fbpx
Wikipedia

Donkey sentence

In semantics, donkey sentences are sentences that contain a pronoun with clear meaning (it is semantically bound) but whose syntactic role in the sentence poses challenges to linguists.[a] Such sentences defy straightforward attempts to generate their formal language equivalents. The difficulty is with understanding how English speakers parse such sentences.[b]

Barker and Shan define a donkey pronoun as "a pronoun that lies outside the restrictor of a quantifier or the if-clause of a conditional, yet covaries with some quantificational element inside it, usually an indefinite."[3] The pronoun in question is sometimes termed a donkey pronoun or donkey anaphora.

The following sentences are examples of donkey sentences.

  • "Omne homo habens asinum videt illum." ("Every man who owns a donkey sees it") — Walter Burley (1328), De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior[4][5]
  • "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it."[6]
  • "Every police officer who arrested a murderer insulted him."

History edit

Walter Burley, a medieval scholastic philosopher, introduced donkey sentences in the context of the theory of suppositio, the medieval equivalent of reference theory.

Peter Geach reintroduced donkey sentences as a counterexample to Richard Montague's proposal for a generalized formal representation of quantification in natural language.[6] His example was reused by David Lewis (1975),[7] Gareth Evans (1977)[8] and many others, and is still quoted in recent publications.

Analysis of donkey sentences edit

The goal of Montague grammar is to show how sentences of a natural language (like English) could be translated into a formal logical language, and so would then be amenable to mathematical analysis. Following Russell, it is typical to translate indefinite noun phrases using an existential quantifier,[9] as in the following simple example from Burchardt et al:

"A woman smokes." is translated as  [10]

The prototypical donkey sentence, "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", requires careful consideration for adequate description (though reading "each" in place of "every" does simplify the formal analysis). The donkey pronoun in this case is the word it. Correctly translating this sentence will require using a universal quantifier for the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey", rather than the expected existential quantifier.

The naive first attempt at translation given below is not a well-formed sentence, since the variable   is left free in the predicate  .[11]

 

It may be attempted to extend the scope of the existential quantifier to bind the free instance of  , but it still does not give a correct translation.[11]

 

This translation is incorrect since it is already true if there exists any object that is not a donkey: Given any object to be substituted for  , substituting any non-donkey object for   makes the material conditional true (since its antecedent is false), and so existential clause is true for every choice of  .

A correct translation into first-order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be

 ,

indicating that indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers, and other times as universal quantifiers.[11]

There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences: they are grammatically correct, they are well-formed and meaningful, and their syntax is regular. However, it is difficult to explain how donkey sentences produce their semantic results, and how those results generalize consistently with all other language use. If such an analysis were successful, it might allow a computer program to accurately translate natural language forms into logical form.[12] It is unknown how natural language users are – apparently effortlessly – agreeing on the meaning of sentences such as the examples.[citation needed]

There may be several equivalent ways of describing this process. In fact, Hans Kamp (1981) and Irene Heim (1982) independently proposed very similar accounts in different terminology, which they called discourse representation theory (DRT) and file change semantics (FCS), respectively.

Theories of donkey anaphora edit

It is usual to distinguish two main kinds of theories about the semantics of donkey pronouns. The most classical proposals fall within the so-called description-theoretic approach, a label that is meant to encompass all the theories that treat the semantics of these pronouns as akin to, or derivative from, the semantics of definite descriptions. The second main family of proposals goes by the name dynamic theories, and they model donkey anaphora – and anaphora in general – on the assumption that the meaning of a sentence lies in its potential to change the context (understood as the information shared by the participants in a conversation).[13]

Description-theoretic approaches edit

Description-theoretic approaches are theories of donkey pronouns in which definite descriptions play an important role. They were pioneered by Gareth Evans's E-type approach,[8] which holds that donkey pronouns can be understood as referring terms whose reference is fixed by description.

For example, in "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.", the donkey pronoun "it" can be expanded as a definite description to yield "Every farmer who owns a donkey beats the donkey he/she owns." This expanded sentence can be interpreted along the lines of Russell's theory of descriptions.[14]

Later authors have attributed an even larger role to definite descriptions, to the point of arguing that donkey pronouns have the semantics,[15][16] and even the syntax,[17] of definite descriptions. Approaches of the latter kind are usually called D-type.

