-014-0164-4. ISSN 0048-5829. S2CID 148982833.
  12. ^ a b Van Deemen, Adrian (2014). "On the empirical relevance of Condorcet's paradox". Public Choice. 158 (3–4): 311–330. doi:10.1007/s11127-013-0133-3. ISSN 0048-5829. S2CID 154862595.
  13. ^ Kurrild-Klitgaard, Peter (2014). "An empirical example of the Condorcet paradox of voting in a large electorate". Public Choice. 107 (1/2): 135–145. doi:10.1023/A:1010304729545. ISSN 0048-5829. S2CID 152300013.
  14. ^ May, Kenneth O. (October 1952). "A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision". Econometrica. 20 (4): 680–684. doi:10.2307/1907651. JSTOR 1907651.

References edit

External links edit

social, choice, theory, this, article, unclear, citation, style, references, used, made, clearer, with, different, consistent, style, citation, footnoting, april, 2021, learn, when, remove, this, message, social, choice, branch, economics, that, analyzes, mech. This article has an unclear citation style The references used may be made clearer with a different or consistent style of citation and footnoting April 2021 Learn how and when to remove this message Social choice theory or social choice is a branch of economics that analyzes mechanisms and procedures for collective decisions 1 Social choice incorporates insights from welfare economics mathematics and political science to find the best ways to combine individual opinions preferences or beliefs into a single coherent measure of well being Whereas decision theory is concerned with individuals making choices based on their preferences social choice theory is concerned with how to translate the preferences of individuals into the preferences of a group A non theoretical example of a collective decision is enacting a law or set of laws under a constitution Another example is voting where individual preferences over candidates are collected to elect a person that best represents the group s preferences 2 It is methodologically individualistic in that it aggregates preferences and behaviors of individual members of society Using elements of formal logic for generality analysis proceeds from a set of seemingly reasonable axioms of social choice to form a social welfare function or constitution 3 Contents 1 History 2 Key results 2 1 Arrow s impossibility theorem 2 2 Condorcet cycles 2 3 Harsanyi s theorem 2 4 Manipulation theorems 2 5 Median voter theorem 2 6 Mechanism design 2 7 Others 3 Interpersonal utility comparison 4 Relationship to public choice theory 5 Empirical research 6 Rules 7 Functions 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 External linksHistory editThe earliest work on social choice theory comes from the writings of the Marquis de Condorcet who formulated several key results including his jury theorem and his example showing the impossibility of majority rule His work was prefigured by Ramon Llull s 1299 manuscript Ars Electionis The Art of Elections which discussed many of the same concepts but was lost until being rediscovered in the early 21st century 4 Kenneth Arrow s book Social Choice and Individual Values is often recognized as inaugurating modern social choice theory 1 Later work also considers approaches to compensations fair division variable populations strategy proofing of social choice mechanisms 5 natural resources 1 capabilities and functionings approaches 6 and measures of welfare 7 8 9 Key results editArrow s impossibility theorem edit Main article Arrow s impossibility theorem Arrow s impossibility theorem is a key result showing that social choice functions based only on ordinal comparisons rather than cardinal utility will behave incoherently unless they are dictatorial or violate Pareto efficiency Such systems violate independence of irrelevant alternatives i e the system will behave erratically when outcomes are added or removed Condorcet cycles edit Main article Condorcet cycle Condorcet s example demonstrates that democracy cannot be thought of as being the same as simple majority rule or majoritarianism otherwise it will be self contradictory when 3 or more options are available Majority rule can create cycles that violate the transitive property Attempting to use majority rule as a social choice function creates situations where we have A better than B and B better than C but C is still better than A This contrasts with May s theorem which shows that simple majority is the optimal voting mechanism when there are only 2 outcomes and only ordinal preferences are allowed Harsanyi s theorem edit Main article Harsanyi s utilitarian theorem Harsanyi s utilitarian theorem shows that if individuals have preferences that are well behaved under uncertainty i e coherent the only coherent and Pareto efficient social choice function is the utilitarian rule This lends some support to the viewpoint expressed of John Stuart Mill who identified democracy with the ideal of maximizing the common good or utility of society as a whole under an equal consideration of interests Manipulation theorems edit Main articles Gibbard