fbpx
Wikipedia

Anaphora (linguistics)

In linguistics, anaphora (/əˈnæfərə/) is the use of an expression whose interpretation depends upon another expression in context (its antecedent or postcedent). In a narrower sense, anaphora is the use of an expression that depends specifically upon an antecedent expression and thus is contrasted with cataphora, which is the use of an expression that depends upon a postcedent expression. The anaphoric (referring) term is called an anaphor. For example, in the sentence Sally arrived, but nobody saw her, the pronoun her is an anaphor, referring back to the antecedent Sally. In the sentence Before her arrival, nobody saw Sally, the pronoun her refers forward to the postcedent Sally, so her is now a cataphor (and an anaphor in the broader, but not the narrower, sense). Usually, an anaphoric expression is a pro-form or some other kind of deictic (contextually dependent) expression.[1] Both anaphora and cataphora are species of endophora, referring to something mentioned elsewhere in a dialog or text.

Anaphora is an important concept for different reasons and on different levels: first, anaphora indicates how discourse is constructed and maintained; second, anaphora binds different syntactical elements together at the level of the sentence; third, anaphora presents a challenge to natural language processing in computational linguistics, since the identification of the reference can be difficult; and fourth, anaphora partially reveals how language is understood and processed, which is relevant to fields of linguistics interested in cognitive psychology.[2]

Nomenclature and examples

The term anaphora is actually used in two ways.

In a broad sense, it denotes the act of referring. Any time a given expression (e.g. a pro-form) refers to another contextual entity, anaphora is present.

In a second, narrower sense, the term anaphora denotes the act of referring backwards in a dialog or text, such as referring to the left when an anaphor points to its left toward its antecedent in languages that are written from left to right. Etymologically, anaphora derives from Ancient Greek ἀναφορά (anaphorá, "a carrying back"), from ἀνά (aná, "up") + φέρω (phérō, "I carry"). In this narrow sense, anaphora stands in contrast to cataphora, which sees the act of referring forward in a dialog or text, or pointing to the right in languages that are written from left to right: Ancient Greek καταφορά (kataphorá, "a downward motion"), from κατά (katá, "downwards") + φέρω (phérō, "I carry"). A pro-form is a cataphor when it points to its right toward its postcedent. Both effects together are called either anaphora (broad sense) or less ambiguously, along with self-reference they comprise the category of endophora.[3]

Examples of anaphora (in the narrow sense) and cataphora are given next. Anaphors and cataphors appear in bold, and their antecedents and postcedents are underlined:

Anaphora (in the narrow sense, species of endophora)
a. Susan dropped the plate. It shattered loudly. – The pronoun it is an anaphor; it points to the left toward its antecedent the plate.
b. The music stopped, and that upset everyone. – The demonstrative pronoun that is an anaphor; it points to the left toward its antecedent The music stopped.
c. Fred was angry, and so was I. – The adverb so is an anaphor; it points to the left toward its antecedent angry.
d. If Sam buys a new bike, I shall do it as well. – The verb phrase do it is an anaphor; it points to the left toward its antecedent buys a new bike.
Cataphora (included in the broad sense of anaphora, species of endophora)
a. Because he was very cold, David put on his coat. – The pronoun he is a cataphor; it points to the right toward its postcedent David.
b. Although Sam might do so, I shall not buy a new bike. – The verb phrase do so is a cataphor; it points to the right toward its postcedent buy a new bike.
c. In their free time, the boys play video games. – The possessive adjective their is a cataphor; it points to the right toward its postcedent the boys.

A further distinction is drawn between endophoric and exophoric reference. Exophoric reference occurs when an expression, an exophor, refers to something that is not directly present in the linguistic context, but is rather present in the situational context. Deictic pro-forms are stereotypical exophors, e.g.

Exophora
a. This garden hose is better than that one. – The demonstrative adjectives this and that are exophors; they point to entities in the situational context.
b. Jerry is standing over there. – The adverb there is an exophor; it points to a location in the situational context.

Exophors cannot be anaphors as they do not substantially refer within the dialog or text, though there is a question of what portions of a conversation or document are accessed by a listener or reader with regard to whether all references to which a term points within that language stream are noticed (i.e., if you hear only a fragment of what someone says using the pronoun her, you might never discover who she is, though if you heard the rest of what the speaker was saying on the same occasion, you might discover who she is, either by anaphoric revelation or by exophoric implication because you realize who she must be according to what else is said about her even if her identity is not explicitly mentioned, as in the case of homophoric reference).

