fbpx
Wikipedia

Anattā

In Buddhism, the term anattā (Pali: 𑀅𑀦𑀢𑁆𑀢𑀸) or anātman (Sanskrit: अनात्मन्) is the doctrine of "non-self" – that no unchanging, permanent self or essence can be found in any phenomenon.[note 1] While often interpreted as a doctrine denying the existence of a self, anatman is more accurately described as a strategy to attain non-attachment by recognizing everything as impermanent, while staying silent on the ultimate existence of an unchanging essence.[1][2][3] In contrast, dominant schools of Hinduism assert the existence of Ātman as pure awareness or witness-consciousness,[4][5][6][note 2] "reify[ing] consciousness as an eternal self."[7]

Translations of
Anatta
EnglishNot self, nonself
Sanskritअनात्मन्
(IAST: anātman)
Chinese無我
(Pinyin: wúwǒ)
Japanese無我
(Rōmaji: muga)
Korean무아
(RR: mua)
Tibetanབདག་མེད་པ
(bdag med)
Vietnamesevô ngã
Glossary of Buddhism

Etymology and nomenclature edit

Anattā is a composite Pali word consisting of an (not) and attā (self-existent essence).[8] The term refers to the central Buddhist concept that there is no phenomenon that has "self" or essence.[1] It is one of the three characteristics of all existence, together with dukkha (suffering, dissatisfaction) and anicca (impermanence).[8]

Anattā is synonymous with Anātman (an + ātman) in Sanskrit Buddhist texts.[9] In some Pali texts, ātman of Vedic texts is also referred to with the term Attan, with the sense of "soul".[8] An alternate use of Attan or Atta is "self, oneself, essence of a person", driven by the Vedic-era Brahmanical belief that atman is the permanent, unchangeable essence of a living being, or the true self.[8][9]

In Buddhism-related English literature, Anattā is rendered as "not-Self", but this translation expresses an incomplete meaning, states Peter Harvey; a more complete rendering is "non-Self" because from its earliest days, Anattā doctrine denied that there is anything called a "Self" in any person or anything else, and that a belief in "Self" is a source of Dukkha (suffering, pain, unsatisfactoriness).[10][11][note 3] Buddhist scholar Richard Gombrich, however, argues that anattā is often mistranslated as meaning "not having a self or essence", but actually means "is not ātman" instead of "does not have ātman."[1] It is also incorrect to translate Anattā simply as "ego-less", according to Peter Harvey, because the Indian concept of ātman and attā is different from the Freudian concept of ego.[15][note 4]

In early Buddhism edit

In early Buddhist texts edit

The concept of Anattā appears in numerous Sutras of the ancient Buddhist Nikāya texts (Pali canon). It appears, for example, as a noun in Samyutta Nikaya III.141, IV.49, V.345, in Sutta II.37 of Anguttara Nikaya, II.37–45 and II.80 of Patisambhidamagga, III.406 of Dhammapada. It also appears as an adjective, for example, in Samyutta Nikaya III.114, III.133, IV.28 and IV.130–166, in Sutta III.66 and V.86 of Vinaya.[8][17] It is also found in the Dhammapada.[18]

The ancient Buddhist texts discuss Attā or Attan (self), sometimes with alternate terms such as Atuman, Tuma, Puggala, Jiva, Satta, Pana and Nama-rupa, thereby providing the context for the Buddhist Anattā doctrine. Examples of such Attā contextual discussions are found in Digha Nikaya I.186–187, Samyutta Nikaya III.179 and IV.54, Vinaya I.14, Majjhima Nikaya I.138, III.19, and III.265–271 and Anguttara Nikaya I.284.[8][17][19] According to Steven Collins, the inquiry of anattā and "denial of self" in the canonical Buddhist texts is "insisted on only in certain theoretical contexts", while they use the terms atta, purisa, puggala quite naturally and freely in various contexts.[19] The elaboration of the anattā doctrine, along with identification of the words such as "puggala" as "permanent subject or soul" appears in later Buddhist literature.[19]

According to Collins, the Suttas present the doctrine in three forms. First, they apply the "no-self, no-identity" investigation to all phenomena as well as any and all objects, yielding the idea that "all things are not-self" (sabbe dhamma anattā).[20] Second, states Collins, the Suttas apply the doctrine to deny self of any person, treating conceit to be evident in any assertion of "this is mine, this I am, this is myself" (etam mamam eso 'ham asmi, eso me atta ti).[21] Third, the Theravada texts apply the doctrine as a nominal reference, to identify examples of "self" and "not-self", respectively the Wrong view and the Right view; this third case of nominative usage is properly translated as "self" (as an identity) and is unrelated to "soul", states Collins.[21] The first two usages incorporate the idea of soul.[22]

No denial of self edit

Buddhist scholars Richard Gombrich and Alexander Wynne argue that the Buddha's descriptions of non-self in early Buddhist texts do not deny that there is a self.[1][2] Wynne and Gombrich both argue that the Buddha's statements on anattā were originally a "not-self" teaching that developed into a "no-self" teaching in later Buddhist thought.[2][1] According to Wynne, early Buddhist texts such as the Anattalakkhaṇa Sutta do not deny that there is a self, stating that the five aggregates that are described as not-self are not descriptions of a human being but descriptions of the human experience.[2] According to Johannes Bronkhorst, it is possible that "original Buddhism did not deny the existence of the soul", even though a firm Buddhist tradition has maintained that the Buddha avoided talking about the soul or even denied its existence.[23]

Tibetologist André Migot states that original Buddhism may not have taught a complete absence of self, pointing to evidence presented by Buddhist and Pali scholars Jean Przyluski and Caroline Rhys Davids that early Buddhism generally believed in a self, making Buddhist schools that admit an existence of a "self" not heretical, but conservative, adhering to ancient beliefs.[24] While there may be ambivalence on the existence or non-existence of self in early Buddhist literature, Bronkhorst suggests that these texts clearly indicate that the Buddhist path of liberation consists not in seeking Atman-like self-knowledge, but in turning away from what might erroneously be regarded as the self.[25] This is a reverse position to the Vedic traditions which recognized the knowledge of the self as "the principal means to achieving liberation."[25]

According to Harvey, the contextual use of Attā in the Nikāyas is two-sided. In one, it directly denies that anything can be found called a self or soul in a human being that is a permanent essence of a human being, a theme found in Brahmanical traditions.[26] In another, states Peter Harvey, such as at Samyutta Nikaya IV.286, the Sutta considers the materialistic concept in the pre-Buddhist Vedic period of "no afterlife, complete annihilation" at death to be a denial of Self, but still "tied up with belief in a Self".[27] "Self exists" is a false premise, assert the early Buddhist texts.[27] However, adds Peter Harvey, these texts do not admit the premise "Self does not exist" either because the wording presumes the concept of "Self" before denying it; instead, the early Buddhist texts use the concept of Anattā as the implicit premise.[27][28]

Developing the self edit

According to Peter Harvey, while the Suttas criticize notions of an eternal, unchanging Self as baseless, they see an enlightened being as one whose empirical self is highly developed.[29] This is paradoxical, states Harvey, in that "the Self-like nibbana state" is a mature self that knows "everything as Selfless".[29] The "empirical self" is the citta (mind/heart, mindset, emotional nature), and the development of self in the Suttas is the development of this citta.[30]

One with "great self", state the early Buddhist Suttas, has a mind which is neither at the mercy of outside stimuli nor its own moods, neither scattered nor diffused, but imbued with self-control, and self-contained towards the single goal of nibbana and a 'Self-like' state.[29] This "great self" is not yet an Arahat, because he still does small evil action which leads to karmic fruition, but he has enough virtue that he does not experience this fruition in hell.[29]

An Arahat, states Harvey, has a fully enlightened state of empirical self, one that lacks the "sense of both 'I am' and 'this I am'", which are illusions that the Arahat has transcended.[31] The Buddhist thought and salvation theory emphasizes a development of self towards a Selfless state not only with respect to oneself, but recognizing the lack of relational essence and Self in others, wherein states Martijn van Zomeren, "self is an illusion".[32]

Karma, rebirth and anattā edit

The four stages of awakening
(according to the Sutta Piṭaka[note 5])

stage's
"fruit"[note 6]

abandoned
fetters

rebirth(s)
until suffering's end

sotāpanna

1. identity view (Anattā)
2. doubt in Buddha
3. ascetic or ritual rules

lower
fetters

up to seven rebirths in
human or heavenly realms

sakadagami[note 7]

once more as
a human

anāgāmi

4. sensual desire
5. ill will

once more in
a heavenly realm
(Pure Abodes)

arahant

6. material-rebirth desire
7. immaterial-rebirth desire
8. conceit
9. restlessness
10. ignorance

higher
fetters

no rebirth

Source: Ñāṇamoli & Bodhi (2001), Middle-Length Discourses, pp. 41-43.

The Buddha emphasized both karma and anattā doctrines.[3] The Buddha criticized the doctrine that posited an unchanging essence as a subject as the basis of rebirth and karmic moral responsibility, which he called "atthikavāda". He also criticized the materialistic doctrine that denied the existence of both soul and rebirth, and thereby denied karmic moral responsibility, which he calls "natthikavāda".[33] Instead, the Buddha asserted that there is no essence, but there is rebirth for which karmic moral responsibility is a must. In the Buddha's framework of karma, right view and right actions are necessary for liberation.[34][35]

Hinduism, Jainism and Buddhism all assert a belief in rebirth, and emphasize moral responsibility in a way different from pre-Buddhist materialistic schools of Indian philosophies.[36][37][38] The materialistic schools of Indian philosophies, such as Charvaka, are called annihilationist schools because they posited that death is the end, there is no afterlife, no soul, no rebirth, no karma, and death is that state where a living being is completely annihilated, dissolved.[39]

Buddha criticized the materialistic annihilationism view that denied rebirth and karma, states Damien Keown.[36] Such beliefs are inappropriate and dangerous, stated Buddha, because they encourage moral irresponsibility and material hedonism.[36] Anattā does not mean there is no afterlife, no rebirth or no fruition of karma, and Buddhism contrasts itself to annihilationist schools.[36] Buddhism also contrasts itself to other Indian religions that champion moral responsibility but posit eternalism with their premise that within each human being there is an essence or eternal soul, and this soul is part of the nature of a living being, existence and metaphysical reality.[40][41][42]

In Theravada Buddhism edit

Traditional views edit

Theravada Buddhism scholars, states Oliver Leaman, consider the Anattā doctrine as one of the main theses of Buddhism.[43] The Buddhist denial of an unchanging, permanent self is what distinguishes Buddhism from major religions of the world such as Christianity and Hinduism, giving it uniqueness, asserts the Theravada tradition.[43] With the doctrine of Anattā, stands or falls the entire Buddhist structure, asserts Nyanatiloka Mahathera.[44]

According to Collins, "insight into the teaching of anattā is held to have two major loci in the intellectual and spiritual education of an individual" as s/he progresses along the Path.[45] The first part of this insight is to avoid sakkayaditthi (Personality Belief), that is converting the "sense of I which is gained from introspection and the fact of physical individuality" into a theoretical belief in a self.[45] "A belief in a (really) existing body" is considered a false belief and a part of the Ten Fetters that must be gradually lost. The second loci is the psychological realization of anattā, or loss of "pride or conceit". This, states Collins, is explained as the conceit of asmimana or "I am"; (...) what this "conceit" refers to is the fact that for the unenlightened man, all experience and action must necessarily appear phenomenologically as happening to or originating from an "I".[45] When a Buddhist gets more enlightened, this happening to or originating in an "I" or sakkdyaditthi is less. The final attainment of enlightenment is the disappearance of this automatic but illusory "I".[45]

The Theravada tradition has long considered the understanding and application of the Anattā doctrine to be a complex teaching, whose "personal, introjected application has always been thought to be possible only for the specialist, the practising monk". The tradition, states Collins, has "insisted fiercely on anattā as a doctrinal position", while in practice it may not play much of a role in the daily religious life of most Buddhists.[20] The Theravada doctrine of Anattā, or not-self not-soul, inspire meditative practices for monks, states Donald Swearer, but for the lay Theravada Buddhists in Southeast Asia, the doctrines of kamma, rebirth and punna (merit) inspire a wide range of ritual practices and ethical behavior.[46]

The Anattā doctrine is key to the concept of Nibbana in the Theravada tradition. The liberated nirvana state, states Collins, is the state of Anattā, a state that is neither universally applicable nor can be explained, but can be realized.[47][note 8]