Discourse representation theory edit

Donkey sentences became a major force in advancing semantic research in the 1980s, with the introduction of discourse representation theory (DRT). During that time, an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences into first-order logic.

The solution that DRT provides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows: The common semantic function of non-anaphoric noun phrases is the introduction of a new discourse referent, which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions. No quantifiers are introduced into the representation, thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had.

Dynamic Predicate Logic edit

Dynamic Predicate Logic models pronouns as first-order logic variables, but allows quantifiers in a formula to bind variables in other formulae.[18]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Maier, Emar (20 Nov 2006). "Situations and Individuals by Paul D. Elbourne". LINGUIST List (review). 17 (3393).
  2. ^ Lewis, David (1998). Papers in Philosophical Logic (PDF). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. p. 3.[permanent dead link]
  3. ^ Barker, Chris; Shan, Chung-chieh (9 June 2008). "Donkey anaphora is in-scope binding". Semantics and Pragmatics. 1 (1): 1–46. doi:10.3765/sp.1.1. ISSN 1937-8912. Retrieved 29 December 2020.
  4. ^ Gualterus Burlaeus (1988). De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior. Meiner Verlag. ISBN 9783787307173.
  5. ^ Keith Allan (2010). Concise Encyclopedia of Semantics. Elsevier. ISBN 9780080959696.
  6. ^ a b Peter Geach (1962). Reference and Generality. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press – via philosophieweb0.001.free.fr/GeachRandG.pdf.
  7. ^ Lewis, David (1975). "Adverbs of quantification". In Keenan, Edward L. (ed.). Formal Semantics of Natural Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780511897696 – via users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LewisQA.pdf.
  8. ^ a b Evans, Gareth (September 1977). "Pronouns, Quantifiers and Relative Clauses (I)". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 7 (3): 467–536. doi:10.1080/00455091.1977.10717030. S2CID 146125231.
  9. ^ Heim, Irene (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases (PDF) (PhD). University of Massachusetts Amherst. pp. 11–12. Retrieved 29 December 2020.
  10. ^ Burchardt, Aljoscha; Walter, Stephan; Koller, Alexander; Kohlhase, Michael; Blackburn, Patrick; Bos, Johan. "Anaphoric Pronouns". Computational Semantics 11.1.1. Saarland University. Retrieved 29 December 2020.
  11. ^ a b c Burchardt, Aljoscha; Walter, Stephan; Koller, Alexander; Kohlhase, Michael; Blackburn, Patrick; Bos, Johan. "Donkey Sentences". Computational Semantics 11.1.2. Saarland University. Retrieved 29 December 2020.
  12. ^ Knott, Alistair (2000). "An Algorithmic Framework for Specifying the Semantics of Discourse Relations" (PDF). Computational Intelligence. 16 (4): 501–510. doi:10.1111/0824-7935.00123. S2CID 1295252.
  13. ^ Elbourne, Paul (2005). Situations and individuals. MIT Press. ISBN 9780262550611.
  14. ^ Partee, Barbara H. (18 March 2008). "Formal Semantics and Current Problems of Semantics, Lecture 6. Kamp-Heim I. Anaphora with Indefinite Antecedents; Donkey Anaphora" (PDF). RGGU: Formal Semantics and Anaphora. University of Massachusetts. p. 9. Retrieved 29 December 2020.
  15. ^ Cooper, Robin (1979). "The interpretation of pronouns". In Frank Heny; Helmut Schnelle (eds.). Syntax and Semantics 10: Selections from the third Gröningen roundtable. Academic Press. ISBN 012613510X.
  16. ^ Neale, Stephen (1990). Descriptions. The MIT Press. ISBN 0262640317.
  17. ^ Heim, Irene; Kratzer, Angelika (1998). Semantics in Generative Grammar. Blackwell. ISBN 0631197133.
  18. ^ Groenendijk, Jeroen; Stokhof, Martin (1991). "Dynamic Predicate Logic" (PDF). Linguistics and Philosophy. 14: 39–100. doi:10.1007/BF00628304. S2CID 62551132.

