fbpx
Wikipedia

Bell's theorem

Bell's theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics, all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden-variable theories, given some basic assumptions about the nature of measurement. "Local" here refers to the principle of locality, the idea that a particle can only be influenced by its immediate surroundings, and that interactions mediated by physical fields cannot propagate faster than the speed of light. "Hidden variables" are putative properties of quantum particles that are not included in quantum theory but nevertheless affect the outcome of experiments. In the words of physicist John Stewart Bell, for whom this family of results is named, "If [a hidden-variable theory] is local it will not agree with quantum mechanics, and if it agrees with quantum mechanics it will not be local."[1]

The term is broadly applied to a number of different derivations, the first of which was introduced by Bell in a 1964 paper titled "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox." Bell's paper was a response to a 1935 thought experiment that Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen proposed, arguing that quantum physics is an "incomplete" theory.[2][3] By 1935, it was already recognized that the predictions of quantum physics are probabilistic. Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen presented a scenario that involves preparing a pair of particles such that the quantum state of the pair is entangled, and then separating the particles to an arbitrarily large distance. The experimenter has a choice of possible measurements that can be performed on one of the particles. When they choose a measurement and obtain a result, the quantum state of the other particle apparently collapses instantaneously into a new state depending upon that result, no matter how far away the other particle is. This suggests that either the measurement of the first particle somehow also interacted with the second particle at faster than the speed of light, or that the entangled particles had some unmeasured property which pre-determined their final quantum states before they were separated. Therefore, assuming locality, quantum mechanics must be incomplete, as it cannot give a complete description of the particle's true physical characteristics. In other words, quantum particles, like electrons and photons, must carry some property or attributes not included in quantum theory, and the uncertainties in quantum theory's predictions would then be due to ignorance or unknowability of these properties, later termed "hidden variables".

Bell carried the analysis of quantum entanglement much further. He deduced that if measurements are performed independently on the two separated particles of an entangled pair, then the assumption that the outcomes depend upon hidden variables within each half implies a mathematical constraint on how the outcomes on the two measurements are correlated. This constraint would later be named the Bell inequality. Bell then showed that quantum physics predicts correlations that violate this inequality. Consequently, the only way that hidden variables could explain the predictions of quantum physics is if they are "nonlocal", which is to say that somehow the two particles are able to interact instantaneously no matter how widely they ever become separated.[4][5]

Multiple variations on Bell's theorem were put forward in the following years, introducing other closely related conditions generally known as Bell (or "Bell-type") inequalities. The first rudimentary experiment designed to test Bell's theorem was performed in 1972 by John Clauser and Stuart Freedman.[6] More advanced experiments, known collectively as Bell tests, have been performed many times since. Often, these experiments have had the goal of "closing loopholes", that is, ameliorating problems of experimental design or set-up that could in principle affect the validity of the findings of earlier Bell tests. To date, Bell tests have consistently found that physical systems obey quantum mechanics and violate Bell inequalities; which is to say that the results of these experiments are incompatible with any local hidden variable theory.[7][8]

The exact nature of the assumptions required to prove a Bell-type constraint on correlations has been debated by physicists and by philosophers. While the significance of Bell's theorem is not in doubt, its full implications for the interpretation of quantum mechanics remain unresolved.

Theorem edit

There are many variations on the basic idea, some employing stronger mathematical assumptions than others.[9] Significantly, Bell-type theorems do not refer to any particular theory of local hidden variables, but instead show that quantum physics violates general assumptions behind classical pictures of nature. The original theorem proved by Bell in 1964 is not the most amenable to experiment, and it is convenient to introduce the genre of Bell-type inequalities with a later example.[10]

Hypothetical characters Alice and Bob stand in widely separated locations. Their colleague Victor prepares a pair of particles and sends one to Alice and the other to Bob. When Alice receives her particle, she chooses to perform one of two possible measurements (perhaps by flipping a coin to decide which). Denote these measurements by   and  . Both   and   are binary measurements: the result of   is either   or  , and likewise for  . When Bob receives his particle, he chooses one of two measurements,   and  , which are also both binary.

Suppose that each measurement reveals a property that the particle already possessed. For instance, if Alice chooses to measure   and obtains the result  , then the particle she received carried a value of   for a property  .[note 1] Consider the following combination:

 

Because both   and   take the values  , then either   or  . In the former case,  , while in the latter case,  . So, one of the terms on the right-hand side of the above expression will vanish, and the other will equal  . Consequently, if the experiment is repeated over many trials, with Victor preparing new pairs of particles, the absolute value of the average of the combination   across all the trials will be less than or equal to 2. No single trial can measure this quantity, because Alice and Bob can only choose one measurement each, but on the assumption that the underlying properties exist, the average value of the sum is just the sum of the averages for each term. Using angle brackets to denote averages,

 
This is a Bell inequality, specifically, the CHSH inequality.[10]: 115  Its derivation here depends upon two assumptions: first, that the underlying physical properties   and   exist independently of being observed or measured (sometimes called the assumption of realism); and second, that Alice's choice of action cannot influence Bob's result or vice versa (often called the assumption of locality).[10]: 117 

Quantum mechanics can violate the CHSH inequality, as follows. Victor prepares a pair of qubits which he describes by the Bell state

 
where   and   are the eigenstates of one of the Pauli matrices,
 
Victor then passes the first qubit to Alice and the second to Bob. Alice and Bob's choices of possible measurements are also defined in terms of the Pauli matrices. Alice measures either of the two observables   and  :
 
and Bob measures either of the two observables
 
Victor can calculate the quantum expectation values for pairs of these observables using the Born rule:
 
While only one of these four measurements can be made in a single trial of the experiment, the sum
 
gives the sum of the average values that Victor expects to find across multiple trials. This value exceeds the classical upper bound of 2 that was deduced from the hypothesis of local hidden variables.[10]: 116  The value   is in fact the largest that quantum physics permits for this combination of expectation values, making it a Tsirelson bound.[13]: 140 
 
An illustration of the CHSH game: the referee, Victor, sends a bit each to Alice and to Bob, and Alice and Bob each send a bit back to the referee.

The CHSH inequality can also be thought of as a game in which Alice and Bob try to coordinate their actions.[14][15] Victor prepares two bits,   and  , independently and at random. He sends bit   to Alice and bit   to Bob. Alice and Bob win if they return answer bits   and   to Victor, satisfying

 
Or, equivalently, Alice and Bob win if the logical AND of   and   is the logical XOR of   and  . Alice and Bob can agree upon any strategy they desire before the game, but they cannot communicate once the game begins. In any theory based on local hidden variables, Alice and Bob's probability of winning is no greater than  , regardless of what strategy they agree upon beforehand. However, if they share an entangled quantum state, their probability of winning can be as large as
 

Variations and related results edit

Bell (1964) edit

Bell's 1964 paper points out that under restricted conditions, local hidden variable models can reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics. He then demonstrates that this cannot hold true in general.[3] Bell considers a refinement by David Bohm of the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) thought experiment. In this scenario, a pair of particles are formed together in such a way that they are described by a spin singlet state (which is an example of an entangled state). The particles then move apart in opposite directions. Each particle is measured by a Stern–Gerlach device, a measuring instrument that can be oriented in different directions and that reports one of two possible outcomes, representable by   and  . The configuration of each measuring instrument is represented by a unit vector, and the quantum-mechanical prediction for the correlation between two detectors with settings   and   is

 

In particular, if the orientation of the two detectors is the same ( ), then the outcome of one measurement is certain to be the negative of the outcome of the other, giving  . And if the orientations of the two detectors are orthogonal ( ), then the outcomes are uncorrelated, and  . Bell proves by example that these special cases can be explained in terms of hidden variables, then proceeds to show that the full range of possibilities involving intermediate angles cannot.

Bell posited that a local hidden variable model for these correlations would explain them in terms of an integral over the possible values of some hidden parameter  :

 
where   is a probability density function. The two functions   and   provide the responses of the two detectors given the orientation vectors and the hidden variable:
 
Crucially, the outcome of detector   does not depend upon  , and likewise the outcome of   does not depend upon  , because the two detectors are physically separated. Now we suppose that the experimenter has a choice of settings for the second detector: it can be set either to   or to  . Bell proves that the difference in correlation between these two choices of detector setting must satisfy the inequality
 
However, it is easy to find situations where quantum mechanics violates the Bell inequality.[16]: 425–426  For example, let the vectors   and   be orthogonal, and let   lie in their plane at a 45° angle from both of them. Then
 
while
 
but
 
Therefore, there is no local hidden variable model that can reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics for all choices of  ,  , and   Experimental results contradict the classical curves and match the curve predicted by quantum mechanics as long as experimental shortcomings are accounted for.[9]

Bell's 1964 theorem requires the possibility of perfect anti-correlations: the ability to make a probability-1 prediction about the result from the second detector, knowing the result from the first. This is related to the "EPR criterion of reality", a concept introduced in the 1935 paper by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen. This paper posits, "If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity."[2]

GHZ–Mermin (1990) edit

Daniel Greenberger, Michael A. Horne, and Anton Zeilinger presented a four-particle thought experiment in 1990, which David Mermin then simplified to use only three particles.[17][18] In this thought experiment, Victor generates a set of three spin-1/2 particles described by the quantum state

 
where as above,   and   are the eigenvectors of the Pauli matrix  . Victor then sends a particle each to Alice, Bob, and Charlie, who wait at widely separated locations. Alice measures either   or   on her particle, and so do Bob and Charlie. The result of each measurement is either   or  . Applying the Born rule to the three-qubit state  , Victor predicts that whenever the three measurements include one   and two  's, the product of the outcomes will always be  . This follows because   is an eigenvector of   with eigenvalue  , and likewise for   and  . Therefore, knowing Alice's result for a   measurement and Bob's result for a   measurement, Victor can predict with probability 1 what result Charlie will return for a   measurement. According to the EPR criterion of reality, there would be an "element of reality" corresponding to the outcome of a   measurement upon Charlie's qubit. Indeed, this same logic applies to both measurements and all three qubits. Per the EPR criterion of reality, then, each particle contains an "instruction set" that determines the outcome of a   or   measurement upon it. The set of all three particles would then be described by the instruction set
 
with each entry being either   or  , and each   or   measurement simply returning the appropriate value.

If Alice, Bob, and Charlie all perform the   measurement, then the product of their results would be  . This value can be deduced from

 
because the square of either   or   is  . Each factor in parentheses equals  , so
 
and the product of Alice, Bob, and Charlie's results will be   with probability unity. But this is inconsistent with quantum physics: Victor can predict using the state   that the measurement   will instead yield   with probability unity.

This thought experiment can also be recast as a traditional Bell inequality or, equivalently, as a nonlocal game in the same spirit as the CHSH game.[19] In it, Alice, Bob, and Charlie receive bits   from Victor, promised to always have an even number of ones, that is,  , and send him back bits  . They win the game if   have an odd number of ones for all inputs except  , when they need to have an even number of ones. That is, they win the game iff  . With local hidden variables the highest probability of victory they can have is 3/4, whereas using the quantum strategy above they win it with certainty. This is an example of quantum pseudo-telepathy.

Kochen–Specker theorem (1967) edit

In quantum theory, orthonormal bases for a Hilbert space represent measurements that can be performed upon a system having that Hilbert space. Each vector in a basis represents a possible outcome of that measurement.[note 2] Suppose that a hidden variable   exists, so that knowing the value of   would imply certainty about the outcome of any measurement. Given a value of  , each measurement outcome — that is, each vector in the Hilbert space — is either impossible or guaranteed. A Kochen–Specker configuration is a finite set of vectors made of multiple interlocking bases, with the property that a vector in it will always be impossible when considered as belonging to one basis and guaranteed when taken as belonging to another. In other words, a Kochen–Specker configuration is an "uncolorable set" that demonstrates the inconsistency of assuming a hidden variable   can be controlling the measurement outcomes.[24]: 196–201 

Free will theorem edit

The Kochen–Specker type of argument, using configurations of interlocking bases, can be combined with the idea of measuring entangled pairs that underlies Bell-type inequalities. This was noted beginning in the 1970s by Kochen,[25] Heywood and Redhead,[26] Stairs,[27] and Brown and Svetlichny.[28] As EPR pointed out, obtaining a measurement outcome on one half of an entangled pair implies certainty about the outcome of a corresponding measurement on the other half. The "EPR criterion of reality" posits that because the second half of the pair was not disturbed, that certainty must be due to a physical property belonging to it.[29] In other words, by this criterion, a hidden variable   must exist within the second, as-yet unmeasured half of the pair. No contradiction arises if only one measurement on the first half is considered. However, if the observer has a choice of multiple possible measurements, and the vectors defining those measurements form a Kochen–Specker configuration, then some outcome on the second half will be simultaneously impossible and guaranteed.

