fbpx
Wikipedia

Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg

Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (30 November 1802 – 24 January 1872) was a German philosopher and philologist.

Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg
Born(1802-11-30)30 November 1802
Died24 January 1872(1872-01-24) (aged 69)
EducationUniversity of Kiel
Leipzig University
University of Berlin (PhD, 1826)
Era19th-century philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolGerman idealism
Aristotelianism
Aristotelian idealism[1]
InstitutionsUniversity of Berlin
ThesisPlatonis de ideis et numeris doctrina ex Aristotele illustrata (On Plato's Doctrine of Ideas and Numbers as Illustrated by Aristotle) (1826)
Academic advisorsKarl Leonhard Reinhold[2]
August Boeckh[3]
Friedrich Schleiermacher[3]
Georg Ludwig König [de]
Doctoral studentsRudolf Christoph Eucken
Friedrich Paulsen
Other notable studentsFranz Brentano
Wilhelm Dilthey
Ernst Laas
Main interests
Logic, metaphysics
Notable ideas
Trendelenburg's gap, motion as the fundamental fact common to being and thought
Putting the organic/teleological view of the world on a modern foundation[4]

Life edit

He was born at Eutin, near Lübeck. He was placed in a gymnasium in Eutin, which was under the direction of Georg Ludwig König [de],[11] a philologist influenced by Immanuel Kant.

He was educated at the universities of Kiel, Leipzig, Berlin. He became more and more attracted to the study of Plato and Aristotle, and his 1826 doctoral dissertation, Platonis de ideis et numeris doctrina ex Aristotele illustrata (On Plato's Doctrine of Ideas and Numbers as Illustrated by Aristotle), was an attempt to reach through Aristotle's criticisms a more accurate knowledge of the Platonic philosophy.[12]

He declined the offer of a classical chair at Kiel, and accepted a post as tutor to the son of an intimate friend of Karl vom Stein zum Altenstein, the Prussian minister of education. He held this position for seven years (1826–1833), occupying his leisure time with the preparation of a critical edition of Aristotle's De anima (1833; 2nd ed. by Christian Belger, 1877). In 1833 Altenstein appointed Trendelenburg extraordinary professor in Berlin, and four years later he was advanced to an ordinary professorship.[12]

Teaching edit

For nearly 40 years, he proved himself markedly successful as a teacher, during the greater part of which time he had to examine in philosophy and pedagogics all candidates for the scholastic profession in Prussia. His teaching method was highly regarded by Søren Kierkegaard who called him "one of the most sober philosophical philologists I know."[13] He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1861.[14] Two of his prominent students were Franz Brentano and Wilhelm Dilthey.

Philosophical work edit

Defense of teleology edit

Trendelenburg's philosophizing is conditioned throughout by his loving study of Plato and Aristotle, whom he regards not as opponents but as building jointly on the broad basis of idealism. His own standpoint may be called a modern version of Aristotelianism. While denying the possibility of an absolute method and an absolute philosophy, as contended for by Hegel and others, Trendelenburg was emphatically an idealist in the ancient or Platonic sense; his whole work was devoted to the demonstration of the ideal in the real. But he maintained that the procedure of philosophy must be analytic, rising from the particular facts to the universal in which we find them explained. We divine the system of the whole from the part we know, but the process of reconstruction must remain approximative. Our position forbids the possibility of a final system. Instead, therefore, of constantly beginning afresh in speculation, it should be our duty to attach ourselves to what may be considered the permanent results of historic developments.[12]

The classical expression of these results Trendelenburg finds mainly in the Platonico-Aristotelian system. The philosophical question is stated thus: How are thought and being united in knowledge? How does thought get at being? And how does being enter into thought? Proceeding on the principle that like can only be known by like, Trendelenburg next reaches a doctrine peculiar to himself (though based upon Aristotle) that plays a central part in his speculations. Motion is the fundamental fact common to being and thought; the actual motion of the external world has its counterpart in the constructive motion involved in every instance of perception or thought. From motion he proceeds to deduce time, space and the categories of mechanics and natural science. These, being thus derived, are at once subjective and objective in their scope. It is true that matter can never be completely resolved into motion, but the irreducible remainder may be treated, like Aristotle, as an abstraction we asymptotically approach but never reach.[12]

The facts of existence, however, are not adequately explained by the mechanical categories. The ultimate interpretation of the universe can only be found in the higher category of End or final cause. Here Trendelenburg finds the dividing line, between philosophical systems. On the one side stand those that acknowledge none but efficient causes, which make force prior to thought, and explain the universe, as it were, a tergo ("from the back"). This may be called, typically, Democritism. On the other side stands the organic or teleological view of the world, which interprets the parts through the idea of the whole, and sees in the efficient causes only the vehicle of ideal ends. This may be called in a wide sense Platonism. Systems like Spinozism, which seem to form a third class, neither sacrificing force to thought nor thought to force, yet by their denial of final causes inevitably fall back into the Democritic or essentially materialistic standpoint, leaving us with the great antagonism of the mechanical and the organic systems of philosophy. The latter view, which receives its first support in the facts of life, or organic nature as such, finds its culmination and ultimate verification in the ethical world, which essentially consists in the realization of ends.