Current disputes edit

The dispute about "self" and "not-self" doctrines has continued throughout the history of Buddhism.[50] In Thai Buddhism, for example, states Paul Williams, some modern era Buddhist scholars have claimed that "Nirvana is indeed the true self", while other Thai Buddhists disagree.[51] For instance, the Dhammakaya tradition in Thailand teaches that it is erroneous to subsume nirvana under the rubric of anattā (non-self); instead, nirvana is taught to be the "true self" or dhammakaya.[52] The Dhammakaya tradition teaching that nirvana is atta, or true self, was criticized as heretical in Buddhism in 1994 by Ven. Payutto, a well-known scholar monk, who stated that 'Buddha taught Nibbana as being non-self".[53][54] The abbot of one major temple in the Dhammakaya tradition, Luang Por Sermchai of Wat Luang Por Sodh Dhammakayaram, argues that it tends to be scholars who hold the view of absolute non-self, rather than Buddhist meditation practitioners. He points to the experiences of prominent forest hermit monks such as Luang Pu Sodh and Ajahn Mun to support the notion of a "true self".[54][55] Similar interpretations on the "true self" were put forth earlier by the 12th Supreme Patriarch of Thailand in 1939. According to Williams, the Supreme Patriarch's interpretation echoes the tathāgatagarbha sutras.[56]

Several notable teachers of the Thai Forest Tradition have also described ideas in contrast to absolute non-self. Ajahn Maha Bua, a well known meditation master, described the citta (mind) as being an indestructible reality that does not fall under anattā.[57] He has stated that not-self is merely a perception that is used to pry one away from infatuation with the concept of a self, and that once this infatuation is gone the idea of not-self must be dropped as well.[58] American monk Thanissaro Bhikkhu of the Thai Forest Tradition describes the Buddha's statements on non-self as a path to awakening rather than a universal truth.[3] Bhikkhu Bodhi authored a rejoinder to Thanissaro, agreeing that anattā is a strategy for awakening but stating that "The reason the teaching of anattā can serve as a strategy of liberation is precisely because it serves to rectify a misconception about the nature of being, hence an ontological error."[59] Thanissaro Bhikkhu states that the Buddha intentionally set aside the question of whether or not there is a self as a useless question, and goes on to call the phrase "there is no self" the "granddaddy of fake Buddhist quotes". He adds that clinging to the idea that there is no self at all would actually prevent enlightenment.[60] Thanissaro Bhikkhu points to the Ananda Sutta (SN 44.10), where the Buddha stays silent when asked whether there is a 'self' or not,[61] as a major cause of the dispute.[62]

Anātman in Mahayana Buddhism edit

Anātman is one of the main bedrock doctrines of Buddhism, and its discussion is found in the later texts of all Buddhist traditions.[43]

There are many different views of anātman (Chinese: 無我; pinyin: wúwǒ; Japanese: 無我 muga; Korean: 무아 mu-a) within various Mahayana schools.[63]

The early Mahayana Buddhist texts link their discussion of "emptiness" (śūnyatā) to anātman and nirvana. They do so, states Mun-Keat Choong, in three ways: first, in the common sense of a monk's meditative state of emptiness; second, with the main sense of anātman or 'everything in the world is empty of self'; third, with the ultimate sense of Nirvana or realization of emptiness and thus an end to rebirth cycles of suffering.[64] The anātman doctrine is another aspect of śūnyatā, its realization is the nature of the nirvana state and to an end to rebirths.[65][66][67]

Nāgārjuna edit

The Buddhist philosopher Nāgārjuna (~200 CE), the founder of Madhyamaka (middle way) school of Mahayana Buddhism, analyzed dharma first as factors of experience.[13] David Kalupahana states that Nāgārjuna analyzed how these experiences relate to "bondage and freedom, action and consequence", and thereafter analyzed the notion of personal self (ātman).[13]

Nāgārjuna extensively wrote about rejecting the metaphysical entity called ātman (self, soul), asserting in chapter 18 of his Mūlamadhyamakakārikā that there is no such substantial entity and that "Buddha taught the doctrine of no-self".[68][69][70]

Nāgārjuna asserted that the notion of a self is associated with the notion of one's own identity and corollary ideas of pride, selfishness and a sense of psychophysical personality.[71] This is all false, and leads to bondage in his Madhyamaka thought. There can be no pride nor possessiveness, in someone who accepts anātman and denies "self" which is the sense of personal identity of oneself, others or anything, states Nāgārjuna.[13][14] Further, all obsessions are avoided when a person accepts emptiness (śūnyatā).[13][72] Nāgārjuna denied there is anything called a self-nature as well as other-nature, emphasizing true knowledge to be comprehending emptiness.[71][73][74] Anyone who has not dissociated from their belief in personality in themselves or others, through the concept of self, is in a state of avidya (ignorance) and caught in the cycle of rebirths and redeaths.[71][75]

Yogācāra edit

The texts attributed to the 5th-century Buddhist philosopher Vasubandhu of the Yogācāra school similarly discuss anātman as a fundamental premise of the Buddha.[76] The Vasubandhu interpretations of no-self thesis were challenged by the 7th-century Buddhist scholar Candrakīrti, who then offered his own theories on its importance.[77][78]

Tathāgatagarbha Sutras: Buddha is True Self edit

Some 1st-millennium CE Buddhist texts suggest concepts that have been controversial because they imply a "self-like" concept.[79][80] In particular are the tathāgatagarbha sūtras, where the title itself means a garbha (womb, matrix, seed) containing Tathāgata (Buddha). These Sutras suggest, states Paul Williams, that "all sentient beings contain a Tathagata" as their "essence, core or essential inner nature".[81] The tathāgatagarbha doctrine, at its earliest probably appeared about the later part of the 3rd century CE, and is verifiable in Chinese translations of 1st millennium CE.[81] Most scholars consider the tathāgatagarbha doctrine of an "essential nature" in every living being is equivalent to "self",[citation needed][note 9] and it contradicts the anātman doctrines in a vast majority of Buddhist texts, leading scholars to posit that the tathāgatagarbha sutras were written to promote Buddhism to non-Buddhists.[83][84]

The Mahayana Mahaparinirvana Sutra explicitly asserts that the Buddha used the term "self" in order to win over non-Buddhist ascetics.[85][86] The Ratnagotravibhāga (also known as Uttaratantra), another text composed in the first half of 1st millennium CE and translated into Chinese in 511 CE, points out that the teaching of the tathāgatagarbha doctrine is intended to win sentient beings over to abandoning "self-love" (atma-sneha) – considered to be one of the defects by Buddhism.[87][88] The 6th-century Chinese tathāgatagarbha translation states that "Buddha has shiwo (true self) which is beyond being and nonbeing".[89] However, the Ratnagotravibhāga asserts that the "self" implied in tathāgatagarbha doctrine is actually "not-self".[89][90]

According to some scholars, the Buddha-nature discussed in these sutras does not represent a substantial self; rather, it is a positive language and expression of śūnyatā "emptiness" and represents the potentiality to realize Buddhahood through Buddhist practices.[87] Other scholars do in fact detect leanings towards monism in these tathagatagarbha references.[91] Michael Zimmermann sees the notion of an unperishing and eternal self in the Tathagatagarbha Sutra.[92] Zimmermann also avers that "the existence of an eternal, imperishable self, that is, buddhahood, is definitely the basic point of the Tathāgatagarbha Sutra".[93] He further indicates that there is no evident interest found in this sutra in the idea of Emptiness (sunyata).[94] Williams states that the "self" in tathāgatagarbha sutras is actually "non-self", and neither identical nor comparable to the Hindu concepts of brahman and self.[87]

Vajrayāna edit

 
Tibetan and Nepalese Buddhist deities Nairatmya and Hevajra in an embrace. Nairatmya is the goddess of emptiness, and of anātman realization.[95][96]

The anātman doctrine is extensively discussed in and partly inspires the ritual practices of the Vajrayāna tradition. The Tibetan terms such as bdag med refer to "without a self, insubstantial, anātman".[97] These discussions, states Jeffrey Hopkins, assert the "non-existence of a permanent, unitary and independent self", and attribute these ideas to the Buddha.[98]

The ritual practices in Vajrayāna Buddhism employs the concept of deities, to end self-grasping, and to manifest as a purified, enlightened deity as part of the Vajrayāna path to liberation from rebirths.[99][100][101] One such deity is goddess Nairatmya (literally, non-soul, non-self).[102][103][104] She symbolizes, states Miranda Shaw, that "self is an illusion" and "all beings and phenomenal appearances lack an abiding self or essence" in Vajrayāna Buddhism.[95]

Difference between Buddhism and Hinduism edit

Atman in Hinduism edit

The Buddhist concept of anattā or anātman is one of the fundamental differences between mainstream Buddhism and mainstream Hinduism, with the latter asserting that ātman ("self") exists.[note 2]

In Hinduism, Atman refers to the essence of human beings, the observing pure awareness or witness-consciousness.[4][5][105][106] It is unaffected by ego,[107][108] distinct from the individual being (jivanatman) embedded in material reality, and characterized by Ahamkara ('I-making'), mind (citta, manas), and all the defiling kleshas (impurities). Embodied personality changes over time, while Atman doesn't.[109]

According to Jayatilleke, the Upanishadic inquiry fails to find an empirical correlate of the assumed Atman, but nevertheless assumes its existence,[110] and Advaitins "reify consciousness as an eternal self."[7] In contrast, the Buddhist inquiry "is satisfied with the empirical investigation which shows that no such Atman exists because there is no evidence" states Jayatilleke.[110] According to Harvey, in Buddhism the negation of temporal existents is applied even more rigorous than in the Upanishads:

While the Upanishads recognized many things as being not-Self, they felt that a real, true Self could be found. They held that when it was found, and known to be identical to Brahman, the basis of everything, this would bring liberation. In the Buddhist Suttas, though, literally everything is seen is non-Self, even Nirvana. When this is known, then liberation – Nirvana – is attained by total non-attachment. Thus both the Upanishads and the Buddhist Suttas see many things as not-Self, but the Suttas apply it, indeed non-Self, to everything.[111]

Both Buddhism and Hinduism distinguish ego-related "I am, this is mine", from their respective abstract doctrines of "Anattā" and "Atman".[112] This, states Peter Harvey, may have been an influence of Buddhism on Hinduism.[113]

Anatman and Niratman edit

The term niratman appears in the Maitrayaniya Upanishad of Hinduism, such as in verses 6.20, 6.21 and 7.4. Niratman literally means "selfless".[114][115] The niratman concept has been interpreted to be analogous to anatman of Buddhism.[116] The ontological teachings, however, are different. In the Upanishad, states Thomas Wood, numerous positive and negative descriptions of various states – such as niratman and sarvasyatman (the self of all) – are used in Maitrayaniya Upanishad to explain the nondual concept of the "highest Self".[115] According to Ramatirtha, states Paul Deussen, the niratman state discussion is referring to stopping the recognition of oneself as an individual soul, and reaching the awareness of universal soul or the metaphysical Brahman.[117]

Correspondence in Pyrrhonism edit

The Greek philosopher Pyrrho traveled to India as part of Alexander the Great's entourage where he was influenced by the Indian gymnosophists,[118] which inspired him to create the philosophy of Pyrrhonism. Philologist Christopher Beckwith argues that Pyrrho based his philosophy on his translation of the three marks of existence into Greek, and that adiaphora (not logically differentiable, not clearly definable, negating Aristotle's use of "diaphora") reflects Pyrrho's understanding of the Buddhist concept of anattā.[119]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Definition:
    • Anatta 2015-12-10 at the Wayback Machine, Encyclopædia Britannica (2013): "Anatta, (Pali: “non-self” or “substanceless”) Sanskrit anatman, in Buddhism, the doctrine that there is in humans no permanent, underlying substance that can be called the soul. Instead, the individual is compounded of five factors (Pali khandha; Sanskrit skandha) that are constantly changing. "
    • Christmas Humphreys (2012). Exploring Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 42–43. ISBN 978-1-136-22877-3.
    • Brian Morris (2006). Religion and Anthropology: A Critical Introduction. Cambridge University Press. p. 51. ISBN 978-0-521-85241-8.: "...anatta is the doctrine of non-self, and is an extreme empiricist doctrine that holds that the notion of an unchanging permanent self is a fiction and has no reality. According to Buddhist doctrine, the individual person consists of five skandhas or heaps—the body, feelings, perceptions, impulses and consciousness. The belief in a self or soul, over these five skandhas, is illusory and the cause of suffering."
    • Richard Gombrich (2006). Theravada Buddhism. Routledge. p. 47. ISBN 978-1-134-90352-8.: "...Buddha's teaching that beings have no soul, no abiding essence. This 'no-soul doctrine' (anatta-vada) he expounded in his second sermon."
  2. ^ a b Atman in Hinduism:
    • Anatta 2015-12-10 at the Wayback Machine, Encyclopædia Britannica (2013): "The concept of anatta, or anatman, is a departure from the Hindu belief in atman ("the self").";
    • Steven Collins (1994), "Religion and Practical Reason" (Editors: Frank Reynolds, David Tracy), State Univ of New York Press, ISBN 978-0-7914-2217-5, page 64; "Central to Buddhist soteriology is the doctrine of not-self (Pali: anattā, Sanskrit: anātman, the opposed doctrine of ātman is central to Brahmanical thought). Put very briefly, this is the [Buddhist] doctrine that human beings have no soul, no self, no unchanging essence.";
    • Edward Roer (Translator), Shankara's Introduction, p. 2, at Google Books to Brihad Aranyaka Upanishad, pages 2–4;
    • Katie Javanaud (2013), Is The Buddhist 'No-Self' Doctrine Compatible With Pursuing Nirvana? 2015-02-06 at the Wayback Machine, Philosophy Now;
    • David Loy (1982), "Enlightenment in Buddhism and Advaita Vedanta: Are Nirvana and Moksha the Same?", International Philosophical Quarterly, Volume 23, Issue 1, pages 65–74;
    • KN Jayatilleke (2010), Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge, ISBN 978-8120806191, pages 246–249, from note 385 onwards;
    • Plott (2000)
  3. ^ Buddha did not deny a being or a thing, referring it to be a collection of impermanent interdependent aggregates, but denied that there is a metaphysical self, soul or identity in anything.[12][13][14]
  4. ^ The term ahamkara is 'ego' in Indian philosophies.[16]
  5. ^ See, for instance, the "Snake-Simile Discourse" (MN 22), where the Buddha states:

    "Monks, this Teaching so well proclaimed by me, is plain, open, explicit, free of patchwork. In this Teaching that is so well proclaimed by me and is plain, open, explicit and free of patchwork; for those who are arahants, free of taints, who have accomplished and completed their task, have laid down the burden, achieved their aim, severed the fetters binding to existence, who are liberated by full knowledge, there is no (future) round of existence that can be ascribed to them. – Majjhima Nikaya i.130 ¶ 42, Translated by Nyanaponika Thera (Nyanaponika, 2006)

  6. ^ The "fruit" (Pali: phala) is the culmination of the "path" (magga). Thus, for example, the "stream-enterer" is the fruit for one on the "stream-entry" path; more specifically, the stream-enterer has abandoned the first three fetters, while one on the path of stream-entry strives to abandon these fetters.
  7. ^ Both the stream-enterer and the once-returner abandon the first three fetters. What distinguishes these stages is that the once-returner additionally attenuates lust, hate and delusion, and will necessarily be reborn only once more.
  8. ^ This is a major difference between the Theravada Buddhists and different Hindu traditions which assert that nirvana is realizing and being in the state of self (soul, atman) and is universally applicable. However, both concur that this state is indescribable, cannot be explained, but can be realized.[48][49]
  9. ^ Wayman and Wayman have disagreed with this view, and they state that the tathāgatagarbha is neither self nor sentient being, nor soul, nor personality.[82]

References edit

  1. ^ a b c d e Gombrich 2009, p. 69–70.
  2. ^ a b c d Wynne 2009, p. 59–63, 76–77.
  3. ^ a b c "Selves & Not-self: The Buddhist Teaching on Anatta", by Thanissaro Bhikkhu. Access to Insight (Legacy Edition), 30 November 2013, http://www.accesstoinsight.org/lib/authors/thanissaro/selvesnotself.html 2013-02-04 at the Wayback Machine
  4. ^ a b Deutsch 1973, p. 48.
  5. ^ a b Dalal 2010, p. 38.
  6. ^ McClelland 2010, p. 34–35.
  7. ^ a b Mackenzie 2012.
  8. ^ a b c d e f Thomas William Rhys Davids; William Stede (1921). Pali-English Dictionary. Motilal Banarsidass. p. 22. ISBN 978-81-208-1144-7. from the original on 2016-12-07. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  9. ^ a b Johannes Bronkhorst (2009). Buddhist Teaching in India. Simon and Schuster. pp. 124–125 with footnotes. ISBN 978-0-86171-566-4. from the original on 2016-12-07. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  10. ^ Peter Harvey (2012). An Introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, History and Practices. Cambridge University Press. pp. 57–62. ISBN 978-0-521-85942-4. from the original on 2020-07-27. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  11. ^ Peter Harvey (2015). Steven M. Emmanuel (ed.). A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 34–37. ISBN 978-1-119-14466-3. from the original on 2017-03-23. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  12. ^ Peter Harvey (2015). Steven M. Emmanuel (ed.). A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. p. 36. ISBN 978-1-119-14466-3. from the original on 2017-03-23. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  13. ^ a b c d e Nāgārjuna (1996). Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna. Translated by David J. Kalupahana. Motilal Banarsidass. p. 56. ISBN 978-81-208-0774-7. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  14. ^ a b David Loy (2009). Awareness Bound and Unbound: Buddhist Essays. State University of New York Press. pp. 105–106. ISBN 978-1-4384-2680-8. from the original on 2019-12-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23., Quote: Nāgārjuna, the second century Indian Buddhist philosopher, used śūnyatā not to characterize the true nature of reality but to deny that anything has any self-existence or reality of its own.
  15. ^ Peter Harvey (2012). An Introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, History and Practices. Cambridge University Press. p. 62. ISBN 978-0-521-85942-4. from the original on 2020-07-27. Retrieved 2016-10-23. Again, anatta does not mean 'egoless', as it is sometimes rendered. The term 'ego' has a range of meanings in English. The Freudian 'ego' is not the same as the Indian atman/atta or permanent Self.
  16. ^ Surendranath Dasgupta (1992). A History of Indian Philosophy. Motilal Banarsidass (Republisher; Originally published by Cambridge University Press). p. 250. ISBN 978-81-208-0412-8. from the original on 2019-06-02. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  17. ^ a b Johannes Bronkhorst (2009). Buddhist Teaching in India. Simon and Schuster. pp. 124–125 with footnotes. ISBN 978-0-86171-566-4. from the original on 2016-12-07. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  18. ^ John Carter; Mahinda Palihawadana (2008). Dhammapada. Oxford University Press. pp. 30–31, 74, 80. ISBN 978-0-19-955513-0. from the original on 2019-12-23. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  19. ^ a b c Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 71–81. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2019-05-01. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  20. ^ a b Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 94–96. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2019-05-01. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  21. ^ a b Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 96–97. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  22. ^ Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 3–5, 35–36, 109–116, 163, 193. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  23. ^ Johannes Bronkhorst (1993). The Two Traditions of Meditation in Ancient India. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 99 with footnote 12. ISBN 978-81-208-1114-0. from the original on 2018-11-20. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  24. ^ Migot, André (1954). "XV. Un grand disciple du Buddha : Sâriputra. Son rôle dans l'histoire du bouddhisme et dans le développement de l'Abhidharma". Bulletin de l'École française d'Extrême-Orient. 46 (2): 492. doi:10.3406/befeo.1954.5607. from the original on 2020-04-20. Retrieved 2020-03-07.
  25. ^ a b Johannes Bronkhorst (2009). Buddhist Teaching in India. Wisdom Publications. p. 25. ISBN 978-0-86171-811-5. from the original on 2019-12-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  26. ^ Peter Harvey (2013). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 1–2, 34–40, 224–225. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.
  27. ^ a b c Peter Harvey (2013). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 39–40. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.
  28. ^ Johannes Bronkhorst (2009). Buddhist Teaching in India. Wisdom Publications. pp. 23–25. ISBN 978-0-86171-811-5. from the original on 2019-12-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  29. ^ a b c d Peter Harvey (1995). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 54–56. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.
  30. ^ Peter Harvey (1995). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 111–112. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.
  31. ^ Peter Harvey (1995). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 31–32, 44, 50–51, 71, 210–216, 246. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.
  32. ^ Martijn van Zomeren (2016). From Self to Social Relationships: An Essentially Relational Perspective on Social Motivation. Cambridge University Press. p. 156. ISBN 978-1-107-09379-9. from the original on 2019-12-21. Retrieved 2016-09-27., Quote: Buddhism is an example of a non-theistic religion, which underlies a cultural matrix in which individuals believe that the self is an illusion. Indeed, its anatta doctrine states that the self is not an essence.
  33. ^ David Kalupahana, Causality: The Central Philosophy of Buddhism. The University Press of Hawaii, 1975, page 44.
  34. ^ Malcolm B. Hamilton (12 June 2012). The Sociology of Religion: Theoretical and Comparative Perspectives. Routledge. pp. 73–80. ISBN 978-1-134-97626-3. from the original on 22 December 2016. Retrieved 23 October 2016.
  35. ^ Raju, P. T. (1985). Structural Depths of Indian Thought. State University of New York Press. pp. 147–151. ISBN 978-0-88706-139-4.
  36. ^ a b c d Damien Keown (2004). Ucchedavāda, śāśvata-vāda, rebirth, in A Dictionary of Buddhism. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-860560-7.
  37. ^ Robert E. Buswell Jr.; Donald S. Lopez Jr. (2013). The Princeton Dictionary of Buddhism. Princeton University Press. pp. 708–709. ISBN 978-1-4008-4805-8. from the original on 2020-05-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  38. ^ Peter Harvey (2012). An Introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, History and Practices. Cambridge University Press. pp. 32–33, 38–39, 46–49. ISBN 978-0-521-85942-4. from the original on 2020-07-27. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  39. ^ Ray Billington (2002). Understanding Eastern Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 43–44, 58–60. ISBN 978-1-134-79349-5. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  40. ^ Norman C. McClelland (2010). Encyclopedia of Reincarnation and Karma. McFarland. p. 89. ISBN 978-0-7864-5675-8. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  41. ^ Hugh Nicholson (2016). The Spirit of Contradiction in Christianity and Buddhism. Oxford University Press. pp. 23–25. ISBN 978-0-19-045534-7. from the original on 2017-01-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  42. ^ Gananath Obeyesekere (2006). Karma and Rebirth: A Cross Cultural Study. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 281–282. ISBN 978-81-208-2609-0. from the original on 2017-01-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  43. ^ a b c Oliver Leaman (2002). Eastern Philosophy: Key Readings. Routledge. pp. 23–27. ISBN 978-1-134-68919-4. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  44. ^ Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. p. 5. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  45. ^ a b c d Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 93–94. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2019-05-01. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  46. ^ Donald K. Swearer (2012). Buddhist World of Southeast Asia, The: Second Edition. State University of New York Press. pp. 2–3. ISBN 978-1-4384-3252-6. from the original on 2019-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  47. ^ Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 82–84. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  48. ^ Steven Collins (1990). Selfless Persons: Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 81–82. ISBN 978-0-521-39726-1. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  49. ^ Loy, David (1982). "Enlightenment in Buddhism and Advaita Vedanta". International Philosophical Quarterly. 22 (1). Philosophy Documentation Center: 65–74. doi:10.5840/ipq19822217.
  50. ^ Potprecha Cholvijarn. Nibbāna as True Reality beyond the Debate. Wat Luang Phor Sodh. p. 45. ISBN 978-974-350-263-7. from the original on 2019-05-02. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  51. ^ Williams 2008, pp. 125–7.
  52. ^ Mackenzie 2007, pp. 100–5, 110.
  53. ^ Mackenzie 2007, p. 51.
  54. ^ a b Williams 2008, p. 127-128.
  55. ^ Seeger 2009, pp. 13 footnote 40.
  56. ^ Williams 2008, p. 126.
  57. ^ pp. 101–103 Maha Boowa, Arahattamagga, Arahattaphala: the Path to Arahantship – A Compilation of Venerable Acariya Maha Boowa's Dhamma Talks about His Path of Practice, translated by Bhikkhu Silaratano, 2005, http://www.forestdhammabooks.com/book/3/Arahattamagga.pdf 2009-03-27 at the Wayback Machine (consulted 16 March 2009)
  58. ^ Archived at Ghostarchive and the : UWE STOES (2015-04-22), Thanassaro Bhikkhu, retrieved 2017-09-30
  59. ^ Bodhi, Bhikkhu (January 2017), "Anatta as Strategy and Ontonology", Investigating the Dhamma, Buddhist Publication Society, p. 25, ISBN 978-1-68172-068-5
  60. ^ Bhikkhu, Thanissaro. "There is no self". Tricycle: The Buddhist Review. from the original on 2018-08-19. Retrieved 2018-08-19.
  61. ^ "Ananda Sutta: To Ananda". www.accesstoinsight.org. from the original on 2017-05-10. Retrieved 2017-05-14.
  62. ^ "Introduction to the Avyakata Samyutta: (Undeclared-connected)". www.accesstoinsight.org. from the original on 2017-05-08. Retrieved 2017-05-14.
  63. ^ King, R., Early Advaita Vedanta and Buddhism: The Mahayana Context of the Gaudapadiya-Karika (Albany: SUNY Press, 1995), p. 97 2016-11-01 at the Wayback Machine.
  64. ^ Mun-Keat Choong (1999). The Notion of Emptiness in Early Buddhism. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 1–4, 85–88. ISBN 978-81-208-1649-7. from the original on 2016-11-27. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  65. ^ Ray Billington (2002). Understanding Eastern Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 58–60. ISBN 978-1-134-79348-8. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  66. ^ David Loy (2009). Awareness Bound and Unbound: Buddhist Essays. State University of New York Press. pp. 35–39. ISBN 978-1-4384-2680-8. from the original on 2019-12-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  67. ^ Stephan Schuhmacher (1994). The Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion: Buddhism, Hinduism, Taoism, Zen. Shambhala. p. 12. ISBN 978-0-87773-980-7. from the original on 2019-12-18. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  68. ^ Nāgārjuna (1996). Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna. Translated by David J. Kalupahana. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 56–57. ISBN 978-81-208-0774-7. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  69. ^ Brad Warner (2011). Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika. Translated by GW Nishijima. Monkfish. pp. 182–191. ISBN 978-0-9833589-0-9. from the original on 2019-12-19. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  70. ^ Nāgārjuna (1995). "Chapters XVIII, XXVII (see Part One and Two)". The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way: Nagarjuna's Mulamadhyamakakarika. Translated by Jay Garfield. Oxford University Press. pp. xxxiv, 76. ISBN 978-0-19-976632-1. from the original on 2019-12-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  71. ^ a b c Nāgārjuna (1996). Mūlamadhyamakakārikā of Nāgārjuna. Translated by David J. Kalupahana. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 56–59. ISBN 978-81-208-0774-7. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  72. ^ David Loy (2009). Awareness Bound and Unbound: Buddhist Essays. State University of New York Press. pp. 36–38. ISBN 978-1-4384-2680-8. from the original on 2019-12-17. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  73. ^ Diane Morgan (2004). The Buddhist Experience in America. Greenwood. p. 46. ISBN 978-0-313-32491-8. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  74. ^ David F. Burton (2015). Emptiness Appraised: A Critical Study of Nagarjuna's Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 31–32, 48 with footnote 38. ISBN 978-1-317-72322-6. from the original on 2019-12-18. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  75. ^ Ian Harris (1991). The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra in Indian Mahāyāna Buddhism. BRILL Academic. pp. 146–147. ISBN 90-04-09448-2. from the original on 2017-02-24. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  76. ^ Steven M. Emmanuel (2015). A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 419–428. ISBN 978-1-119-14466-3. from the original on 2017-03-23. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  77. ^ James Duerlinger (2013). The Refutation of the Self in Indian Buddhism: Candrakīrti on the Selflessness of Persons. Routledge. pp. 52–54. ISBN 978-0-415-65749-5. from the original on 2019-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  78. ^ Ronald W. Neufeldt (31 May 1986). Karma and Rebirth: Post Classical Developments. State University of New York Press. pp. 216–220. ISBN 978-1-4384-1445-4. from the original on 2019-12-25. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  79. ^ Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. pp. 125–127. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  80. ^ S. K. Hookham (1991). The Buddha Within: Tathagatagarbha Doctrine According to the Shentong Interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga. State University of New York Press. pp. 100–104. ISBN 978-0-7914-0357-0. from the original on 2016-11-20. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  81. ^ a b Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. p. 104. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  82. ^ Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. p. 107. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  83. ^ Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. pp. 104–105, 108. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  84. ^ Merv Fowler (1999). Buddhism: Beliefs and Practices. Sussex Academic Press. pp. 101–102. ISBN 978-1-898723-66-0. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23., Quote: "Some texts of the tathāgatagarbha literature, such as the Mahaparinirvana Sutra actually refer to an atman, though other texts are careful to avoid the term. This would be in direct opposition to the general teachings of Buddhism on anātman. Indeed, the distinctions between the general Indian concept of atman and the popular Buddhist concept of Buddha-nature are often blurred to the point that writers consider them to be synonymous."
  85. ^ Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. p. 109. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23. Quote: "... it refers to the Buddha using the term "self" in order to win over non-Buddhist ascetics."
  86. ^ John W. Pettit (1999). Mipham's Beacon of Certainty: Illuminating the View of Dzogchen, the Great Perfection. Simon and Schuster. pp. 48–49. ISBN 978-0-86171-157-4. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  87. ^ a b c Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. pp. 109–112. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  88. ^ Christopher Bartley (2015). An Introduction to Indian Philosophy: Hindu and Buddhist Ideas from Original Sources. Bloomsbury Academic. p. 105. ISBN 978-1-4725-2437-9. from the original on 2019-05-02. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  89. ^ a b Paul Williams (2008). Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations. Routledge. p. 112. ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1. from the original on 2016-11-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  90. ^ S. K. Hookham (1991). The Buddha Within: Tathagatagarbha Doctrine According to the Shentong Interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga. State University of New York Press. p. 96. ISBN 978-0-7914-0357-0. from the original on 2016-11-20. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  91. ^ Jamie Hubbard, Absolute Delusion, Perfect Buddhahood, University of Hawai’i Press, Honolulu, 2001, pp. 99–100
  92. ^ Zimmermann, Michael (2002), , Biblotheca Philologica et Philosophica Buddhica VI, The International Research Institute for Advanced Buddhology, Soka University, p. 64
  93. ^ Michael Zimmermann, A Buddha Within, p. 64
  94. ^ Zimmermann, A Buddha Within, p. 81
  95. ^ a b Miranda Eberle Shaw (2006). Buddhist Goddesses of India. Princeton University Press. pp. 387–390. ISBN 0-691-12758-1.
  96. ^ Kun-Dga'-Bstan; Kunga Tenpay Nyima; Jared Rhoton (2003). The Three Levels of Spiritual Perception: A Commentary on the Three Visions. Simon and Schuster. p. 392. ISBN 978-0-86171-368-4. from the original on 2019-12-19. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  97. ^ Garab Dorje (1996). The Golden Letters: The Three Statements of Garab Dorje, the First Teacher of Dzogchen, Together with a Commentary by. Snow Lion Publications. p. 319. ISBN 978-1-55939-050-7. from the original on 2019-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  98. ^ Jeffrey Hopkins (2006). Absorption in No External World. Snow Lion Publications. pp. 400–405. ISBN 978-1-55939-946-3.
  99. ^ Khenchen Konchog Gyaltshen (2010). A Complete Guide to the Buddhist Path. Snow Lion Publications. pp. 259–261. ISBN 978-1-55939-790-2. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  100. ^ Karma-Ran-Byun-Kun-Khyab-Phrin-Las; Denis Tondrup (1997). Luminous Mind: The Way of the Buddha. Simon and Schuster. pp. 204–206. ISBN 978-0-86171-118-5. from the original on 2019-12-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  101. ^ Geshe Kelsang Gyatso (2000). Essence of Vajrayana: The Highest Yoga Tantra Practice of Heruka Body Mandala. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 140–143. ISBN 978-81-208-1729-6. from the original on 2018-12-25. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  102. ^ John A. Grimes (1996). A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy: Sanskrit Terms Defined in English. State University of New York Press. p. 199. ISBN 978-0-7914-3067-5. from the original on 2019-12-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  103. ^ A. K. Warder (2000). Indian Buddhism. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 473–474. ISBN 978-81-208-1741-8. from the original on 2017-02-28. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  104. ^ Asaṅga; Janice Dean Willis (2002). On Knowing Reality: The Tattvārtha Chapter of Asaṅga's Bodhisattvabhūmi. Motilal Banarsidass. p. 24. ISBN 978-81-208-1106-5. from the original on 2019-12-20. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  105. ^ Norman C. McClelland (2010). Encyclopedia of Reincarnation and Karma. McFarland. pp. 34–35. ISBN 978-0-7864-5675-8. from the original on 2016-11-26. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  106. ^ [a] Julius Lipner (2012). Hindus: Their Religious Beliefs and Practices. Routledge. pp. 53–56, 81, 160–161, 269–270. ISBN 978-1-135-24060-8. from the original on 2020-06-17. Retrieved 2021-08-17.;
    [b] P. T. Raju (1985). Structural Depths of Indian Thought. State University of New York Press. pp. 26–37. ISBN 978-0-88706-139-4.;
    [c] Gavin D. Flood (1996). An Introduction to Hinduism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 15, 84–85. ISBN 978-0-521-43878-0.
  107. ^ James Hart (2009), Who One Is: Book 2: Existenz and Transcendental Phenomenology, Springer, ISBN 978-1402091773, pages 2–3, 46–47
  108. ^ Richard White (2012), The Heart of Wisdom: A Philosophy of Spiritual Life, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, ISBN 978-1442221161, pages 125–131
  109. ^ Plott 2000, p. 60-62.
  110. ^ a b Jayatilleke 1963, p. 39.
  111. ^ Peter Harvey (2012). An Introduction to Buddhism: Teachings, History and Practices. Cambridge University Press. pp. 59–60. ISBN 978-0-521-85942-4. from the original on 2020-07-27. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  112. ^ Harvey 2013b, p. 34, 38.
  113. ^ Peter Harvey (2013). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. p. 34. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27., Quote: "The post-Buddhist Matri Upanishad holds that only defiled individual self, rather than the universal one, thinks 'this is I' or 'this is mine'. This is very reminiscent of Buddhism, and may well have been influenced by it to divorce the universal Self from such egocentric associations".
  114. ^ Paul Deussen (1980). Sixty Upanishads of the Veda. Motilal Banarsidass. p. 361. ISBN 978-81-208-1468-4.
  115. ^ a b Thomas E. Wood (1992). The Māṇḍūkya Upaniṣad and the Āgama Śāstra: An Investigation Into the Meaning of the Vedānta. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 67–68. ISBN 978-81-208-0930-7. from the original on 2019-12-20. Retrieved 2018-09-21.
  116. ^ Shinkan Murakami (1971). "Niratman and anatman". Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies (Indogaku Bukkyōgaku Kenkyū). 19 (2): 61–68.
  117. ^ Paul Deussen (1980). Sixty Upanishads of the Veda. Motilal Banarsidass. pp. 358–359 introductory note, 361 with footnote 1, 380. ISBN 978-81-208-1468-4.
  118. ^ Bett, Richard; Zalta, Edward (Winter 2014). "Pyrrho". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on March 18, 2019. Retrieved February 19, 2018.
  119. ^ Beckwith, Christopher I. (2015). Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia (PDF). Princeton University Press. pp. 22–59. ISBN 9781400866328. (PDF) from the original on 2016-11-30. Retrieved 2019-05-13.

