fbpx
Wikipedia

Isomorphism

In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between them. The word isomorphism is derived from the Ancient Greek: ἴσος isos "equal", and μορφή morphe "form" or "shape".

The group of fifth roots of unity under multiplication is isomorphic to the group of rotations of the regular pentagon under composition.

The interest in isomorphisms lies in the fact that two isomorphic objects have the same properties (excluding further information such as additional structure or names of objects). Thus isomorphic structures cannot be distinguished from the point of view of structure only, and may be identified. In mathematical jargon, one says that two objects are the same up to an isomorphism.[citation needed]

An automorphism is an isomorphism from a structure to itself. An isomorphism between two structures is a canonical isomorphism (a canonical map that is an isomorphism) if there is only one isomorphism between the two structures (as is the case for solutions of a universal property), or if the isomorphism is much more natural (in some sense) than other isomorphisms. For example, for every prime number p, all fields with p elements are canonically isomorphic, with a unique isomorphism. The isomorphism theorems provide canonical isomorphisms that are not unique.

The term isomorphism is mainly used for algebraic structures. In this case, mappings are called homomorphisms, and a homomorphism is an isomorphism if and only if it is bijective.

In various areas of mathematics, isomorphisms have received specialized names, depending on the type of structure under consideration. For example:

Category theory, which can be viewed as a formalization of the concept of mapping between structures, provides a language that may be used to unify the approach to these different aspects of the basic idea.

Examples edit

Logarithm and exponential edit

Let   be the multiplicative group of positive real numbers, and let   be the additive group of real numbers.

The logarithm function   satisfies   for all   so it is a group homomorphism. The exponential function   satisfies   for all   so it too is a homomorphism.

The identities   and   show that   and   are inverses of each other. Since   is a homomorphism that has an inverse that is also a homomorphism,   is an isomorphism of groups.

The   function is an isomorphism which translates multiplication of positive real numbers into addition of real numbers. This facility makes it possible to multiply real numbers using a ruler and a table of logarithms, or using a slide rule with a logarithmic scale.

Integers modulo 6 edit

Consider the group   the integers from 0 to 5 with addition modulo 6. Also consider the group   the ordered pairs where the x coordinates can be 0 or 1, and the y coordinates can be 0, 1, or 2, where addition in the x-coordinate is modulo 2 and addition in the y-coordinate is modulo 3.

These structures are isomorphic under addition, under the following scheme:

 
or in general  

For example,   which translates in the other system as  

Even though these two groups "look" different in that the sets contain different elements, they are indeed isomorphic: their structures are exactly the same. More generally, the direct product of two cyclic groups   and   is isomorphic to   if and only if m and n are coprime, per the Chinese remainder theorem.

Relation-preserving isomorphism edit

If one object consists of a set X with a binary relation R and the other object consists of a set Y with a binary relation S then an isomorphism from X to Y is a bijective function   such that:[1]

 

S is reflexive, irreflexive, symmetric, antisymmetric, asymmetric, transitive, total, trichotomous, a partial order, total order, well-order, strict weak order, total preorder (weak order), an equivalence relation, or a relation with any other special properties, if and only if R is.

For example, R is an ordering ≤ and S an ordering   then an isomorphism from X to Y is a bijective function   such that

 
Such an isomorphism is called an order isomorphism or (less commonly) an isotone isomorphism.

If   then this is a relation-preserving automorphism.

Applications edit

In algebra, isomorphisms are defined for all algebraic structures. Some are more specifically studied; for example:

Just as the automorphisms of an algebraic structure form a group, the isomorphisms between two algebras sharing a common structure form a heap. Letting a particular isomorphism identify the two structures turns this heap into a group.

In mathematical analysis, the Laplace transform is an isomorphism mapping hard differential equations into easier algebraic equations.

In graph theory, an isomorphism between two graphs G and H is a bijective map f from the vertices of G to the vertices of H that preserves the "edge structure" in the sense that there is an edge from vertex u to vertex v in G if and only if there is an edge from   to   in H. See graph isomorphism.