A listener might, for example, realize through listening to other clauses and sentences that she is a Queen because of some of her attributes or actions mentioned. But which queen? Homophoric reference occurs when a generic phrase obtains a specific meaning through knowledge of its context. For example, the referent of the phrase the Queen (using an emphatic definite article, not the less specific a Queen, but also not the more specific Queen Elizabeth) must be determined by the context of the utterance, which would identify the identity of the queen in question. Until further revealed by additional contextual words, gestures, images or other media, a listener would not even know what monarchy or historical period is being discussed, and even after hearing her name is Elizabeth does not know, even if an English-UK Queen Elizabeth becomes indicated, if this queen means Queen Elizabeth I or Queen Elizabeth II and must await further clues in additional communications. Similarly, in discussing 'The Mayor' (of a city), the Mayor's identity must be understood broadly through the context which the speech references as general 'object' of understanding; is a particular human person meant, a current or future or past office-holder, the office in a strict legal sense, or the office in a general sense which includes activities a mayor might conduct, might even be expected to conduct, while they may not be explicitly defined for this office.

In generative grammar

The term anaphor is used in a special way in the generative grammar tradition. Here it denotes what would normally be called a reflexive or reciprocal pronoun, such as himself or each other in English, and analogous forms in other languages. The use of the term anaphor in this narrow sense is unique to generative grammar, and in particular, to the traditional binding theory.[4] This theory investigates the syntactic relationship that can or must hold between a given pro-form and its antecedent (or postcedent). In this respect, anaphors (reflexive and reciprocal pronouns) behave very differently from, for instance, personal pronouns.[5]

Complement anaphora

In some cases, anaphora may refer not to its usual antecedent, but to its complement set. In the following example a, the anaphoric pronoun they refers to the children who are eating the ice-cream. Contrastingly, example b has they seeming to refer to the children who are not eating ice-cream:

a. Only a few of the children ate their ice-cream. They ate the strawberry flavor first. They meaning the children who ate ice-cream
b. Only a few of the children ate their ice-cream. They threw it around the room instead. They meaning either the children who did not eat ice-cream or perhaps the children who did not eat ice-cream and some of those who ate ice-cream but did not finish it or who threw around the ice-cream of those who did not eat it, or even all the children, those who ate ice-cream throwing around part of their ice-cream, the ice-cream of others, the same ice-cream which they may have eaten before or after throwing it, or perhaps only some of the children so that they does not mean to be all-inclusive[6]

In its narrower definition, an anaphoric pronoun must refer to some noun (phrase) that has already been introduced into the discourse. In complement anaphora cases, however, the anaphor refers to something that is not yet present in the discourse, since the pronoun's referent has not been formerly introduced, including the case of 'everything but' what has been introduced. The set of ice-cream-eating-children in example b is introduced into the discourse, but then the pronoun they refers to the set of non-ice-cream-eating-children, a set which has not been explicitly mentioned.[7]

Both semantic and pragmatics considerations attend this phenomenon, which following discourse representation theory since the early 1980s, such as work by Kamp (1981) and Heim (File Change Semantics, 1982), and generalized quantifier theory, such as work by Barwise and Cooper (1981), was studied in a series of psycholinguistic experiments in the early 1990s by Moxey and Sanford (1993) and Sanford et al. (1994).[6][8] In complement anaphora as in the case of the pronoun in example b, this anaphora refers to some sort of complement set (i.e. only to the set of non-ice-cream-eating-children) or to the maximal set (i.e. to all the children, both ice-cream-eating-children and non-ice-cream-eating-children) or some hybrid or variant set, including potentially one of those noted to the right of example b. The various possible referents in complement anaphora are discussed by Corblin (1996), Kibble (1997), and Nouwen (2003).[7] Resolving complement anaphora is of interest in shedding light on brain access to information, calculation, mental modeling, communication.[9][10]

Anaphora resolution – centering theory

There are many theories that attempt to prove how anaphors are related and trace back to their antecedents, with centering theory (Grosz, Joshi, and Weinstein 1983) being one of them. Taking the computational theory of mind view of language, centering theory gives a computational analysis of underlying antecedents. In their original theory, Grosz, Joshi, & Weinstein (1983) propose that some discourse entities in utterances are more "central" than others, and this degree of centrality imposes constraints on what can be the antecedent.

