fbpx
Wikipedia

Normativity

Normative generally means relating to an evaluative standard. Normativity is the phenomenon in human societies of designating some actions or outcomes as good, desirable, or permissible, and others as bad, undesirable, or impermissible. A norm in this sense means a standard for evaluating or making judgments about behavior or outcomes. "Normative" is sometimes also used, somewhat confusingly, to mean relating to a descriptive standard: doing what is normally done or what most others are expected to do in practice. In this sense a norm is not evaluative, a basis for judging behavior or outcomes; it is simply a fact or observation about behavior or outcomes, without judgment. Many researchers in science, law, and philosophy try to restrict the use of the term "normative" to the evaluative sense and refer to the description of behavior and outcomes as positive, descriptive, predictive, or empirical.[1][2]

Normative has specialised meanings in different academic disciplines such as philosophy, social sciences, and law. In most contexts, normative means 'relating to an evaluation or value judgment.' Normative propositions tend to evaluate some object or some course of action. Normative content differs from descriptive content.[3]

Though philosophers disagree about how normativity should be understood; it has become increasingly common to understand normative claims as claims about reasons.[4] As Derek Parfit explains:

We can have reasons to believe something, to do something, to have some desire or aim, and to have many other attitudes and emotions, such as fear, regret, and hope. Reasons are given by facts, such as the fact that someone's finger-prints are on some gun, or that calling an ambulance would save someone's life. It is hard to explain the concept of a reason, or what the phrase 'a reason' means. Facts give us reasons, we might say, when they count in favour of our having some attitude, or our acting in some way. But 'counts in favour of' means roughly 'gives a reason for'. The concept of a reason is best explained by example. One example is the thought that we always have a reason to want to avoid being in agony.[5]

Philosophy edit

In philosophy, normative theory aims to make moral judgements on events, focusing on preserving something they deem as morally good, or preventing a change for the worse.[6] The theory has its origins in Greece.[7] Normative statements of such a type make claims about how institutions should or ought to be designed, how to value them, which things are good or bad, and which actions are right or wrong.[8] Claims are usually contrasted with positive (i.e. descriptive, explanatory, or constative) claims when describing types of theories, beliefs, or propositions. Positive statements are (purportedly) factual, empirical statements that attempt to describe reality.[citation needed]

For example, "children should eat vegetables", and "those who would sacrifice liberty for security deserve neither" are philosophically normative claims. On the other hand, "vegetables contain a relatively high proportion of vitamins", and "a common consequence of sacrificing liberty for security is a loss of both" are positive claims. Whether a statement is philosophically normative is logically independent of whether it is verified, verifiable, or popularly held.

There are several schools of thought regarding the status of philosophically normative statements and whether they can be rationally discussed or defended. Among these schools are the tradition of practical reason extending from Aristotle through Kant to Habermas, which asserts that they can, and the tradition of emotivism, which maintains that they are merely expressions of emotions and have no cognitive content.

There is large debate in philosophy surrounding whether one can get a normative statement of such a type from an empirical one (i.e. whether one can get an 'ought' from an 'is', or a 'value' from a 'fact'). Aristotle is one scholar who believed that one could in fact get an ought from an is. He believed that the universe was teleological and that everything in it has a purpose. To explain why something is a certain way, Aristotle believed one could simply say that it is trying to be what it ought to be.[9] On the contrary, David Hume believed one cannot get an ought from an is because no matter how much one thinks something ought to be a certain way it will not change the way it is. Despite this, Hume used empirical experimental methods whilst looking at the philosophically normative. Similar to this was Kames, who also used the study of facts and the objective to discover a correct system of morals.[10] The assumption that 'is' can lead to 'ought' is an important component of the philosophy of Roy Bhaskar.[11]

Philosophically normative statements and norms, as well as their meanings, are an integral part of human life. They are fundamental for prioritizing goals and organizing and planning. Thought, belief, emotion, and action are the basis of much ethical and political discourse; indeed, normativity of such a type is arguably the key feature distinguishing ethical and political discourse from other discourses (such as natural science).[citation needed]