Sources edit

  • Anderson, Carol (2013), Pain and Its Ending: The Four Noble Truths in the Theravada Buddhist Canon, Routledge
  • Buswell, Robert E. Jr.; Lopez, Donald Jr. (2003), The Princeton Dictionary of Buddhism, Princeton University Press
  • Carter, John Ross (1987), "Four Noble Truths", in Jones, Lindsay (ed.), MacMillan Encyclopedia of Religions, MacMillan
  • Dalal, Roshen (2010). The religions of India : a concise guide to nine major faiths (Rev. ed.). New Delhi: Penguin Books. ISBN 978-0-14-341517-6.
  • Dalai Lama (1997), Healing Anger: The Power of Patience from a Buddhist Perspective. Translated by Geshe Thupten Jinpa. Snow Lion Publications. Source: (accessed: Sunday March 25, 2007)
  • Deutsch, Eliot (1973), Advaita Vedanta: A Philosophical Reconstruction, University of Hawaii Press
  • Gombrich, Richard Francis (1988). Theravāda Buddhism: A Social History from Ancient Benares to Modern Colombo. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-07585-5. from the original on 2016-12-22. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  • Gombrich, Richard; Obeyesekere, Gananath (1988). Buddhism Transformed: Religious Change in Sri Lanka. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 978-81-208-0702-0. from the original on 2019-12-24. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  • Gombrich, Richard F. (1997). How Buddhism Began: The Conditioned Genesis of the Early Teachings. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-19639-5. from the original on 2020-05-19. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  • Gombrich, R. F. (1990). Recovering the Buddha's Message (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 2012-04-26. Retrieved 2011-12-10.
  • Gombrich, Richard Francis (2009). What the Buddha thought. Equinox Pub. ISBN 9781845536145.
  • Harvey, Graham (2016), Religions in Focus: New Approaches to Tradition and Contemporary Practices, Routledge
  • Harvey, Peter (2013). An Introduction to Buddhism. Cambridge University Press.

Harvey, Peter (2013b). The Selfless Mind: Personality, Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism. Routledge. pp. 34, 38. ISBN 978-1-136-78336-4. from the original on 2016-09-01. Retrieved 2016-09-27.