In the theory, there are different types of centers: forward facing, backwards facing, and preferred.

Forward facing centers

A ranked list of discourse entities in an utterance. The ranking is debated, some focusing on theta relations (Yıldırım et al. 2004) and some providing definitive lists.[example needed]

Backwards facing center

The highest ranked discourse entity in the previous utterance.[example needed]

Preferred center

The highest ranked discourse entity in the previous utterance realised in the current utterance.[example needed]

See also

  • Antecedent – Expression that gives its meaning to a pro-form in grammar
  • Binding – Distribution of anaphoric elements
  • Coreference – Two or more expressions in a text with the same referent
  • Donkey sentence – Sentence containing a pronoun with clear meaning but unclear syntactic role
  • Endophora – Expressions that derive their reference from something within the surrounding text
  • Exophora – Reference to something not in the immediate text
  • Generic antecedent – Representatives of classes in a situation in which gender is typically unknown
  • Logophoricity – Binding relation that may employ a morphologically different set of anaphoric forms
  • Modal subordination – A phenomenon sometimes viewed as modal or temporal anaphora
  • Pro-form – Word or form that substitutes for another word

Notes

  1. ^ Tognini-Bonelli (2001:70) writes that "an anaphor is a linguistic entity which indicates a referential tie to some other linguistic entity in the same text".
  2. ^ The four ways just listed in which anaphora is important for linguistics are from McEnery (2000:3).
  3. ^ Concerning the term endophora, see Bussmann et al. (1998:58f.).
  4. ^ The traditional binding theory is associated above all with Chomsky's analysis from the early 1980s (Chomsky 1981).
  5. ^ See Büring (2005) for an introduction to and discussion of anaphors (in the sense of generative grammar) in the traditional binding theory.
  6. ^ a b Nobuaki, Akagi; Ursini, Francesco-Alessio (2011). . Proceedings of Australasian Language Technology Association Workshop. pp. 131–139. Archived from the original on 4 March 2016. Retrieved 28 July 2015.
  7. ^ a b Nouwen, Rick (2003). "Complement Anaphora and Interpretation". Journal of Semantics. 20 (1): 73–113. doi:10.1093/jos/20.1.73.
  8. ^ Moxey, L; Sanford, A (1993). "Communicating quantities: A psychological perspective". Laurence Erlbaum Associates.
  9. ^ Kotek, Hadas. "Resolving Complement Anaphora" (PDF). SSN 1736-6305 Vol. 2. Proceedings of the Second Workshop on Anaphora Resolution (2008). Retrieved 28 July 2015.
  10. ^ Garnham, A (2001). Mental models and the interpretation of anaphora. Hove, UK: Psychology Press.

Literature

  • Büring, Daniel (2005). Binding theory. Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-81280-1.
  • Bussmann, H., G. Trauth, and K. Kazzazi 1998. Routledge dictionary of language and linguistics. Taylor and Francis.
  • Chomsky, N. 1981/1993. Lectures on government and binding: The Pisa lectures. Mouton de Gruyter.
  • Corblin, F. 1996. "Quantification et anaphore discursive: la reference aux comple-mentaires". Linguages. 123, 51–74.
  • Grosz, Barbara J.; Joshi, Aravind K.; and Weinstein, Scott (1983). "Providing a unified account of definite noun phrases in discourse". In Proceedings, 21st Annual Meeting of the Association of Computational Linguistics. 44–50.
  • Kibble, R. 1997. "Complement anaphora and dynamic binding". In Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory VII, ed. A. Lawson, 258–275. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University.
  • McEnery, T. 2000. Corpus-based and computational approaches to discourse anaphora. John Benjamins.
  • Moxey, L. and A. Sanford 1993. Communicating quantities: A psychological perspective. Laurence Erlbaum Associates.
  • Nouwen, R. 2003. "Complement anaphora and interpretation". Journal of Semantics, 20, 73–113.
  • Sanford, A., L. Moxey and K. Patterson 1994. "Psychological studies of quantifiers". Journal of Semantics 11, 153–170.
  • Schmolz, H. 2015. Anaphora Resolution and Text Retrieval. A Linguistic Analysis of Hypertexts. De Gruyter.
  • Tognini-Bonelli, E. 2001. Corpus linguistics at work. John Benjamins.
  • Yıldırım, Savaş & Kiliçaslan, Yilmaz & Erman Aykaç, R. 2004. A Computational Model for Anaphora Resolution in Turkish via Centering Theory: an Initial Approach. 124–128.