This type of argument gained attention when an instance of it was advanced by John Conway and Simon Kochen under the name of the free will theorem.[30][31][32] The Conway–Kochen theorem uses a pair of entangled qutrits and a Kochen–Specker configuration discovered by Asher Peres.[33]

Quasiclassical entanglement edit

As Bell pointed out, some predictions of quantum mechanics can be replicated in local hidden variable models, including special cases of correlations produced from entanglement. This topic has been studied systematically in the years since Bell's theorem. In 1989, Reinhard Werner introduced what are now called Werner states, joint quantum states for a pair of systems that yield EPR-type correlations but also admit a hidden-variable model.[34] Werner states are bipartite quantum states that are invariant under unitaries of symmetric tensor-product form:

 

In 2004, Robert Spekkens introduced a toy model that starts with the premise of local, discretized degrees of freedom and then imposes a "knowledge balance principle" that restricts how much an observer can know about those degrees of freedom, thereby making them into hidden variables. The allowed states of knowledge ("epistemic states") about the underlying variables ("ontic states") mimic some features of quantum states. Correlations in the toy model can emulate some aspects of entanglement, like monogamy, but by construction, the toy model can never violate a Bell inequality.[35][36]

History edit

Background edit

The question of whether quantum mechanics can be "completed" by hidden variables dates to the early years of quantum theory. In his 1932 textbook on quantum mechanics, the Hungarian-born polymath John von Neumann presented what he claimed to be a proof that there could be no "hidden parameters". The validity and definitiveness of von Neumann's proof were questioned by Hans Reichenbach, in more detail by Grete Hermann, and possibly in conversation though not in print by Albert Einstein.[note 3] (Simon Kochen and Ernst Specker rejected von Neumann's key assumption as early as 1961, but did not publish a criticism of it until 1967.[42])

Einstein argued persistently that quantum mechanics could not be a complete theory. His preferred argument relied on a principle of locality:

Consider a mechanical system constituted of two partial systems A and B which have interaction with each other only during limited time. Let the ψ function before their interaction be given. Then the Schrödinger equation will furnish the ψ function after their interaction has taken place. Let us now determine the physical condition of the partial system A as completely as possible by measurements. Then the quantum mechanics allows us to determine the ψ function of the partial system B from the measurements made, and from the ψ function of the total system. This determination, however, gives a result which depends upon which of the determining magnitudes specifying the condition of A has been measured (for instance coordinates or momenta). Since there can be only one physical condition of B after the interaction and which can reasonably not be considered as dependent on the particular measurement we perform on the system A separated from B it may be concluded that the ψ function is not unambiguously coordinated with the physical condition. This coordination of several ψ functions with the same physical condition of system B shows again that the ψ function cannot be interpreted as a (complete) description of a physical condition of a unit system.[43]

The EPR thought experiment is similar, also considering two separated systems A and B described by a joint wave function. However, the EPR paper adds the idea later known as the EPR criterion of reality, according to which the ability to predict with probability 1 the outcome of a measurement upon B implies the existence of an "element of reality" within B.[44]

In 1951, David Bohm proposed a variant of the EPR thought experiment in which the measurements have discrete ranges of possible outcomes, unlike the position and momentum measurements considered by EPR.[45] The year before, Chien-Shiung Wu and Irving Shaknov had successfully measured polarizations of photons produced in entangled pairs, thereby making the Bohm version of the EPR thought experiment practically feasible.[46]

By the late 1940s, the mathematician George Mackey had grown interested in the foundations of quantum physics, and in 1957 he drew up a list of postulates that he took to be a precise definition of quantum mechanics.[47] Mackey conjectured that one of the postulates was redundant, and shortly thereafter, Andrew M. Gleason proved that it was indeed deducible from the other postulates.[48][49] Gleason's theorem provided an argument that a broad class of hidden-variable theories are incompatible with quantum mechanics.[note 4] More specifically, Gleason's theorem rules out hidden-variable models that are "noncontextual". Any hidden-variable model for quantum mechanics must, in order to avoid the implications of Gleason's theorem, involve hidden variables that are not properties belonging to the measured system alone but also dependent upon the external context in which the measurement is made. This type of dependence is often seen as contrived or undesirable; in some settings, it is inconsistent with special relativity.[5][51] The Kochen–Specker theorem refines this statement by constructing a specific finite subset of rays on which no such probability measure can be defined.[5][52]

Tsung-Dao Lee came close to deriving Bell's theorem in 1960. He considered events where two kaons were produced traveling in opposite directions, and came to the conclusion that hidden variables could not explain the correlations that could be obtained in such situations. However, complications arose due to the fact that kaons decay, and he did not go so far as to deduce a Bell-type inequality.[note 5]

Bell's publications edit

Bell chose to publish his theorem in a comparatively obscure journal because it did not require page charges, in fact paying the authors who published there at the time. Because the journal did not provide free reprints of articles for the authors to distribute, however, Bell had to spend the money he received to buy copies that he could send to other physicists.[53] While the articles printed in the journal themselves listed the publication's name simply as Physics, the covers carried the trilingual version Physics Physique Физика to reflect that it would print articles in English, French and Russian.[41]: 92–100, 289 

Prior to proving his 1964 result, Bell also proved a result equivalent to the Kochen–Specker theorem (hence the latter is sometimes also known as the Bell–Kochen–Specker or Bell–KS theorem). However, publication of this theorem was inadvertently delayed until 1966.[5][54] In that paper, Bell argued that because an explanation of quantum phenomena in terms of hidden variables would require nonlocality, the EPR paradox "is resolved in the way which Einstein would have liked least."[54]

Experiments edit

 
Scheme of a "two-channel" Bell test
The source S produces pairs of "photons", sent in opposite directions. Each photon encounters a two-channel polariser whose orientation (a or b) can be set by the experimenter. Emerging signals from each channel are detected and coincidences of four types (++, −−, +− and −+) counted by the coincidence monitor.

In 1967, the unusual title Physics Physique Физика caught the attention of John Clauser, who then discovered Bell's paper and began to consider how to perform a Bell test in the laboratory.[55] Clauser and Stuart Freedman would go on to perform a Bell test in 1972.[56][57] This was only a limited test, because the choice of detector settings was made before the photons had left the source. In 1982, Alain Aspect and collaborators performed the first Bell test to remove this limitation.[58] This began a trend of progressively more stringent Bell tests. The GHZ thought experiment was implemented in practice, using entangled triplets of photons, in 2000.[59] By 2002, testing the CHSH inequality was feasible in undergraduate laboratory courses.[60]

In Bell tests, there may be problems of experimental design or set-up that affect the validity of the experimental findings. These problems are often referred to as "loopholes". The purpose of the experiment is to test whether nature can be described by local hidden-variable theory, which would contradict the predictions of quantum mechanics.

The most prevalent loopholes in real experiments are the detection and locality loopholes.[61] The detection loophole is opened when a small fraction of the particles (usually photons) are detected in the experiment, making it possible to explain the data with local hidden variables by assuming that the detected particles are an unrepresentative sample. The locality loophole is opened when the detections are not done with a spacelike separation, making it possible for the result of one measurement to influence the other without contradicting relativity. In some experiments there may be additional defects that make local-hidden-variable explanations of Bell test violations possible.[62]

Although both the locality and detection loopholes had been closed in different experiments, a long-standing challenge was to close both simultaneously in the same experiment. This was finally achieved in three experiments in 2015.[63][64][65][66][67] Regarding these results, Alain Aspect writes that "no experiment ... can be said to be totally loophole-free," but he says the experiments "remove the last doubts that we should renounce" local hidden variables, and refers to examples of remaining loopholes as being "far fetched" and "foreign to the usual way of reasoning in physics."[68]

These efforts to experimentally validate violations of the Bell inequalities would later result in Clauser, Aspect, and Anton Zeilinger being awarded the 2022 Nobel Prize in Physics.[69]

Interpretations edit

Reactions to Bell's theorem have been many and varied. Maximilian Schlosshauer, Johannes Kofler, and Zeilinger write that Bell inequalities provide "a wonderful example of how we can have a rigorous theoretical result tested by numerous experiments, and yet disagree about the implications."[70]

The Copenhagen Interpretation edit

The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. It is one of the oldest of numerous proposed interpretations of quantum mechanics, as features of it date to the development of quantum mechanics during 1925–1927, and it remains one of the most commonly taught.[71] There is no definitive historical statement of what is the Copenhagen interpretation. In particular, there were fundamental disagreements between the views of Bohr and Heisenberg.[72][73][74] Some basic principles generally accepted as part of the Copenhagen collection include the idea that quantum mechanics is intrinsically indeterministic, with probabilities calculated using the Born rule,[75] and the complementarity principle: certain properties cannot be jointly defined for the same system at the same time. In order to talk about a specific property of a system, that system must be considered within the context of a specific laboratory arrangement. Observable quantities corresponding to mutually exclusive laboratory arrangements cannot be predicted together, but considering multiple such mutually exclusive experiments is necessary to characterize a system.[72] Bohr himself used complementarity to argue that the EPR "paradox" was fallacious, noting that since measurements of position and of momentum are complementary, making the choice to measure one excludes the possibility of measuring the other. Consequently, he argued, a fact deduced regarding one arrangement of laboratory apparatus could not be combined with a fact deduced by means of the other, and so, the inference of predetermined position and momentum values for the second particle was not valid.[38]: 194–197  Bohr concluded that EPR's "arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete."[76]

Copenhagen-type interpretations generally take the violation of Bell inequalities as grounds to reject the assumption often called counterfactual definiteness or "realism", which is not necessarily the same as abandoning realism in a broader philosophical sense.[77][78] For example, Roland Omnès argues for the rejection of hidden variables and concludes that "quantum mechanics is probably as realistic as any theory of its scope and maturity ever will be."[79]: 531  This is also the route taken by interpretations that descend from the Copenhagen tradition, such as consistent histories (often advertised as "Copenhagen done right"),[80] as well as QBism.[81]

Many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics edit

The Many-worlds interpretation, also known as the Everett interpretation, is local and deterministic, as it consists of the unitary part of quantum mechanics without collapse. It can generate correlations that violate a Bell inequality because it violates an implicit assumption by Bell that measurements have a single outcome. In fact, Bell's theorem can be proven in the Many-Worlds framework from the assumption that a measurement has a single outcome. Therefore, a violation of a Bell inequality can be interpreted as a demonstration that measurements have multiple outcomes.[82]

The explanation it provides for the Bell correlations is that when Alice and Bob make their measurements, they split into local branches. From the point of view of each copy of Alice, there are multiple copies of Bob experiencing different results, so Bob cannot have a definite result, and the same is true from the point of view of each copy of Bob. They will obtain a mutually well-defined result only when their future light cones overlap. At this point we can say that the Bell correlation starts existing, but it was produced by a purely local mechanism. Therefore, the violation of a Bell inequality cannot be interpreted as a proof of non-locality.[83]

Non-local hidden variables edit

Most advocates of the hidden-variables idea believe that experiments have ruled out local hidden variables.[note 6] They are ready to give up locality, explaining the violation of Bell's inequality by means of a non-local hidden variable theory, in which the particles exchange information about their states. This is the basis of the Bohm interpretation of quantum mechanics, which requires that all particles in the universe be able to instantaneously exchange information with all others. One challenge for non-local hidden variable theories is to explain why this instantaneous communication can exist at the level of the hidden variables, but it cannot be used to send signals.[86] A 2007 experiment ruled out a large class of non-Bohmian non-local hidden variable theories, though not Bohmian mechanics itself.[87]

The transactional interpretation, which postulates waves traveling both backwards and forwards in time, is likewise non-local.[88]

Superdeterminism edit

A necessary assumption to derive Bell's theorem is that the hidden variables are not correlated with the measurement settings. This assumption has been justified on the grounds that the experimenter has "free will" to choose the settings, and that it is necessary to do science in the first place. A (hypothetical) theory where the choice of measurement is necessarily correlated with the system being measured is known as superdeterministic.[61]

A few advocates of deterministic models have not given up on local hidden variables. For example, Gerard 't Hooft has argued that superdeterminism cannot be dismissed.[89]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ We are for convenience assuming that the response of the detector to the underlying property is deterministic. This assumption can be replaced; it is equivalent to postulating a joint probability distribution over all the observables of the experiment.[11][12]
  2. ^ In more detail, as developed by Paul Dirac,[20] David Hilbert,[21] John von Neumann,[22] and Hermann Weyl,[23] the state of a quantum mechanical system is a vector   belonging to a (separable) Hilbert space  . Physical quantities of interest — position, momentum, energy, spin — are represented by "observables", which are self-adjoint linear operators acting on the Hilbert space. When an observable is measured, the result will be one of its eigenvalues with probability given by the Born rule: in the simplest case the eigenvalue   is non-degenerate and the probability is given by  , where   is its associated eigenvector. More generally, the eigenvalue is degenerate and the probability is given by  , where   is the projector onto its associated eigenspace. For the purposes of this discussion, we can take the eigenvalues to be non-degenerate.
  3. ^ See Reichenbach[37] and Jammer,[38]: 276  Mermin and Schack,[39] and for Einstein's remarks, Clauser and Shimony[40] and Wick.[41]: 286 
  4. ^ A hidden-variable theory that is deterministic implies that the probability of a given outcome is always either 0 or 1. For example, a Stern–Gerlach measurement on a spin-1 atom will report that the atom's angular momentum along the chosen axis is one of three possible values, which can be designated  ,   and  . In a deterministic hidden-variable theory, there exists an underlying physical property that fixes the result found in the measurement. Conditional on the value of the underlying physical property, any given outcome (for example, a result of  ) must be either impossible or guaranteed. But Gleason's theorem implies that there can be no such deterministic probability measure, because it proves that any probability measure must take the form of a mapping   for some density operator  . This mapping is continuous on the unit sphere of the Hilbert space, and since this unit sphere is connected, no continuous probability measure on it can be deterministic.[50]: §1.3 
  5. ^ This was reported by Max Jammer.[38]: 308  Lee is best known for his prediction with Chen-Ning Yang of the violation of parity conservation, a prediction that earned them the Nobel Prize after it was confirmed by Chien-Shiung Wu, who did not share in the Prize.
  6. ^ E. T. Jaynes was one exception,[84] but Jaynes' arguments have not generally been found persuasive.[85]