s theorem and Gibbard Satterthwaite theorem Gibbard s theorem provides limitations on the ability of any voting rule to elicit honest showing that no voting rule is strategyproof i e does not depend on other voters choices for elections with 3 or more outcomes The Gibbard Satterthwaite theorem proves a stronger result for ranked choice voting systems showing that no such voting rule can be sincere i e free of reversed preferences Median voter theorem edit Main article Median voter theorem Mechanism design edit Main article Mechanism design The field of mechanism design a subset of social choice theory deals with the identification of rules that preserve while incentivizing agents to honestly reveal their preferences One particularly important result is the revelation principle which is almost a reversal of Gibbard s theorem for any given social choice function there exists a mechanism that obtains the same results but incentivizes participants to be completely honest Because mechanism design drops some of the assumptions made by voting theory it is possible to design mechanisms for social choice to accomplish impossible tasks For example by allowing agents to compensate each other for losses with transfers the Vickrey Clarke Groves VCG mechanism can achieve the impossible according to Gibbard s theorem the mechanism ensures honest behavior from participants while still achieving a Pareto efficient outcome As a result the VCG mechanism can be considered a better way to make decisions than democratic voting when monetary transfers are available Others edit The Campbell Kelley theorem states that if there exists a Condorcet winner then selecting that winner is the unique resolvable neutral anonymous and non manipulable voting rule 2 further explanation needed Interpersonal utility comparison editSocial choice theory is the study of theoretical and practical methods to aggregate or combine individual preferences into a collective social welfare function The field generally assumes that individuals have preferences and it follows that they can be modeled using utility functions by the VNM theorem But much of the research in the field assumes that those utility functions are internal to humans lack a meaningful unit of measure and cannot be compared across different individuals 10 Whether this type of interpersonal utility comparison is possible or not significantly alters the available mathematical structures for social welfare functions and social choice theory In one perspective following Jeremy Bentham utilitarians have argued that preferences and utility functions of individuals are interpersonally comparable and may therefore be added together to arrive at a measure of aggregate utility Utilitarian ethics call for maximizing this aggregate In contrast many twentieth century economists following Lionel Robbins questioned whether such measures of utility could be measured or even considered meaningful Following arguments similar to those espoused by behaviorists in psychology Robbins argued concepts of utility were unscientific and unfalsifiable Consider for instance the law of diminishing marginal utility according to which utility of an added quantity of a good decreases with the amount of the good that is already in possession of the individual It has been used to defend transfers of wealth from the rich to the poor on the premise that the former do not derive as much utility as the latter from an extra unit of income Robbins 1935 pp 138 40 argues that this notion is beyond positive science that is one cannot measure changes in the utility of someone else nor is it required by positive theory Apologists of the interpersonal comparison of utility have argued that Robbins claimed too much John Harsanyi agrees that full comparability of mental states such as utility is not practically possible but believes human beings can make some interpersonal comparisons of utility because they have similar backgrounds cultural experiences and psychology Amartya Sen 1970 p 99 argues that even if interpersonal comparisons of utility are imperfect we can still say that despite being positive for Nero the Great Fire of Rome had a negative overall value citation needed Harsanyi and Sen thus argue that at least partial comparability of utility is possible and social choice theory proceeds under that assumption Relationship to public choice theory editSee also Public choice Despite the similar names public choice and social choice are two distinct fields though the two are closely related The Journal of Economic Literature classification codes place Social Choice under Microeconomics at JEL D71 with Clubs Committees and Associations whereas most Public Choice subcategories are in JEL D72 Economic Models of Political Processes Rent Seeking Elections Legislatures and Voting Behavior Empirical research editSince Arrow social choice theory has been characterized by being predominantly mathematical and theoretical but some research has aimed at estimating the frequency of various