Much modern moral/ethical philosophy takes as its starting point the apparent variance between peoples and cultures regarding the ways they define what is considered to be appropriate/desirable/praiseworthy/valuable/good etc. (In other words, variance in how individuals, groups and societies define what is in accordance with their philosophically normative standards.) This has led philosophers such as A.J. Ayer and J.L. Mackie (for different reasons and in different ways) to cast doubt on the meaningfulness of normative statements of such a type. However, other philosophers, such as Christine Korsgaard, have argued for a source of philosophically normative value which is independent of individuals' subjective morality and which consequently attains (a lesser or greater degree of) objectivity.[12]

Social sciences edit

In the social sciences, the term "normative" has broadly the same meaning as its usage in philosophy, but may also relate, in a sociological context, to the role of cultural 'norms'; the shared values or institutions that structural functionalists regard as constitutive of the social structure and social cohesion. These values and units of socialization thus act to encourage or enforce social activity and outcomes that ought to (with respect to the norms implicit in those structures) occur, while discouraging or preventing social activity that ought not occur. That is, they promote social activity that is socially valued (see philosophy above). While there are always anomalies in social activity (typically described as "crime" or anti-social behaviour, see also normality (behavior)) the normative effects of popularly endorsed beliefs (such as "family values" or "common sense") push most social activity towards a generally homogeneous set. From such reasoning, however, functionalism shares an affinity with ideological conservatism.

Normative economics deals with questions of what sort of economic policies should be pursued, in order to achieve desired (that is, valued) economic outcomes.

Politics edit

The use of normativity and normative theory in the study of politics has been questioned, particularly since the rise in popularity of logical positivism. It has been suggested by some that normative theory is not appropriate to be used in the study of politics, because of its value based nature, and a positive, value neutral approach should be taken instead, applying theory to what is, not to what ought to be.[13] Others have argued, however, that to abandon the use of normative theory in politics is misguided, if not pointless, as not only is normative theory more than a projection of a theorist's views and values, but also this theory provides important contributions to political debate.[14] Pietrzyk-Reeves discussed the idea that political science can never truly be value free, and so to not use normative theory is not entirely helpful. Furthermore, perhaps the normative dimension political study has is what separates it from many branches of social sciences.[13]

International relations edit

In the academic discipline of International relations, Smith, Baylis & Owens in the Introduction to their 2008 [15] book make the case that the normative position or normative theory is to make the world a better place and that this theoretical worldview aims to do so by being aware of implicit assumptions and explicit assumptions that constitute a non-normative position, and align or position the normative towards the loci of other key socio-political theories such as political liberalism, Marxism, political constructivism, political realism, political idealism and political globalization.

Law edit

In law, as an academic discipline, the term "normative" is used to describe the way something ought to be done according to a value position. As such, normative arguments can be conflicting, insofar as different values can be inconsistent with one another. For example, from one normative value position the purpose of the criminal process may be to repress crime. From another value position, the purpose of the criminal justice system could be to protect individuals from the moral harm of wrongful conviction.

Standards documents edit

The CEN-CENELEC Internal Regulations describe "normative" as applying to a document or element "that provides rules, guidelines or characteristics for activities or their results" which are mandatory.[16]