Further reading edit

  • Abbott, Barbara. 'Donkey Demonstratives'. Natural Language Semantics 10 (2002): 285–298.
  • Barker, Chris. 'Individuation and Quantification'. Linguistic Inquiry 30 (1999): 683–691.
  • Barker, Chris. 'Presuppositions for Proportional Quantifiers'. Natural Language Semantics 4 (1996): 237–259.
  • Brasoveanu, Adrian. Structured Nominal and Modal Reference. Rutgers University PhD dissertation, 2007.
  • Brasoveanu, Adrian. 'Uniqueness Effects in Donkey Sentences and Correlatives'.Sinn und Bedeutung 12 (2007):1.[c]
  • Burgess, John P. ' E Pluribus Unum: Plural Logic and Set Theory', Philosophia Mathematica 12 (2004): 193–221.
  • Cheng, Lisa LS and C.-T. James Huang. 'Two Types of Donkey Sentences'. Natural Language Semantics 4 (1996): 121–163.
  • Cohen, Ariel. Think Generic! Stanford, California: CSLI Publications, 1999.
  • Conway, L. and S. Crain. 'Donkey Anaphora in Child Grammar'. In Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society (NELS) 25. University of Massachusetts Amherst, 1995.
  • Evans, Gareth. 'Pronouns'. Linguistic Inquiry 11 (1980): 337–362.
  • Geurts, Bart. Presuppositions and Pronouns. Oxford: Elsevier, 1999.
  • Harman, Gilbert. 'Anaphoric Pronouns as Bound Variables: Syntax or Semantics?' Language 52 (1976): 78–81.
  • Heim, Irene. 'E-Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora'. Linguistics and Philosophy 13 (1990): 137–177.
  • Just, MA. 'Comprehending Quantified Sentences: The Relation between Sentencepicture and Semantic Memory Verification'. Cognitive Psychology 6 (1974): 216–236.
  • Just, MA and PA Carpenter. 'Comprehension of Negation with Quantification'. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 10 (1971): 244–253.
  • Kadmon, N. Formal Pragmatics: Semantics, Pragmatics, Presupposition, and Focus. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 2001.
  • Kamp, Hans and Reyle, U. From Discourse to Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1993.
  • Kanazawa, Makoto. 'Singular Donkey Pronouns Are Semantically Singular'. Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (2001): 383–403.
  • Kanazawa, Makoto. 'Weak vs. Strong Readings of Donkey Sentences and Monotonicity Inference in a Dynamic Setting'. Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (1994): 109–158.
  • Krifka, Manfred. 'Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences'. In Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 6. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University, 1996. Pages 136–153.
  • Lappin, Shalom. 'An Intensional Parametric Semantics for Vague Quantifiers'. Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (2000): 599–620.
  • Lappin, Shalom and Nissim Francez. 'E-type Pronouns, i-Sums, and Donkey Anaphora'. Linguistics and Philosophy 17 (1994): 391–428.
  • Lappin, Shalom. 'Donkey Pronouns Unbound'. Theoretical Linguistics 15 (1989): 263–286.
  • Lewis, David. Parts of Classes, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 1991.
  • Lewis, David. 'General Semantics'. Synthese 22 (1970): 18–27.
  • Moltmann, Friederike. 'Unbound Anaphoric Pronouns: E-Type, Dynamic and Structured Propositions Approaches'. Synthese 153 (2006): 199–260.
  • Moltmann, Friederike. 'Presuppositions and Quantifier Domains'. Synthese 149 (2006): 179–224.
  • Montague, Richard. 'Universal Grammar'. Theoria 26 (1970): 373–398.
  • Neale, Stephen. Descriptions. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990.
  • Neale, Stephen. 'Descriptive Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora'. Journal of Philosophy 87 (1990): 113–150.
  • Partee, Barbara H. 'Opacity, Coreference, and Pronouns'. Synthese 21 (1970): 359–385.
  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. Word and Object. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1970.
  • Rooij, Robert van. Journal of Semantics 23 (2006): 383–402.
  • Yoon, Y-E. Weak and Strong Interpretations of Quantifiers and Definite NPs in English and Korean. University of Texas at Austin PhD dissertation, 1994.

Notes edit

  1. ^ Emar Maier describes donkey pronouns as "bound but not c-commanded" in a Linguist List review of Paul D. Elbourne's Situations and Individuals (MIT Press, 2006).[1]
  2. ^ David Lewis describes this as his motivation for considering the issue in the introduction to Papers in Philosophical Logic, a collection of reprints of his articles. "There was no satisfactory way to assign relative scopes to quantifier phrases."[2]
  3. ^ In 2007, Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs in Hindi, and analysis of complex and modal versions of donkey pronouns in English.