External links

anaphora, linguistics, other, uses, anaphora, linguistics, anaphora, expression, whose, interpretation, depends, upon, another, expression, context, antecedent, postcedent, narrower, sense, anaphora, expression, that, depends, specifically, upon, antecedent, e. For other uses see Anaphora In linguistics anaphora e ˈ n ae f er e is the use of an expression whose interpretation depends upon another expression in context its antecedent or postcedent In a narrower sense anaphora is the use of an expression that depends specifically upon an antecedent expression and thus is contrasted with cataphora which is the use of an expression that depends upon a postcedent expression The anaphoric referring term is called an anaphor For example in the sentence Sally arrived but nobody saw her the pronoun her is an anaphor referring back to the antecedent Sally In the sentence Before her arrival nobody saw Sally the pronoun her refers forward to the postcedent Sally so her is now a cataphor and an anaphor in the broader but not the narrower sense Usually an anaphoric expression is a pro form or some other kind of deictic contextually dependent expression 1 Both anaphora and cataphora are species of endophora referring to something mentioned elsewhere in a dialog or text Anaphora is an important concept for different reasons and on different levels first anaphora indicates how discourse is constructed and maintained second anaphora binds different syntactical elements together at the level of the sentence third anaphora presents a challenge to natural language processing in computational linguistics since the identification of the reference can be difficult and fourth anaphora partially reveals how language is understood and processed which is relevant to fields of linguistics interested in cognitive psychology 2 Contents 1 Nomenclature and examples 2 In generative grammar 3 Complement anaphora 4 Anaphora resolution centering theory 4 1 Forward facing centers 4 2 Backwards facing center 4 3 Preferred center 5 See also 6 Notes 7 Literature 8 External linksNomenclature and examples EditThe term anaphora is actually used in two ways In a broad sense it denotes the act of referring Any time a given expression e g a pro form refers to another contextual entity anaphora is present In a second narrower sense the term anaphora denotes the act of referring backwards in a dialog or text such as referring to the left when an anaphor points to its left toward its antecedent in languages that are written from left to right Etymologically anaphora derives from Ancient Greek ἀnafora anaphora a carrying back from ἀna ana up ferw pherō I carry In this narrow sense anaphora stands in contrast to cataphora which sees the act of referring forward in a dialog or text or pointing to the right in languages that are written from left to right Ancient Greek katafora kataphora a downward motion from kata kata downwards ferw pherō I carry A pro form is a cataphor when it points to its right toward its postcedent Both effects together are called either anaphora broad sense or less ambiguously along with self reference they comprise the category of endophora 3 Examples of anaphora in the narrow sense and cataphora are given next Anaphors and cataphors appear in bold and their antecedents and postcedents are underlined Anaphora in the narrow sense species of endophora dd a Susan dropped the plate It shattered loudly The pronoun it is an anaphor it points to the left toward its antecedent the plate dd b The music stopped and that upset everyone The demonstrative pronoun that is an anaphor it points to the left toward its antecedent The music stopped dd c Fred was angry and so was I The adverb so is an anaphor it points to the left toward its antecedent angry dd d If Sam buys a new bike I shall do it as well The verb phrase do it is an anaphor it points to the left toward its antecedent buys a new bike dd Cataphora included in the broad sense of anaphora species of endophora dd a Because he was very cold David put on his coat The pronoun he is a cataphor it points to the right toward its postcedent David dd b Although Sam might do so I shall not buy a new bike The verb phrase do so is a cataphor it points to the right toward its postcedent buy a new bike dd c In their free time the boys play video games The possessive adjective their is a cataphor it points to the right toward its postcedent the boys dd A further distinction is drawn between endophoric and exophoric reference Exophoric reference occurs when an expression an exophor refers to something that is not directly present in the linguistic context but is rather present in the situational context Deictic pro forms are stereotypical exophors e g Exophora dd a This garden hose is better than that one The demonstrative adjectives this and that are exophors they point to entities in the situational context dd b Jerry is standing over there The adverb there is an exophor it points to a location in the situational context dd Exophors cannot be anaphors as they do not substantially refer within the dialog or text though there is a question of what portions of a