Normative elements are defined in International Organization for Standardization Directives Part 2 as "elements that describe the scope of the document, and which set out provisions".[17] Provisions include "requirements", which are criteria that must be fulfilled and cannot be deviated from, and "recommendations" and "statements", which are not necessary to comply with.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Bicchieri, Cristina (2005). The Grammar of Society:The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521574907.
  2. ^ Bicchieri, Cristina (2017). Norms in the Wild: How to Diagnose, Measure, and Change Social Norms. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780190622053.
  3. ^ Jarvis., Thomson, Judith (2008). Normativity. Chicago, Ill.: Open Court. ISBN 9780812696585. OCLC 227918828.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  4. ^ Thomas, Scanlon (2014). Being realistic about reasons (First ed.). Oxford. ISBN 9780199678488. OCLC 862091562.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  5. ^ Parfit, Derek (2011). On what matters Volume one. Edited and Introduced by Samuel Scheffler. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780191576706. OCLC 744616054.
  6. ^ Strauss, Leo (2017-09-08), "What Is Political Philosophy? The Problem of Political Philosophy", Behavioralism in Political Science, Routledge, pp. 93–108, doi:10.4324/9781351314367-5, ISBN 978-1-351-31436-7, retrieved 2020-12-14
  7. ^ Bauböck, Rainer (2008), "Normative political theory and empirical research", Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 40–60, doi:10.1017/cbo9780511801938.004, ISBN 978-0-511-80193-8, retrieved 2020-12-14
  8. ^ Leftwich, Adrian (2004). What is politics?: the activity and its study. Oxford: Polity.
  9. ^ Gray, JW (July 19, 2011). "The Is/Ought Gap: How Do We Get "Ought" from "Is?"". Ethical realism. Retrieved December 14, 2020.
  10. ^ Shaver, Robert. "Hume's Moral Theory?" History of Philosophy Quarterly, vol. 12, no. 3, 1995, pp. 317–331., www.jstor.org/stable/27744669. Accessed 14 Dec. 2020.
  11. ^ Leigh Price (2019) Introduction to the special issue: normativity, Journal of Critical Realism, 18:3, 221-238 [1]
  12. ^ Korsgaard, C. (1992). "The Sources of Normativity" (PDF). The Tanner Lectures on Human Value.
  13. ^ a b Pietrzyk-Reeves, Dorota (2017). "Normative Political Theory". Teoria Polityki. 1. doi:10.4467/00000000tp.17.009.6588. S2CID 150007680.
  14. ^ Della Porta, D; Keating, M (2008). Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences: A Pluralist Perspective. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Retrieved 1 December 2022.
  15. ^ The Globalization of World Politics: An introduction to international relations, New York, Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199297771, Fourth edition, pp.2-13
  16. ^ "Internal Regulations, Part 3: Principles and rules for the structure and drafting of CEN and CENELEC documents" (PDF). CEN-CENELEC. 2022. Retrieved 2023-05-13.
  17. ^ "ISO/IEC Directives, Part 2, Principles and rules for the structure and drafting of ISO and IEC documents". ISO IEC. 2021. Retrieved 2023-05-17.

Further reading edit

  • Canguilhem, Georges, The Normal and the Pathological, ISBN 0-942299-59-0.
  • Andreas Dorschel, 'Is there any normative claim internal to stating facts?', in: Communication & Cognition XXI (1988), no. 1, pp. 5–16.