voting paradoxes such as the Condorcet paradox 11 12 A summary of 37 individual studies covering a total of 265 real world elections large and small found 25 instances of a Condorcet paradox for a total likelihood of 9 4 12 325 While examples of the paradox seem to occur often in small settings like parliaments very few examples have been found in larger groups electorates although some have been identified 13 However the frequency of such paradoxes depends heavily on the number of options and other factors Rules editLet X displaystyle X nbsp be a set of possible states of the world or alternatives Society wishes to choose a single state from X displaystyle X nbsp For example in a single winner election X displaystyle X nbsp may represent the set of candidates in a resource allocation setting X displaystyle X nbsp may represent all possible allocations Let I displaystyle I nbsp be a finite set representing a collection of individuals For each i I displaystyle i in I nbsp let u i X R displaystyle u i X longrightarrow mathbb R nbsp be a utility function describing the amount of happiness an individual i derives from each possible state A social choice rule is a mechanism which uses the data u i i I displaystyle u i i in I nbsp to select some element s from X displaystyle X nbsp which are best for society The question of what best means is a common question in social choice theory The following rules are most common Utilitarian rule sometimes called the max sum rule or Benthamite welfare aims to maximize the sum of utilities Egalitarian rule sometimes called the max min rule or Rawlsian welfare aims to maximize the smallest utility Functions editA social choice function or a voting rule takes an individual s complete and transitive preferences over a set of outcomes and returns a single chosen outcome or a set of tied outcomes We can think of this subset as the winners of an election and compare different social choice functions based on which axioms or mathematical properties they fulfill 2 Arrow s impossibility theorem is what often comes to mind when one thinks about impossibility theorems in voting There are several famous theorems concerning social choice functions The Gibbard Satterthwaite theorem states that all non dictatorial voting rules that is resolute it always returns a single winner no matter what the ballots are and non imposed every alternative could be chosen with more than three alternatives candidates is manipulable That is a voter can cast a ballot that misrepresents their preferences to obtain a result that is more favorable to them under their sincere preferences May s theorem states that when there are only two candidates simple majority vote is the unique neutral anonymous and positively responsive voting rule 14 See also editCompensation principle Computational social choice Condorcet paradox Emotional choice theory Extended sympathy Game theory Group decision making Justice economics Liberal paradox Mechanism design Nakamura number Rational choice theory Rule according to higher law Voting systemNotes edit a b c Amartya Sen 2008 Social Choice The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition Abstract amp TOC a b c Zwicker William S Moulin Herve 2016 Brandt Felix Conitzer Vincent Endriss Ulle Lang Jerome eds Introduction to the Theory of Voting Handbook of Computational Social Choice Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 23 56 doi 10 1017 cbo9781107446984 003 ISBN 978 1 107 44698 4 retrieved 2021 12 24 For example in Kenneth J Arrow 1951 Social Choice and Individual Values New York Wiley ch II section 2 A Notation for Preferences and Choice and ch III The Social Welfare Function Colomer Josep M 2013 02 01 Ramon Llull from Ars electionis to social choice theory Social Choice and Welfare 40 2 317 328 doi 10 1007 s00355 011 0598 2 ISSN 1432 217X Walter Bossert and John A Weymark 2008 Social Choice New Developments The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition Abstract amp TOC Kaushik Basu Lopez Calva Luis F 2011 Functionings and Capabilities Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare Vol 2 pp 153 187 doi 10 1016 S0169 7218 10 00016 X ISBN 9780444508942 d Aspremont Claude Gevers Louis 2002 Chapter 10 Social welfare functionals and interpersonal comparability Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare Vol 1 pp 459 541 doi 10 1016 S1574 0110 02 80014 5 ISBN 9780444829146 Amartya Sen 1987 2008 Justice The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition Abstract amp TOC Bertil Tungodden 2008 Justice New Perspectives The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition Abstract Louis Kaplow 2008 Pareto Principle and Competing Principles The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition Abstract Amartya K Sen 1979 1984 Collective Choice and Social Welfare New York Elsevier description ch 9 Equity and Justice pp 131 51 ch 9 Impersonality and Collective Quasi Orderings pp 152 160 Kenneth J Arrow 1983 Collected Papers v 1 Social Choice and Justice Cambridge