External links edit

  • SEP Entry
  • Barker, Chris. 'A Presuppositional Account of Proportional Ambiguity'. In Proceedings of Semantic and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 3. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University, 1993. Pages 1–18.
  • Brasoveanu, Adrian. 'Donkey Pluralities: Plural Information States vs. Non-Atomic Individuals'. In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 11. Edited by E. Puig-Waldmüller. Barcelona: Pompeu Fabra University, 2007. Pages 106–120.
  • Evans, Gareth. 'Pronouns, Quantifiers, and Relative Clauses (I)'. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1977): 467–536.
  • Geurts, Bart. 'Donkey Business'. Linguistics and Philosophy 25 (2002): 129–156.
  • Huang, C-T James. 'Logical Form'. Chapter 3 in Government and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program: Principles and Parameters in Syntactic Theory edited by Gert Webelhuth. Oxford and Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing, 1995. Pages 127–177.
  • Kamp, Hans. 'A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation'. In J. Groenendijk and others (eds.). Formal Methods in the Study of Language. Amsterdam: Mathematics Center, 1981.
  • Kitagawa, Yoshihisa. 'Copying Variables'. Chapter 2 in Functional Structure(s), Form and Interpretation: Perspectives from East Asian Languages. Edited by Yen-hui Audrey Li and others. Routledge, 2003. Pages 28–64.
  • Lewis, David. 'Adverbs of Quantification'. In Formal Semantics of Natural Language. Edited by Edward L Keenan. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975. Pages 3–15.
  • Montague, Richard. 'The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English'. In KJJ Hintikka and others (eds). Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford Workshop on Grammar and Semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1973. Pages 212–242.