In mathematical analysis, an isomorphism between two Hilbert spaces is a bijection preserving addition, scalar multiplication, and inner product.

In early theories of logical atomism, the formal relationship between facts and true propositions was theorized by Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein to be isomorphic. An example of this line of thinking can be found in Russell's Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy.

In cybernetics, the good regulator or Conant–Ashby theorem is stated "Every good regulator of a system must be a model of that system". Whether regulated or self-regulating, an isomorphism is required between the regulator and processing parts of the system.

Category theoretic view edit

In category theory, given a category C, an isomorphism is a morphism   that has an inverse morphism   that is,   and   For example, a bijective linear map is an isomorphism between vector spaces, and a bijective continuous function whose inverse is also continuous is an isomorphism between topological spaces, called a homeomorphism.

Two categories C and D are isomorphic if there exist functors   and   which are mutually inverse to each other, that is,   (the identity functor on D) and   (the identity functor on C).

Isomorphism vs. bijective morphism edit

In a concrete category (roughly, a category whose objects are sets (perhaps with extra structure) and whose morphisms are structure-preserving functions), such as the category of topological spaces or categories of algebraic objects (like the category of groups, the category of rings, and the category of modules), an isomorphism must be bijective on the underlying sets. In algebraic categories (specifically, categories of varieties in the sense of universal algebra), an isomorphism is the same as a homomorphism which is bijective on underlying sets. However, there are concrete categories in which bijective morphisms are not necessarily isomorphisms (such as the category of topological spaces).

Relation with equality edit

In certain areas of mathematics, notably category theory, it is valuable to distinguish between equality on the one hand and isomorphism on the other.[2] Equality is when two objects are exactly the same, and everything that is true about one object is true about the other, while an isomorphism implies everything that is true about a designated part of one object's structure is true about the other's. For example, the sets

 
are equal; they are merely different representations—the first an intensional one (in set builder notation), and the second extensional (by explicit enumeration)—of the same subset of the integers. By contrast, the sets   and   are not equal—the first has elements that are letters, while the second has elements that are numbers. These are isomorphic as sets, since finite sets are determined up to isomorphism by their cardinality (number of elements) and these both have three elements, but there are many choices of isomorphism—one isomorphism is
  while another is  

and no one isomorphism is intrinsically better than any other.[note 1][note 2] On this view and in this sense, these two sets are not equal because one cannot consider them identical: one can choose an isomorphism between them, but that is a weaker claim than identity—and valid only in the context of the chosen isomorphism.

Another example is more formal and more directly illustrates the motivation for distinguishing equality from isomorphism: the distinction between a finite-dimensional vector space V and its dual space   of linear maps from V to its field of scalars   These spaces have the same dimension, and thus are isomorphic as abstract vector spaces (since algebraically, vector spaces are classified by dimension, just as sets are classified by cardinality), but there is no "natural" choice of isomorphism   If one chooses a basis for V, then this yields an isomorphism: For all  

 

This corresponds to transforming a column vector (element of V) to a row vector (element of V*) by transpose, but a different choice of basis gives a different isomorphism: the isomorphism "depends on the choice of basis". More subtly, there is a map from a vector space V to its double dual   that does not depend on the choice of basis: For all  

 

This leads to a third notion, that of a natural isomorphism: while   and   are different sets, there is a "natural" choice of isomorphism between them. This intuitive notion of "an isomorphism that does not depend on an arbitrary choice" is formalized in the notion of a natural transformation; briefly, that one may consistently identify, or more generally map from, a finite-dimensional vector space to its double dual,   for any vector space in a consistent way. Formalizing this intuition is a motivation for the development of category theory.

However, there is a case where the distinction between natural isomorphism and equality is usually not made. That is for the objects that may be characterized by a universal property. In fact, there is a unique isomorphism, necessarily natural, between two objects sharing the same universal property. A typical example is the set of real numbers, which may be defined through infinite decimal expansion, infinite binary expansion, Cauchy sequences, Dedekind cuts and many other ways. Formally, these constructions define different objects which are all solutions with the same universal property. As these objects have exactly the same properties, one may forget the method of construction and consider them as equal. This is what everybody does when referring to "the set of the real numbers". The same occurs with quotient spaces: they are commonly constructed as sets of equivalence classes. However, referring to a set of sets may be counterintuitive, and so quotient spaces are commonly considered as a pair of a set of undetermined objects, often called "points", and a surjective map onto this set.