normativity, normative, redirects, here, other, uses, normative, disambiguation, normative, generally, means, relating, evaluative, standard, phenomenon, human, societies, designating, some, actions, outcomes, good, desirable, permissible, others, undesirable,. Normative redirects here For other uses see Normative disambiguation Normative generally means relating to an evaluative standard Normativity is the phenomenon in human societies of designating some actions or outcomes as good desirable or permissible and others as bad undesirable or impermissible A norm in this sense means a standard for evaluating or making judgments about behavior or outcomes Normative is sometimes also used somewhat confusingly to mean relating to a descriptive standard doing what is normally done or what most others are expected to do in practice In this sense a norm is not evaluative a basis for judging behavior or outcomes it is simply a fact or observation about behavior or outcomes without judgment Many researchers in science law and philosophy try to restrict the use of the term normative to the evaluative sense and refer to the description of behavior and outcomes as positive descriptive predictive or empirical 1 2 Normative has specialised meanings in different academic disciplines such as philosophy social sciences and law In most contexts normative means relating to an evaluation or value judgment Normative propositions tend to evaluate some object or some course of action Normative content differs from descriptive content 3 Though philosophers disagree about how normativity should be understood it has become increasingly common to understand normative claims as claims about reasons 4 As Derek Parfit explains We can have reasons to believe something to do something to have some desire or aim and to have many other attitudes and emotions such as fear regret and hope Reasons are given by facts such as the fact that someone s finger prints are on some gun or that calling an ambulance would save someone s life It is hard to explain the concept of a reason or what the phrase a reason means Facts give us reasons we might say when they count in favour of our having some attitude or our acting in some way But counts in favour of means roughly gives a reason for The concept of a reason is best explained by example One example is the thought that we always have a reason to want to avoid being in agony 5 Contents 1 Philosophy 2 Social sciences 3 Politics 4 International relations 5 Law 6 Standards documents 7 See also 8 References 9 Further readingPhilosophy editMain article Ethics In philosophy normative theory aims to make moral judgements on events focusing on preserving something they deem as morally good or preventing a change for the worse 6 The theory has its origins in Greece 7 Normative statements of such a type make claims about how institutions should or ought to be designed how to value them which things are good or bad and which actions are right or wrong 8 Claims are usually contrasted with positive i e descriptive explanatory or constative claims when describing types of theories beliefs or propositions Positive statements are purportedly factual empirical statements that attempt to describe reality citation needed For example children should eat vegetables and those who would sacrifice liberty for security deserve neither are philosophically normative claims On the other hand vegetables contain a relatively high proportion of vitamins and a common consequence of sacrificing liberty for security is a loss of both are positive claims Whether a statement is philosophically normative is logically independent of whether it is verified verifiable or popularly held There are several schools of thought regarding the status of philosophically normative statements and whether they can be rationally discussed or defended Among these schools are the tradition of practical reason extending from Aristotle through Kant to Habermas which asserts that they can and the tradition of emotivism which maintains that they are merely expressions of emotions and have no cognitive content There is large debate in philosophy surrounding whether one can get a normative statement of such a type from an empirical one i e whether one can get an ought from an is or a value from a fact Aristotle is one scholar who believed that one could in fact get an ought from an is He believed that the universe was teleological and that everything in it has a purpose To explain why something is a certain way Aristotle believed one could simply say that it is trying to be what it ought to be 9 On the contrary David Hume believed one cannot get an ought from an is because no matter how much one thinks something ought to be a certain way it will not change the way it is Despite this Hume used empirical experimental methods whilst looking at the philosophically normative Similar to this was Kames who also used the study of facts and the objective to discover a correct system of morals 10 The assumption that is can lead to ought is an important component of the philosophy of Roy Bhaskar 11 Philosophically normative statements and norms as well as their meanings are an integral part of human life They are fundamental for prioritizing goals and organizing and planning Thought belief emotion and action are the basis of much ethical and political discourse indeed normativity of such a type is arguably the key feature distinguishing ethical and political discourse from other discourses such as natural science citation needed Much modern moral ethical philosophy takes as its starting point the apparent variance between peoples and cultures regarding the ways they define what is considered to be appropriate desirable praiseworthy valuable good etc In other words variance in how individuals groups and societies define what is in accordance with their philosophically normative standards This has led philosophers such as A J Ayer and J L Mackie for different reasons and in different ways to cast doubt on the meaningfulness of normative statements of such a type However other philosophers such as Christine Korsgaard have argued for a source of philosophically normative value which is independent of individuals subjective morality and which consequently attains a lesser or greater degree of objectivity 12 Social sciences editIn the social sciences the term normative has broadly the same meaning as its usage in philosophy but may also relate in a sociological context to the role of cultural norms the shared values or institutions that structural functionalists regard as constitutive of the social structure and social cohesion These values