donkey, sentence, semantics, donkey, sentences, sentences, that, contain, pronoun, with, clear, meaning, semantically, bound, whose, syntactic, role, sentence, poses, challenges, linguists, such, sentences, defy, straightforward, attempts, generate, their, for. In semantics donkey sentences are sentences that contain a pronoun with clear meaning it is semantically bound but whose syntactic role in the sentence poses challenges to linguists a Such sentences defy straightforward attempts to generate their formal language equivalents The difficulty is with understanding how English speakers parse such sentences b Barker and Shan define a donkey pronoun as a pronoun that lies outside the restrictor of a quantifier or the if clause of a conditional yet covaries with some quantificational element inside it usually an indefinite 3 The pronoun in question is sometimes termed a donkey pronoun or donkey anaphora The following sentences are examples of donkey sentences Omne homo habens asinum videt illum Every man who owns a donkey sees it Walter Burley 1328 De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior 4 5 Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it 6 Every police officer who arrested a murderer insulted him Contents 1 History 2 Analysis of donkey sentences 3 Theories of donkey anaphora 3 1 Description theoretic approaches 3 2 Discourse representation theory 3 3 Dynamic Predicate Logic 4 See also 5 References 6 Further reading 7 Notes 8 External linksHistory editWalter Burley a medieval scholastic philosopher introduced donkey sentences in the context of the theory of suppositio the medieval equivalent of reference theory Peter Geach reintroduced donkey sentences as a counterexample to Richard Montague s proposal for a generalized formal representation of quantification in natural language 6 His example was reused by David Lewis 1975 7 Gareth Evans 1977 8 and many others and is still quoted in recent publications Analysis of donkey sentences editThe goal of Montague grammar is to show how sentences of a natural language like English could be translated into a formal logical language and so would then be amenable to mathematical analysis Following Russell it is typical to translate indefinite noun phrases using an existential quantifier 9 as in the following simple example from Burchardt et al A woman smokes is translated as x WOMAN x SMOKES x displaystyle exists x text WOMAN x land text SMOKES x nbsp 10 The prototypical donkey sentence Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it requires careful consideration for adequate description though reading each in place of every does simplify the formal analysis The donkey pronoun in this case is the word it Correctly translating this sentence will require using a universal quantifier for the indefinite noun phrase a donkey rather than the expected existential quantifier The naive first attempt at translation given below is not a well formed sentence since the variable y displaystyle y nbsp is left free in the predicate BEAT x y displaystyle text BEAT x y nbsp 11 x FARMER x y DONKEY y OWNS x y BEAT x y displaystyle forall x text FARMER x land exists y text DONKEY y land text OWNS x y rightarrow text BEAT x y nbsp It may be attempted to extend the scope of the existential quantifier to bind the free instance of y displaystyle y nbsp but it still does not give a correct translation 11 x y FARMER x DONKEY y OWNS x y BEAT x y displaystyle forall x exists y text FARMER x land text DONKEY y land text OWNS x y rightarrow text BEAT x y nbsp This translation is incorrect since it is already true if there exists any object that is not a donkey Given any object to be substituted for x displaystyle x nbsp substituting any non donkey object for y displaystyle y nbsp makes the material conditional true since its antecedent is false and so existential clause is true for every choice of x displaystyle x nbsp A correct translation into first order logic for the donkey sentence seems to be x y FARMER x DONKEY y OWNS x y BEAT x y displaystyle forall x forall y text FARMER x land text DONKEY y land text OWNS x y rightarrow text BEAT x y nbsp indicating that indefinites must sometimes be interpreted as existential quantifiers and other times as universal quantifiers 11 There is nothing wrong with donkey sentences they are grammatically correct they are well formed and meaningful and their syntax is regular However it is difficult to explain how donkey sentences produce their semantic results and how those results generalize consistently with all other language use If such an analysis were successful it might allow a computer program to accurately translate natural language forms into logical form 12 It is unknown how natural language users are apparently effortlessly agreeing on the meaning of sentences such as the examples citation needed There may be several equivalent ways of describing this process In fact Hans Kamp 1981 and Irene Heim 1982 independently proposed very similar accounts in different terminology which they called discourse representation theory DRT and file change semantics FCS respectively Theories of donkey anaphora editIt is usual to distinguish two main kinds of theories about the semantics of donkey pronouns The most classical proposals fall within the so called description theoretic approach a label that is meant to encompass all the theories that treat the semantics of these pronouns as akin to or derivative from the semantics of definite descriptions The second main family of proposals goes by the name dynamic theories and they model donkey