If one wishes to distinguish between an arbitrary isomorphism (one that depends on a choice) and a natural isomorphism (one that can be done consistently), one may write   for an unnatural isomorphism and for a natural isomorphism, as in   and   This convention is not universally followed, and authors who wish to distinguish between unnatural isomorphisms and natural isomorphisms will generally explicitly state the distinction.

Generally, saying that two objects are equal is reserved for when there is a notion of a larger (ambient) space that these objects live in. Most often, one speaks of equality of two subsets of a given set (as in the integer set example above), but not of two objects abstractly presented. For example, the 2-dimensional unit sphere in 3-dimensional space

 
and the Riemann sphere   which can be presented as the one-point compactification of the complex plane   or as the complex projective line (a quotient space)
 
are three different descriptions for a mathematical object, all of which are isomorphic, but not equal because they are not all subsets of a single space: the first is a subset of   the second is  [note 3] plus an additional point, and the third is a subquotient of  

In the context of category theory, objects are usually at most isomorphic—indeed, a motivation for the development of category theory was showing that different constructions in homology theory yielded equivalent (isomorphic) groups. Given maps between two objects X and Y, however, one asks if they are equal or not (they are both elements of the set   hence equality is the proper relationship), particularly in commutative diagrams.

See also: homotopy type theory, in which isomorphisms can be treated as kinds of equality.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^   have a conventional order, namely alphabetical order, and similarly 1, 2, 3 have the order from the integers, and thus one particular isomorphism is "natural", namely
     
    More formally, as sets these are isomorphic, but not naturally isomorphic (there are multiple choices of isomorphism), while as ordered sets they are naturally isomorphic (there is a unique isomorphism, given above), since finite total orders are uniquely determined up to unique isomorphism by cardinality. This intuition can be formalized by saying that any two finite totally ordered sets of the same cardinality have a natural isomorphism, the one that sends the least element of the first to the least element of the second, the least element of what remains in the first to the least element of what remains in the second, and so forth, but in general, pairs of sets of a given finite cardinality are not naturally isomorphic because there is more than one choice of map—except if the cardinality is 0 or 1, where there is a unique choice.
  2. ^ In fact, there are precisely   different isomorphisms between two sets with three elements. This is equal to the number of automorphisms of a given three-element set (which in turn is equal to the order of the symmetric group on three letters), and more generally one has that the set of isomorphisms between two objects, denoted   is a torsor for the automorphism group of A,   and also a torsor for the automorphism group of B. In fact, automorphisms of an object are a key reason to be concerned with the distinction between isomorphism and equality, as demonstrated in the effect of change of basis on the identification of a vector space with its dual or with its double dual, as elaborated in the sequel.
  3. ^ Being precise, the identification of the complex numbers with the real plane,
     
    depends on a choice of   one can just as easily choose   which yields a different identification—formally, complex conjugation is an automorphism—but in practice one often assumes that one has made such an identification.

References edit

  1. ^ Vinberg, Ėrnest Borisovich (2003). A Course in Algebra. American Mathematical Society. p. 3. ISBN 9780821834138.
  2. ^ Mazur 2007

Further reading edit

  • Mazur, Barry (12 June 2007), When is one thing equal to some other thing? (PDF)