References edit

  1. ^ Bell, John S. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. p. 65. ISBN 9780521368698. OCLC 15053677.
  2. ^ a b Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
  3. ^ a b Bell, J. S. (1964). "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox" (PDF). Physics Physique Физика. 1 (3): 195–200. doi:10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195.
  4. ^ Parker, Sybil B. (1994). McGraw-Hill Encyclopaedia of Physics (2nd ed.). McGraw-Hill. p. 542. ISBN 978-0-07-051400-3.
  5. ^ a b c d Mermin, N. David (July 1993). "Hidden Variables and the Two Theorems of John Bell" (PDF). Reviews of Modern Physics. 65 (3): 803–15. arXiv:1802.10119. Bibcode:1993RvMP...65..803M. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.65.803. S2CID 119546199.
  6. ^ "The Nobel Prize in Physics 2022". Nobel Prize (Press release). The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences. October 4, 2022. Retrieved 6 October 2022.
  7. ^ The BIG Bell Test Collaboration (9 May 2018). "Challenging local realism with human choices". Nature. 557 (7704): 212–216. arXiv:1805.04431. Bibcode:2018Natur.557..212B. doi:10.1038/s41586-018-0085-3. PMID 29743691. S2CID 13665914.
  8. ^ Wolchover, Natalie (2017-02-07). "Experiment Reaffirms Quantum Weirdness". Quanta Magazine. Retrieved 2020-02-08.
  9. ^ a b Shimony, Abner. "Bell's Theorem". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  10. ^ a b c d Nielsen, Michael A.; Chuang, Isaac L. (2010). Quantum Computation and Quantum Information (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-107-00217-3. OCLC 844974180.
  11. ^ Fine, Arthur (1982-02-01). "Hidden Variables, Joint Probability, and the Bell Inequalities". Physical Review Letters. 48 (5): 291–295. Bibcode:1982PhRvL..48..291F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.48.291. ISSN 0031-9007.
  12. ^ Braunstein, Samuel L.; Caves, Carlton M. (August 1990). "Wringing out better Bell inequalities". Annals of Physics. 202 (1): 22–56. Bibcode:1990AnPhy.202...22B. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(90)90339-P.
  13. ^ Rau, Jochen (2021). Quantum theory : an information processing approach. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-192-65027-6. OCLC 1256446911.
  14. ^ Cleve, R.; Hoyer, P.; Toner, B.; Watrous, J. (2004). "Consequences and limits of nonlocal strategies". Proceedings. 19th IEEE Annual Conference on Computational Complexity, 2004. IEEE. pp. 236–249. arXiv:quant-ph/0404076. Bibcode:2004quant.ph..4076C. doi:10.1109/CCC.2004.1313847. ISBN 0-7695-2120-7. OCLC 55954993. S2CID 8077237.
  15. ^ Barnum, H.; Beigi, S.; Boixo, S.; Elliott, M. B.; Wehner, S. (2010-04-06). "Local Quantum Measurement and No-Signaling Imply Quantum Correlations". Physical Review Letters. 104 (14): 140401. arXiv:0910.3952. Bibcode:2010PhRvL.104n0401B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.104.140401. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 20481921. S2CID 17298392.
  16. ^ Griffiths, David J. (2005). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 0-13-111892-7. OCLC 53926857.
  17. ^ Greenberger, D.; Horne, M.; Shimony, A.; Zeilinger, A. (1990). "Bell's theorem without inequalities". American Journal of Physics. 58 (12): 1131. Bibcode:1990AmJPh..58.1131G. doi:10.1119/1.16243.
  18. ^ Mermin, N. David (1990). "Quantum mysteries revisited". American Journal of Physics. 58 (8): 731–734. Bibcode:1990AmJPh..58..731M. doi:10.1119/1.16503.
  19. ^ Brassard, Gilles; Broadbent, Anne; Tapp, Alain (2005). "Recasting Mermin's multi-player game into the framework of pseudo-telepathy". Quantum Information and Computation. 5 (7): 538–550. arXiv:quant-ph/0408052. Bibcode:2004quant.ph..8052B. doi:10.26421/QIC5.7-2.
  20. ^ Dirac, Paul Adrien Maurice (1930). The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
  21. ^ Hilbert, David (2009). Sauer, Tilman; Majer, Ulrich (eds.). Lectures on the Foundations of Physics 1915–1927: Relativity, Quantum Theory and Epistemology. Springer. doi:10.1007/b12915. ISBN 978-3-540-20606-4. OCLC 463777694.
  22. ^ von Neumann, John (1932). Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. Berlin: Springer. English translation: Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Translated by Beyer, Robert T. Princeton University Press. 1955.
  23. ^ Weyl, Hermann (1950) [1931]. The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics. Translated by Robertson, H. P. Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-60269-1. Translated from the German Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik (2nd ed.). S. Hirzel Verlag [de]. 1931.
  24. ^ Peres, Asher (1993). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer. ISBN 0-7923-2549-4. OCLC 28854083.
  25. ^ Redhead, Michael; Brown, Harvey (1991-07-01). "Nonlocality in Quantum Mechanics". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 65 (1): 119–160. doi:10.1093/aristoteliansupp/65.1.119. ISSN 0309-7013. JSTOR 4106773. A similar approach was arrived at independently by Simon Kochen, although never published (private communication).
  26. ^ Heywood, Peter; Redhead, Michael L. G. (May 1983). "Nonlocality and the Kochen–Specker paradox". Foundations of Physics. 13 (5): 481–499. Bibcode:1983FoPh...13..481H. doi:10.1007/BF00729511. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 120340929.
  27. ^ Stairs, Allen (December 1983). "Quantum Logic, Realism, and Value Definiteness". Philosophy of Science. 50 (4): 578–602. doi:10.1086/289140. ISSN 0031-8248. S2CID 122885859.
  28. ^ Brown, H. R.; Svetlichny, G. (November 1990). "Nonlocality and Gleason's lemma. Part I. Deterministic theories". Foundations of Physics. 20 (11): 1379–1387. Bibcode:1990FoPh...20.1379B. doi:10.1007/BF01883492. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 122868901.
  29. ^ Glick, David; Boge, Florian J. (2019-10-22). "Is the Reality Criterion Analytic?". Erkenntnis. 86 (6): 1445–1451. arXiv:1909.11893. Bibcode:2019arXiv190911893G. doi:10.1007/s10670-019-00163-w. ISSN 0165-0106. S2CID 202889160.
  30. ^ Conway, John; Kochen, Simon (2006). "The Free Will Theorem". Foundations of Physics. 36 (10): 1441. arXiv:quant-ph/0604079. Bibcode:2006FoPh...36.1441C. doi:10.1007/s10701-006-9068-6. S2CID 12999337.
  31. ^ Rehmeyer, Julie (2008-08-15). "Do subatomic particles have free will?". Science News. Retrieved 2022-04-23.
  32. ^ Thomas, Rachel (2011-12-27). "John Conway – discovering free will (part I)". Plus Magazine. Retrieved 2022-04-23.
  33. ^ Conway, John H.; Kochen, Simon (2009). "The strong free will theorem" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 56 (2): 226–232.
  34. ^ Werner, Reinhard F. (1989-10-01). "Quantum states with Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen correlations admitting a hidden-variable model". Physical Review A. 40 (8): 4277–4281. Bibcode:1989PhRvA..40.4277W. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.40.4277. ISSN 0556-2791. PMID 9902666.
  35. ^ Spekkens, Robert W. (2007-03-19). "Evidence for the epistemic view of quantum states: A toy theory". Physical Review A. 75 (3): 032110. arXiv:quant-ph/0401052. Bibcode:2007PhRvA..75c2110S. doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.75.032110. ISSN 1050-2947. S2CID 117284016.
  36. ^ Catani, Lorenzo; Browne, Dan E. (2017-07-27). "Spekkens' toy model in all dimensions and its relationship with stabiliser quantum mechanics". New Journal of Physics. 19 (7): 073035. arXiv:1701.07801. Bibcode:2017NJPh...19g3035C. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/aa781c. ISSN 1367-2630. S2CID 119428107.
  37. ^ Reichenbach, Hans (1944). Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. University of California Press. p. 14. OCLC 872622725.
  38. ^ a b c Jammer, Max (1974). The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. John Wiley and Sons. ISBN 0-471-43958-4.
  39. ^ Mermin, N. David; Schack, Rüdiger (2018). "Homer nodded: von Neumann's surprising oversight". Foundations of Physics. 48 (9): 1007–1020. arXiv:1805.10311. Bibcode:2018FoPh...48.1007M. doi:10.1007/s10701-018-0197-5. S2CID 118951033.
  40. ^ Clauser, J. F.; Shimony, A. (1978). "Bell's theorem: Experimental tests and implications" (PDF). Reports on Progress in Physics. 41 (12): 1881–1927. Bibcode:1978RPPh...41.1881C. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.482.4728. doi:10.1088/0034-4885/41/12/002. S2CID 250885175. (PDF) from the original on 2017-09-23. Retrieved 2017-10-28.
  41. ^ a b Wick, David (1995). "Bell's Theorem". The Infamous Boundary: Seven Decades of Heresy in Quantum Physics. New York: Springer. pp. 92–100. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-4030-3_11. ISBN 978-0-387-94726-6.
  42. ^ Conway, John; Kochen, Simon (2002). "The Geometry of the Quantum Paradoxes". In Bertlmann, Reinhold A.; Zeilinger, Anton (eds.). Quantum [Un]speakables: From Bell to Quantum Information. Berlin: Springer. pp. 257–269. ISBN 3-540-42756-2. OCLC 49404213.
  43. ^ Einstein, Albert (March 1936). "Physics and reality". Journal of the Franklin Institute. 221 (3): 349–382. Bibcode:1936FrInJ.221..349E. doi:10.1016/S0016-0032(36)91047-5.
  44. ^ Harrigan, Nicholas; Spekkens, Robert W. (2010). "Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states". Foundations of Physics. 40 (2): 125. arXiv:0706.2661. Bibcode:2010FoPh...40..125H. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9347-0. S2CID 32755624.
  45. ^ Bohm, David (1989) [1951]. Quantum Theory (Dover reprint ed.). Prentice-Hall. pp. 614–623. ISBN 978-0-486-65969-5. OCLC 1103789975.
  46. ^ Wu, C.-S.; Shaknov, I. (1950). "The Angular Correlation of Scattered Annihilation Radiation". Physical Review. 77 (1): 136. Bibcode:1950PhRv...77..136W. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.77.136.
  47. ^ Mackey, George W. (1957). "Quantum Mechanics and Hilbert Space". The American Mathematical Monthly. 64 (8P2): 45–57. doi:10.1080/00029890.1957.11989120. JSTOR 2308516.
  48. ^ Gleason, Andrew M. (1957). "Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space". Indiana University Mathematics Journal. 6 (4): 885–893. doi:10.1512/iumj.1957.6.56050. MR 0096113.
  49. ^ Chernoff, Paul R. "Andy Gleason and Quantum Mechanics" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 56 (10): 1253–1259.
  50. ^ Wilce, A. (2017). "Quantum Logic and Probability Theory". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  51. ^ Shimony, Abner (1984). "Contextual Hidden Variable Theories and Bell's Inequalities". British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 35 (1): 25–45. doi:10.1093/bjps/35.1.25.
  52. ^ Peres, Asher (1991). "Two simple proofs of the Kochen-Specker theorem". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and General. 24 (4): L175–L178. Bibcode:1991JPhA...24L.175P. doi:10.1088/0305-4470/24/4/003. ISSN 0305-4470.
  53. ^ Whitaker, Andrew (2016). John Stewart Bell and Twentieth Century Physics: Vision and Integrity. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-874299-9.
  54. ^ a b Bell, J. S. (1966). "On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics". Reviews of Modern Physics. 38 (3): 447–452. Bibcode:1966RvMP...38..447B. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.38.447. OSTI 1444158.
  55. ^ Kaiser, David (2012-01-30). "How the Hippies Saved Physics: Science, Counterculture, and the Quantum Revival [Excerpt]". Scientific American. Retrieved 2020-02-11.
  56. ^ Freedman, S. J.; Clauser, J. F. (1972). "Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories" (PDF). Physical Review Letters. 28 (938): 938–941. Bibcode:1972PhRvL..28..938F. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.28.938.
  57. ^ Freedman, Stuart Jay (1972-05-05). Experimental test of local hidden-variable theories (PDF) (PhD). University of California, Berkeley.
  58. ^ Aspect, Alain; Dalibard, Jean; Roger, Gérard (1982). "Experimental Test of Bell's Inequalities Using Time-Varying Analyzers". Physical Review Letters. 49 (25): 1804–7. Bibcode:1982PhRvL..49.1804A. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.49.1804.
  59. ^ Pan, Jian-Wei; Bouwmeester, D.; Daniell, M.; Weinfurter, H.; Zeilinger, A. (2000). "Experimental test of quantum nonlocality in three-photon GHZ entanglement". Nature. 403 (6769): 515–519. Bibcode:2000Natur.403..515P. doi:10.1038/35000514. PMID 10676953. S2CID 4309261.
  60. ^ Dehlinger, Dietrich; Mitchell, M. W. (2002). "Entangled photons, nonlocality, and Bell inequalities in the undergraduate laboratory". American Journal of Physics. 70 (9): 903–910. arXiv:quant-ph/0205171. Bibcode:2002AmJPh..70..903D. doi:10.1119/1.1498860. S2CID 49487096.
  61. ^ a b Larsson, Jan-Åke (2014). "Loopholes in Bell inequality tests of local realism". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical. 47 (42): 424003. arXiv:1407.0363. Bibcode:2014JPhA...47P4003L. doi:10.1088/1751-8113/47/42/424003. S2CID 40332044.
  62. ^ Gerhardt, I.; Liu, Q.; Lamas-Linares, A.; Skaar, J.; Scarani, V.; et al. (2011). "Experimentally faking the violation of Bell's inequalities". Physical Review Letters. 107 (17): 170404. arXiv:1106.3224. Bibcode:2011PhRvL.107q0404G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.107.170404. PMID 22107491. S2CID 16306493.
  63. ^ Merali, Zeeya (27 August 2015). "Quantum 'spookiness' passes toughest test yet". Nature News. 525 (7567): 14–15. Bibcode:2015Natur.525...14M. doi:10.1038/nature.2015.18255. PMID 26333448. S2CID 4409566.
  64. ^ Markoff, Jack (21 October 2015). "Sorry, Einstein. Quantum Study Suggests 'Spooky Action' Is Real". New York Times. Retrieved 21 October 2015.
  65. ^ Hensen, B.; et al. (21 October 2015). "Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1.3 kilometres". Nature. 526 (7575): 682–686. arXiv:1508.05949. Bibcode:2015Natur.526..682H. doi:10.1038/nature15759. PMID 26503041. S2CID 205246446.
  66. ^ Shalm, L. K.; et al. (16 December 2015). "Strong Loophole-Free Test of Local Realism". Physical Review Letters. 115 (25): 250402. arXiv:1511.03189. Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115y0402S. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.250402. PMC 5815856. PMID 26722906.
  67. ^ Giustina, M.; et al. (16 December 2015). "Significant-Loophole-Free Test of Bell's Theorem with Entangled Photons". Physical Review Letters. 115 (25): 250401. arXiv:1511.03190. Bibcode:2015PhRvL.115y0401G. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.115.250401. PMID 26722905. S2CID 13789503.
  68. ^ Aspect, Alain (December 16, 2015). "Closing the Door on Einstein and Bohr's Quantum Debate". Physics. 8: 123. Bibcode:2015PhyOJ...8..123A. doi:10.1103/Physics.8.123.
  69. ^ Ahlander, Johan; Burger, Ludwig; Pollard, Niklas (2022-10-04). "Nobel physics prize goes to sleuths of 'spooky' quantum science". Reuters. Retrieved 2022-10-04.
  70. ^ Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013-01-06). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196.
  71. ^ Siddiqui, Shabnam; Singh, Chandralekha (2017). "How diverse are physics instructors' attitudes and approaches to teaching undergraduate level quantum mechanics?". European Journal of Physics. 38 (3): 035703. Bibcode:2017EJPh...38c5703S. doi:10.1088/1361-6404/aa6131.
  72. ^ a b Faye, Jan (2019). "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2019-04-29. Retrieved 2021-09-16.
  73. ^ Camilleri, K.; Schlosshauer, M. (2015). "Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment: Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr's Doctrine of Classical Concepts?". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 49: 73–83. arXiv:1502.06547. Bibcode:2015SHPMP..49...73C. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.01.005. S2CID 27697360.
  74. ^ Peres, Asher (2002). "Popper's experiment and the Copenhagen interpretation". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 33: 23. arXiv:quant-ph/9910078. Bibcode:1999quant.ph.10078P. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(01)00034-X.
  75. ^ Bohr, N. (1928). "The Quantum Postulate and the Recent Development of Atomic Theory". Nature. 121 (3050): 580–590. Bibcode:1928Natur.121..580B. doi:10.1038/121580a0., p. 586: "In this connexion [Born] succeeded in obtaining a statistical interpretation of the wave functions, allowing a calculation of the probability of the individual transition processes required by the quantum postulate."
  76. ^ Bohr, N. (1935-10-13). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?" (PDF). Physical Review. 48 (8): 696–702. Bibcode:1935PhRv...48..696B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.48.696. (PDF) from the original on 2020-01-09. Retrieved 2021-09-16.
  77. ^ Werner, Reinhard F. (2014-10-24). "Comment on 'What Bell did'". Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical. 47 (42): 424011. Bibcode:2014JPhA...47P4011W. doi:10.1088/1751-8113/47/42/424011. ISSN 1751-8113. S2CID 122180759.
  78. ^ Żukowski, Marek (2017). "Bell's Theorem Tells Us Not What Quantum Mechanics is, but What Quantum Mechanics is Not". In Bertlmann, Reinhold; Zeilinger, Anton (eds.). Quantum [Un]Speakables II. The Frontiers Collection. Cham: Springer International Publishing. pp. 175–185. arXiv:1501.05640. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-38987-5_10. ISBN 978-3-319-38985-1. S2CID 119214547.
  79. ^ Omnès, R. (1994). The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-03669-4. OCLC 439453957.
  80. ^ Hohenberg, P. C. (2010-10-05). "Colloquium : An introduction to consistent quantum theory". Reviews of Modern Physics. 82 (4): 2835–2844. arXiv:0909.2359. Bibcode:2010RvMP...82.2835H. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.82.2835. ISSN 0034-6861. S2CID 20551033.
  81. ^ Healey, Richard (2016). "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. from the original on 2021-08-17. Retrieved 2021-09-16.
  82. ^ Deutsch, David; Hayden, Patrick (2000). "Information flow in entangled quantum systems". Proceedings of the Royal Society A. 456 (1999): 1759–1774. arXiv:quant-ph/9906007. Bibcode:2000RSPSA.456.1759D. doi:10.1098/rspa.2000.0585. S2CID 13998168.
  83. ^ Brown, Harvey R.; Timpson, Christopher G. (2016). "Bell on Bell's Theorem: The Changing Face of Nonlocality". In Bell, Mary; Gao, Shan (eds.). Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 years of Bell's theorem. Cambridge University Press. pp. 91–123. arXiv:1501.03521. doi:10.1017/CBO9781316219393.008. ISBN 9781316219393. S2CID 118686956.
  84. ^ Jaynes, E. T. (1989). "Clearing up Mysteries — the Original Goal". Maximum Entropy and Bayesian Methods (PDF). pp. 1–27. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.46.1264. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-7860-8_1. ISBN 978-90-481-4044-2. (PDF) from the original on 2011-10-28. Retrieved 2011-10-18.
  85. ^ Gill, Richard D. (2002). "Time, Finite Statistics, and Bell's Fifth Position". Proceedings of the Conference Foundations of Probability and Physics - 2 : Växjö (Soland), Sweden, June 2-7, 2002. Vol. 5. Växjö University Press. pp. 179–206. arXiv:quant-ph/0301059.
  86. ^ Wood, Christopher J.; Spekkens, Robert W. (2015-03-03). "The lesson of causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations: causal explanations of Bell-inequality violations require fine-tuning". New Journal of Physics. 17 (3): 033002. arXiv:1208.4119. Bibcode:2015NJPh...17c3002W. doi:10.1088/1367-2630/17/3/033002. ISSN 1367-2630. S2CID 118518558.
  87. ^ Gröblacher, Simon; Paterek, Tomasz; Kaltenbaek, Rainer; Brukner, Časlav; Żukowski, Marek; Aspelmeyer, Markus; Zeilinger, Anton (2007). "An experimental test of non-local realism". Nature. 446 (7138): 871–5. arXiv:0704.2529. Bibcode:2007Natur.446..871G. doi:10.1038/nature05677. PMID 17443179. S2CID 4412358.
  88. ^ Kastner, Ruth E. (May 2010). "The quantum liar experiment in Cramer's transactional interpretation". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 41 (2): 86–92. arXiv:0906.1626. Bibcode:2010SHPMP..41...86K. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2010.01.001. S2CID 16242184. from the original on 2018-06-24. Retrieved 2021-09-16.
  89. ^ 't Hooft, Gerard (2016). The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Fundamental Theories of Physics. Vol. 185. Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-41285-6. ISBN 978-3-319-41284-9. OCLC 951761277. S2CID 7779840. from the original on 2021-12-29. Retrieved 2020-08-27.