MA Belknap Press Description contents and chapter preview links Charles Blackorby Walter Bossert and David Donaldson 2002 Utilitarianism and the Theory of Justice in Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare edited by Kenneth J Arrow Amartya K Sen and Kotaro Suzumura v 1 ch 11 pp 543 596 Abstract Dutta Bhaskar 2002 Chapter 12 Inequality poverty and welfare Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare Vol 1 pp 597 633 doi 10 1016 S1574 0110 02 80016 9 ISBN 9780444829146 Lionel Robbins 1932 1935 2nd ed An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science London Macmillan Links for 1932 HTML and 1935 facsimile Kurrild Klitgaard Peter 2014 Empirical social choice An introduction Public Choice 158 3 4 297 310 doi 10 1007 s11127 014 0164 4 ISSN 0048 5829 S2CID 148982833 a b Van Deemen Adrian 2014 On the empirical relevance of Condorcet s paradox Public Choice 158 3 4 311 330 doi 10 1007 s11127 013 0133 3 ISSN 0048 5829 S2CID 154862595 Kurrild Klitgaard Peter 2014 An empirical example of the Condorcet paradox of voting in a large electorate Public Choice 107 1 2 135 145 doi 10 1023 A 1010304729545 ISSN 0048 5829 S2CID 152300013 May Kenneth O October 1952 A Set of Independent Necessary and Sufficient Conditions for Simple Majority Decision Econometrica 20 4 680 684 doi 10 2307 1907651 JSTOR 1907651 References editArrow Kenneth J 1951 2nd ed 1963 Social Choice and Individual Values New York Wiley ISBN 0 300 01364 7 1972 General Economic Equilibrium Purpose Analytic Techniques Collective Choice Nobel Prize Lecture Link to text with Section 8 on the theory and background 1983 Collected Papers v 1 Social Choice and Justice Oxford Blackwell ISBN 0 674 13760 4 Arrow Kenneth J Amartya K Sen and Kotaro Suzumura eds 1997 Social Choice Re Examined 2 vol London Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 0 312 12739 1 amp ISBN 0 312 12741 3 eds 2002 Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare v 1 Chapter preview links ed 2011 Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare v 2 Amsterdam Elsevier Chapter preview links Bossert Walter and John A Weymark 2008 Social Choice New Developments The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition London Palgrave Macmillan Abstract Dryzek John S and Christian List 2003 Social Choice Theory and Deliberative Democracy A Reconciliation British Journal of Political Science 33 1 pp 1 28 https www jstor org discover 10 2307 4092266 uid 3739936 amp uid 2 amp uid 4 amp uid 3739256 amp sid 21102056001967 2002 PDF link Feldman Allan M and Roberto Serrano 2006 Welfare Economics and Social Choice Theory 2nd ed New York Springer ISBN 0 387 29367 1 ISBN 978 0 387 29367 7 Arrow searchable chapter previews Fleurbaey Marc 1996 Theories economiques de la justice Paris Economica Gaertner Wulf 2006 A primer in social choice theory Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 929751 1 Harsanyi John C 1987 Interpersonal Utility Comparisons The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 2 London Palgrave pp 955 58 Moulin Herve 1988 Axioms of cooperative decision making Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 42458 5 Myerson Roger B June 2013 Fundamentals of social choice theory Quarterly Journal of Political Science 8 3 305 337 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 297 6781 doi 10 1561 100 00013006 Nitzan Shmuel 2010 Collective Preference and Choice Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 72213 1 Robbins Lionel 1935 An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science 2nd ed London Macmillan ch VI 1938 Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility A Comment Economic Journal 43 4 635 41 Sen Amartya K 1970 1984 Collective Choice and Social Welfare New York Elsevier ISBN 0 444 85127 5 Description 1998 The Possibility of Social Choice Nobel Prize Lecture 1 1987 Social Choice The New Palgrave A Dictionary of Economics v 4 London Palgrave pp 382 93 2008 Social Choice The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd Edition London Palgrave Abstract Shoham Yoav Leyton Brown Kevin 2009 Multiagent Systems Algorithmic Game Theoretic and Logical Foundations New York Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 89943 7 A comprehensive reference from a computational perspective see Chapter 9 Downloadable free online Suzumura Kotaro 1983 Rational Choice Collective Decisions and Social Welfare Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 23862 5 Taylor Alan D 2005 Social choice and the mathematics of manipulation New York Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 00883 9 External links editList Christian Social Choice Theory In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Social Choice Bibliography by J S Kelly Archived 2017 12 23 at the Wayback Machine Electowiki a wiki covering many subjects of social choice and voting theory Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Social choice theory amp oldid 1216864231, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.