External links edit

isomorphism, this, article, about, mathematics, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, . This article is about mathematics For other uses see Isomorphism disambiguation This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Isomorphism news newspapers books scholar JSTOR September 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics an isomorphism is a structure preserving mapping between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between them The word isomorphism is derived from the Ancient Greek ἴsos isos equal and morfh morphe form or shape The group of fifth roots of unity under multiplication is isomorphic to the group of rotations of the regular pentagon under composition The interest in isomorphisms lies in the fact that two isomorphic objects have the same properties excluding further information such as additional structure or names of objects Thus isomorphic structures cannot be distinguished from the point of view of structure only and may be identified In mathematical jargon one says that two objects are the same up to an isomorphism citation needed An automorphism is an isomorphism from a structure to itself An isomorphism between two structures is a canonical isomorphism a canonical map that is an isomorphism if there is only one isomorphism between the two structures as is the case for solutions of a universal property or if the isomorphism is much more natural in some sense than other isomorphisms For example for every prime number p all fields with p elements are canonically isomorphic with a unique isomorphism The isomorphism theorems provide canonical isomorphisms that are not unique The term isomorphism is mainly used for algebraic structures In this case mappings are called homomorphisms and a homomorphism is an isomorphism if and only if it is bijective In various areas of mathematics isomorphisms have received specialized names depending on the type of structure under consideration For example An isometry is an isomorphism of metric spaces A homeomorphism is an isomorphism of topological spaces A diffeomorphism is an isomorphism of spaces equipped with a differential structure typically differentiable manifolds A symplectomorphism is an isomorphism of symplectic manifolds A permutation is an automorphism of a set In geometry isomorphisms and automorphisms are often called transformations for example rigid transformations affine transformations projective transformations Category theory which can be viewed as a formalization of the concept of mapping between structures provides a language that may be used to unify the approach to these different aspects of the basic idea Contents 1 Examples 1 1 Logarithm and exponential 1 2 Integers modulo 6 1 3 Relation preserving isomorphism 2 Applications 3 Category theoretic view 3 1 Isomorphism vs bijective morphism 4 Relation with equality 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 Further reading 9 External linksExamples editLogarithm and exponential edit Let R displaystyle mathbb R nbsp be the multiplicative group of positive real numbers and let R displaystyle mathbb R nbsp be the additive group of real numbers The logarithm function log R R displaystyle log mathbb R to mathbb R nbsp satisfies log xy log x log y displaystyle log xy log x log y nbsp for all x y R displaystyle x y in mathbb R nbsp so it is a group homomorphism The exponential function exp R R displaystyle exp mathbb R to mathbb R nbsp satisfies exp x y exp x exp y displaystyle exp x y exp x exp y nbsp for all x y R displaystyle x y in mathbb R nbsp so it too is a homomorphism The identities log exp x x displaystyle log exp x x nbsp and exp log y y displaystyle exp log y y nbsp show that log displaystyle log nbsp and exp displaystyle exp nbsp are inverses of each other Since log displaystyle log nbsp is a homomorphism that has an inverse that is also a homomorphism log displaystyle log nbsp is an isomorphism of groups The log displaystyle log nbsp function is an isomorphism which translates multiplication of positive real numbers into addition of real numbers This facility makes it possible to multiply real numbers using a ruler and a table of logarithms or using a slide rule with a logarithmic scale Integers modulo 6 edit Consider the group Z6 displaystyle mathbb Z 6 nbsp the integers from 0 to 5 with addition modulo 6 Also consider the group Z2 Z3 displaystyle left mathbb Z 2 times mathbb Z 3 right nbsp the ordered pairs where the x coordinates can be 0 or 1 and the y coordinates can be 0 1 or 2 where addition in the x coordinate is modulo 2 and addition in the y coordinate is modulo 3 These structures are isomorphic under addition under the following scheme 0 0 0 1 1 1 0 2 2 1 0 3 0 1 4 1 2 5 displaystyle begin alignedat 4 0 0 amp mapsto 0 1 1 amp mapsto 1 0 2 amp mapsto 2 1 0 amp mapsto 3 0 1 amp mapsto 4 1 2 amp mapsto 5 end alignedat nbsp or in general a b 3a 4b mod6 displaystyle a b mapsto 3a 4b mod 6 nbsp For example 1 1 1 0 0 1 