Further reading edit

The following are intended for general audiences.

  • Aczel, Amir D. (2001). Entanglement: The greatest mystery in physics. New York: Four Walls Eight Windows.
  • Afriat, A.; Selleri, F. (1999). The Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox. New York and London: Plenum Press.
  • Baggott, J. (1992). The Meaning of Quantum Theory. Oxford University Press.
  • Gilder, Louisa (2008). The Age of Entanglement: When Quantum Physics Was Reborn. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
  • Greene, Brian (2004). The Fabric of the Cosmos. Vintage. ISBN 0-375-72720-5.
  • Mermin, N. David (1981). "Bringing home the atomic world: Quantum mysteries for anybody". American Journal of Physics. 49 (10): 940–943. Bibcode:1981AmJPh..49..940M. doi:10.1119/1.12594. S2CID 122724592.
  • Mermin, N. David (April 1985). "Is the moon there when nobody looks? Reality and the quantum theory". Physics Today. 38 (4): 38–47. Bibcode:1985PhT....38d..38M. doi:10.1063/1.880968.

The following are more technically oriented.

  • Aspect, A.; et al. (1981). "Experimental Tests of Realistic Local Theories via Bell's Theorem". Phys. Rev. Lett. 47 (7): 460–463. Bibcode:1981PhRvL..47..460A. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.47.460.
  • Aspect, A.; et al. (1982). "Experimental Realization of Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen–Bohm Gedankenexperiment: A New Violation of Bell's Inequalities". Phys. Rev. Lett. 49 (2): 91–94. Bibcode:1982PhRvL..49...91A. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.49.91.
  • Aspect, A.; Grangier, P. (1985). "About resonant scattering and other hypothetical effects in the Orsay atomic-cascade experiment tests of Bell inequalities: a discussion and some new experimental data". Lettere al Nuovo Cimento. 43 (8): 345–348. doi:10.1007/bf02746964. S2CID 120840672.
  • Bell, J. S. (1971). "Introduction to the hidden variable question". Proceedings of the International School of Physics 'Enrico Fermi', Course IL, Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. pp. 171–81.
  • Bell, J. S. (2004). "Bertlmann's Socks and the Nature of Reality". Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. pp. 139–158.
  • D'Espagnat, B. (1979). "The Quantum Theory and Reality" (PDF). Scientific American. 241 (5): 158–181. Bibcode:1979SciAm.241e.158D. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican1179-158. (PDF) from the original on 2009-03-27. Retrieved 2009-03-18.
  • Fry, E. S.; Walther, T.; Li, S. (1995). "Proposal for a loophole-free test of the Bell inequalities" (PDF). Phys. Rev. A. 52 (6): 4381–4395. Bibcode:1995PhRvA..52.4381F. doi:10.1103/physreva.52.4381. hdl:1969.1/126533. PMID 9912775. from the original on 2021-12-29. Retrieved 2018-03-19.
  • Fry, E. S.; Walther, T. (2002). "Atom based tests of the Bell Inequalities — the legacy of John Bell continues". In Bertlmann, R. A.; Zeilinger, A. (eds.). Quantum [Un]speakables. Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer. pp. 103–117.
  • Goldstein, Sheldon; et al. (2011). "Bell's theorem". Scholarpedia. 6 (10): 8378. Bibcode:2011SchpJ...6.8378G. doi:10.4249/scholarpedia.8378.
  • Griffiths, R. B. (2001). Consistent Quantum Theory. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-80349-6. OCLC 1180958776.
  • Hardy, L. (1993). "Nonlocality for 2 particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states". Physical Review Letters. 71 (11): 1665–1668. Bibcode:1993PhRvL..71.1665H. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.71.1665. PMID 10054467. S2CID 11839894.
  • Matsukevich, D. N.; Maunz, P.; Moehring, D. L.; Olmschenk, S.; Monroe, C. (2008). "Bell Inequality Violation with Two Remote Atomic Qubits". Phys. Rev. Lett. 100 (15): 150404. arXiv:0801.2184. Bibcode:2008PhRvL.100o0404M. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.100.150404. PMID 18518088. S2CID 11536757.
  • Rieffel, Eleanor G.; Polak, Wolfgang H. (4 March 2011). "4.4 EPR Paradox and Bell's Theorem". Quantum Computing: A Gentle Introduction. MIT Press. pp. 60–65. ISBN 978-0-262-01506-6.
  • Sulcs, S. (2003). "The Nature of Light and Twentieth Century Experimental Physics". Foundations of Science. 8 (4): 365–391. doi:10.1023/A:1026323203487. S2CID 118769677.
  • van Fraassen, B. C. (1991). Quantum Mechanics: An Empiricist View. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-198-24861-3. OCLC 22906474.