  • Jayatilleke, K.N. (1963), (1st ed.), London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd., archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-12-24, retrieved 2021-08-17
  • Keown, Damien (2000). Buddhism: A Very Short Introduction (Kindle ed.). Oxford University Press.
  • Lopez, Donald S (1995). Buddhism in Practice (PDF). Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-04442-2.
  • Lopez, Donald, jr. (2009), Buddhism and Science: A Guide for the Perplexed, University of Chicago Press{{citation}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  • Mackenzie, Matthew (2012). "Luminosity, Subjectivity, and Temporality: An Examination of Buddhist and Advaita views of Consciousness". In Kuznetsova, Irina; Ganeri, Jonardon; Ram-Prasad, Chakravarthi (eds.). Hindu and Buddhist Ideas in Dialogue: Self and No-Self. Routledge.
  • Mackenzie, Rory (2007), (PDF), Routledge, ISBN 978-1-134-13262-1, archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-10-22, retrieved 2016-11-09
  • Makransky, John J. (1997), Buddhahood Embodied: Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet, SUNY
  • McClelland, Norman C. (2010). Encyclopedia of reincarnation and karma. Jefferson, N.C.: McFarland. ISBN 978-0-7864-5675-8.
  • K. R. Norman (1981), A Note on Attā in the Alagaddūpama Sutta 2012-04-26 at the Wayback Machine. Studies in Indian Philosophy LD Series, 84 – 1981
  • Plott, John C. (2000), Global History of Philosophy: The Axial Age, Volume 1, Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-8120801585
  • Raju, P. T. (1985). Structural Depths of Indian Thought. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-88706-139-4.
  • Reat, N. Ross (1994). Buddhism: A History. Jain Publishing. ISBN 978-0-87573-002-8. from the original on 2019-12-21. Retrieved 2016-10-23.
  • Samuel, Geoffrey (2008), The Origins of Yoga and Tantra: Indic Religions to the Thirteenth Century, Cambridge University Press
  • Seeger, Martin (2009), "Phra Payutto and Debates 'On the Very Idea of the Pali Canon' in Thai Buddhism", Buddhist Studies Review, 26 (1): 1–31, doi:10.1558/bsrv.v26i1.1
  • Schmidt-Leukel, Perry (2006), Understanding Buddhism, Dunedin Academic Press, ISBN 978-1-903765-18-0, from the original on 2020-05-19, retrieved 2016-10-23
  • Spiro, Melford E. (1982), Buddhism and Society: A Great Tradition and Its Burmese Vicissitudes, University of California Press
  • Vetter, Tilmann (1988), The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism, BRILL
  • Williams, Paul (2002), Buddhist Thought (Kindle ed.), Taylor & Francis
  • Williams, Paul (2008), (PDF) (2 ed.), Routledge, ISBN 978-1-134-25056-1, archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-03-29, retrieved 2016-11-09
  • Wynne, Alexander (2009). "Early Evidence for the 'no self' doctrine?" (PDF). Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies: 59–63, 76–77. (PDF) from the original on 2017-06-02. Retrieved 2017-04-23.
  • Wynn, Alexander (2010). "The atman and its negation". Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies. 33 (1–2): 103–171. from the original on 2014-09-03. Retrieved 2014-08-30.