conversation or document are accessed by a listener or reader with regard to whether all references to which a term points within that language stream are noticed i e if you hear only a fragment of what someone says using the pronoun her you might never discover who she is though if you heard the rest of what the speaker was saying on the same occasion you might discover who she is either by anaphoric revelation or by exophoric implication because you realize who she must be according to what else is said about her even if her identity is not explicitly mentioned as in the case of homophoric reference A listener might for example realize through listening to other clauses and sentences that she is a Queen because of some of her attributes or actions mentioned But which queen Homophoric reference occurs when a generic phrase obtains a specific meaning through knowledge of its context For example the referent of the phrase the Queen using an emphatic definite article not the less specific a Queen but also not the more specific Queen Elizabeth must be determined by the context of the utterance which would identify the identity of the queen in question Until further revealed by additional contextual words gestures images or other media a listener would not even know what monarchy or historical period is being discussed and even after hearing her name is Elizabeth does not know even if an English UK Queen Elizabeth becomes indicated if this queen means Queen Elizabeth I or Queen Elizabeth II and must await further clues in additional communications Similarly in discussing The Mayor of a city the Mayor s identity must be understood broadly through the context which the speech references as general object of understanding is a particular human person meant a current or future or past office holder the office in a strict legal sense or the office in a general sense which includes activities a mayor might conduct might even be expected to conduct while they may not be explicitly defined for this office In generative grammar EditSee also Binding linguistics and Government and binding theory The term anaphor is used in a special way in the generative grammar tradition Here it denotes what would normally be called a reflexive or reciprocal pronoun such as himself or each other in English and analogous forms in other languages The use of the term anaphor in this narrow sense is unique to generative grammar and in particular to the traditional binding theory 4 This theory investigates the syntactic relationship that can or must hold between a given pro form and its antecedent or postcedent In this respect anaphors reflexive and reciprocal pronouns behave very differently from for instance personal pronouns 5 Complement anaphora EditIn some cases anaphora may refer not to its usual antecedent but to its complement set In the following example a the anaphoric pronoun they refers to the children who are eating the ice cream Contrastingly example b has they seeming to refer to the children who are not eating ice cream a Only a few of the children ate their ice cream They ate the strawberry flavor first They meaning the children who ate ice cream dd b Only a few of the children ate their ice cream They threw it around the room instead They meaning either the children who did not eat ice cream or perhaps the children who did not eat ice cream and some of those who ate ice cream but did not finish it or who threw around the ice cream of those who did not eat it or even all the children those who ate ice cream throwing around part of their ice cream the ice cream of others the same ice cream which they may have eaten before or after throwing it or perhaps only some of the children so that they does not mean to be all inclusive 6 dd In its narrower definition an anaphoric pronoun must refer to some noun phrase that has already been introduced into the discourse In complement anaphora cases however the anaphor refers to something that is not yet present in the discourse since the pronoun s referent has not been formerly introduced including the case of everything but what has been introduced The set of ice cream eating children in example b is introduced into the discourse but then the pronoun they refers to the set of non ice cream eating children a set which has not been explicitly mentioned 7 Both semantic and pragmatics considerations attend this phenomenon which following discourse representation theory since the early 1980s such as work by Kamp 1981 and Heim File Change Semantics 1982 and generalized quantifier theory such as work by Barwise and Cooper 1981 was studied in a series of psycholinguistic experiments in the early 1990s by Moxey and Sanford 1993 and Sanford et al 1994 6 8 In complement anaphora as in the case of the pronoun in example b this anaphora refers to some sort of complement set i e only to the set of non ice cream eating children or to the maximal set i e to all the children both ice cream eating children and non ice cream eating children or some hybrid or variant set including potentially one of those noted to the right of example b The various possible referents in complement anaphora