External links edit

bell, theorem, bell, inequality, redirects, here, related, experiments, bell, test, term, encompassing, number, closely, related, results, physics, which, determine, that, quantum, mechanics, incompatible, with, local, hidden, variable, theories, given, some, . Bell inequality redirects here For the related experiments see Bell test Bell s theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden variable theories given some basic assumptions about the nature of measurement Local here refers to the principle of locality the idea that a particle can only be influenced by its immediate surroundings and that interactions mediated by physical fields cannot propagate faster than the speed of light Hidden variables are putative properties of quantum particles that are not included in quantum theory but nevertheless affect the outcome of experiments In the words of physicist John Stewart Bell for whom this family of results is named If a hidden variable theory is local it will not agree with quantum mechanics and if it agrees with quantum mechanics it will not be local 1 The term is broadly applied to a number of different derivations the first of which was introduced by Bell in a 1964 paper titled On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox Bell s paper was a response to a 1935 thought experiment that Albert Einstein Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen proposed arguing that quantum physics is an incomplete theory 2 3 By 1935 it was already recognized that the predictions of quantum physics are probabilistic Einstein Podolsky and Rosen presented a scenario that involves preparing a pair of particles such that the quantum state of the pair is entangled and then separating the particles to an arbitrarily large distance The experimenter has a choice of possible measurements that can be performed on one of the particles When they choose a measurement and obtain a result the quantum state of the other particle apparently collapses instantaneously into a new state depending upon that result no matter how far away the other particle is This suggests that either the measurement of the first particle somehow also interacted with the second particle at faster than the speed of light or that the entangled particles had some unmeasured property which pre determined their final quantum states before they were separated Therefore assuming locality quantum mechanics must be incomplete as it cannot give a complete description of the particle s true physical characteristics In other words quantum particles like electrons and photons must carry some property or attributes not included in quantum theory and the uncertainties in quantum theory s predictions would then be due to ignorance or unknowability of these properties later termed hidden variables Bell carried the analysis of quantum entanglement much further He deduced that if measurements are performed independently on the two separated particles of an entangled pair then the assumption that the outcomes depend upon hidden variables within each half implies a mathematical constraint on how the outcomes on the two measurements are correlated This constraint would later be named the Bell inequality Bell then showed that quantum physics predicts correlations that violate this inequality Consequently the only way that hidden variables could explain the predictions of quantum physics is if they are nonlocal which is to say that somehow the two particles are able to interact instantaneously no matter how widely they ever become separated 4 5 Multiple variations on Bell s theorem were put forward in the following years introducing other closely related conditions generally known as Bell or Bell type inequalities The first rudimentary experiment designed to test Bell s theorem was performed in 1972 by John Clauser and Stuart Freedman 6 More advanced experiments known collectively as Bell tests have been performed many times since Often these experiments have had the goal of closing loopholes that is ameliorating problems of experimental design or set up that could in principle affect the validity of the findings of earlier Bell tests To date Bell tests have consistently found that physical systems obey quantum mechanics and violate Bell inequalities which is to say that the results of these experiments are incompatible with any local hidden variable theory 7 8 The exact nature of the assumptions required to prove a Bell type constraint on correlations has been debated by physicists and by philosophers While the significance of Bell s theorem is not in doubt its full implications for the interpretation of quantum mechanics remain unresolved Contents 1 Theorem 2 Variations and related results 2 1 Bell 1964 2 2 GHZ Mermin 1990 2 3 Kochen Specker theorem 1967 2 4 Free will theorem 2 5 Quasiclassical entanglement 3 History 3 1 Background 3 2 Bell s publications 4 Experiments 5 Interpretations 5 1 The Copenhagen Interpretation 5 2 Many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics 5 3 Non local hidden variables 5 4 Superdeterminism 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksTheorem editThere are many variations on the basic idea some employing stronger mathematical assumptions than others 9 Significantly Bell type theorems do not refer to any particular theory of local hidden variables but instead show that quantum physics violates general assumptions behind classical pictures of nature The original theorem proved by Bell in 1964 is not the most amenable to experiment and it is convenient to introduce the genre of Bell type inequalities with a later example 10 Hypothetical characters Alice and Bob stand in widely separated locations Their colleague Victor prepares a pair of particles and sends one to Alice and the other to Bob When Alice receives her particle she chooses to perform one of two possible measurements perhaps by flipping a coin to decide which Denote these measurements by A0 displaystyle A 0 nbsp and A1 displaystyle A 1 nbsp Both A0 displaystyle A 0 nbsp and A1 displaystyle A 1 nbsp are binary measurements the result of A0 displaystyle A 0 nbsp is either 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp or 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp and likewise for A1 displaystyle A 1 nbsp When Bob receives his particle he chooses one of two measurements B0 displaystyle B 0 nbsp and B1 displaystyle B 1 nbsp which are also both binary Suppose that each measurement reveals a property that the particle already possessed For instance if Alice chooses to measure A0 displaystyle A 0 nbsp and obtains the result 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp then the particle she received carried a value of 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp for a property a0 displaystyle a 0 nbsp note 1 Consider the following combination a0b0 a0b1 a1b0 a1b1 a0 a1 b0 a0 a1 b1 displaystyle a 0 b 0 a 0 b 1 a 1 b 0 a 1 b 1 a 0 a 1 b 0 a 0 a 1 b 1 nbsp Because both a0 displaystyle a 0 nbsp and a1 displaystyle a 1 nbsp take the values 1 displaystyle pm 1 nbsp then either a0 a1 displaystyle a 0 a 1 nbsp or a0 a1 displaystyle a 0 a 1 nbsp In the former case a0 a1 b1 0 displaystyle a 0 a 1 b 1 0 nbsp while in the latter case a0 a1 b0 0 displaystyle a 0 a 1 b 0 0 nbsp So one of the terms on the right hand side of the above expression will vanish and the other will equal 2 displaystyle pm 2 nbsp Consequently if the experiment is repeated over many trials with Victor preparing new pairs of particles the absolute value of the average of the combination a0b0 a0b1 a1b0 a1b1 displaystyle a 0 b 0 a 0 b 1 a 1 b 0 a 1 b 1 nbsp across all the trials will be less than or equal to 2 No single trial can measure this quantity because Alice and Bob can only choose one measurement each but on the assumption that the underlying properties exist the average value of the sum is just the sum of the averages for each term Using angle brackets to denote averages A0B0 A0B1 A1B0 A1B1 2 displaystyle langle A 0 B 0 rangle langle A 0 B 1 rangle langle A 1 B 0 rangle langle A 1 B 1 rangle leq 2 nbsp This is a Bell inequality specifically the CHSH inequality 10 115 Its derivation here depends upon two assumptions first that the underlying physical properties a0 a1 b0 displaystyle a 0 a 1 b 0 nbsp and b1 displaystyle b 1 nbsp exist independently of being observed or measured sometimes called the assumption of realism and second that Alice s choice of action cannot influence Bob s result or vice versa often called the assumption of locality 10 117 Quantum mechanics can violate the CHSH inequality as follows Victor prepares a pair of qubits which he describes by the Bell state ps 0 1 1 0 2 displaystyle psi rangle frac 0 rangle otimes 1 rangle 1 rangle otimes 0 rangle sqrt 2 nbsp where 0 displaystyle 0 rangle nbsp and 1 displaystyle 1 rangle nbsp are the eigenstates of one of the Pauli matrices sz 100 1 displaystyle sigma z begin pmatrix 1 amp 0 0 amp 1 end pmatrix nbsp Victor then passes the first qubit to Alice and the second to Bob Alice and Bob s choices of possible measurements are also defined in terms of the Pauli matrices Alice measures either of the two observables sz displaystyle sigma z nbsp and sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp A0 sz A1 sx 0110 displaystyle A 0 sigma z A 1 sigma x begin pmatrix 0 amp 1 1 amp 0 end pmatrix nbsp and Bob measures either of the two observables B0 sx sz2 B1 sx sz2 displaystyle B 0 frac sigma x sigma z sqrt 2 B 1 frac sigma x sigma z sqrt 2 nbsp Victor can calculate the quantum expectation values for pairs of these observables using the Born rule A0 B0 12 A0 B1 12 A1 B0 12 A1 B1 12 displaystyle langle A 0 otimes B 0 rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 langle A 0 otimes B 1 rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 langle A 1 otimes B 0 rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 langle A 1 otimes B 1 rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 nbsp While only one of these four measurements can be made in a single trial of the experiment the sum A0 B0 A0 B1 A1 B0 A1 B1 22 displaystyle langle A 0 otimes B 0 rangle langle A 0 otimes B 1 rangle langle A 1 otimes B 0 rangle langle A 1 otimes B 1 rangle 2 sqrt 2 nbsp gives the sum of the average values that Victor expects to find across multiple trials This value exceeds the classical upper bound of 2 that was deduced from the hypothesis of local hidden variables 10 116 The value 22 displaystyle 2 sqrt 2 nbsp is in fact the largest that quantum physics permits for this combination of expectation values making it a Tsirelson bound 13 140 nbsp An illustration of the CHSH game the referee Victor sends a bit each to Alice and to Bob and Alice and Bob each send a bit back to the referee The CHSH inequality can also be thought of as a game in which Alice and Bob try to coordinate their actions 14 15 Victor prepares two bits x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp independently and at random He sends bit x displaystyle x nbsp to Alice and bit y displaystyle y nbsp to Bob Alice and Bob win if they return answer bits a displaystyle a nbsp and b displaystyle b nbsp to Victor satisfyingxy a bmod2 displaystyle xy a b mod 2 nbsp Or equivalently Alice and Bob win if the logical AND of x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp is the logical XOR of a displaystyle a nbsp and b displaystyle b nbsp Alice and Bob can agree upon any strategy they desire before the game but they cannot communicate once the game begins In any theory based on local hidden variables Alice and Bob s probability of winning is no greater than 3 4 displaystyle 3 4 nbsp regardless of what strategy they agree upon beforehand However if they share an entangled quantum state their probability of winning can be as large as 2 24 0 85 displaystyle frac 2 sqrt 2 4 approx 0 85 nbsp Variations and related results editBell 1964 edit Bell s 1964 paper points out that under restricted conditions local hidden variable models can reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics He then demonstrates that this cannot hold true in general 3 Bell considers a refinement by David Bohm of the Einstein Podolsky Rosen EPR thought experiment In this scenario a pair of particles are formed together in such a way that they are described by a spin singlet state which is an example of an entangled state The particles then move apart in opposite directions Each particle is measured by a Stern Gerlach device a measuring instrument that can be oriented in different directions and that reports one of two possible outcomes representable by 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp and 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp The configuration of each measuring instrument is represented by a unit vector and the quantum mechanical prediction for the correlation between two detectors with settings a displaystyle vec a nbsp and b displaystyle vec b nbsp isP a b a b displaystyle P vec a vec b vec a cdot vec b nbsp In particular if the orientation of the two detectors is the same a b displaystyle vec a vec b nbsp then the outcome of one measurement is certain to be the negative of the outcome of the other giving P a a 1 displaystyle P vec a vec a 1 nbsp And if the orientations of the two detectors are orthogonal a b 0 displaystyle vec a cdot vec b 0 nbsp then the outcomes are uncorrelated and P a b 0 displaystyle P vec a vec b 0 nbsp Bell proves by example that these special cases can be explained in terms of hidden variables then proceeds to show that the full range of possibilities involving intermediate angles cannot Bell posited that a local hidden variable model for these correlations would explain them in terms of an integral over the possible values of some hidden parameter l displaystyle lambda nbsp P a b dlr l A a l B b l displaystyle P vec a vec b int d lambda rho lambda A vec a lambda B vec b lambda nbsp where r l displaystyle rho lambda nbsp is a probability density function The two functions A a l displaystyle A vec a lambda nbsp and B b l displaystyle B vec b lambda nbsp provide the responses of the two detectors given the orientation vectors and the hidden variable A a l 1 B b l 1 displaystyle A vec a lambda pm 1 B vec b lambda pm 1 nbsp Crucially the outcome of detector A displaystyle A nbsp does not depend upon b displaystyle vec b nbsp and likewise the outcome of B displaystyle B nbsp does not depend upon a displaystyle vec a nbsp because the two detectors are physically separated Now we suppose that the experimenter has a choice of settings for the second detector it can be set either to b displaystyle vec b nbsp or to c displaystyle vec c nbsp Bell proves that the difference in correlation between these two choices of detector setting must satisfy the inequality P a b P a c 1 P b c displaystyle P vec a vec b P vec a vec c leq 1 P vec b vec c nbsp However it is easy to find situations where quantum mechanics violates the Bell inequality 16 425 426 For example let the vectors a displaystyle vec a nbsp and b displaystyle vec b nbsp be orthogonal and let c displaystyle vec c nbsp lie in their plane at a 45 angle from both of them Then P a b 0 displaystyle P vec a vec b 0 nbsp while P a c P b c 22 displaystyle P vec a vec c P vec b vec c frac sqrt 2 2 nbsp but 22 1 22 displaystyle frac sqrt 2 2 nleq 1 frac sqrt 2 2 nbsp Therefore there is no local hidden variable model that can