Trendelenburg's Naturrecht [the right of nature] may, therefore, be taken as in a manner the completion of his system, his working out of the ideal as present in the real. The ethical end is taken to be the idea of humanity, not in the abstract as formulated by Immanuel Kant, but in the context of the state and of history. Law is treated throughout as the vehicle of ethical requirements. In Trendelenburg's treatment of the state, as the ethical organism in which the individual (the potential man) may be said first to emerge into actuality, we may trace his nurture on the best ideas of Hellenic antiquity.[12]

Fischer–Trendelenburg debate edit

In 1865 he became involved in an acrimonious controversy on the interpretation of Kant's doctrine of space with Kuno Fischer, whom he attacked in Kuno Fischer und sein Kant (1869), which drew forth the reply Anti-Trendelenburg (1870).[12] The controversy became known in the history of philosophy as the Fischer–Trendelenburg debate.

Trendelenburg's position on the debate (the position that "Kant may establish that space and time are a priori and intuitive conditions for experience in the "Transcendental Aesthetic," but this in no way entails that space and time have nothing to do with the objects outside of possible experience") has been variously dubbed as "Neglected Alternative," "Trendelenburg's gap" [die trendelenburgische Lücke], "Pistorius's gap [die pistorische Lücke]" (named after Hermann Andreas Pistorius), or "third possibility" [die dritte Möglichkeit].[15]

Family edit

His son, Friedrich Trendelenburg, was a prominent surgeon; several medical techniques and matters are named for him.

Works (selection) edit

Trendelenburg was also the author of the following:[16]

  • Elementa Logices Aristotelicae (1836; 9th ed., 1892; Eng. trans. 1881), a selection of passages from the Organon with Latin translation and notes, containing the substance of Aristotle's logical doctrine, supplemented by Erlauterungen zu den Elementen der Aristotelischen Logik (1842; 3rd ed., 1876).
  • Logische Untersuchungen (Logical Investigations), 2 vols. (1840; 3rd ed. 1870), and Die logische Frage in Hegels System (1843), important factors in the reaction against Hegel.
  • Historische Beiträge zur Philosophie (1846–1867), in three volumes, the first of which (Geschichte der Kategorienlehre) contains a history of the doctrine of the Categories.
  • Geschichte der Kategorienlehre I: Aristotle Kategorienlehre; II: Die Kategorienlehre in der Geschichte der Philosophie (1846, reprint: Hildesheim, Olms, 1979).
  • Des Naturrecht aufdem Grunde der Ethik (1860).
  • Lücken im Völkerrecht (1870), a treatise on the defects of international law, occasioned by the war of 1870.
  • Kleine Schriften (1871), papers dealing with non-philosophical, chiefly national and educational subjects.
  • Zur Geschichte des Wortes Person, Kant-Studien, Bd. 13, Berlin 1908
  • Ethische Untersuchungen: Genetisch-kritische Fragmentedition. Edited by Christian Biehl. Exempla critica 5. De Gruyter, Berlin/Boston 2022

Translations edit

  • A Contribution to the History of the Word Person: A Posthumous Treatise, Open Court Pub. Co., 1910.
  • Outlines of Logic: An English Translation of Trendelenburg's Elementa, 1898.

