fbpx
Wikipedia

ω-consistent theory

In mathematical logic, an ω-consistent (or omega-consistent, also called numerically segregative)[1] theory is a theory (collection of sentences) that is not only (syntactically) consistent[2] (that is, does not prove a contradiction), but also avoids proving certain infinite combinations of sentences that are intuitively contradictory. The name is due to Kurt Gödel, who introduced the concept in the course of proving the incompleteness theorem.[3]

Definition edit

A theory T is said to interpret the language of arithmetic if there is a translation of formulas of arithmetic into the language of T so that T is able to prove the basic axioms of the natural numbers under this translation.

A T that interprets arithmetic is ω-inconsistent if, for some property P of natural numbers (defined by a formula in the language of T), T proves P(0), P(1), P(2), and so on (that is, for every standard natural number n, T proves that P(n) holds), but T also proves that there is some natural number n such that P(n) fails.[2] This may not generate a contradiction within T because T may not be able to prove for any specific value of n that P(n) fails, only that there is such an n. In particular, such n is necessarily a nonstandard integer in any model for T (Quine has thus called such theories "numerically insegregative").[4]

T is ω-consistent if it is not ω-inconsistent.

There is a weaker but closely related property of Σ1-soundness. A theory T is Σ1-sound (or 1-consistent, in another terminology)[5] if every Σ01-sentence[6] provable in T is true in the standard model of arithmetic N (i.e., the structure of the usual natural numbers with addition and multiplication). If T is strong enough to formalize a reasonable model of computation, Σ1-soundness is equivalent to demanding that whenever T proves that a Turing machine C halts, then C actually halts. Every ω-consistent theory is Σ1-sound, but not vice versa.

More generally, we can define an analogous concept for higher levels of the arithmetical hierarchy. If Γ is a set of arithmetical sentences (typically Σ0n for some n), a theory T is Γ-sound if every Γ-sentence provable in T is true in the standard model. When Γ is the set of all arithmetical formulas, Γ-soundness is called just (arithmetical) soundness. If the language of T consists only of the language of arithmetic (as opposed to, for example, set theory), then a sound system is one whose model can be thought of as the set ω, the usual set of mathematical natural numbers. The case of general T is different, see ω-logic below.

Σn-soundness has the following computational interpretation: if the theory proves that a program C using a Σn−1-oracle halts, then C actually halts.

Examples edit

Consistent, ω-inconsistent theories edit

Write PA for the theory Peano arithmetic, and Con(PA) for the statement of arithmetic that formalizes the claim "PA is consistent". Con(PA) could be of the form "No natural number n is the Gödel number of a proof in PA that 0=1".[7] Now, the consistency of PA implies the consistency of PA + ¬Con(PA). Indeed, if PA + ¬Con(PA) was inconsistent, then PA alone would prove ¬Con(PA)→0=1, and a reductio ad absurdum in PA would produce a proof of Con(PA). By Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, PA would be inconsistent.

Therefore, assuming that PA is consistent, PA + ¬Con(PA) is consistent too. However, it would not be ω-consistent. This is because, for any particular n, PA, and hence PA + ¬Con(PA), proves that n is not the Gödel number of a proof that 0=1. However, PA + ¬Con(PA) proves that, for some natural number n, n is the Gödel number of such a proof (this is just a direct restatement of the claim ¬Con(PA)).

In this example, the axiom ¬Con(PA) is Σ1, hence the system PA + ¬Con(PA) is in fact Σ1-unsound, not just ω-inconsistent.

Arithmetically sound, ω-inconsistent theories edit

Let T be PA together with the axioms c ≠ n for each natural number n, where c is a new constant added to the language. Then T is arithmetically sound (as any nonstandard model of PA can be expanded to a model of T), but ω-inconsistent (as it proves  , and c ≠ n for every number n).

Σ1-sound ω-inconsistent theories using only the language of arithmetic can be constructed as follows. Let IΣn be the subtheory of PA with the induction schema restricted to Σn-formulas, for any n > 0. The theory IΣn + 1 is finitely axiomatizable, let thus A be its single axiom, and consider the theory T = IΣn + ¬A. We can assume that A is an instance of the induction schema, which has the form

 

If we denote the formula

 

by P(n), then for every natural number n, the theory T (actually, even the pure predicate calculus) proves P(n). On the other hand, T proves the formula  , because it is logically equivalent to the axiom ¬A. Therefore, T is ω-inconsistent.

It is possible to show that T is Πn + 3-sound. In fact, it is Πn + 3-conservative over the (obviously sound) theory IΣn. The argument is more complicated (it relies on the provability of the Σn + 2-reflection principle for IΣn in IΣn + 1).