displaystyle 1 1 1 0 0 1 nbsp which translates in the other system as 1 3 4 displaystyle 1 3 4 nbsp Even though these two groups look different in that the sets contain different elements they are indeed isomorphic their structures are exactly the same More generally the direct product of two cyclic groups Zm displaystyle mathbb Z m nbsp and Zn displaystyle mathbb Z n nbsp is isomorphic to Zmn displaystyle mathbb Z mn nbsp if and only if m and n are coprime per the Chinese remainder theorem Relation preserving isomorphism edit If one object consists of a set X with a binary relation R and the other object consists of a set Y with a binary relation S then an isomorphism from X to Y is a bijective function f X Y displaystyle f X to Y nbsp such that 1 S f u f v if and only if R u v displaystyle operatorname S f u f v quad text if and only if quad operatorname R u v nbsp S is reflexive irreflexive symmetric antisymmetric asymmetric transitive total trichotomous a partial order total order well order strict weak order total preorder weak order an equivalence relation or a relation with any other special properties if and only if R is For example R is an ordering and S an ordering displaystyle scriptstyle sqsubseteq nbsp then an isomorphism from X to Y is a bijective function f X Y displaystyle f X to Y nbsp such thatf u f v if and only if u v displaystyle f u sqsubseteq f v quad text if and only if quad u leq v nbsp Such an isomorphism is called an order isomorphism or less commonly an isotone isomorphism If X Y displaystyle X Y nbsp then this is a relation preserving automorphism Applications editIn algebra isomorphisms are defined for all algebraic structures Some are more specifically studied for example Linear isomorphisms between vector spaces they are specified by invertible matrices Group isomorphisms between groups the classification of isomorphism classes of finite groups is an open problem Ring isomorphism between rings Field isomorphisms are the same as ring isomorphism between fields their study and more specifically the study of field automorphisms is an important part of Galois theory Just as the automorphisms of an algebraic structure form a group the isomorphisms between two algebras sharing a common structure form a heap Letting a particular isomorphism identify the two structures turns this heap into a group In mathematical analysis the Laplace transform is an isomorphism mapping hard differential equations into easier algebraic equations In graph theory an isomorphism between two graphs G and H is a bijective map f from the vertices of G to the vertices of H that preserves the edge structure in the sense that there is an edge from vertex u to vertex v in G if and only if there is an edge from f u displaystyle f u nbsp to f v displaystyle f v nbsp in H See graph isomorphism In mathematical analysis an isomorphism between two Hilbert spaces is a bijection preserving addition scalar multiplication and inner product In early theories of logical atomism the formal relationship between facts and true propositions was theorized by Bertrand Russell and Ludwig Wittgenstein to be isomorphic An example of this line of thinking can be found in Russell s Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy In cybernetics the good regulator or Conant Ashby theorem is stated Every good regulator of a system must be a model of that system Whether regulated or self regulating an isomorphism is required between the regulator and processing parts of the system Category theoretic view editIn category theory given a category C an isomorphism is a morphism f a b displaystyle f a to b nbsp that has an inverse morphism g b a displaystyle g b to a nbsp that is fg 1b displaystyle fg 1 b nbsp and gf 1a displaystyle gf 1 a nbsp For example a bijective linear map is an isomorphism between vector spaces and a bijective continuous function whose inverse is also continuous is an isomorphism between topological spaces called a homeomorphism Two categories C and D are isomorphic if there exist functors F C D displaystyle F C to D nbsp and G D C displaystyle G D to C nbsp which are mutually inverse to each other that is FG 1D displaystyle FG 1 D nbsp the identity functor on D and GF 1C displaystyle GF 1 C nbsp the identity functor on C Isomorphism vs bijective morphism edit In a concrete category roughly a category whose objects are sets perhaps with extra structure and whose morphisms are structure preserving functions such as the category of topological spaces or categories of algebraic objects like the category of groups the category of rings and the category of modules an isomorphism must be bijective on the underlying sets In algebraic categories specifically categories of varieties in the sense of universal algebra an isomorphism is the same as a homomorphism which is bijective on underlying sets However there are concrete categories in which bijective morphisms are not necessarily isomorphisms such as the category of topological spaces