External links edit

anattā, this, article, about, concept, buddhism, concept, hinduism, anātman, hinduism, buddhism, term, anattā, pali, 𑀅𑀦𑀢, 𑀢, anātman, sanskrit, अन, मन, doctrine, self, that, unchanging, permanent, self, essence, found, phenomenon, note, while, often, interpret. This article is about the concept in Buddhism For the concept in Hinduism see Anatman Hinduism In Buddhism the term anatta Pali 𑀅𑀦𑀢 𑀢 or anatman Sanskrit अन त मन is the doctrine of non self that no unchanging permanent self or essence can be found in any phenomenon note 1 While often interpreted as a doctrine denying the existence of a self anatman is more accurately described as a strategy to attain non attachment by recognizing everything as impermanent while staying silent on the ultimate existence of an unchanging essence 1 2 3 In contrast dominant schools of Hinduism assert the existence of Atman as pure awareness or witness consciousness 4 5 6 note 2 reify ing consciousness as an eternal self 7 Translations ofAnattaEnglishNot self nonselfSanskritअन त मन IAST anatman Chinese無我 Pinyin wuwǒ Japanese無我 Rōmaji muga Korean무아 RR mua Tibetanབདག མ ད པ bdag med Vietnamesevo ngaGlossary of Buddhism Contents 1 Etymology and nomenclature 2 In early Buddhism 2 1 In early Buddhist texts 2 2 No denial of self 2 3 Developing the self 2 4 Karma rebirth and anatta 3 In Theravada Buddhism 3 1 Traditional views 3 2 Current disputes 4 Anatman in Mahayana Buddhism 4 1 Nagarjuna 4 2 Yogacara 4 3 Tathagatagarbha Sutras Buddha is True Self 4 4 Vajrayana 5 Difference between Buddhism and Hinduism 5 1 Atman in Hinduism 5 2 Anatman and Niratman 6 Correspondence in Pyrrhonism 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 10 Sources 11 External linksEtymology and nomenclature editAnatta is a composite Pali word consisting of an not and atta self existent essence 8 The term refers to the central Buddhist concept that there is no phenomenon that has self or essence 1 It is one of the three characteristics of all existence together with dukkha suffering dissatisfaction and anicca impermanence 8 Anatta is synonymous with Anatman an atman in Sanskrit Buddhist texts 9 In some Pali texts atman of Vedic texts is also referred to with the term Attan with the sense of soul 8 An alternate use of Attan or Atta is self oneself essence of a person driven by the Vedic era Brahmanical belief that atman is the permanent unchangeable essence of a living being or the true self 8 9 In Buddhism related English literature Anatta is rendered as not Self but this translation expresses an incomplete meaning states Peter Harvey a more complete rendering is non Self because from its earliest days Anatta doctrine denied that there is anything called a Self in any person or anything else and that a belief in Self is a source of Dukkha suffering pain unsatisfactoriness 10 11 note 3 Buddhist scholar Richard Gombrich however argues that anatta is often mistranslated as meaning not having a self or essence but actually means is not atman instead of does not have atman 1 It is also incorrect to translate Anatta simply as ego less according to Peter Harvey because the Indian concept of atman and atta is different from the Freudian concept of ego 15 note 4 In early Buddhism editIn early Buddhist texts edit The concept of Anatta appears in numerous Sutras of the ancient Buddhist Nikaya texts Pali canon It appears for example as a noun in Samyutta Nikaya III 141 IV 49 V 345 in Sutta II 37 of Anguttara Nikaya II 37 45 and II 80 of Patisambhidamagga III 406 of Dhammapada It also appears as an adjective for example in Samyutta Nikaya III 114 III 133 IV 28 and IV 130 166 in Sutta III 66 and V 86 of Vinaya 8 17 It is also found in the Dhammapada 18 The ancient Buddhist texts discuss Atta or Attan self sometimes with alternate terms such as Atuman Tuma Puggala Jiva Satta Pana and Nama rupa thereby providing the context for the Buddhist Anatta doctrine Examples of such Atta contextual discussions are found in Digha Nikaya I 186 187 Samyutta Nikaya III 179 and IV 54 Vinaya I 14 Majjhima Nikaya I 138 III 19 and III 265 271 and Anguttara Nikaya I 284 8 17 19 According to Steven Collins the inquiry of anatta and denial of self in the canonical Buddhist texts is insisted on only in certain theoretical contexts while they use the terms atta purisa puggala quite naturally and freely in various contexts 19 The elaboration of the anatta doctrine along with identification of the words such as puggala as permanent subject or soul appears in later Buddhist literature 19 According to Collins the Suttas present the doctrine in three forms First they apply the no self no identity investigation to all phenomena as well as any and all objects yielding the idea that all things are not self sabbe dhamma anatta 20 Second states Collins the Suttas apply the doctrine to deny self of any person treating conceit to be evident in any assertion of this is mine this I am this is myself etam mamam eso ham asmi eso me atta ti 21 Third the Theravada texts apply the doctrine as a nominal reference to identify examples of self and not self respectively the Wrong view and the Right view this third case of nominative usage is properly translated as self as an identity and is unrelated to soul states Collins 21 The first two usages incorporate the idea of soul 22 No denial of self edit Buddhist scholars Richard Gombrich and Alexander Wynne argue that the Buddha s descriptions of non self in early Buddhist texts do not deny that there is a self 1 2 Wynne and Gombrich both argue that the Buddha s statements on anatta were originally a not self teaching that developed into a no self teaching in later Buddhist thought 2 1 According to Wynne early Buddhist texts such as the Anattalakkhaṇa Sutta do not deny that there is a self stating that the five aggregates that are described as not self are not descriptions of a human being but descriptions of the human experience 2 According to Johannes Bronkhorst it is possible that original Buddhism did not deny the existence of the soul even though a firm Buddhist tradition has maintained that the Buddha avoided talking about the soul or even denied its existence 23 Tibetologist Andre Migot states that original Buddhism may not have taught a complete absence of self pointing to evidence presented by Buddhist and Pali scholars Jean Przyluski and Caroline Rhys Davids that early Buddhism generally believed in a self making Buddhist schools that admit an existence of a self not heretical but conservative adhering to ancient beliefs 24 While there may be ambivalence on the existence or non existence of self in early Buddhist literature Bronkhorst suggests that these texts clearly indicate that the Buddhist path of liberation consists not in seeking Atman like self knowledge but in turning away from what might erroneously be regarded as the self 25 This is a reverse position to the Vedic traditions which recognized the knowledge of the self as the principal means to achieving liberation 25 According to Harvey the contextual use of Atta in the Nikayas is two sided In one it directly denies that anything can be found called a self or soul in a human being that is a permanent essence of a human being a theme found in Brahmanical traditions 26 In another states Peter Harvey such as at Samyutta Nikaya IV 286 the Sutta considers the materialistic concept in the pre Buddhist Vedic period of no afterlife complete annihilation at death to be a denial of Self but still tied up with belief in a Self 27 Self exists is a false premise assert the early Buddhist texts 27 However adds Peter Harvey these texts do not admit the premise Self does not exist either because the wording presumes the concept of Self before denying it instead the early Buddhist texts use the concept of Anatta as the implicit premise 27 28 Developing the self edit Main articles Buddhist Paths to liberation and Personal identity Theories According to Peter Harvey while the Suttas criticize notions of an eternal unchanging Self as baseless they see an enlightened being as one whose empirical self is highly developed 29 This is paradoxical states Harvey in that the Self like nibbana state is a mature self that knows everything as Selfless 29 The empirical self is the citta mind heart mindset emotional nature and the development of self in the Suttas is the development of this citta 30 One with great self state the early Buddhist Suttas has a mind which is neither at the mercy of outside stimuli nor its own moods neither scattered nor diffused but imbued with self control and self contained towards the single goal of nibbana and a Self like state 29 This great self is not yet an Arahat because he still does small evil action which leads to karmic fruition but he has enough virtue that he does not experience this fruition in hell 29 An Arahat states Harvey has a fully enlightened state of empirical self one that lacks the sense of both I am and this I am which are illusions that the Arahat has transcended 31 The Buddhist thought and salvation theory emphasizes a development of self towards a Selfless state not only with respect to oneself but recognizing the lack of relational essence and Self in others wherein states Martijn van Zomeren self is an illusion 32 Karma rebirth and anatta edit The four stages of awakening according to the Sutta Piṭaka note 5 stage s fruit note 6 abandonedfetters rebirth s until suffering s end sotapanna 1 identity view Anatta 2 doubt in Buddha 3 ascetic or ritual rules lowerfetters up to seven rebirths inhuman or heavenly realms sakadagami note 7 once more as a human anagami 4 sensual desire 5 ill will once more ina heavenly realm Pure Abodes arahant 6 material rebirth desire 7 immaterial rebirth desire 8 conceit 9 restlessness 10 ignorance higherfetters no rebirth Source Naṇamoli amp Bodhi 2001 Middle Length Discourses pp 41 43 The Buddha emphasized both karma and anatta doctrines 3 The Buddha criticized the doctrine that posited an unchanging essence as a subject as the basis of rebirth and karmic moral responsibility which he called atthikavada He also criticized the materialistic doctrine that denied the existence of both soul and rebirth and thereby denied karmic moral responsibility which he calls natthikavada 33 Instead the Buddha asserted that there is no essence but there is rebirth for which karmic moral responsibility is a must In the Buddha s framework of karma right view and right actions are necessary for liberation 34 35 Hinduism Jainism and Buddhism all assert a belief in rebirth and emphasize moral responsibility in a way different from pre Buddhist materialistic schools of Indian philosophies 36 37 38 The materialistic schools of Indian philosophies such as Charvaka are called annihilationist schools because they posited that death is the end there is no afterlife no soul no rebirth no karma and death is that state where a living being is completely annihilated dissolved 39 Buddha criticized the materialistic annihilationism view that denied rebirth and karma states Damien Keown 36 Such beliefs are inappropriate and dangerous stated Buddha because they encourage moral irresponsibility and material hedonism 36 Anatta does not mean there is no afterlife no rebirth or no fruition of karma and Buddhism contrasts itself to annihilationist schools 36 Buddhism also contrasts itself to other Indian religions that champion moral responsibility but posit eternalism with their premise that within each human being there is an essence or eternal soul and this soul is part of the nature of a living being existence and metaphysical reality 40 41 42 In Theravada Buddhism editTraditional views edit Theravada Buddhism scholars states Oliver Leaman consider the Anatta doctrine as one of the main theses of Buddhism 43 The Buddhist denial of an unchanging permanent self is what distinguishes Buddhism from major religions of the world such as Christianity and Hinduism giving it uniqueness asserts the Theravada tradition 43 With the doctrine of Anatta stands or falls the entire Buddhist structure asserts Nyanatiloka Mahathera 44 According to Collins insight into the teaching of anatta is held to have two major loci in the intellectual and spiritual education of an individual as s he progresses along the Path 45 The first part of this insight is to avoid sakkayaditthi Personality Belief that is converting the sense of I which is gained from introspection and the fact of physical individuality into a theoretical belief in a self 45 A belief in a really existing body is considered a false belief and a part of the Ten Fetters that must be gradually lost The second loci is the psychological realization of anatta or loss of pride or conceit This states Collins is explained as the conceit of asmimana or I am what this conceit refers to is the fact that for the unenlightened man all experience and action must necessarily appear phenomenologically as happening to or originating from an I 45 When a Buddhist gets more enlightened this happening to or originating in an I or sakkdyaditthi is less The final attainment of enlightenment is the disappearance of this automatic but illusory I 45 The Theravada tradition has long considered the understanding and application of the Anatta doctrine to be a complex teaching whose personal introjected application has always been thought to be possible only for the specialist the practising monk The tradition states Collins has insisted fiercely on anatta as a doctrinal position while in practice it may not play much of a role in the daily religious life of most Buddhists 20 The Theravada doctrine of Anatta or not self not soul inspire meditative practices for monks states Donald Swearer but for the lay Theravada Buddhists in Southeast Asia the doctrines of kamma rebirth and punna merit inspire a wide range of ritual practices and ethical behavior 46 The Anatta doctrine is key to the concept of Nibbana in the Theravada tradition The liberated nirvana state states Collins is the state of Anatta a state that is neither universally applicable nor can be explained but can be realized 47 note 8 Current disputes edit See also Buddhism in Thailand The dispute about self and not self doctrines has continued throughout the history of Buddhism 50 In Thai Buddhism for example states Paul Williams some modern era Buddhist scholars have claimed that Nirvana is indeed the true self while other Thai Buddhists disagree 51 For instance the Dhammakaya tradition in Thailand teaches that it is erroneous to subsume nirvana under the rubric of anatta non self instead nirvana is taught to be the true self or dhammakaya 52 The Dhammakaya tradition teaching that nirvana is atta or true self was criticized as heretical in Buddhism in 1994 by Ven Payutto a well known scholar monk who stated that Buddha taught Nibbana as being non self 53 54 The abbot of one major temple in the Dhammakaya tradition Luang Por Sermchai of Wat Luang Por Sodh Dhammakayaram argues that it tends to be scholars who hold the view of absolute non self rather than Buddhist meditation practitioners He points to the experiences of prominent forest hermit monks such as Luang Pu Sodh and Ajahn Mun to support the notion of a true self 54 55 Similar interpretations on the true self were put forth earlier by the 12th Supreme Patriarch of Thailand in 1939 According to Williams the Supreme Patriarch s interpretation echoes the tathagatagarbha sutras 56 Several notable teachers of the Thai Forest Tradition have also described ideas in contrast to absolute non self Ajahn Maha Bua a well known meditation master described the citta mind as being an indestructible reality that does not fall under anatta 57 He has stated that not self is merely a perception that is used to pry one away from infatuation with the concept of a self and that once this infatuation is gone the idea of not self must be dropped as well 58 American monk Thanissaro Bhikkhu of the Thai Forest Tradition describes the Buddha s statements on non self as a path to awakening rather than a universal truth 3 Bhikkhu Bodhi authored a rejoinder to Thanissaro agreeing that anatta is a strategy for awakening but stating that The reason the teaching of anatta can serve as a strategy of liberation is precisely because it serves to rectify a misconception about the nature of being hence an ontological error 59 Thanissaro Bhikkhu states that the Buddha intentionally set aside the question of whether or not there is a self as a useless question and goes on to call the phrase there is no self the granddaddy of fake Buddhist quotes He adds that clinging to the idea that there is no self at all would actually prevent enlightenment 60 Thanissaro Bhikkhu points to the Ananda Sutta SN 44 10 where the Buddha stays silent when asked whether there is a self or not 61 as a major cause of the dispute 62 Anatman in Mahayana Buddhism editMain article Madhyamaka See also sunyata Anatman is one of the main bedrock doctrines of Buddhism and its discussion is found in the later texts of all Buddhist traditions 43 There are many different views of anatman Chinese 無我 pinyin wuwǒ Japanese 無我 muga Korean 무아 mu a within various Mahayana schools 63 The early Mahayana Buddhist texts link their discussion of emptiness sunyata to anatman and nirvana They do so states Mun Keat Choong in three ways first in the common sense of a monk s meditative state of emptiness second with the main sense of anatman or everything in the world is empty of self third with the ultimate sense of Nirvana or realization of emptiness and thus an end to rebirth cycles of suffering 64 The anatman doctrine is another aspect of sunyata its realization is the nature of the nirvana state and to an end to rebirths 65 66 67 Nagarjuna edit The Buddhist philosopher Nagarjuna 200 CE the founder of Madhyamaka middle way school of Mahayana Buddhism analyzed dharma first as factors of experience 13 David Kalupahana states that Nagarjuna analyzed how these experiences relate to bondage and freedom action and consequence and thereafter analyzed the notion of personal self atman 13 Nagarjuna extensively wrote about rejecting the metaphysical entity called atman self soul asserting in chapter 18 of his Mulamadhyamakakarika that there is no such substantial entity and that Buddha taught the doctrine of no self 68 69 70 Nagarjuna asserted that the notion of a self is associated with the notion of one s own identity and corollary ideas of pride selfishness and a sense of psychophysical personality 71 This is all false and leads to bondage in his Madhyamaka thought There can be no pride nor possessiveness in someone who accepts anatman and denies self which is the sense of personal identity of oneself others or anything states Nagarjuna 13 14 Further all obsessions are avoided when a person accepts emptiness sunyata 13 72 Nagarjuna denied there is anything called