anaphora and anaphora in general on the assumption that the meaning of a sentence lies in its potential to change the context understood as the information shared by the participants in a conversation 13 Description theoretic approaches edit This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it March 2020 Description theoretic approaches are theories of donkey pronouns in which definite descriptions play an important role They were pioneered by Gareth Evans s E type approach 8 which holds that donkey pronouns can be understood as referring terms whose reference is fixed by description For example in Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it the donkey pronoun it can be expanded as a definite description to yield Every farmer who owns a donkey beats the donkey he she owns This expanded sentence can be interpreted along the lines of Russell s theory of descriptions 14 Later authors have attributed an even larger role to definite descriptions to the point of arguing that donkey pronouns have the semantics 15 16 and even the syntax 17 of definite descriptions Approaches of the latter kind are usually called D type Discourse representation theory edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed January 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Donkey sentences became a major force in advancing semantic research in the 1980s with the introduction of discourse representation theory DRT During that time an effort was made to settle the inconsistencies which arose from the attempts to translate donkey sentences into first order logic The solution that DRT provides for the donkey sentence problem can be roughly outlined as follows The common semantic function of non anaphoric noun phrases is the introduction of a new discourse referent which is in turn available for the binding of anaphoric expressions No quantifiers are introduced into the representation thus overcoming the scope problem that the logical translations had Dynamic Predicate Logic edit This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it March 2020 Dynamic Predicate Logic models pronouns as first order logic variables but allows quantifiers in a formula to bind variables in other formulae 18 See also editEpsilon calculus Extension of a formal language by the epsilon operator Garden path sentence Sentence that starts in a way that a reader s likely interpretation will be wrong Generic antecedent Representatives of classes in a situation in which gender is typically unknown Lambda calculus Mathematical logic system based on functions Montague grammar Approach to natural language semantics Singular they Gender neutral English pronounReferences edit Maier Emar 20 Nov 2006 Situations and Individuals by Paul D Elbourne LINGUIST List review 17 3393 Lewis David 1998 Papers in Philosophical Logic PDF Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press p 3 permanent dead link Barker Chris Shan Chung chieh 9 June 2008 Donkey anaphora is in scope binding Semantics and Pragmatics 1 1 1 46 doi 10 3765 sp 1 1 ISSN 1937 8912 Retrieved 29 December 2020 Gualterus Burlaeus 1988 De puritate artis logicae tractatus longior Meiner Verlag ISBN 9783787307173 Keith Allan 2010 Concise Encyclopedia of Semantics Elsevier ISBN 9780080959696 a b Peter Geach 1962 Reference and Generality Ithaca and London Cornell University Press via philosophieweb0 001 free fr GeachRandG pdf Lewis David 1975 Adverbs of quantification In Keenan Edward L ed Formal Semantics of Natural Language Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780511897696 via users ox ac uk sfop0776 LewisQA pdf a b Evans Gareth September 1977 Pronouns Quantifiers and Relative Clauses I Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 3 467 536 doi 10 1080 00455091 1977 10717030 S2CID 146125231 Heim Irene 1982 The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases PDF PhD University of Massachusetts Amherst pp 11 12 Retrieved 29 December 2020 Burchardt Aljoscha Walter Stephan Koller Alexander Kohlhase Michael Blackburn Patrick Bos Johan Anaphoric Pronouns Computational Semantics 11 1 1 Saarland University Retrieved 29 December 2020 a b c Burchardt Aljoscha Walter Stephan Koller Alexander Kohlhase Michael Blackburn Patrick Bos Johan Donkey Sentences Computational Semantics 11 1 2 Saarland University Retrieved 29 December 2020 Knott Alistair 2000 An Algorithmic Framework for Specifying the Semantics of Discourse Relations PDF Computational Intelligence 16 4 501 510 doi 10 1111 0824 7935 00123 S2CID 1295252 Elbourne Paul 2005 Situations and individuals MIT Press ISBN 9780262550611 Partee Barbara H 18 March 2008 Formal Semantics and Current Problems of Semantics Lecture 6 Kamp Heim I Anaphora with Indefinite Antecedents Donkey Anaphora PDF RGGU Formal Semantics and Anaphora University of Massachusetts p 9 Retrieved 29 December 2020 Cooper Robin 1979 The interpretation of pronouns In Frank Heny Helmut Schnelle eds Syntax and Semantics 10 Selections from the third Groningen roundtable Academic Press ISBN 012613510X Neale Stephen 1990 Descriptions The MIT Press ISBN 0262640317 Heim Irene Kratzer Angelika 1998 Semantics in Generative Grammar Blackwell ISBN 0631197133 Groenendijk Jeroen Stokhof Martin 1991 Dynamic Predicate Logic PDF Linguistics and Philosophy 14 39 100 doi 10 1007 BF00628304 S2CID 62551132 Further reading editAbbott Barbara Donkey Demonstratives Natural Language Semantics 10 2002 285 298 Barker Chris Individuation and Quantification Linguistic Inquiry 30 1999 683 691 Barker Chris Presuppositions for Proportional Quantifiers Natural Language Semantics 4 