Relation with equality editSee also Equality mathematics In certain areas of mathematics notably category theory it is valuable to distinguish between equality on the one hand and isomorphism on the other 2 Equality is when two objects are exactly the same and everything that is true about one object is true about the other while an isomorphism implies everything that is true about a designated part of one object s structure is true about the other s For example the setsA x Z x2 lt 2 and B 1 0 1 displaystyle A left x in mathbb Z mid x 2 lt 2 right quad text and quad B 1 0 1 nbsp are equal they are merely different representations the first an intensional one in set builder notation and the second extensional by explicit enumeration of the same subset of the integers By contrast the sets A B C displaystyle A B C nbsp and 1 2 3 displaystyle 1 2 3 nbsp are not equal the first has elements that are letters while the second has elements that are numbers These are isomorphic as sets since finite sets are determined up to isomorphism by their cardinality number of elements and these both have three elements but there are many choices of isomorphism one isomorphism is A 1 B 2 C 3 displaystyle text A mapsto 1 text B mapsto 2 text C mapsto 3 nbsp while another is A 3 B 2 C 1 displaystyle text A mapsto 3 text B mapsto 2 text C mapsto 1 nbsp and no one isomorphism is intrinsically better than any other note 1 note 2 On this view and in this sense these two sets are not equal because one cannot consider them identical one can choose an isomorphism between them but that is a weaker claim than identity and valid only in the context of the chosen isomorphism Another example is more formal and more directly illustrates the motivation for distinguishing equality from isomorphism the distinction between a finite dimensional vector space V and its dual space V f V K displaystyle V left varphi V to mathbf K right nbsp of linear maps from V to its field of scalars K displaystyle mathbf K nbsp These spaces have the same dimension and thus are isomorphic as abstract vector spaces since algebraically vector spaces are classified by dimension just as sets are classified by cardinality but there is no natural choice of isomorphism V V displaystyle V mathrel overset sim to V nbsp If one chooses a basis for V then this yields an isomorphism For all u v V displaystyle u v in V nbsp v ϕv V such that ϕv u vTu displaystyle v mathrel overset sim mapsto phi v in V quad text such that quad phi v u v mathrm T u nbsp This corresponds to transforming a column vector element of V to a row vector element of V by transpose but a different choice of basis gives a different isomorphism the isomorphism depends on the choice of basis More subtly there is a map from a vector space V to its double dual V x V K displaystyle V left x V to mathbf K right nbsp that does not depend on the choice of basis For all v V and f V displaystyle v in V text and varphi in V nbsp v xv V such that xv ϕ ϕ v displaystyle v mathrel overset sim mapsto x v in V quad text such that quad x v phi phi v nbsp This leads to a third notion that of a natural isomorphism while V displaystyle V nbsp and V displaystyle V nbsp are different sets there is a natural choice of isomorphism between them This intuitive notion of an isomorphism that does not depend on an arbitrary choice is formalized in the notion of a natural transformation briefly that one may consistently identify or more generally map from a finite dimensional vector space to its double dual V V displaystyle V mathrel overset sim to V nbsp for any vector space in a consistent way Formalizing this intuition is a motivation for the development of category theory However there is a case where the distinction between natural isomorphism and equality is usually not made That is for the objects that may be characterized by a universal property In fact there is a unique isomorphism necessarily natural between two objects sharing the same universal property A typical example is the set of real numbers which may be defined through infinite decimal expansion infinite binary expansion Cauchy sequences Dedekind cuts and many other ways Formally these constructions define different objects which are all solutions with the same universal property As these objects have exactly the same properties one may forget the method of construction and consider them as equal This is what everybody does when referring to the set of the real numbers The same occurs with quotient spaces they are commonly constructed as sets of equivalence classes However referring to a set of sets may be counterintuitive and so quotient spaces are commonly considered as a pair of a set of undetermined objects often called points and a surjective map onto this set If one wishes to distinguish between an arbitrary isomorphism one that depends on a choice and a natural isomorphism one that can be done consistently one may write displaystyle approx nbsp for an unnatural isomorphism and for a