and units of socialization thus act to encourage or enforce social activity and outcomes that ought to with respect to the norms implicit in those structures occur while discouraging or preventing social activity that ought not occur That is they promote social activity that is socially valued see philosophy above While there are always anomalies in social activity typically described as crime or anti social behaviour see also normality behavior the normative effects of popularly endorsed beliefs such as family values or common sense push most social activity towards a generally homogeneous set From such reasoning however functionalism shares an affinity with ideological conservatism Normative economics deals with questions of what sort of economic policies should be pursued in order to achieve desired that is valued economic outcomes Politics editSee also Political philosophy The use of normativity and normative theory in the study of politics has been questioned particularly since the rise in popularity of logical positivism It has been suggested by some that normative theory is not appropriate to be used in the study of politics because of its value based nature and a positive value neutral approach should be taken instead applying theory to what is not to what ought to be 13 Others have argued however that to abandon the use of normative theory in politics is misguided if not pointless as not only is normative theory more than a projection of a theorist s views and values but also this theory provides important contributions to political debate 14 Pietrzyk Reeves discussed the idea that political science can never truly be value free and so to not use normative theory is not entirely helpful Furthermore perhaps the normative dimension political study has is what separates it from many branches of social sciences 13 International relations editIn the academic discipline of International relations Smith Baylis amp Owens in the Introduction to their 2008 15 book make the case that the normative position or normative theory is to make the world a better place and that this theoretical worldview aims to do so by being aware of implicit assumptions and explicit assumptions that constitute a non normative position and align or position the normative towards the loci of other key socio political theories such as political liberalism Marxism political constructivism political realism political idealism and political globalization Law editSee also Normative jurisprudence In law as an academic discipline the term normative is used to describe the way something ought to be done according to a value position As such normative arguments can be conflicting insofar as different values can be inconsistent with one another For example from one normative value position the purpose of the criminal process may be to repress crime From another value position the purpose of the criminal justice system could be to protect individuals from the moral harm of wrongful conviction Standards documents editThe CEN CENELEC Internal Regulations describe normative as applying to a document or element that provides rules guidelines or characteristics for activities or their results which are mandatory 16 Normative elements are defined in International Organization for Standardization Directives Part 2 as elements that describe the scope of the document and which set out provisions 17 Provisions include requirements which are criteria that must be fulfilled and cannot be deviated from and recommendations and statements which are not necessary to comply with See also edit nbsp Look up normativity in Wiktionary the free dictionary Conformity Decision theory Economics Hypothesis Is ought problem Linguistic prescription Norm philosophy Normative economics Normative ethics Normative science Philosophy of law Political science Scientific method ValueReferences edit Bicchieri Cristina 2005 The Grammar of Society The Nature and Dynamics of Social Norms Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521574907 Bicchieri Cristina 2017 Norms in the Wild How to Diagnose Measure and Change Social Norms Oxford University Press ISBN 9780190622053 Jarvis Thomson Judith 2008 Normativity Chicago Ill Open Court ISBN 9780812696585 OCLC 227918828 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Thomas Scanlon 2014 Being realistic about reasons First ed Oxford ISBN 9780199678488 OCLC 862091562 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Parfit Derek 2011 On what matters Volume one Edited and Introduced by Samuel Scheffler Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 9780191576706 OCLC 744616054 Strauss Leo 2017 09 08 What Is Political Philosophy The Problem of Political Philosophy Behavioralism in Political Science Routledge pp 93 108 doi 10 4324 9781351314367 5 ISBN 978 1 351 31436 7 retrieved 2020 12 14 Baubock Rainer 2008 Normative political theory and empirical research Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 40 60 doi 10 1017 cbo9780511801938 004 ISBN 978 0 511 80193 8 retrieved 2020 12 14 Leftwich Adrian 2004 What is politics the activity and its study Oxford Polity Gray JW July 19 2011 The Is Ought Gap How Do We Get Ought from Is Ethical realism Retrieved December 14 2020 Shaver Robert Hume s Moral Theory History of Philosophy Quarterly vol 12 no 3 1995 pp 317 331 www jstor org stable 27744669 Accessed 14 Dec 2020 Leigh Price 2019 Introduction to the special issue normativity Journal of Critical Realism 18 3 221 238 1 Korsgaard C 1992 The Sources of Normativity PDF The Tanner Lectures on Human Value a b Pietrzyk Reeves Dorota 2017 Normative Political Theory Teoria Polityki 1 doi 10 4467 00000000tp 17 009 6588 S2CID 150007680 Della Porta D Keating M 2008 Approaches and Methodologies in the Social Sciences A Pluralist Perspective Cambridge Cambridge University Press Retrieved 1 December 2022 The Globalization of World Politics An introduction to international relations New York Oxford University Press ISBN 9780199297771 Fourth edition pp 2 13 Internal Regulations Part 3 Principles and rules for the structure and drafting of CEN and CENELEC documents PDF CEN CENELEC 2022 Retrieved 2023 05 13 ISO IEC Directives Part 2 Principles and rules for the structure and drafting of ISO and IEC documents ISO IEC 2021 Retrieved 2023 05 17 Further reading editCanguilhem Georges The Normal and the Pathological ISBN 0 942299 59 0 Andreas Dorschel Is there any normative claim internal to stating facts in Communication amp Cognition XXI 1988 no 1 pp 5 16 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Normativity amp oldid 1224126108, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.