Arithmetically unsound, ω-consistent theories edit

Let ω-Con(PA) be the arithmetical sentence formalizing the statement "PA is ω-consistent". Then the theory PA + ¬ω-Con(PA) is unsound (Σ3-unsound, to be precise), but ω-consistent. The argument is similar to the first example: a suitable version of the HilbertBernaysLöb derivability conditions holds for the "provability predicate" ω-Prov(A) = ¬ω-Con(PA + ¬A), hence it satisfies an analogue of Gödel's second incompleteness theorem.

ω-logic edit

The concept of theories of arithmetic whose integers are the true mathematical integers is captured by ω-logic.[8] Let T be a theory in a countable language that includes a unary predicate symbol N intended to hold just of the natural numbers, as well as specified names 0, 1, 2, ..., one for each (standard) natural number (which may be separate constants, or constant terms such as 0, 1, 1+1, 1+1+1, ..., etc.). Note that T itself could be referring to more general objects, such as real numbers or sets; thus in a model of T the objects satisfying N(x) are those that T interprets as natural numbers, not all of which need be named by one of the specified names.

The system of ω-logic includes all axioms and rules of the usual first-order predicate logic, together with, for each T-formula P(x) with a specified free variable x, an infinitary ω-rule of the form:

From   infer  .

That is, if the theory asserts (i.e. proves) P(n) separately for each natural number n given by its specified name, then it also asserts P collectively for all natural numbers at once via the evident finite universally quantified counterpart of the infinitely many antecedents of the rule. For a theory of arithmetic, meaning one with intended domain the natural numbers such as Peano arithmetic, the predicate N is redundant and may be omitted from the language, with the consequent of the rule for each P simplifying to  .

An ω-model of T is a model of T whose domain includes the natural numbers and whose specified names and symbol N are standardly interpreted, respectively as those numbers and the predicate having just those numbers as its domain (whence there are no nonstandard numbers). If N is absent from the language then what would have been the domain of N is required to be that of the model, i.e. the model contains only the natural numbers. (Other models of T may interpret these symbols nonstandardly; the domain of N need not even be countable, for example.) These requirements make the ω-rule sound in every ω-model. As a corollary to the omitting types theorem, the converse also holds: the theory T has an ω-model if and only if it is consistent in ω-logic.

There is a close connection of ω-logic to ω-consistency. A theory consistent in ω-logic is also ω-consistent (and arithmetically sound). The converse is false, as consistency in ω-logic is a much stronger notion than ω-consistency. However, the following characterization holds: a theory is ω-consistent if and only if its closure under unnested applications of the ω-rule is consistent.

Relation to other consistency principles edit

If the theory T is recursively axiomatizable, ω-consistency has the following characterization, due to Craig Smoryński:[9]

T is ω-consistent if and only if   is consistent.

Here,   is the set of all Π02-sentences valid in the standard model of arithmetic, and   is the uniform reflection principle for T, which consists of the axioms

 

for every formula   with one free variable. In particular, a finitely axiomatizable theory T in the language of arithmetic is ω-consistent if and only if T + PA is  -sound.

Notes edit

  1. ^ W. V. O. Quine (1971), Set Theory and Its Logic.
  2. ^ a b S. C. Kleene, Introduction to Metamathematics (1971), p.207. Bibliotheca Mathematica: A Series of Monographs on Pure and Applied Mathematics Vol. I, Wolters-Noordhoff, North-Holland 0-7204-2103-9, Elsevier 0-444-10088-1.
  3. ^ Smorynski, "The incompleteness theorems", Handbook of Mathematical Logic, 1977, p. 851.
  4. ^ Floyd, Putnam, A Note on Wittgenstein's "Notorious Paragraph" about the Gödel Theorem (2000)
  5. ^ H. Friedman, "Adventures in Gödel Incompleteness" (2023), p.14. Accessed 12 September 2023.
  6. ^ The definition of this symbolism can be found at arithmetical hierarchy.
  7. ^ This formulation uses 0=1 instead of a direct contradiction; that gives the same result, because PA certainly proves ¬0=1, so if it proved 0=1 as well we would have a contradiction, and on the other hand, if PA proves a contradiction, then it proves anything, including 0=1.
  8. ^ J. Barwise (ed.), Handbook of Mathematical Logic, North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1977.
  9. ^ Smoryński, Craig (1985). Self-reference and modal logic. Berlin: Springer. ISBN 978-0-387-96209-2. Reviewed in Boolos, G.; Smorynski, C. (1988). "Self-Reference and Modal Logic". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 53: 306. doi:10.2307/2274450. JSTOR 2274450.