reproduce the predictions of quantum mechanics for all choices of a displaystyle vec a nbsp b displaystyle vec b nbsp and c displaystyle vec c nbsp Experimental results contradict the classical curves and match the curve predicted by quantum mechanics as long as experimental shortcomings are accounted for 9 Bell s 1964 theorem requires the possibility of perfect anti correlations the ability to make a probability 1 prediction about the result from the second detector knowing the result from the first This is related to the EPR criterion of reality a concept introduced in the 1935 paper by Einstein Podolsky and Rosen This paper posits If without in any way disturbing a system we can predict with certainty i e with probability equal to unity the value of a physical quantity then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity 2 GHZ Mermin 1990 edit Main article GHZ experiment Daniel Greenberger Michael A Horne and Anton Zeilinger presented a four particle thought experiment in 1990 which David Mermin then simplified to use only three particles 17 18 In this thought experiment Victor generates a set of three spin 1 2 particles described by the quantum state ps 12 000 111 displaystyle psi rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 000 rangle 111 rangle nbsp where as above 0 displaystyle 0 rangle nbsp and 1 displaystyle 1 rangle nbsp are the eigenvectors of the Pauli matrix sz displaystyle sigma z nbsp Victor then sends a particle each to Alice Bob and Charlie who wait at widely separated locations Alice measures either sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp or sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp on her particle and so do Bob and Charlie The result of each measurement is either 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp or 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp Applying the Born rule to the three qubit state ps displaystyle psi rangle nbsp Victor predicts that whenever the three measurements include one sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp and two sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp s the product of the outcomes will always be 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp This follows because ps displaystyle psi rangle nbsp is an eigenvector of sx sy sy displaystyle sigma x otimes sigma y otimes sigma y nbsp with eigenvalue 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp and likewise for sy sx sy displaystyle sigma y otimes sigma x otimes sigma y nbsp and sy sy sx displaystyle sigma y otimes sigma y otimes sigma x nbsp Therefore knowing Alice s result for a sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp measurement and Bob s result for a sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp measurement Victor can predict with probability 1 what result Charlie will return for a sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp measurement According to the EPR criterion of reality there would be an element of reality corresponding to the outcome of a sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp measurement upon Charlie s qubit Indeed this same logic applies to both measurements and all three qubits Per the EPR criterion of reality then each particle contains an instruction set that determines the outcome of a sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp or sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp measurement upon it The set of all three particles would then be described by the instruction set ax ay bx by cx cy displaystyle a x a y b x b y c x c y nbsp with each entry being either 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp or 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp and each sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp or sy displaystyle sigma y nbsp measurement simply returning the appropriate value If Alice Bob and Charlie all perform the sx displaystyle sigma x nbsp measurement then the product of their results would be axbxcx displaystyle a x b x c x nbsp This value can be deduced from axbycy aybxcy aybycx axbxcxay2by2cy2 axbxcx displaystyle a x b y c y a y b x c y a y b y c x a x b x c x a y 2 b y 2 c y 2 a x b x c x nbsp because the square of either 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp or 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp is 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp Each factor in parentheses equals 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp so axbxcx 1 displaystyle a x b x c x 1 nbsp and the product of Alice Bob and Charlie s results will be 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp with probability unity But this is inconsistent with quantum physics Victor can predict using the state ps displaystyle psi rangle nbsp that the measurement sx sx sx displaystyle sigma x otimes sigma x otimes sigma x nbsp will instead yield 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp with probability unity This thought experiment can also be recast as a traditional Bell inequality or equivalently as a nonlocal game in the same spirit as the CHSH game 19 In it Alice Bob and Charlie receive bits x y z displaystyle x y z nbsp from Victor promised to always have an even number of ones that is x y z 0 displaystyle x oplus y oplus z 0 nbsp and send him back bits a b c displaystyle a b c nbsp They win the game if a b c displaystyle a b c nbsp have an odd number of ones for all inputs except x y z 0 displaystyle x y z 0 nbsp when they need to have an even number of ones That is they win the game iff a b c x y z displaystyle a oplus b oplus c x lor y lor z nbsp With local hidden variables the highest probability of victory they can have is 3 4 whereas using the quantum strategy above they win it with certainty This is an example of quantum pseudo telepathy Kochen Specker theorem 1967 edit Main article Kochen Specker theorem In quantum theory orthonormal bases for a Hilbert space represent measurements that can be performed upon a system having that Hilbert space Each vector in a basis represents a possible outcome of that measurement note 2 Suppose that a hidden variable l displaystyle lambda nbsp exists so that knowing the value of l displaystyle lambda nbsp would imply certainty about the outcome of any measurement Given a value of l displaystyle lambda nbsp each measurement outcome that is each vector in the Hilbert space is either impossible or guaranteed A Kochen Specker configuration is a finite set of vectors made of multiple interlocking bases with the property that a vector in it will always be impossible when considered as belonging to one basis and guaranteed when taken as belonging to another In other words a Kochen Specker configuration is an uncolorable set that demonstrates the inconsistency of assuming a hidden variable l displaystyle lambda nbsp can be controlling the measurement outcomes 24 196 201 Free will theorem edit Main article Free will theorem The Kochen Specker type of argument using configurations of interlocking bases can be combined with the idea of measuring entangled pairs that underlies Bell type inequalities This was noted beginning in the 1970s by Kochen 25 Heywood and Redhead 26 Stairs 27 and Brown and Svetlichny 28 As EPR pointed out obtaining a measurement outcome on one half of an entangled pair implies certainty about the outcome of a corresponding measurement on the other half The EPR criterion of reality posits that because the second half of the pair was not disturbed that certainty must be due to a physical property belonging to it 29 In other words by this criterion a hidden variable l displaystyle lambda nbsp must exist within the second as yet unmeasured half of the pair No contradiction arises if only one measurement on the first half is considered However if the observer has a choice of multiple possible measurements and the vectors defining those measurements form a Kochen Specker configuration then some outcome on the second half will be simultaneously impossible and guaranteed This type of argument gained attention when an instance of it was advanced by John Conway and Simon Kochen under the name of the free will theorem 30 31 32 The Conway Kochen theorem uses a pair of entangled qutrits and a Kochen Specker configuration discovered by Asher Peres 33 Quasiclassical entanglement edit Main articles Spekkens toy model and Werner state As Bell pointed out some predictions of quantum mechanics can be replicated in local hidden variable models including special cases of correlations produced from entanglement This topic has been studied systematically in the years since Bell s theorem In 1989 Reinhard Werner introduced what are now called Werner states joint quantum states for a pair of systems that yield EPR type correlations but also admit a hidden variable model 34 Werner states are bipartite quantum states that are invariant under unitaries of symmetric tensor product form rAB U U rAB U U displaystyle rho AB U otimes U rho AB U dagger otimes U dagger nbsp In 2004 Robert Spekkens introduced a toy model that starts with the premise of local discretized degrees of freedom and then imposes a knowledge balance principle that restricts how much an observer can know about those degrees of freedom thereby making them into hidden variables The allowed states of knowledge epistemic states about the underlying variables ontic states mimic some features of quantum states Correlations in the toy model can emulate some aspects of entanglement like monogamy but by construction the toy model can never violate a Bell inequality 35 36 History editBackground edit Main articles EPR paradox and History of quantum mechanics The question of whether quantum mechanics can be completed by hidden variables dates to the early years of quantum theory In his 1932 textbook on quantum mechanics the Hungarian born polymath John von Neumann presented what he claimed to be a proof that there could be no hidden parameters The validity and definitiveness of von Neumann s proof were questioned by Hans Reichenbach in more detail by Grete Hermann and possibly in conversation though not in print by Albert Einstein note 3 Simon Kochen and Ernst Specker rejected von Neumann s key assumption as early as 1961 but did not publish a criticism of it until 1967 42 Einstein argued persistently that quantum mechanics could not be a complete theory His preferred argument relied on a principle of locality Consider a mechanical system constituted of two partial systems A and B which have interaction with each other only during limited time Let the ps function before their interaction be given Then the Schrodinger equation will furnish the ps function after their interaction has taken place Let us now determine the physical condition of the partial system A as completely as possible by measurements Then the quantum mechanics allows us to determine the ps function of the partial system B from the measurements made and from the ps function of the total system This determination however gives a result which depends upon which of the determining magnitudes specifying the condition of A has been measured for instance coordinates or momenta Since there can be only one physical condition of B after the interaction and which can reasonably not be considered as dependent on the particular measurement we perform on the system A separated from B it may be concluded that the ps function is not unambiguously coordinated with the physical condition This coordination of several ps functions with the same physical condition of system B shows again that the ps function cannot be interpreted as a complete description of a physical condition of a unit system 43 The EPR thought experiment is similar also considering two separated systems A and B described by a joint wave function However the EPR paper adds the idea later known as the EPR criterion of reality according to which the ability to predict with probability 1 the outcome of a measurement upon B implies the existence of an element of reality within B 44 In 1951 David Bohm proposed a variant of the EPR thought experiment in which the measurements have discrete ranges of possible outcomes unlike the position and momentum measurements considered by EPR 45 The year before Chien Shiung Wu and Irving Shaknov had successfully measured polarizations of photons produced in entangled pairs thereby making the Bohm version of the EPR thought experiment practically feasible 46 By the late 1940s the mathematician George Mackey had grown interested in the foundations of quantum physics and in 1957 he drew up a list of postulates that he took to be a precise definition of quantum mechanics 47 Mackey conjectured that one of the postulates was redundant and shortly thereafter Andrew M Gleason proved that it was indeed deducible from the other postulates 48 49 Gleason s theorem provided an argument that a broad class of hidden variable theories are incompatible with quantum mechanics note 4 More specifically Gleason s theorem rules out hidden variable models that are noncontextual Any hidden variable model for quantum mechanics must in order to avoid the implications of Gleason s theorem involve hidden variables that are not properties belonging to the measured system alone but also dependent upon the external context in which the measurement is made This type of dependence is often seen as contrived or undesirable in some settings it is inconsistent with special relativity 5 51 The Kochen Specker theorem refines this statement by constructing a specific finite subset of rays on which no such probability measure can be defined 5 52 Tsung Dao Lee came close to deriving Bell s theorem in 1960 He considered events where two kaons were produced traveling in opposite directions and came to the conclusion that hidden variables could not explain the correlations that could be obtained in such situations However complications arose due to the fact that kaons decay and he did not go so far as to deduce a Bell type inequality note 5 Bell s publications edit Bell chose to publish his theorem in a comparatively obscure journal because it did not require page charges in fact paying the authors who published there at the time Because the journal did not provide free reprints of articles for the authors to distribute however Bell had to spend the money he received to buy copies that he could send to other physicists 53 While the articles printed in the journal themselves listed the publication s name simply as Physics the covers carried the trilingual version Physics Physique Fizika to reflect that it would print articles in English French and Russian 41 92 100 289 Prior to proving his 1964 result Bell also proved a result equivalent to the Kochen Specker theorem hence the latter is sometimes also known as the Bell Kochen Specker or Bell KS theorem However publication of this theorem was inadvertently delayed until 1966 5 54 In that paper Bell argued that because an explanation of quantum phenomena in terms of hidden variables would require nonlocality the EPR paradox is resolved in the way which Einstein would have liked least 54 Experiments edit nbsp Scheme of a two channel Bell testThe source S produces pairs of photons sent in opposite directions Each photon encounters a two channel polariser whose orientation a or b can be set by the experimenter Emerging signals from each channel are detected and coincidences of four types and counted by