a self nature as well as other nature emphasizing true knowledge to be comprehending emptiness 71 73 74 Anyone who has not dissociated from their belief in personality in themselves or others through the concept of self is in a state of avidya ignorance and caught in the cycle of rebirths and redeaths 71 75 Yogacara edit The texts attributed to the 5th century Buddhist philosopher Vasubandhu of the Yogacara school similarly discuss anatman as a fundamental premise of the Buddha 76 The Vasubandhu interpretations of no self thesis were challenged by the 7th century Buddhist scholar Candrakirti who then offered his own theories on its importance 77 78 Tathagatagarbha Sutras Buddha is True Self edit Some 1st millennium CE Buddhist texts suggest concepts that have been controversial because they imply a self like concept 79 80 In particular are the tathagatagarbha sutras where the title itself means a garbha womb matrix seed containing Tathagata Buddha These Sutras suggest states Paul Williams that all sentient beings contain a Tathagata as their essence core or essential inner nature 81 The tathagatagarbha doctrine at its earliest probably appeared about the later part of the 3rd century CE and is verifiable in Chinese translations of 1st millennium CE 81 Most scholars consider the tathagatagarbha doctrine of an essential nature in every living being is equivalent to self citation needed note 9 and it contradicts the anatman doctrines in a vast majority of Buddhist texts leading scholars to posit that the tathagatagarbha sutras were written to promote Buddhism to non Buddhists 83 84 The Mahayana Mahaparinirvana Sutra explicitly asserts that the Buddha used the term self in order to win over non Buddhist ascetics 85 86 The Ratnagotravibhaga also known as Uttaratantra another text composed in the first half of 1st millennium CE and translated into Chinese in 511 CE points out that the teaching of the tathagatagarbha doctrine is intended to win sentient beings over to abandoning self love atma sneha considered to be one of the defects by Buddhism 87 88 The 6th century Chinese tathagatagarbha translation states that Buddha has shiwo true self which is beyond being and nonbeing 89 However the Ratnagotravibhaga asserts that the self implied in tathagatagarbha doctrine is actually not self 89 90 According to some scholars the Buddha nature discussed in these sutras does not represent a substantial self rather it is a positive language and expression of sunyata emptiness and represents the potentiality to realize Buddhahood through Buddhist practices 87 Other scholars do in fact detect leanings towards monism in these tathagatagarbha references 91 Michael Zimmermann sees the notion of an unperishing and eternal self in the Tathagatagarbha Sutra 92 Zimmermann also avers that the existence of an eternal imperishable self that is buddhahood is definitely the basic point of the Tathagatagarbha Sutra 93 He further indicates that there is no evident interest found in this sutra in the idea of Emptiness sunyata 94 Williams states that the self in tathagatagarbha sutras is actually non self and neither identical nor comparable to the Hindu concepts of brahman and self 87 Vajrayana edit nbsp Tibetan and Nepalese Buddhist deities Nairatmya and Hevajra in an embrace Nairatmya is the goddess of emptiness and of anatman realization 95 96 The anatman doctrine is extensively discussed in and partly inspires the ritual practices of the Vajrayana tradition The Tibetan terms such as bdag med refer to without a self insubstantial anatman 97 These discussions states Jeffrey Hopkins assert the non existence of a permanent unitary and independent self and attribute these ideas to the Buddha 98 The ritual practices in Vajrayana Buddhism employs the concept of deities to end self grasping and to manifest as a purified enlightened deity as part of the Vajrayana path to liberation from rebirths 99 100 101 One such deity is goddess Nairatmya literally non soul non self 102 103 104 She symbolizes states Miranda Shaw that self is an illusion and all beings and phenomenal appearances lack an abiding self or essence in Vajrayana Buddhism 95 Difference between Buddhism and Hinduism editAtman in Hinduism edit The Buddhist concept of anatta or anatman is one of the fundamental differences between mainstream Buddhism and mainstream Hinduism with the latter asserting that atman self exists note 2 In Hinduism Atman refers to the essence of human beings the observing pure awareness or witness consciousness 4 5 105 106 It is unaffected by ego 107 108 distinct from the individual being jivanatman embedded in material reality and characterized by Ahamkara I making mind citta manas and all the defiling kleshas impurities Embodied personality changes over time while Atman doesn t 109 According to Jayatilleke the Upanishadic inquiry fails to find an empirical correlate of the assumed Atman but nevertheless assumes its existence 110 and Advaitins reify consciousness as an eternal self 7 In contrast the Buddhist inquiry is satisfied with the empirical investigation which shows that no such Atman exists because there is no evidence states Jayatilleke 110 According to Harvey in Buddhism the negation of temporal existents is applied even more rigorous than in the Upanishads While the Upanishads recognized many things as being not Self they felt that a real true Self could be found They held that when it was found and known to be identical to Brahman the basis of everything this would bring liberation In the Buddhist Suttas though literally everything is seen is non Self even Nirvana When this is known then liberation Nirvana is attained by total non attachment Thus both the Upanishads and the Buddhist Suttas see many things as not Self but the Suttas apply it indeed non Self to everything 111 Both Buddhism and Hinduism distinguish ego related I am this is mine from their respective abstract doctrines of Anatta and Atman 112 This states Peter Harvey may have been an influence of Buddhism on Hinduism 113 Anatman and Niratman edit The term niratman appears in the Maitrayaniya Upanishad of Hinduism such as in verses 6 20 6 21 and 7 4 Niratman literally means selfless 114 115 The niratman concept has been interpreted to be analogous to anatman of Buddhism 116 The ontological teachings however are different In the Upanishad states Thomas Wood numerous positive and negative descriptions of various states such as niratman and sarvasyatman the self of all are used in Maitrayaniya Upanishad to explain the nondual concept of the highest Self 115 According to Ramatirtha states Paul Deussen the niratman state discussion is referring to stopping the recognition of oneself as an individual soul and reaching the awareness of universal soul or the metaphysical Brahman 117 Correspondence in Pyrrhonism editMain article Similarities between Pyrrhonism and Buddhism The Greek philosopher Pyrrho traveled to India as part of Alexander the Great s entourage where he was influenced by the Indian gymnosophists 118 which inspired him to create the philosophy of Pyrrhonism Philologist Christopher Beckwith argues that Pyrrho based his philosophy on his translation of the three marks of existence into Greek and that adiaphora not logically differentiable not clearly definable negating Aristotle s use of diaphora reflects Pyrrho s understanding of the Buddhist concept of anatta 119 See also editAhamkara Anicca Asceticism Atman Buddhism Atman Hinduism Buddhist logico epistemology Catuṣkoṭi Dukkha Ego death Enlightenment religious Jiva Nirvana Non essentialism Mahaparinibbaṇa Sutta Mahaparinirvana Sutra Open individualism Philosophy of self Ship of Theseus a related view in ancient Greek philosophy Skandhas Tathagatagarbha Teletransportation paradox Vertiginous questionNotes edit Definition Anatta Archived 2015 12 10 at the Wayback Machine Encyclopaedia Britannica 2013 Anatta Pali non self or substanceless Sanskrit anatman in Buddhism the doctrine that there is in humans no permanent underlying substance that can be called the soul Instead the individual is compounded of five factors Pali khandha Sanskrit skandha that are constantly changing Christmas Humphreys 2012 Exploring Buddhism Routledge pp 42 43 ISBN 978 1 136 22877 3 Brian Morris 2006 Religion and Anthropology A Critical Introduction Cambridge University Press p 51 ISBN 978 0 521 85241 8 anatta is the doctrine of non self and is an extreme empiricist doctrine that holds that the notion of an unchanging permanent self is a fiction and has no reality According to Buddhist doctrine the individual person consists of five skandhas or heaps the body feelings perceptions impulses and consciousness The belief in a self or soul over these five skandhas is illusory and the cause of suffering Richard Gombrich 2006 Theravada Buddhism Routledge p 47 ISBN 978 1 134 90352 8 Buddha s teaching that beings have no soul no abiding essence This no soul doctrine anatta vada he expounded in his second sermon a b Atman in Hinduism Anatta Archived 2015 12 10 at the Wayback Machine Encyclopaedia Britannica 2013 The concept of anatta or anatman is a departure from the Hindu belief in atman the self Steven Collins 1994 Religion and Practical Reason Editors Frank Reynolds David Tracy State Univ of New York Press ISBN 978 0 7914 2217 5 page 64 Central to Buddhist soteriology is the doctrine of not self Pali anatta Sanskrit anatman the opposed doctrine of atman is central to Brahmanical thought Put very briefly this is the Buddhist doctrine that human beings have no soul no self no unchanging essence Edward Roer Translator Shankara s Introduction p 2 at Google Books to Brihad Aranyaka Upanishad pages 2 4 Katie Javanaud 2013 Is The Buddhist No Self Doctrine Compatible With Pursuing Nirvana Archived 2015 02 06 at the Wayback Machine Philosophy Now David Loy 1982 Enlightenment in Buddhism and Advaita Vedanta Are Nirvana and Moksha the Same International Philosophical Quarterly Volume 23 Issue 1 pages 65 74 KN Jayatilleke 2010 Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge ISBN 978 8120806191 pages 246 249 from note 385 onwards Plott 2000 Buddha did not deny a being or a thing referring it to be a collection of impermanent interdependent aggregates but denied that there is a metaphysical self soul or identity in anything 12 13 14 The term ahamkara is ego in Indian philosophies 16 See for instance the Snake Simile Discourse MN 22 where the Buddha states Monks this Teaching so well proclaimed by me is plain open explicit free of patchwork In this Teaching that is so well proclaimed by me and is plain open explicit and free of patchwork for those who are arahants free of taints who have accomplished and completed their task have laid down the burden achieved their aim severed the fetters binding to existence who are liberated by full knowledge there is no future round of existence that can be ascribed to them Majjhima Nikaya i 130 42 Translated by Nyanaponika Thera Nyanaponika 2006 The fruit Pali phala is the culmination of the path magga Thus for example the stream enterer is the fruit for one on the stream entry path more specifically the stream enterer has abandoned the first three fetters while one on the path of stream entry strives to abandon these fetters Both the stream enterer and the once returner abandon the first three fetters What distinguishes these stages is that the once returner additionally attenuates lust hate and delusion and will necessarily be reborn only once more This is a major difference between the Theravada Buddhists and different Hindu traditions which assert that nirvana is realizing and being in the state of self soul atman and is universally applicable However both concur that this state is indescribable cannot be explained but can be realized 48 49 Wayman and Wayman have disagreed with this view and they state that the tathagatagarbha is neither self nor sentient being nor soul nor personality 82 References edit a b c d e Gombrich 2009 p 69 70 a b c d Wynne 2009 p 59 63 76 77 a b c Selves amp Not self The Buddhist Teaching on Anatta by Thanissaro Bhikkhu Access to Insight Legacy Edition 30 November 2013 http www accesstoinsight org lib authors thanissaro selvesnotself html Archived 2013 02 04 at the Wayback Machine a b Deutsch 1973 p 48 a b Dalal 2010 p 38 McClelland 2010 p 34 35 a b Mackenzie 2012 a b c d e f Thomas William Rhys Davids William Stede 1921 Pali English Dictionary Motilal Banarsidass p 22 ISBN 978 81 208 1144 7 Archived from the original on 2016 12 07 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Johannes Bronkhorst 2009 Buddhist Teaching in India Simon and Schuster pp 124 125 with footnotes ISBN 978 0 86171 566 4 Archived from the original on 2016 12 07 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Peter Harvey 2012 An Introduction to Buddhism Teachings History and Practices Cambridge University Press pp 57 62 ISBN 978 0 521 85942 4 Archived from the original on 2020 07 27 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Peter Harvey 2015 Steven M Emmanuel ed A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons pp 34 37 ISBN 978 1 119 14466 3 Archived from the original on 2017 03 23 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Peter Harvey 2015 Steven M Emmanuel ed A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons p 36 ISBN 978 1 119 14466 3 Archived from the original on 2017 03 23 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c d e Nagarjuna 1996 Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna Translated by David J Kalupahana Motilal Banarsidass p 56 ISBN 978 81 208 0774 7 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b David Loy 2009 Awareness Bound and Unbound Buddhist Essays State University of New York Press pp 105 106 ISBN 978 1 4384 2680 8 Archived from the original on 2019 12 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Quote Nagarjuna the second century Indian Buddhist philosopher used sunyata not to characterize the true nature of reality but to deny that anything has any self existence or reality of its own Peter Harvey 2012 An Introduction to Buddhism Teachings History and Practices Cambridge University Press p 62 ISBN 978 0 521 85942 4 Archived from the original on 2020 07 27 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Again anatta does not mean egoless as it is sometimes rendered The term ego has a range of meanings in English The Freudian ego is not the same as the Indian atman atta or permanent Self Surendranath Dasgupta 1992 A History of Indian Philosophy Motilal Banarsidass Republisher Originally published by Cambridge University Press p 250 ISBN 978 81 208 0412 8 Archived from the original on 2019 06 02 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Johannes Bronkhorst 2009 Buddhist Teaching in India Simon and Schuster pp 124 125 with footnotes ISBN 978 0 86171 566 4 Archived from the original on 2016 12 07 Retrieved 2016 10 23 John Carter Mahinda Palihawadana 2008 Dhammapada Oxford University Press pp 30 31 74 80 ISBN 978 0 19 955513 0 Archived from the original on 2019 12 23 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 71 81 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2019 05 01 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 94 96 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2019 05 01 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 96 97 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 3 5 35 36 109 116 163 193 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Johannes Bronkhorst 1993 The Two Traditions of Meditation in Ancient India Motilal Banarsidass pp 99 with footnote 12 ISBN 978 81 208 1114 0 Archived from the original on 2018 11 20 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Migot Andre 1954 XV Un grand disciple du Buddha Sariputra Son role dans l histoire du bouddhisme et dans le developpement de l Abhidharma Bulletin de l Ecole francaise d Extreme Orient 46 2 492 doi 10 3406 befeo 1954 5607 Archived from the original on 2020 04 20 Retrieved 2020 03 07 a b Johannes Bronkhorst 2009 Buddhist Teaching in India Wisdom Publications p 25 ISBN 978 0 86171 811 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Peter Harvey 2013 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 1 2 34 40 224 225 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 a b c Peter Harvey 2013 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 39 40 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Johannes Bronkhorst 2009 Buddhist Teaching in India Wisdom Publications pp 23 25 ISBN 978 0 86171 811 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c d Peter Harvey 1995 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 54 56 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Peter Harvey 1995 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 111 112 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Peter Harvey 1995 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 31 32 44 50 51 71 210 216 246 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Martijn van Zomeren 2016 From Self to Social Relationships An Essentially Relational Perspective on Social Motivation Cambridge University Press p 156 ISBN 978 1 107 09379 9 Archived from the original on 2019 12 21 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Quote Buddhism is an example of a non theistic religion which underlies a cultural matrix in which individuals believe that the self is an illusion Indeed its anatta doctrine states that the self is not an essence David Kalupahana Causality The Central Philosophy of Buddhism The University Press of Hawaii 1975 page 44 Malcolm B Hamilton 12 June 2012 The Sociology of Religion Theoretical and Comparative Perspectives Routledge pp 73 80 ISBN 978 1 134 97626 3 Archived from the original on 22 December 2016 Retrieved 23 October 2016 Raju P T 1985 Structural Depths of Indian Thought State University of New York Press pp 147 151 ISBN 978 0 88706 139 4 a b c d Damien Keown 2004 Ucchedavada sasvata vada rebirth in A Dictionary of Buddhism Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 860560 7 Robert E Buswell Jr Donald S Lopez Jr 2013 The Princeton Dictionary of Buddhism Princeton University Press pp 708 709 ISBN 978 1 4008 4805 8 Archived from the original on 2020 05 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Peter Harvey 2012 An Introduction to Buddhism Teachings History and Practices Cambridge University Press pp 32 33 38 39 46 49 ISBN 978 0 521 85942 4 Archived from the original on 2020 07 27 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Ray Billington 2002 Understanding Eastern Philosophy Routledge pp 43 44 58 60 ISBN 978 1 134 79349 5 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Norman C McClelland 2010 Encyclopedia of Reincarnation and Karma McFarland p 89 ISBN 978 0 7864 5675 8 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Hugh