1996 237 259 Brasoveanu Adrian Structured Nominal and Modal Reference Rutgers University PhD dissertation 2007 Brasoveanu Adrian Uniqueness Effects in Donkey Sentences and Correlatives Sinn und Bedeutung 12 2007 1 c Burgess John P E Pluribus Unum Plural Logic and Set Theory Philosophia Mathematica 12 2004 193 221 Cheng Lisa LS and C T James Huang Two Types of Donkey Sentences Natural Language Semantics 4 1996 121 163 Cohen Ariel Think Generic Stanford California CSLI Publications 1999 Conway L and S Crain Donkey Anaphora in Child Grammar In Proceedings of the North East Linguistics Society NELS 25 University of Massachusetts Amherst 1995 Evans Gareth Pronouns Linguistic Inquiry 11 1980 337 362 Geurts Bart Presuppositions and Pronouns Oxford Elsevier 1999 Harman Gilbert Anaphoric Pronouns as Bound Variables Syntax or Semantics Language 52 1976 78 81 Heim Irene E Type Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora Linguistics and Philosophy 13 1990 137 177 Just MA Comprehending Quantified Sentences The Relation between Sentencepicture and Semantic Memory Verification Cognitive Psychology 6 1974 216 236 Just MA and PA Carpenter Comprehension of Negation with Quantification Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior 10 1971 244 253 Kadmon N Formal Pragmatics Semantics Pragmatics Presupposition and Focus Oxford Blackwell Publishers 2001 Kamp Hans and Reyle U From Discourse to Logic Dordrecht Kluwer 1993 Kanazawa Makoto Singular Donkey Pronouns Are Semantically Singular Linguistics and Philosophy 24 2001 383 403 Kanazawa Makoto Weak vs Strong Readings of Donkey Sentences and Monotonicity Inference in a Dynamic Setting Linguistics and Philosophy 17 1994 109 158 Krifka Manfred Pragmatic Strengthening in Plural Predications and Donkey Sentences In Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory SALT 6 Ithaca New York Cornell University 1996 Pages 136 153 Lappin Shalom An Intensional Parametric Semantics for Vague Quantifiers Linguistics and Philosophy 23 2000 599 620 Lappin Shalom and Nissim Francez E type Pronouns i Sums and Donkey Anaphora Linguistics and Philosophy 17 1994 391 428 Lappin Shalom Donkey Pronouns Unbound Theoretical Linguistics 15 1989 263 286 Lewis David Parts of Classes Oxford Blackwell Publishing 1991 Lewis David General Semantics Synthese 22 1970 18 27 Moltmann Friederike Unbound Anaphoric Pronouns E Type Dynamic and Structured Propositions Approaches Synthese 153 2006 199 260 Moltmann Friederike Presuppositions and Quantifier Domains Synthese 149 2006 179 224 Montague Richard Universal Grammar Theoria 26 1970 373 398 Neale Stephen Descriptions Cambridge MIT Press 1990 Neale Stephen Descriptive Pronouns and Donkey Anaphora Journal of Philosophy 87 1990 113 150 Partee Barbara H Opacity Coreference and Pronouns Synthese 21 1970 359 385 Quine Willard Van Orman Word and Object Cambridge Massachusetts MIT Press 1970 Rooij Robert van Free Choice Counterfactual Donkeys Journal of Semantics 23 2006 383 402 Yoon Y E Weak and Strong Interpretations of Quantifiers and Definite NPs in English and Korean University of Texas at Austin PhD dissertation 1994 Notes edit Emar Maier describes donkey pronouns as bound but not c commanded in a Linguist List review of Paul D Elbourne s Situations and Individuals MIT Press 2006 1 David Lewis describes this as his motivation for considering the issue in the introduction to Papers in Philosophical Logic a collection of reprints of his articles There was no satisfactory way to assign relative scopes to quantifier phrases 2 In 2007 Adrian Brasoveanu published studies of donkey pronoun analogs in Hindi and analysis of complex and modal versions of donkey pronouns in English External links editThe Handbook of Philosophical Logic Discourse Representation Theory Introduction to Discourse Representation Theory SEP Entry Archive of CSI 5386 Donkey Sentence Discussion Barker Chris A Presuppositional Account of Proportional Ambiguity In Proceedings of Semantic and Linguistic Theory SALT 3 Ithaca New York Cornell University 1993 Pages 1 18 Brasoveanu Adrian Donkey Pluralities Plural Information States vs Non Atomic Individuals In Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 11 Edited by E Puig Waldmuller Barcelona Pompeu Fabra University 2007 Pages 106 120 Evans Gareth Pronouns Quantifiers and Relative Clauses I Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 1977 467 536 Geurts Bart Donkey Business Linguistics and Philosophy 25 2002 129 156 Huang C T James Logical Form Chapter 3 in Government and Binding Theory and the Minimalist Program Principles and Parameters in Syntactic Theory edited by Gert Webelhuth Oxford and Cambridge Blackwell Publishing 1995 Pages 127 177 Kamp Hans A Theory of Truth and Semantic Representation In J Groenendijk and others eds Formal Methods in the Study of Language Amsterdam Mathematics Center 1981 Kitagawa Yoshihisa Copying Variables Chapter 2 in Functional Structure s Form and Interpretation Perspectives from East Asian Languages Edited by Yen hui Audrey Li and others Routledge 2003 Pages 28 64 Lewis David Adverbs of Quantification In Formal Semantics of Natural Language Edited by Edward L Keenan Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1975 Pages 3 15 Montague Richard The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English In KJJ Hintikka and others eds Proceedings of the 1970 Stanford Workshop on Grammar and Semantics Dordrecht Reidel 1973 Pages 212 242 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Donkey sentence amp oldid 1213113326, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.