the coincidence monitor Main article Bell test In 1967 the unusual title Physics Physique Fizika caught the attention of John Clauser who then discovered Bell s paper and began to consider how to perform a Bell test in the laboratory 55 Clauser and Stuart Freedman would go on to perform a Bell test in 1972 56 57 This was only a limited test because the choice of detector settings was made before the photons had left the source In 1982 Alain Aspect and collaborators performed the first Bell test to remove this limitation 58 This began a trend of progressively more stringent Bell tests The GHZ thought experiment was implemented in practice using entangled triplets of photons in 2000 59 By 2002 testing the CHSH inequality was feasible in undergraduate laboratory courses 60 In Bell tests there may be problems of experimental design or set up that affect the validity of the experimental findings These problems are often referred to as loopholes The purpose of the experiment is to test whether nature can be described by local hidden variable theory which would contradict the predictions of quantum mechanics The most prevalent loopholes in real experiments are the detection and locality loopholes 61 The detection loophole is opened when a small fraction of the particles usually photons are detected in the experiment making it possible to explain the data with local hidden variables by assuming that the detected particles are an unrepresentative sample The locality loophole is opened when the detections are not done with a spacelike separation making it possible for the result of one measurement to influence the other without contradicting relativity In some experiments there may be additional defects that make local hidden variable explanations of Bell test violations possible 62 Although both the locality and detection loopholes had been closed in different experiments a long standing challenge was to close both simultaneously in the same experiment This was finally achieved in three experiments in 2015 63 64 65 66 67 Regarding these results Alain Aspect writes that no experiment can be said to be totally loophole free but he says the experiments remove the last doubts that we should renounce local hidden variables and refers to examples of remaining loopholes as being far fetched and foreign to the usual way of reasoning in physics 68 These efforts to experimentally validate violations of the Bell inequalities would later result in Clauser Aspect and Anton Zeilinger being awarded the 2022 Nobel Prize in Physics 69 Interpretations editMain article Interpretations of quantum mechanics Reactions to Bell s theorem have been many and varied Maximilian Schlosshauer Johannes Kofler and Zeilinger write that Bell inequalities provide a wonderful example of how we can have a rigorous theoretical result tested by numerous experiments and yet disagree about the implications 70 The Copenhagen Interpretation edit The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg It is one of the oldest of numerous proposed interpretations of quantum mechanics as features of it date to the development of quantum mechanics during 1925 1927 and it remains one of the most commonly taught 71 There is no definitive historical statement of what is the Copenhagen interpretation In particular there were fundamental disagreements between the views of Bohr and Heisenberg 72 73 74 Some basic principles generally accepted as part of the Copenhagen collection include the idea that quantum mechanics is intrinsically indeterministic with probabilities calculated using the Born rule 75 and the complementarity principle certain properties cannot be jointly defined for the same system at the same time In order to talk about a specific property of a system that system must be considered within the context of a specific laboratory arrangement Observable quantities corresponding to mutually exclusive laboratory arrangements cannot be predicted together but considering multiple such mutually exclusive experiments is necessary to characterize a system 72 Bohr himself used complementarity to argue that the EPR paradox was fallacious noting that since measurements of position and of momentum are complementary making the choice to measure one excludes the possibility of measuring the other Consequently he argued a fact deduced regarding one arrangement of laboratory apparatus could not be combined with a fact deduced by means of the other and so the inference of predetermined position and momentum values for the second particle was not valid 38 194 197 Bohr concluded that EPR s arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete 76 Copenhagen type interpretations generally take the violation of Bell inequalities as grounds to reject the assumption often called counterfactual definiteness or realism which is not necessarily the same as abandoning realism in a broader philosophical sense 77 78 For example Roland Omnes argues for the rejection of hidden variables and concludes that quantum mechanics is probably as realistic as any theory of its scope and maturity ever will be 79 531 This is also the route taken by interpretations that descend from the Copenhagen tradition such as consistent histories often advertised as Copenhagen done right 80 as well as QBism 81 Many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics edit The Many worlds interpretation also known as the Everett interpretation is local and deterministic as it consists of the unitary part of quantum mechanics without collapse It can generate correlations that violate a Bell inequality because it violates an implicit assumption by Bell that measurements have a single outcome In fact Bell s theorem can be proven in the Many Worlds framework from the assumption that a measurement has a single outcome Therefore a violation of a Bell inequality can be interpreted as a demonstration that measurements have multiple outcomes 82 The explanation it provides for the Bell correlations is that when Alice and Bob make their measurements they split into local branches From the point of view of each copy of Alice there are multiple copies of Bob experiencing different results so Bob cannot have a definite result and the same is true from the point of view of each copy of Bob They will obtain a mutually well defined result only when their future light cones overlap At this point we can say that the Bell correlation starts existing but it was produced by a purely local mechanism Therefore the violation of a Bell inequality cannot be interpreted as a proof of non locality 83 Non local hidden variables edit Most advocates of the hidden variables idea believe that experiments have ruled out local hidden variables note 6 They are ready to give up locality explaining the violation of Bell s inequality by means of a non local hidden variable theory in which the particles exchange information about their states This is the basis of the Bohm interpretation of quantum mechanics which requires that all particles in the universe be able to instantaneously exchange information with all others One challenge for non local hidden variable theories is to explain why this instantaneous communication can exist at the level of the hidden variables but it cannot be used to send signals 86 A 2007 experiment ruled out a large class of non Bohmian non local hidden variable theories though not Bohmian mechanics itself 87 The transactional interpretation which postulates waves traveling both backwards and forwards in time is likewise non local 88 Superdeterminism edit Main article Superdeterminism A necessary assumption to derive Bell s theorem is that the hidden variables are not correlated with the measurement settings This assumption has been justified on the grounds that the experimenter has free will to choose the settings and that it is necessary to do science in the first place A hypothetical theory where the choice of measurement is necessarily correlated with the system being measured is known as superdeterministic 61 A few advocates of deterministic models have not given up on local hidden variables For example Gerard t Hooft has argued that superdeterminism cannot be dismissed 89 See also edit nbsp physics portalEinstein s thought experiments Epistemological Letters Fundamental Fysiks Group Leggett inequality Leggett Garg inequality Mermin s device Mott problem PBR theorem Quantum contextuality Quantum nonlocality Renninger negative result experimentNotes edit We are for convenience assuming that the response of the detector to the underlying property is deterministic This assumption can be replaced it is equivalent to postulating a joint probability distribution over all the observables of the experiment 11 12 In more detail as developed by Paul Dirac 20 David Hilbert 21 John von Neumann 22 and Hermann Weyl 23 the state of a quantum mechanical system is a vector ps displaystyle psi rangle nbsp belonging to a separable Hilbert space H displaystyle mathcal H nbsp Physical quantities of interest position momentum energy spin are represented by observables which are self adjoint linear operators acting on the Hilbert space When an observable is measured the result will be one of its eigenvalues with probability given by the Born rule in the simplest case the eigenvalue h displaystyle eta nbsp is non degenerate and the probability is given by h ps 2 displaystyle langle eta psi rangle 2 nbsp where h displaystyle eta rangle nbsp is its associated eigenvector More generally the eigenvalue is degenerate and the probability is given by ps Phps displaystyle langle psi P eta psi rangle nbsp where Ph displaystyle P eta nbsp is the projector onto its associated eigenspace For the purposes of this discussion we can take the eigenvalues to be non degenerate See Reichenbach 37 and Jammer 38 276 Mermin and Schack 39 and for Einstein s remarks Clauser and Shimony 40 and Wick 41 286 A hidden variable theory that is deterministic implies that the probability of a given outcome is always either 0 or 1 For example a Stern Gerlach measurement on a spin 1 atom will report that the atom s angular momentum along the chosen axis is one of three possible values which can be designated displaystyle nbsp 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp and displaystyle nbsp In a deterministic hidden variable theory there exists an underlying physical property that fixes the result found in the measurement Conditional on the value of the underlying physical property any given outcome for example a result of displaystyle nbsp must be either impossible or guaranteed But Gleason s theorem implies that there can be no such deterministic probability measure because it proves that any probability measure must take the form of a mapping u ru u displaystyle u to langle rho u u rangle nbsp for some density operator r displaystyle rho nbsp This mapping is continuous on the unit sphere of the Hilbert space and since this unit sphere is connected no continuous probability measure on it can be deterministic 50 1 3 This was reported by Max Jammer 38 308 Lee is best known for his prediction with Chen Ning Yang of the violation of parity conservation a prediction that earned them the Nobel Prize after it was confirmed by Chien Shiung Wu who did not share in the Prize E T Jaynes was one exception 84 but Jaynes arguments have not generally been found persuasive 85 References edit Bell John S 1987 Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics Cambridge University Press p 65 ISBN 9780521368698 OCLC 15053677 a b Einstein A Podolsky B Rosen N 1935 05 15 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete Physical Review 47 10 777 780 Bibcode 1935PhRv 47 777E doi 10 1103 PhysRev 47 777 a b Bell J S 1964 On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox PDF Physics Physique Fizika 1 3 195 200 doi 10 1103 PhysicsPhysiqueFizika 1 195 Parker Sybil B 1994 McGraw Hill Encyclopaedia of Physics 2nd ed McGraw Hill p 542 ISBN 978 0 07 051400 3 a b c d Mermin N David July 1993 Hidden Variables and the Two Theorems of John Bell PDF Reviews of Modern Physics 65 3 803 15 arXiv 1802 10119 Bibcode 1993RvMP 65 803M doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 65 803 S2CID 119546199 The Nobel Prize in Physics 2022 Nobel Prize Press release The Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences October 4 2022 Retrieved 6 October 2022 The BIG Bell Test Collaboration 9 May 2018 Challenging local realism with human choices Nature 557 7704 212 216 arXiv 1805 04431 Bibcode 2018Natur 557 212B doi 10 1038 s41586 018 0085 3 PMID 29743691 S2CID 13665914 Wolchover Natalie 2017 02 07 Experiment Reaffirms Quantum Weirdness Quanta Magazine Retrieved 2020 02 08 a b Shimony Abner Bell s Theorem In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b c d Nielsen Michael A Chuang Isaac L 2010 Quantum Computation and Quantum Information 2nd ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 107 00217 3 OCLC 844974180 Fine Arthur 1982 02 01 Hidden Variables Joint Probability and the Bell Inequalities Physical Review Letters 48 5 291 295 Bibcode 1982PhRvL 48 291F doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 48 291 ISSN 0031 9007 Braunstein Samuel L Caves Carlton M August 1990 Wringing out better Bell inequalities Annals of Physics 202 1 22 56 Bibcode 1990AnPhy 202 22B doi 10 1016 0003 4916 90 90339 P Rau Jochen 2021 Quantum theory an information processing approach Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 192 65027 6 OCLC 1256446911 Cleve R Hoyer P Toner B Watrous J 2004 Consequences and limits of nonlocal strategies Proceedings 19th IEEE Annual Conference on Computational Complexity 2004 IEEE pp 236 249 arXiv quant ph 0404076 Bibcode 2004quant ph 4076C doi 10 1109 CCC 2004 1313847 ISBN 0 7695 2120 7 OCLC 55954993 S2CID 8077237 Barnum H Beigi S Boixo S Elliott M B Wehner S 2010 04 06 Local Quantum Measurement and No Signaling Imply Quantum Correlations Physical Review Letters 104 14 140401 arXiv 0910 3952 Bibcode 2010PhRvL 104n0401B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 104 140401 ISSN 0031 9007 PMID 20481921 S2CID 17298392 Griffiths David J 2005 Introduction to Quantum Mechanics 2nd ed Upper Saddle River NJ Pearson Prentice Hall ISBN 0 13 111892 7 OCLC 53926857 Greenberger D Horne M Shimony A Zeilinger A 1990 Bell s theorem without inequalities American Journal of Physics 58 12 1131 Bibcode 1990AmJPh 58 1131G doi 10 1119 1 16243 Mermin N David 1990 Quantum mysteries revisited American Journal of Physics 58 8 731 734 Bibcode 1990AmJPh 58 731M doi 10 1119 1 16503 Brassard Gilles Broadbent Anne Tapp Alain 2005 Recasting Mermin s multi player game into the framework of pseudo telepathy Quantum Information and Computation 5 7 538 550 arXiv quant ph 0408052 Bibcode 2004quant ph 8052B doi 10 26421 QIC5 7 2 Dirac Paul Adrien Maurice 1930 The Principles of Quantum Mechanics Oxford Clarendon Press Hilbert David 2009 Sauer Tilman Majer Ulrich eds Lectures on the Foundations of Physics 1915 1927 Relativity Quantum Theory and Epistemology Springer doi 10 1007 b12915 ISBN 978 3 540 20606 4 OCLC 463777694 von Neumann John 1932 Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik Berlin Springer English translation Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Translated by Beyer Robert T Princeton University Press 1955 Weyl Hermann 1950 1931 The Theory of Groups and Quantum Mechanics Translated by Robertson H P Dover ISBN 978 0 486 60269 1 