are discussed by Corblin 1996 Kibble 1997 and Nouwen 2003 7 Resolving complement anaphora is of interest in shedding light on brain access to information calculation mental modeling communication 9 10 Anaphora resolution centering theory EditThere are many theories that attempt to prove how anaphors are related and trace back to their antecedents with centering theory Grosz Joshi and Weinstein 1983 being one of them Taking the computational theory of mind view of language centering theory gives a computational analysis of underlying antecedents In their original theory Grosz Joshi amp Weinstein 1983 propose that some discourse entities in utterances are more central than others and this degree of centrality imposes constraints on what can be the antecedent In the theory there are different types of centers forward facing backwards facing and preferred Forward facing centers Edit A ranked list of discourse entities in an utterance The ranking is debated some focusing on theta relations Yildirim et al 2004 and some providing definitive lists example needed Backwards facing center Edit The highest ranked discourse entity in the previous utterance example needed Preferred center Edit The highest ranked discourse entity in the previous utterance realised in the current utterance example needed See also EditAntecedent Expression that gives its meaning to a pro form in grammar Binding Distribution of anaphoric elements Coreference Two or more expressions in a text with the same referent Donkey sentence Sentence containing a pronoun with clear meaning but unclear syntactic role Endophora Expressions that derive their reference from something within the surrounding text Exophora Reference to something not in the immediate text Generic antecedent Representatives of classes in a situation in which gender is typically unknown Logophoricity Binding relation that may employ a morphologically different set of anaphoric forms Modal subordination A phenomenon sometimes viewed as modal or temporal anaphora Pro form Word or form that substitutes for another wordNotes Edit Tognini Bonelli 2001 70 writes that an anaphor is a linguistic entity which indicates a referential tie to some other linguistic entity in the same text The four ways just listed in which anaphora is important for linguistics are from McEnery 2000 3 Concerning the term endophora see Bussmann et al 1998 58f The traditional binding theory is associated above all with Chomsky s analysis from the early 1980s Chomsky 1981 See Buring 2005 for an introduction to and discussion of anaphors in the sense of generative grammar in the traditional binding theory a b Nobuaki Akagi Ursini Francesco Alessio 2011 The Interpretation of Complement Anaphora The Case ofThe Others Proceedings of Australasian Language Technology Association Workshop pp 131 139 Archived from the original on 4 March 2016 Retrieved 28 July 2015 a b Nouwen Rick 2003 Complement Anaphora and Interpretation Journal of Semantics 20 1 73 113 doi 10 1093 jos 20 1 73 Moxey L Sanford A 1993 Communicating quantities A psychological perspective Laurence Erlbaum Associates Kotek Hadas Resolving Complement Anaphora PDF SSN 1736 6305 Vol 2 Proceedings of the Second Workshop on Anaphora Resolution 2008 Retrieved 28 July 2015 Garnham A 2001 Mental models and the interpretation of anaphora Hove UK Psychology Press Literature EditBuring Daniel 2005 Binding theory Cambridge Textbooks in Linguistics Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 81280 1 Bussmann H G Trauth and K Kazzazi 1998 Routledge dictionary of language and linguistics Taylor and Francis Chomsky N 1981 1993 Lectures on government and binding The Pisa lectures Mouton de Gruyter Corblin F 1996 Quantification et anaphore discursive la reference aux comple mentaires Linguages 123 51 74 Grosz Barbara J Joshi Aravind K and Weinstein Scott 1983 Providing a unified account of definite noun phrases in discourse In Proceedings 21st Annual Meeting of the Association of Computational Linguistics 44 50 Kibble R 1997 Complement anaphora and dynamic binding In Proceedings from Semantics and Linguistic Theory VII ed A Lawson 258 275 Ithaca New York Cornell University McEnery T 2000 Corpus based and computational approaches to discourse anaphora John Benjamins Moxey L and A Sanford 1993 Communicating quantities A psychological perspective Laurence Erlbaum Associates Nouwen R 2003 Complement anaphora and interpretation Journal of Semantics 20 73 113 Sanford A L Moxey and K Patterson 1994 Psychological studies of quantifiers Journal of Semantics 11 153 170 Schmolz H 2015 Anaphora Resolution and Text Retrieval A Linguistic Analysis of Hypertexts De Gruyter Tognini Bonelli E 2001 Corpus linguistics at work John Benjamins Yildirim Savas amp Kilicaslan Yilmaz amp Erman Aykac R 2004 A Computational Model for Anaphora Resolution in Turkish via Centering Theory an Initial Approach 124 128 External links EditKing Jeffrey C Anaphora In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy What is anaphora Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Anaphora linguistics amp oldid 1133072769, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.