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b Steven Rockefeller, John Dewey: Religious Faith and Democratic Humanism, Columbia University Press, 1994, p. 78: "[Morris's] studies with Trendelenburg left him with the lasting conviction that philosophy must be grounded in scientific methods of truth, but Trendelenburg guided him away from British empiricism to an Aristotelian idealism."
  2. ^ Beiser 2013, p. 17.
  3. ^ a b c Beiser 2013, p. 20.
  4. ^ Beiser 2013, p. 122.
  5. ^ Fugali, Edoardo (2009). "Toward the Rebirth of Aristotelian Psychology: Trendelenburg and Brentano". Psychology and Philosophy. Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind. Vol. 8. pp. 179–202. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-8582-6_10. ISBN 978-1-4020-8581-9.
  6. ^ "Frege's Technical Concepts", in Frege Synthesized: Essays on the Philosophical and Foundational Work of G. Frege, L. Haaparanta and J. Hintikka, Synthese Library, D. Reidel, 1986, pp. 253–295
  7. ^ Richard Purkarthofer, Traces of a Profound and Sober Thinker in Kierkegaard's Postscript. Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook, 2005, pp. 192–207
  8. ^ [1] Gabriel Ferreira, "Kierkegaard Descends to the Underworld: Some remarks on the Kierkegaardian appropriation of an argument by F. A. Trendelenburg". Cognitio, 2013, pp. 235-246
  9. ^ Joachim Wach, Die Typenlehre Trendelenburgs und ihr Einfluss auf Dilthey : eine philosophie- und geistesgeschichtliche Studie (1917)
  10. ^ Rudolf A. Makkreel, Dilthey: Philosopher of the Human Studies, Princeton University Press, 1975, p. 48.
  11. ^ Morris 1874, p. 289.
  12. ^ a b c d e f Chisholm 1911, p. 246.
  13. ^ Søren Kierkegaard's Journals and Papers, V A 98, 1844
  14. ^ "Book of Members, 1780–2010: Chapter T" (PDF). American Academy of Arts and Sciences. Retrieved 23 September 2016.
  15. ^ Andrew F. Specht, "Kant and the Neglected Alternative", December 2014, p. 4.
  16. ^ Chisholm 1911, pp. 246–247.

Attribution:

References edit

  • Frederick Beiser, Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg and Lotze, Oxford University Press, 2013 [Currently the most complete discussion of Trendelenburg's philosophy.]
  • Graham Bird, A Companion to Kant, John Wiley and Sons, 2009 p. 486ff has an article about Trendelenburg's dispute with Fisher over Kant's definition of space
  • Hermann Bonitz, Zur Erinnering an Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (Berlin, 1872)
  • Buchholtz, Georg (1904). Die ethischen Grundgedanken Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburgs. Blankenhain: Schlimper.
  • Ernst Bratuschek, Adolf Trendelenburg (Berlin, 1873) [The first complete intellectual biography of Trendelenburg.]
  • George Sylvester Morris, Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg (1874).
  • Paul Kleinert, Grabrede (Berlin, 1872)
  • Carl von Prantl, Gedächtnisrede (Munich, 1873)