natural isomorphism as in V V displaystyle V approx V nbsp and V V displaystyle V cong V nbsp This convention is not universally followed and authors who wish to distinguish between unnatural isomorphisms and natural isomorphisms will generally explicitly state the distinction Generally saying that two objects are equal is reserved for when there is a notion of a larger ambient space that these objects live in Most often one speaks of equality of two subsets of a given set as in the integer set example above but not of two objects abstractly presented For example the 2 dimensional unit sphere in 3 dimensional spaceS2 x y z R3 x2 y2 z2 1 displaystyle S 2 left x y z in mathbb R 3 mid x 2 y 2 z 2 1 right nbsp and the Riemann sphere C displaystyle widehat mathbb C nbsp which can be presented as the one point compactification of the complex plane C displaystyle mathbb C cup infty nbsp or as the complex projective line a quotient space PC1 C2 0 0 C displaystyle mathbf P mathbb C 1 left mathbb C 2 setminus 0 0 right left mathbb C right nbsp are three different descriptions for a mathematical object all of which are isomorphic but not equal because they are not all subsets of a single space the first is a subset of R3 displaystyle mathbb R 3 nbsp the second is C R2 displaystyle mathbb C cong mathbb R 2 nbsp note 3 plus an additional point and the third is a subquotient of C2 displaystyle mathbb C 2 nbsp In the context of category theory objects are usually at most isomorphic indeed a motivation for the development of category theory was showing that different constructions in homology theory yielded equivalent isomorphic groups Given maps between two objects X and Y however one asks if they are equal or not they are both elements of the set hom X Y displaystyle hom X Y nbsp hence equality is the proper relationship particularly in commutative diagrams See also homotopy type theory in which isomorphisms can be treated as kinds of equality See also edit nbsp Mathematics portalBisimulation Equivalence relation Heap mathematics Isometry Isomorphism class Isomorphism theorem Universal property Coherent isomorphismNotes edit A B C displaystyle A B C nbsp have a conventional order namely alphabetical order and similarly 1 2 3 have the order from the integers and thus one particular isomorphism is natural namely A 1 B 2 C 3 displaystyle text A mapsto 1 text B mapsto 2 text C mapsto 3 nbsp More formally as sets these are isomorphic but not naturally isomorphic there are multiple choices of isomorphism while as ordered sets they are naturally isomorphic there is a unique isomorphism given above since finite total orders are uniquely determined up to unique isomorphism by cardinality This intuition can be formalized by saying that any two finite totally ordered sets of the same cardinality have a natural isomorphism the one that sends the least element of the first to the least element of the second the least element of what remains in the first to the least element of what remains in the second and so forth but in general pairs of sets of a given finite cardinality are not naturally isomorphic because there is more than one choice of map except if the cardinality is 0 or 1 where there is a unique choice In fact there are precisely 3 6 displaystyle 3 6 nbsp different isomorphisms between two sets with three elements This is equal to the number of automorphisms of a given three element set which in turn is equal to the order of the symmetric group on three letters and more generally one has that the set of isomorphisms between two objects denoted Iso A B displaystyle operatorname Iso A B nbsp is a torsor for the automorphism group of A Aut A displaystyle operatorname Aut A nbsp and also a torsor for the automorphism group of B In fact automorphisms of an object are a key reason to be concerned with the distinction between isomorphism and equality as demonstrated in the effect of change of basis on the identification of a vector space with its dual or with its double dual as elaborated in the sequel Being precise the identification of the complex numbers with the real plane C R 1 R i R2 displaystyle mathbb C cong mathbb R cdot 1 oplus mathbb R cdot i mathbb R 2 nbsp depends on a choice of i displaystyle i nbsp one can just as easily choose i displaystyle i nbsp which yields a different identification formally complex conjugation is an automorphism but in practice one often assumes that one has made such an identification References edit Vinberg Ėrnest Borisovich 2003 A Course in Algebra American Mathematical Society p 3 ISBN 9780821834138 Mazur 2007Further reading editMazur Barry 12 June 2007 When is one thing equal to some other thing PDF External links edit nbsp Look up isomorphism in Wiktionary the free dictionary Isomorphism Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Weisstein Eric W Isomorphism MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Isomorphism amp oldid 1212225616, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.