Bibliography edit

consistent, theory, mathematical, logic, consistent, omega, consistent, also, called, numerically, segregative, theory, theory, collection, sentences, that, only, syntactically, consistent, that, does, prove, contradiction, also, avoids, proving, certain, infi. In mathematical logic an w consistent or omega consistent also called numerically segregative 1 theory is a theory collection of sentences that is not only syntactically consistent 2 that is does not prove a contradiction but also avoids proving certain infinite combinations of sentences that are intuitively contradictory The name is due to Kurt Godel who introduced the concept in the course of proving the incompleteness theorem 3 Contents 1 Definition 2 Examples 2 1 Consistent w inconsistent theories 2 2 Arithmetically sound w inconsistent theories 2 3 Arithmetically unsound w consistent theories 3 w logic 4 Relation to other consistency principles 5 Notes 6 BibliographyDefinition editA theory T is said to interpret the language of arithmetic if there is a translation of formulas of arithmetic into the language of T so that T is able to prove the basic axioms of the natural numbers under this translation A T that interprets arithmetic is w inconsistent if for some property P of natural numbers defined by a formula in the language of T T proves P 0 P 1 P 2 and so on that is for every standard natural number n T proves that P n holds but T also proves that there is some natural number n such that P n fails 2 This may not generate a contradiction within T because T may not be able to prove for any specific value of n that P n fails only that there is such an n In particular such n is necessarily a nonstandard integer in any model for T Quine has thus called such theories numerically insegregative 4 T is w consistent if it is not w inconsistent There is a weaker but closely related property of S1 soundness A theory T is S1 sound or 1 consistent in another terminology 5 if every S01 sentence 6 provable in T is true in the standard model of arithmetic N i e the structure of the usual natural numbers with addition and multiplication If T is strong enough to formalize a reasonable model of computation S1 soundness is equivalent to demanding that whenever T proves that a Turing machine C halts then C actually halts Every w consistent theory is S1 sound but not vice versa More generally we can define an analogous concept for higher levels of the arithmetical hierarchy If G is a set of arithmetical sentences typically S0n for some n a theory T is G sound if every G sentence provable in T is true in the standard model When G is the set of all arithmetical formulas G soundness is called just arithmetical soundness If the language of T consists only of the language of arithmetic as opposed to for example set theory then a sound system is one whose model can be thought of as the set w the usual set of mathematical natural numbers The case of general T is different see w logic below Sn soundness has the following computational interpretation if the theory proves that a program C using a Sn 1 oracle halts then C actually halts Examples editConsistent w inconsistent theories edit Write PA for the theory Peano arithmetic and Con PA for the statement of arithmetic that formalizes the claim PA is consistent Con PA could be of the form No natural number n is the Godel number of a proof in PA that 0 1 7 Now the consistency of PA implies the consistency of PA Con PA Indeed if PA Con PA was inconsistent then PA alone would prove Con PA 0 1 and a reductio ad absurdum in PA would produce a proof of Con PA By Godel s second incompleteness theorem PA would be inconsistent Therefore assuming that PA is consistent PA Con PA is consistent too However it would not be w consistent This is because for any particular n PA and hence PA Con PA proves that n is not the Godel number of a proof that 0 1 However PA Con PA proves that for some natural number n n is the Godel number of such a proof this is just a direct restatement of the claim Con PA In this example the axiom Con PA is S1 hence the system PA Con PA is in fact S1 unsound not just w inconsistent Arithmetically sound w inconsistent theories edit Let T be PA together with the axioms c n for each natural number n where c is a new constant added to the language Then T is arithmetically sound as any nonstandard model of PA can be expanded to a model of T but w inconsistent as it proves x c x displaystyle exists x c x nbsp and c n for every number n S1 sound w inconsistent theories using only the language of arithmetic can be constructed as follows Let ISn be the subtheory of PA with the induction schema restricted to Sn formulas for any n gt 0 The theory ISn 1 is finitely axiomatizable let thus A be its single axiom and consider the theory T ISn A We can assume that A is an instance of the induction schema which has the form w B 0 w x B x w B x 1 w x B x w displaystyle forall w B 0 w land forall x B x w to B x 1 w to forall x B x w nbsp dd If we denote the formula w B 0 w x B x w B x 1 w B n w displaystyle forall w B 0 w land forall x B x w to B x 1 w to B n w nbsp dd by P n then for every natural number n the theory T actually even the pure predicate calculus proves P n On the other hand T proves the formula x P x displaystyle exists x neg P x nbsp because it is logically equivalent to the axiom A Therefore T is w inconsistent It is possible to show that T is Pn 3 sound In fact it is Pn 3 conservative over the obviously sound theory ISn The argument is more complicated it relies on the provability of the Sn 2 