External links edit

friedrich, adolf, trendelenburg, november, 1802, january, 1872, german, philosopher, philologist, born, 1802, november, 1802eutin, lübeck, holy, roman, empiredied24, january, 1872, 1872, aged, berlin, brandenburg, prussia, german, empireeducationuniversity, ki. Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg 30 November 1802 24 January 1872 was a German philosopher and philologist Friedrich Adolf TrendelenburgBorn 1802 11 30 30 November 1802Eutin Lubeck Holy Roman EmpireDied24 January 1872 1872 01 24 aged 69 Berlin Brandenburg Prussia German EmpireEducationUniversity of KielLeipzig UniversityUniversity of Berlin PhD 1826 Era19th century philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolGerman idealismAristotelianismAristotelian idealism 1 InstitutionsUniversity of BerlinThesisPlatonis de ideis et numeris doctrina ex Aristotele illustrata On Plato s Doctrine of Ideas and Numbers as Illustrated by Aristotle 1826 Academic advisorsKarl Leonhard Reinhold 2 August Boeckh 3 Friedrich Schleiermacher 3 Georg Ludwig Konig de Doctoral studentsRudolf Christoph EuckenFriedrich PaulsenOther notable studentsFranz BrentanoWilhelm DiltheyErnst LaasMain interestsLogic metaphysicsNotable ideasTrendelenburg s gap motion as the fundamental fact common to being and thoughtPutting the organic teleological view of the world on a modern foundation 4 Contents 1 Life 2 Teaching 3 Philosophical work 3 1 Defense of teleology 3 2 Fischer Trendelenburg debate 4 Family 5 Works selection 5 1 Translations 6 Notes 7 References 8 External linksLife editHe was born at Eutin near Lubeck He was placed in a gymnasium in Eutin which was under the direction of Georg Ludwig Konig de 11 a philologist influenced by Immanuel Kant He was educated at the universities of Kiel Leipzig Berlin He became more and more attracted to the study of Plato and Aristotle and his 1826 doctoral dissertation Platonis de ideis et numeris doctrina ex Aristotele illustrata On Plato s Doctrine of Ideas and Numbers as Illustrated by Aristotle was an attempt to reach through Aristotle s criticisms a more accurate knowledge of the Platonic philosophy 12 He declined the offer of a classical chair at Kiel and accepted a post as tutor to the son of an intimate friend of Karl vom Stein zum Altenstein the Prussian minister of education He held this position for seven years 1826 1833 occupying his leisure time with the preparation of a critical edition of Aristotle s De anima 1833 2nd ed by Christian Belger 1877 In 1833 Altenstein appointed Trendelenburg extraordinary professor in Berlin and four years later he was advanced to an ordinary professorship 12 Teaching editFor nearly 40 years he proved himself markedly successful as a teacher during the greater part of which time he had to examine in philosophy and pedagogics all candidates for the scholastic profession in Prussia His teaching method was highly regarded by Soren Kierkegaard who called him one of the most sober philosophical philologists I know 13 He was elected a Foreign Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences in 1861 14 Two of his prominent students were Franz Brentano and Wilhelm Dilthey Philosophical work editDefense of teleology edit Trendelenburg s philosophizing is conditioned throughout by his loving study of Plato and Aristotle whom he regards not as opponents but as building jointly on the broad basis of idealism His own standpoint may be called a modern version of Aristotelianism While denying the possibility of an absolute method and an absolute philosophy as contended for by Hegel and others Trendelenburg was emphatically an idealist in the ancient or Platonic sense his whole work was devoted to the demonstration of the ideal in the real But he maintained that the procedure of philosophy must be analytic rising from the particular facts to the universal in which we find them explained We divine the system of the whole from the part we know but the process of reconstruction must remain approximative Our position forbids the possibility of a final system Instead therefore of constantly beginning afresh in speculation it should be our duty to attach ourselves to what may be considered the permanent results of historic developments 12 The classical expression of these results Trendelenburg finds mainly in the Platonico Aristotelian system The philosophical question is stated thus How are thought and being united in knowledge How does thought get at being And how does being enter into thought Proceeding on the principle that like can only be known by like Trendelenburg next reaches a doctrine peculiar to himself though based upon Aristotle that plays a central part in his speculations Motion is the fundamental fact common to being and thought the actual motion of the external world has its counterpart in the constructive motion involved in every instance of perception or thought From motion he proceeds to deduce time space and the categories of mechanics and natural science These being thus derived are at once subjective and objective in their scope It is true that matter can never be completely resolved into motion but the irreducible remainder may be treated like Aristotle as an abstraction we asymptotically approach but never reach 12 The facts of existence however are not adequately explained by the mechanical categories The ultimate interpretation of the universe can only be found in the higher category of End or final cause Here Trendelenburg finds the dividing line between philosophical systems On the one side stand those that acknowledge none but efficient causes which make force prior to thought and explain the universe as it were a tergo from the back This may be called typically Democritism On the other side stands the organic or teleological view of the world which interprets the parts through the idea of the whole and sees in the efficient causes only the vehicle of ideal ends This may be called in a wide sense Platonism Systems like Spinozism which seem to form a third class neither sacrificing force to thought nor thought to force yet by their denial of final causes inevitably fall back into the Democritic or essentially materialistic standpoint leaving us with the great antagonism of the mechanical and the organic systems