Nicholson 2016 The Spirit of Contradiction in Christianity and Buddhism Oxford University Press pp 23 25 ISBN 978 0 19 045534 7 Archived from the original on 2017 01 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Gananath Obeyesekere 2006 Karma and Rebirth A Cross Cultural Study Motilal Banarsidass pp 281 282 ISBN 978 81 208 2609 0 Archived from the original on 2017 01 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c Oliver Leaman 2002 Eastern Philosophy Key Readings Routledge pp 23 27 ISBN 978 1 134 68919 4 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press p 5 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c d Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 93 94 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2019 05 01 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Donald K Swearer 2012 Buddhist World of Southeast Asia The Second Edition State University of New York Press pp 2 3 ISBN 978 1 4384 3252 6 Archived from the original on 2019 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 82 84 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Steven Collins 1990 Selfless Persons Imagery and Thought in Theravada Buddhism Cambridge University Press pp 81 82 ISBN 978 0 521 39726 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Loy David 1982 Enlightenment in Buddhism and Advaita Vedanta International Philosophical Quarterly 22 1 Philosophy Documentation Center 65 74 doi 10 5840 ipq19822217 Potprecha Cholvijarn Nibbana as True Reality beyond the Debate Wat Luang Phor Sodh p 45 ISBN 978 974 350 263 7 Archived from the original on 2019 05 02 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Williams 2008 pp 125 7 Mackenzie 2007 pp 100 5 110 Mackenzie 2007 p 51 a b Williams 2008 p 127 128 Seeger 2009 pp 13 footnote 40 Williams 2008 p 126 pp 101 103 Maha Boowa Arahattamagga Arahattaphala the Path to Arahantship A Compilation of Venerable Acariya Maha Boowa s Dhamma Talks about His Path of Practice translated by Bhikkhu Silaratano 2005 http www forestdhammabooks com book 3 Arahattamagga pdf Archived 2009 03 27 at the Wayback Machine consulted 16 March 2009 Archived at Ghostarchive and the Wayback Machine UWE STOES 2015 04 22 Thanassaro Bhikkhu retrieved 2017 09 30 Bodhi Bhikkhu January 2017 Anatta as Strategy and Ontonology Investigating the Dhamma Buddhist Publication Society p 25 ISBN 978 1 68172 068 5 Bhikkhu Thanissaro There is no self Tricycle The Buddhist Review Archived from the original on 2018 08 19 Retrieved 2018 08 19 Ananda Sutta To Ananda www accesstoinsight org Archived from the original on 2017 05 10 Retrieved 2017 05 14 Introduction to the Avyakata Samyutta Undeclared connected www accesstoinsight org Archived from the original on 2017 05 08 Retrieved 2017 05 14 King R Early Advaita Vedanta and Buddhism The Mahayana Context of the Gaudapadiya Karika Albany SUNY Press 1995 p 97 Archived 2016 11 01 at the Wayback Machine Mun Keat Choong 1999 The Notion of Emptiness in Early Buddhism Motilal Banarsidass pp 1 4 85 88 ISBN 978 81 208 1649 7 Archived from the original on 2016 11 27 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Ray Billington 2002 Understanding Eastern Philosophy Routledge pp 58 60 ISBN 978 1 134 79348 8 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 David Loy 2009 Awareness Bound and Unbound Buddhist Essays State University of New York Press pp 35 39 ISBN 978 1 4384 2680 8 Archived from the original on 2019 12 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Stephan Schuhmacher 1994 The Encyclopedia of Eastern Philosophy and Religion Buddhism Hinduism Taoism Zen Shambhala p 12 ISBN 978 0 87773 980 7 Archived from the original on 2019 12 18 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Nagarjuna 1996 Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna Translated by David J Kalupahana Motilal Banarsidass pp 56 57 ISBN 978 81 208 0774 7 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Brad Warner 2011 Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Translated by GW Nishijima Monkfish pp 182 191 ISBN 978 0 9833589 0 9 Archived from the original on 2019 12 19 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Nagarjuna 1995 Chapters XVIII XXVII see Part One and Two The Fundamental Wisdom of the Middle Way Nagarjuna s Mulamadhyamakakarika Translated by Jay Garfield Oxford University Press pp xxxiv 76 ISBN 978 0 19 976632 1 Archived from the original on 2019 12 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c Nagarjuna 1996 Mulamadhyamakakarika of Nagarjuna Translated by David J Kalupahana Motilal Banarsidass pp 56 59 ISBN 978 81 208 0774 7 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 David Loy 2009 Awareness Bound and Unbound Buddhist Essays State University of New York Press pp 36 38 ISBN 978 1 4384 2680 8 Archived from the original on 2019 12 17 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Diane Morgan 2004 The Buddhist Experience in America Greenwood p 46 ISBN 978 0 313 32491 8 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 David F Burton 2015 Emptiness Appraised A Critical Study of Nagarjuna s Philosophy Routledge pp 31 32 48 with footnote 38 ISBN 978 1 317 72322 6 Archived from the original on 2019 12 18 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Ian Harris 1991 The Continuity of Madhyamaka and Yogacara in Indian Mahayana Buddhism BRILL Academic pp 146 147 ISBN 90 04 09448 2 Archived from the original on 2017 02 24 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Steven M Emmanuel 2015 A Companion to Buddhist Philosophy John Wiley amp Sons pp 419 428 ISBN 978 1 119 14466 3 Archived from the original on 2017 03 23 Retrieved 2016 10 23 James Duerlinger 2013 The Refutation of the Self in Indian Buddhism Candrakirti on the Selflessness of Persons Routledge pp 52 54 ISBN 978 0 415 65749 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Ronald W Neufeldt 31 May 1986 Karma and Rebirth Post Classical Developments State University of New York Press pp 216 220 ISBN 978 1 4384 1445 4 Archived from the original on 2019 12 25 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge pp 125 127 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 S K Hookham 1991 The Buddha Within Tathagatagarbha Doctrine According to the Shentong Interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga State University of New York Press pp 100 104 ISBN 978 0 7914 0357 0 Archived from the original on 2016 11 20 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge p 104 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge p 107 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge pp 104 105 108 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Merv Fowler 1999 Buddhism Beliefs and Practices Sussex Academic Press pp 101 102 ISBN 978 1 898723 66 0 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Quote Some texts of the tathagatagarbha literature such as the Mahaparinirvana Sutra actually refer to an atman though other texts are careful to avoid the term This would be in direct opposition to the general teachings of Buddhism on anatman Indeed the distinctions between the general Indian concept of atman and the popular Buddhist concept of Buddha nature are often blurred to the point that writers consider them to be synonymous Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge p 109 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Quote it refers to the Buddha using the term self in order to win over non Buddhist ascetics John W Pettit 1999 Mipham s Beacon of Certainty Illuminating the View of Dzogchen the Great Perfection Simon and Schuster pp 48 49 ISBN 978 0 86171 157 4 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b c Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge pp 109 112 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Christopher Bartley 2015 An Introduction to Indian Philosophy Hindu and Buddhist Ideas from Original Sources Bloomsbury Academic p 105 ISBN 978 1 4725 2437 9 Archived from the original on 2019 05 02 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a b Paul Williams 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations Routledge p 112 ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 Archived from the original on 2016 11 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 S K Hookham 1991 The Buddha Within Tathagatagarbha Doctrine According to the Shentong Interpretation of the Ratnagotravibhaga State University of New York Press p 96 ISBN 978 0 7914 0357 0 Archived from the original on 2016 11 20 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Jamie Hubbard Absolute Delusion Perfect Buddhahood University of Hawai i Press Honolulu 2001 pp 99 100 Zimmermann Michael 2002 A Buddha Within The Tathagatagarbhasutra Biblotheca Philologica et Philosophica Buddhica VI The International Research Institute for Advanced Buddhology Soka University p 64 Michael Zimmermann A Buddha Within p 64 Zimmermann A Buddha Within p 81 a b Miranda Eberle Shaw 2006 Buddhist Goddesses of India Princeton University Press pp 387 390 ISBN 0 691 12758 1 Kun Dga Bstan Kunga Tenpay Nyima Jared Rhoton 2003 The Three Levels of Spiritual Perception A Commentary on the Three Visions Simon and Schuster p 392 ISBN 978 0 86171 368 4 Archived from the original on 2019 12 19 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Garab Dorje 1996 The Golden Letters The Three Statements of Garab Dorje the First Teacher of Dzogchen Together with a Commentary by Snow Lion Publications p 319 ISBN 978 1 55939 050 7 Archived from the original on 2019 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Jeffrey Hopkins 2006 Absorption in No External World Snow Lion Publications pp 400 405 ISBN 978 1 55939 946 3 Khenchen Konchog Gyaltshen 2010 A Complete Guide to the Buddhist Path Snow Lion Publications pp 259 261 ISBN 978 1 55939 790 2 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Karma Ran Byun Kun Khyab Phrin Las Denis Tondrup 1997 Luminous Mind The Way of the Buddha Simon and Schuster pp 204 206 ISBN 978 0 86171 118 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Geshe Kelsang Gyatso 2000 Essence of Vajrayana The Highest Yoga Tantra Practice of Heruka Body Mandala Motilal Banarsidass pp 140 143 ISBN 978 81 208 1729 6 Archived from the original on 2018 12 25 Retrieved 2016 10 23 John A Grimes 1996 A Concise Dictionary of Indian Philosophy Sanskrit Terms Defined in English State University of New York Press p 199 ISBN 978 0 7914 3067 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 A K Warder 2000 Indian Buddhism Motilal Banarsidass pp 473 474 ISBN 978 81 208 1741 8 Archived from the original on 2017 02 28 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Asaṅga Janice Dean Willis 2002 On Knowing Reality The Tattvartha Chapter of Asaṅga s Bodhisattvabhumi Motilal Banarsidass p 24 ISBN 978 81 208 1106 5 Archived from the original on 2019 12 20 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Norman C McClelland 2010 Encyclopedia of Reincarnation and Karma McFarland pp 34 35 ISBN 978 0 7864 5675 8 Archived from the original on 2016 11 26 Retrieved 2016 10 23 a Julius Lipner 2012 Hindus Their Religious Beliefs and Practices Routledge pp 53 56 81 160 161 269 270 ISBN 978 1 135 24060 8 Archived from the original on 2020 06 17 Retrieved 2021 08 17 b P T Raju 1985 Structural Depths of Indian Thought State University of New York Press pp 26 37 ISBN 978 0 88706 139 4 c Gavin D Flood 1996 An Introduction to Hinduism Cambridge University Press pp 15 84 85 ISBN 978 0 521 43878 0 James Hart 2009 Who One Is Book 2 Existenz and Transcendental Phenomenology Springer ISBN 978 1402091773 pages 2 3 46 47 Richard White 2012 The Heart of Wisdom A Philosophy of Spiritual Life Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers ISBN 978 1442221161 pages 125 131 Plott 2000 p 60 62 a b Jayatilleke 1963 p 39 Peter Harvey 2012 An Introduction to Buddhism Teachings History and Practices Cambridge University Press pp 59 60 ISBN 978 0 521 85942 4 Archived from the original on 2020 07 27 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Harvey 2013b p 34 38 Peter Harvey 2013 The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge p 34 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Quote The post Buddhist Matri Upanishad holds that only defiled individual self rather than the universal one thinks this is I or this is mine This is very reminiscent of Buddhism and may well have been influenced by it to divorce the universal Self from such egocentric associations Paul Deussen 1980 Sixty Upanishads of the Veda Motilal Banarsidass p 361 ISBN 978 81 208 1468 4 a b Thomas E Wood 1992 The Maṇḍukya Upaniṣad and the Agama Sastra An Investigation Into the Meaning of the Vedanta Motilal Banarsidass pp 67 68 ISBN 978 81 208 0930 7 Archived from the original on 2019 12 20 Retrieved 2018 09 21 Shinkan Murakami 1971 Niratman and anatman Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies Indogaku Bukkyōgaku Kenkyu 19 2 61 68 Paul Deussen 1980 Sixty Upanishads of the Veda Motilal Banarsidass pp 358 359 introductory note 361 with footnote 1 380 ISBN 978 81 208 1468 4 Bett Richard Zalta Edward Winter 2014 Pyrrho The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on March 18 2019 Retrieved February 19 2018 Beckwith Christopher I 2015 Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia PDF Princeton University Press pp 22 59 ISBN 9781400866328 Archived PDF from the original on 2016 11 30 Retrieved 2019 05 13 Sources editAnderson Carol 2013 Pain and Its Ending The Four Noble Truths in the Theravada Buddhist Canon Routledge Buswell Robert E Jr Lopez Donald Jr 2003 The Princeton Dictionary of Buddhism Princeton University Press Carter John Ross 1987 Four Noble Truths in Jones Lindsay ed MacMillan Encyclopedia of Religions MacMillan Dalal Roshen 2010 The religions of India a concise guide to nine major faiths Rev ed New Delhi Penguin Books ISBN 978 0 14 341517 6 Dalai Lama 1997 Healing Anger The Power of Patience from a Buddhist Perspective Translated by Geshe Thupten Jinpa Snow Lion Publications Source 1 accessed Sunday March 25 2007 Deutsch Eliot 1973 Advaita Vedanta A Philosophical Reconstruction University of Hawaii Press Gombrich Richard Francis 1988 Theravada Buddhism A Social History from Ancient Benares to Modern Colombo Routledge ISBN 978 0 415 07585 5 Archived from the original on 2016 12 22 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Gombrich Richard Obeyesekere Gananath 1988 Buddhism Transformed Religious Change in Sri Lanka Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 978 81 208 0702 0 Archived from the original on 2019 12 24 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Gombrich Richard F 1997 How Buddhism Began The Conditioned Genesis of the Early Teachings Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 19639 5 Archived from the original on 2020 05 19 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Gombrich R F 1990 Recovering the Buddha s Message PDF Archived PDF from the original on 2012 04 26 Retrieved 2011 12 10 Gombrich Richard Francis 2009 What the Buddha thought Equinox Pub ISBN 9781845536145 Harvey Graham 2016 Religions in Focus New Approaches to Tradition and Contemporary Practices Routledge Harvey Peter 2013 An Introduction to Buddhism Cambridge University Press Harvey Peter 2013b The Selfless Mind Personality Consciousness and Nirvana in Early Buddhism Routledge pp 34 38 ISBN 978 1 136 78336 4 Archived from the original on 2016 09 01 Retrieved 2016 09 27 Jayatilleke K N 1963 Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge 1st ed London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd archived from the original PDF on 2018 12 24 retrieved 2021 08 17 Keown Damien 2000 Buddhism A Very Short Introduction Kindle ed Oxford University Press Lopez Donald S 1995 Buddhism in Practice PDF Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 04442 2 Lopez Donald jr 2009 Buddhism and Science A Guide for the Perplexed University of Chicago Press a href Template Citation html title Template Citation citation a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Mackenzie Matthew 2012 Luminosity Subjectivity and Temporality An Examination of Buddhist and Advaita views of Consciousness In Kuznetsova Irina Ganeri Jonardon Ram Prasad Chakravarthi eds Hindu and Buddhist Ideas in Dialogue Self and No Self Routledge Mackenzie Rory 2007 New Buddhist Movements in Thailand Towards an Understanding of Wat Phra Dhammakaya and Santi Asoke PDF Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 13262 1 archived from the original PDF on 2020 10 22 retrieved 2016 11 09 Makransky John J 1997 Buddhahood Embodied Sources of Controversy in India and Tibet SUNY McClelland Norman C 2010 Encyclopedia of reincarnation and karma Jefferson N C McFarland ISBN 978 0 7864 5675 8 K R Norman 1981 A Note on Atta in the Alagaddupama Sutta Archived 2012 04 26 at the Wayback Machine Studies in Indian Philosophy LD Series 84 1981 Plott John C 2000 Global History of Philosophy The Axial Age Volume 1 Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 978 8120801585 Raju P T 1985 Structural Depths of Indian Thought State University of New York Press ISBN 978 0 88706 139 4 Reat N Ross 1994 Buddhism A History Jain Publishing ISBN 978 0 87573 002 8 Archived from the original on 2019 12 21 Retrieved 2016 10 23 Samuel Geoffrey 2008 The Origins of Yoga and Tantra Indic Religions to the Thirteenth Century Cambridge University Press Seeger Martin 2009 Phra Payutto and Debates On the Very Idea of the Pali Canon in Thai Buddhism Buddhist Studies Review 26 1 1 31 doi 10 1558 bsrv v26i1 1 Schmidt Leukel Perry 2006 Understanding Buddhism Dunedin Academic Press ISBN 978 1 903765 18 0 archived from the original on 2020 05 19 retrieved 2016 10 23 Spiro Melford E 1982 Buddhism and Society A Great Tradition and Its Burmese Vicissitudes University of California Press Vetter Tilmann 1988 The Ideas and Meditative Practices of Early Buddhism BRILL Williams Paul 2002 Buddhist Thought Kindle ed Taylor amp Francis Williams Paul 2008 Mahayana Buddhism The Doctrinal Foundations PDF 2 ed Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 25056 1 archived from the original PDF on 2017 03 29 retrieved 2016 11 09 Wynne Alexander 2009 Early Evidence for the no self doctrine PDF Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies 59 63 76 77 Archived PDF from the original on 2017 06 02 Retrieved 2017 04 23 Wynn Alexander 2010 The atman and its negation Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 33 1 2 103 171 Archived from the original on 2014 09 03 Retrieved 2014 08 30 External links editNirvana Sutra Kosho Yamamoto s English translation of the Mahayana Mahaparinirvaṇa Sutra Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Anatta amp oldid 1223241402, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.