reflection principle for ISn in ISn 1 Arithmetically unsound w consistent theories edit Let w Con PA be the arithmetical sentence formalizing the statement PA is w consistent Then the theory PA w Con PA is unsound S3 unsound to be precise but w consistent The argument is similar to the first example a suitable version of the Hilbert Bernays Lob derivability conditions holds for the provability predicate w Prov A w Con PA A hence it satisfies an analogue of Godel s second incompleteness theorem w logic editNot to be confused with W logic The concept of theories of arithmetic whose integers are the true mathematical integers is captured by w logic 8 Let T be a theory in a countable language that includes a unary predicate symbol N intended to hold just of the natural numbers as well as specified names 0 1 2 one for each standard natural number which may be separate constants or constant terms such as 0 1 1 1 1 1 1 etc Note that T itself could be referring to more general objects such as real numbers or sets thus in a model of T the objects satisfying N x are those that T interprets as natural numbers not all of which need be named by one of the specified names The system of w logic includes all axioms and rules of the usual first order predicate logic together with for each T formula P x with a specified free variable x an infinitary w rule of the form From P 0 P 1 P 2 displaystyle P 0 P 1 P 2 ldots nbsp infer x N x P x displaystyle forall x N x to P x nbsp That is if the theory asserts i e proves P n separately for each natural number n given by its specified name then it also asserts P collectively for all natural numbers at once via the evident finite universally quantified counterpart of the infinitely many antecedents of the rule For a theory of arithmetic meaning one with intended domain the natural numbers such as Peano arithmetic the predicate N is redundant and may be omitted from the language with the consequent of the rule for each P simplifying to x P x displaystyle forall x P x nbsp An w model of T is a model of T whose domain includes the natural numbers and whose specified names and symbol N are standardly interpreted respectively as those numbers and the predicate having just those numbers as its domain whence there are no nonstandard numbers If N is absent from the language then what would have been the domain of N is required to be that of the model i e the model contains only the natural numbers Other models of T may interpret these symbols nonstandardly the domain of N need not even be countable for example These requirements make the w rule sound in every w model As a corollary to the omitting types theorem the converse also holds the theory T has an w model if and only if it is consistent in w logic There is a close connection of w logic to w consistency A theory consistent in w logic is also w consistent and arithmetically sound The converse is false as consistency in w logic is a much stronger notion than w consistency However the following characterization holds a theory is w consistent if and only if its closure under unnested applications of the w rule is consistent Relation to other consistency principles editIf the theory T is recursively axiomatizable w consistency has the following characterization due to Craig Smorynski 9 T is w consistent if and only if T R F N T T h P 2 0 N displaystyle T mathrm RFN T mathrm Th Pi 2 0 mathbb N nbsp is consistent Here T h P 2 0 N displaystyle mathrm Th Pi 2 0 mathbb N nbsp is the set of all P02 sentences valid in the standard model of arithmetic and R F N T displaystyle mathrm RFN T nbsp is the uniform reflection principle for T which consists of the axioms x P r o v T f x f x displaystyle forall x mathrm Prov T ulcorner varphi dot x urcorner to varphi x nbsp for every formula f displaystyle varphi nbsp with one free variable In particular a finitely axiomatizable theory T in the language of arithmetic is w consistent if and only if T PA is S 2 0 displaystyle Sigma 2 0 nbsp sound Notes edit W V O Quine 1971 Set Theory and Its Logic a b S C Kleene Introduction to Metamathematics 1971 p 207 Bibliotheca Mathematica A Series of Monographs on Pure and Applied Mathematics Vol I Wolters Noordhoff North Holland 0 7204 2103 9 Elsevier 0 444 10088 1 Smorynski The incompleteness theorems Handbook of Mathematical Logic 1977 p 851 Floyd Putnam A Note on Wittgenstein s Notorious Paragraph about the Godel Theorem 2000 H Friedman Adventures in Godel Incompleteness 2023 p 14 Accessed 12 September 2023 The definition of this symbolism can be found at arithmetical hierarchy This formulation uses 0 1 instead of a direct contradiction that gives the same result because PA certainly proves 0 1 so if it proved 0 1 as well we would have a contradiction and on the other hand if PA proves a contradiction then it proves anything including 0 1 J Barwise ed Handbook of Mathematical Logic North Holland Amsterdam 1977 Smorynski Craig 1985 Self reference and modal logic Berlin Springer ISBN 978 0 387 96209 2 Reviewed in Boolos G Smorynski C 1988 Self Reference and Modal Logic The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 306 doi 10 2307 2274450 JSTOR 2274450 Bibliography editKurt Godel 1931 Uber formal unentscheidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica und verwandter Systeme I In Monatshefte fur Mathematik Translated into English as On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related Systems Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title W consistent theory amp oldid 1200879833, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.