of philosophy The latter view which receives its first support in the facts of life or organic nature as such finds its culmination and ultimate verification in the ethical world which essentially consists in the realization of ends Trendelenburg s Naturrecht the right of nature may therefore be taken as in a manner the completion of his system his working out of the ideal as present in the real The ethical end is taken to be the idea of humanity not in the abstract as formulated by Immanuel Kant but in the context of the state and of history Law is treated throughout as the vehicle of ethical requirements In Trendelenburg s treatment of the state as the ethical organism in which the individual the potential man may be said first to emerge into actuality we may trace his nurture on the best ideas of Hellenic antiquity 12 Fischer Trendelenburg debate edit In 1865 he became involved in an acrimonious controversy on the interpretation of Kant s doctrine of space with Kuno Fischer whom he attacked in Kuno Fischer und sein Kant 1869 which drew forth the reply Anti Trendelenburg 1870 12 The controversy became known in the history of philosophy as the Fischer Trendelenburg debate Trendelenburg s position on the debate the position that Kant may establish that space and time are a priori and intuitive conditions for experience in the Transcendental Aesthetic but this in no way entails that space and time have nothing to do with the objects outside of possible experience has been variously dubbed as Neglected Alternative Trendelenburg s gap die trendelenburgische Lucke Pistorius s gap die pistorische Lucke named after Hermann Andreas Pistorius or third possibility die dritte Moglichkeit 15 Family editHis son Friedrich Trendelenburg was a prominent surgeon several medical techniques and matters are named for him Works selection editTrendelenburg was also the author of the following 16 Elementa Logices Aristotelicae 1836 9th ed 1892 Eng trans 1881 a selection of passages from the Organon with Latin translation and notes containing the substance of Aristotle s logical doctrine supplemented by Erlauterungen zu den Elementen der Aristotelischen Logik 1842 3rd ed 1876 Logische Untersuchungen Logical Investigations 2 vols 1840 3rd ed 1870 and Die logische Frage in Hegels System 1843 important factors in the reaction against Hegel Historische Beitrage zur Philosophie 1846 1867 in three volumes the first of which Geschichte der Kategorienlehre contains a history of the doctrine of the Categories Geschichte der Kategorienlehre I Aristotle Kategorienlehre II Die Kategorienlehre in der Geschichte der Philosophie 1846 reprint Hildesheim Olms 1979 Des Naturrecht aufdem Grunde der Ethik 1860 Lucken im Volkerrecht 1870 a treatise on the defects of international law occasioned by the war of 1870 Kleine Schriften 1871 papers dealing with non philosophical chiefly national and educational subjects Zur Geschichte des Wortes Person Kant Studien Bd 13 Berlin 1908 Ethische Untersuchungen Genetisch kritische Fragmentedition Edited by Christian Biehl Exempla critica 5 De Gruyter Berlin Boston 2022 Translations edit A Contribution to the History of the Word Person A Posthumous Treatise Open Court Pub Co 1910 Outlines of Logic An English Translation of Trendelenburg s Elementa 1898 Notes edit a b Steven Rockefeller John Dewey Religious Faith and Democratic Humanism Columbia University Press 1994 p 78 Morris s studies with Trendelenburg left him with the lasting conviction that philosophy must be grounded in scientific methods of truth but Trendelenburg guided him away from British empiricism to an Aristotelian idealism Beiser 2013 p 17 a b c Beiser 2013 p 20 Beiser 2013 p 122 Fugali Edoardo 2009 Toward the Rebirth of Aristotelian Psychology Trendelenburg and Brentano Psychology and Philosophy Studies in the History of Philosophy of Mind Vol 8 pp 179 202 doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 8582 6 10 ISBN 978 1 4020 8581 9 Frege s Technical Concepts in Frege Synthesized Essays on the Philosophical and Foundational Work of G Frege L Haaparanta and J Hintikka Synthese Library D Reidel 1986 pp 253 295 Richard Purkarthofer Traces of a Profound and Sober Thinker in Kierkegaard s Postscript Kierkegaard Studies Yearbook 2005 pp 192 207 1 Gabriel Ferreira Kierkegaard Descends to the Underworld Some remarks on the Kierkegaardian appropriation of an argument by F A Trendelenburg Cognitio 2013 pp 235 246 Joachim Wach Die Typenlehre Trendelenburgs und ihr Einfluss auf Dilthey eine philosophie und geistesgeschichtliche Studie 1917 Rudolf A Makkreel Dilthey Philosopher of the Human Studies Princeton University Press 1975 p 48 Morris 1874 p 289 a b c d e f Chisholm 1911 p 246 Soren Kierkegaard s Journals and Papers V A 98 1844 Book of Members 1780 2010 Chapter T PDF American Academy of Arts and Sciences Retrieved 23 September 2016 Andrew F Specht Kant and the Neglected Alternative December 2014 p 4 Chisholm 1911 pp 246 247 Attribution nbsp This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Trendelenburg Friedrich Adolf Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 27 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 246 247 References editFrederick Beiser Late German Idealism Trendelenburg and Lotze Oxford University Press 2013 Currently the most complete discussion of Trendelenburg s philosophy Graham Bird A Companion to Kant John Wiley and Sons 2009 p 486ff has an article about Trendelenburg s dispute with Fisher over Kant s definition of space Hermann Bonitz Zur Erinnering an Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg Berlin 1872 Buchholtz Georg 1904 Die ethischen Grundgedanken Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburgs Blankenhain Schlimper Ernst Bratuschek Adolf Trendelenburg Berlin 1873 The first complete intellectual biography of Trendelenburg George Sylvester Morris Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg 1874 Paul Kleinert Grabrede Berlin 1872 Carl von Prantl Gedachtnisrede Munich 1873 External links editFriedrich Adolf Trendelenburg at the Mathematics Genealogy Project Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Friedrich Adolf Trendelenburg amp oldid 1222035326 Fischer Trendelenburg debate, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.