Translated from the German Gruppentheorie und Quantenmechanik 2nd ed S Hirzel Verlag de 1931 Peres Asher 1993 Quantum Theory Concepts and Methods Kluwer ISBN 0 7923 2549 4 OCLC 28854083 Redhead Michael Brown Harvey 1991 07 01 Nonlocality in Quantum Mechanics Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volumes 65 1 119 160 doi 10 1093 aristoteliansupp 65 1 119 ISSN 0309 7013 JSTOR 4106773 A similar approach was arrived at independently by Simon Kochen although never published private communication Heywood Peter Redhead Michael L G May 1983 Nonlocality and the Kochen Specker paradox Foundations of Physics 13 5 481 499 Bibcode 1983FoPh 13 481H doi 10 1007 BF00729511 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 120340929 Stairs Allen December 1983 Quantum Logic Realism and Value Definiteness Philosophy of Science 50 4 578 602 doi 10 1086 289140 ISSN 0031 8248 S2CID 122885859 Brown H R Svetlichny G November 1990 Nonlocality and Gleason s lemma Part I Deterministic theories Foundations of Physics 20 11 1379 1387 Bibcode 1990FoPh 20 1379B doi 10 1007 BF01883492 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 122868901 Glick David Boge Florian J 2019 10 22 Is the Reality Criterion Analytic Erkenntnis 86 6 1445 1451 arXiv 1909 11893 Bibcode 2019arXiv190911893G doi 10 1007 s10670 019 00163 w ISSN 0165 0106 S2CID 202889160 Conway John Kochen Simon 2006 The Free Will Theorem Foundations of Physics 36 10 1441 arXiv quant ph 0604079 Bibcode 2006FoPh 36 1441C doi 10 1007 s10701 006 9068 6 S2CID 12999337 Rehmeyer Julie 2008 08 15 Do subatomic particles have free will Science News Retrieved 2022 04 23 Thomas Rachel 2011 12 27 John Conway discovering free will part I Plus Magazine Retrieved 2022 04 23 Conway John H Kochen Simon 2009 The strong free will theorem PDF Notices of the AMS 56 2 226 232 Werner Reinhard F 1989 10 01 Quantum states with Einstein Podolsky Rosen correlations admitting a hidden variable model Physical Review A 40 8 4277 4281 Bibcode 1989PhRvA 40 4277W doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 40 4277 ISSN 0556 2791 PMID 9902666 Spekkens Robert W 2007 03 19 Evidence for the epistemic view of quantum states A toy theory Physical Review A 75 3 032110 arXiv quant ph 0401052 Bibcode 2007PhRvA 75c2110S doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 75 032110 ISSN 1050 2947 S2CID 117284016 Catani Lorenzo Browne Dan E 2017 07 27 Spekkens toy model in all dimensions and its relationship with stabiliser quantum mechanics New Journal of Physics 19 7 073035 arXiv 1701 07801 Bibcode 2017NJPh 19g3035C doi 10 1088 1367 2630 aa781c ISSN 1367 2630 S2CID 119428107 Reichenbach Hans 1944 Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics University of California Press p 14 OCLC 872622725 a b c Jammer Max 1974 The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics John Wiley and Sons ISBN 0 471 43958 4 Mermin N David Schack Rudiger 2018 Homer nodded von Neumann s surprising oversight Foundations of Physics 48 9 1007 1020 arXiv 1805 10311 Bibcode 2018FoPh 48 1007M doi 10 1007 s10701 018 0197 5 S2CID 118951033 Clauser J F Shimony A 1978 Bell s theorem Experimental tests and implications PDF Reports on Progress in Physics 41 12 1881 1927 Bibcode 1978RPPh 41 1881C CiteSeerX 10 1 1 482 4728 doi 10 1088 0034 4885 41 12 002 S2CID 250885175 Archived PDF from the original on 2017 09 23 Retrieved 2017 10 28 a b Wick David 1995 Bell s Theorem The Infamous Boundary Seven Decades of Heresy in Quantum Physics New York Springer pp 92 100 doi 10 1007 978 1 4612 4030 3 11 ISBN 978 0 387 94726 6 Conway John Kochen Simon 2002 The Geometry of the Quantum Paradoxes In Bertlmann Reinhold A Zeilinger Anton eds Quantum Un speakables From Bell to Quantum Information Berlin Springer pp 257 269 ISBN 3 540 42756 2 OCLC 49404213 Einstein Albert March 1936 Physics and reality Journal of the Franklin Institute 221 3 349 382 Bibcode 1936FrInJ 221 349E doi 10 1016 S0016 0032 36 91047 5 Harrigan Nicholas Spekkens Robert W 2010 Einstein incompleteness and the epistemic view of quantum states Foundations of Physics 40 2 125 arXiv 0706 2661 Bibcode 2010FoPh 40 125H doi 10 1007 s10701 009 9347 0 S2CID 32755624 Bohm David 1989 1951 Quantum Theory Dover reprint ed Prentice Hall pp 614 623 ISBN 978 0 486 65969 5 OCLC 1103789975 Wu C S Shaknov I 1950 The Angular Correlation of Scattered Annihilation Radiation Physical Review 77 1 136 Bibcode 1950PhRv 77 136W doi 10 1103 PhysRev 77 136 Mackey George W 1957 Quantum Mechanics and Hilbert Space The American Mathematical Monthly 64 8P2 45 57 doi 10 1080 00029890 1957 11989120 JSTOR 2308516 Gleason Andrew M 1957 Measures on the closed subspaces of a Hilbert space Indiana University Mathematics Journal 6 4 885 893 doi 10 1512 iumj 1957 6 56050 MR 0096113 Chernoff Paul R Andy Gleason and Quantum Mechanics PDF Notices of the AMS 56 10 1253 1259 Wilce A 2017 Quantum Logic and Probability Theory Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Shimony Abner 1984 Contextual Hidden Variable Theories and Bell s Inequalities British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 1 25 45 doi 10 1093 bjps 35 1 25 Peres Asher 1991 Two simple proofs of the Kochen Specker theorem Journal of Physics A Mathematical and General 24 4 L175 L178 Bibcode 1991JPhA 24L 175P doi 10 1088 0305 4470 24 4 003 ISSN 0305 4470 Whitaker Andrew 2016 John Stewart Bell and Twentieth Century Physics Vision and Integrity Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 874299 9 a b Bell J S 1966 On the problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics Reviews of Modern Physics 38 3 447 452 Bibcode 1966RvMP 38 447B doi 10 1103 revmodphys 38 447 OSTI 1444158 Kaiser David 2012 01 30 How the Hippies Saved Physics Science Counterculture and the Quantum Revival Excerpt Scientific American Retrieved 2020 02 11 Freedman S J Clauser J F 1972 Experimental test of local hidden variable theories PDF Physical Review Letters 28 938 938 941 Bibcode 1972PhRvL 28 938F doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 28 938 Freedman Stuart Jay 1972 05 05 Experimental test of local hidden variable theories PDF PhD University of California Berkeley Aspect Alain Dalibard Jean Roger Gerard 1982 Experimental Test of Bell s Inequalities Using Time Varying Analyzers Physical Review Letters 49 25 1804 7 Bibcode 1982PhRvL 49 1804A doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 49 1804 Pan Jian Wei Bouwmeester D Daniell M Weinfurter H Zeilinger A 2000 Experimental test of quantum nonlocality in three photon GHZ entanglement Nature 403 6769 515 519 Bibcode 2000Natur 403 515P doi 10 1038 35000514 PMID 10676953 S2CID 4309261 Dehlinger Dietrich Mitchell M W 2002 Entangled photons nonlocality and Bell inequalities in the undergraduate laboratory American Journal of Physics 70 9 903 910 arXiv quant ph 0205171 Bibcode 2002AmJPh 70 903D doi 10 1119 1 1498860 S2CID 49487096 a b Larsson Jan Ake 2014 Loopholes in Bell inequality tests of local realism Journal of Physics A Mathematical and Theoretical 47 42 424003 arXiv 1407 0363 Bibcode 2014JPhA 47P4003L doi 10 1088 1751 8113 47 42 424003 S2CID 40332044 Gerhardt I Liu Q Lamas Linares A Skaar J Scarani V et al 2011 Experimentally faking the violation of Bell s inequalities Physical Review Letters 107 17 170404 arXiv 1106 3224 Bibcode 2011PhRvL 107q0404G doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 107 170404 PMID 22107491 S2CID 16306493 Merali Zeeya 27 August 2015 Quantum spookiness passes toughest test yet Nature News 525 7567 14 15 Bibcode 2015Natur 525 14M doi 10 1038 nature 2015 18255 PMID 26333448 S2CID 4409566 Markoff Jack 21 October 2015 Sorry Einstein Quantum Study Suggests Spooky Action Is Real New York Times Retrieved 21 October 2015 Hensen B et al 21 October 2015 Loophole free Bell inequality violation using electron spins separated by 1 3 kilometres Nature 526 7575 682 686 arXiv 1508 05949 Bibcode 2015Natur 526 682H doi 10 1038 nature15759 PMID 26503041 S2CID 205246446 Shalm L K et al 16 December 2015 Strong Loophole Free Test of Local Realism Physical Review Letters 115 25 250402 arXiv 1511 03189 Bibcode 2015PhRvL 115y0402S doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 115 250402 PMC 5815856 PMID 26722906 Giustina M et al 16 December 2015 Significant Loophole Free Test of Bell s Theorem with Entangled Photons Physical Review Letters 115 25 250401 arXiv 1511 03190 Bibcode 2015PhRvL 115y0401G doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 115 250401 PMID 26722905 S2CID 13789503 Aspect Alain December 16 2015 Closing the Door on Einstein and Bohr s Quantum Debate Physics 8 123 Bibcode 2015PhyOJ 8 123A doi 10 1103 Physics 8 123 Ahlander Johan Burger Ludwig Pollard Niklas 2022 10 04 Nobel physics prize goes to sleuths of spooky quantum science Reuters Retrieved 2022 10 04 Schlosshauer Maximilian Kofler Johannes Zeilinger Anton 2013 01 06 A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 3 222 230 arXiv 1301 1069 Bibcode 2013SHPMP 44 222S doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2013 04 004 S2CID 55537196 Siddiqui Shabnam Singh Chandralekha 2017 How diverse are physics instructors attitudes and approaches to teaching undergraduate level quantum mechanics European Journal of Physics 38 3 035703 Bibcode 2017EJPh 38c5703S doi 10 1088 1361 6404 aa6131 a b Faye Jan 2019 Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2019 04 29 Retrieved 2021 09 16 Camilleri K Schlosshauer M 2015 Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr s Doctrine of Classical Concepts Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 49 73 83 arXiv 1502 06547 Bibcode 2015SHPMP 49 73C doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 01 005 S2CID 27697360 Peres Asher 2002 Popper s experiment and the Copenhagen interpretation Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 23 arXiv quant ph 9910078 Bibcode 1999quant ph 10078P doi 10 1016 S1355 2198 01 00034 X Bohr N 1928 The Quantum Postulate and the Recent Development of Atomic Theory Nature 121 3050 580 590 Bibcode 1928Natur 121 580B doi 10 1038 121580a0 p 586 In this connexion Born succeeded in obtaining a statistical interpretation of the wave functions allowing a calculation of the probability of the individual transition processes required by the quantum postulate Bohr N 1935 10 13 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete PDF Physical Review 48 8 696 702 Bibcode 1935PhRv 48 696B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 48 696 Archived PDF from the original on 2020 01 09 Retrieved 2021 09 16 Werner Reinhard F 2014 10 24 Comment on What Bell did Journal of Physics A Mathematical and Theoretical 47 42 424011 Bibcode 2014JPhA 47P4011W doi 10 1088 1751 8113 47 42 424011 ISSN 1751 8113 S2CID 122180759 Zukowski Marek 2017 Bell s Theorem Tells Us Not What Quantum Mechanics is but What Quantum Mechanics is Not In Bertlmann Reinhold Zeilinger Anton eds Quantum Un Speakables II The Frontiers Collection Cham Springer International Publishing pp 175 185 arXiv 1501 05640 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 38987 5 10 ISBN 978 3 319 38985 1 S2CID 119214547 Omnes R 1994 The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 03669 4 OCLC 439453957 Hohenberg P C 2010 10 05 Colloquium An introduction to consistent quantum theory Reviews of Modern Physics 82 4 2835 2844 arXiv 0909 2359 Bibcode 2010RvMP 82 2835H doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 82 2835 ISSN 0034 6861 S2CID 20551033 Healey Richard 2016 Quantum Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Archived from the original on 2021 08 17 Retrieved 2021 09 16 Deutsch David Hayden Patrick 2000 Information flow in entangled quantum systems Proceedings of the Royal Society A 456 1999 1759 1774 arXiv quant ph 9906007 Bibcode 2000RSPSA 456 1759D doi 10 1098 rspa 2000 0585 S2CID 13998168 Brown Harvey R Timpson Christopher G 2016 Bell on Bell s Theorem The Changing Face of Nonlocality In Bell Mary Gao Shan eds Quantum Nonlocality and Reality 50 years of Bell s theorem Cambridge University Press pp 91 123 arXiv 1501 03521 doi 10 1017 CBO9781316219393 008 ISBN 9781316219393 S2CID 118686956 Jaynes E T 1989 Clearing up Mysteries the Original Goal Maximum Entropy and Bayesian Methods PDF pp 1 27 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 46 1264 doi 10 1007 978 94 015 7860 8 1 ISBN 978 90 481 4044 2 Archived PDF from the original on 2011 10 28 Retrieved 2011 10 18 Gill Richard D 2002 Time Finite Statistics and Bell s Fifth Position Proceedings of the Conference Foundations of Probability and Physics 2 Vaxjo Soland Sweden June 2 7 2002 Vol 5 Vaxjo University Press pp 179 206 arXiv quant ph 0301059 Wood Christopher J Spekkens Robert W 2015 03 03 The lesson of causal discovery algorithms for quantum correlations causal explanations of Bell inequality violations require fine tuning New Journal of Physics 17 3 033002 arXiv 1208 4119 Bibcode 2015NJPh 17c3002W doi 10 1088 1367 2630 17 3 033002 ISSN 1367 2630 S2CID 118518558 Groblacher Simon Paterek Tomasz Kaltenbaek Rainer Brukner Caslav Zukowski Marek Aspelmeyer Markus Zeilinger Anton 2007 An experimental test of non local realism Nature 446 7138 871 5 arXiv 0704 2529 Bibcode 2007Natur 446 871G doi 10 1038 nature05677 PMID 17443179 S2CID 4412358 Kastner Ruth E May 2010 The quantum liar experiment in Cramer s transactional interpretation Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 41 2 86 92 arXiv 0906 1626 Bibcode 2010SHPMP 41 86K doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2010 01 001 S2CID 16242184 Archived from the original on 2018 06 24 Retrieved 2021 09 16 t Hooft Gerard 2016 The Cellular Automaton Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Fundamental Theories of Physics Vol 185 Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 319 41285 6 ISBN 978 3 319 41284 9 OCLC 951761277 S2CID 7779840 Archived from the original on 2021 12 29 Retrieved 2020 08 27 Further reading editThe following are intended for general audiences Aczel Amir D 2001 Entanglement The greatest mystery in physics New York Four Walls Eight Windows Afriat A Selleri F 1999 The Einstein Podolsky and Rosen Paradox New York and London Plenum Press Baggott J 1992 The Meaning of Quantum Theory Oxford University Press Gilder Louisa 2008 The Age of Entanglement When Quantum Physics Was Reborn New York Alfred A Knopf Greene Brian 2004 The Fabric of the Cosmos Vintage ISBN 0 375 72720 5 Mermin N David 1981 Bringing home the atomic world Quantum mysteries for anybody American Journal of Physics 49 10 940 943 Bibcode 1981AmJPh 49 940M doi 10 1119 1 12594 S2CID 122724592 Mermin N David April 1985 Is the moon there when nobody looks Reality and the quantum theory Physics Today 38 4 38 47 Bibcode 1985PhT 38d 38M doi 10 1063 1 880968 The following are more technically oriented Aspect A et al 1981 Experimental Tests of Realistic Local Theories via Bell s Theorem Phys Rev Lett 47 7 460 463 Bibcode 1981PhRvL 47 460A doi 10 1103 physrevlett 47 460 Aspect A et al 1982 Experimental Realization of Einstein Podolsky Rosen Bohm Gedankenexperiment A New Violation of Bell s Inequalities Phys Rev Lett 49 2 91 94 Bibcode 1982PhRvL 49 91A doi 10 1103 physrevlett 49 91 Aspect A Grangier P 1985 About resonant scattering and other hypothetical effects in the Orsay atomic cascade experiment tests of Bell inequalities a discussion and some new experimental data Lettere al Nuovo Cimento 43 8 345 348 doi 10 1007 bf02746964 S2CID 120840672 Bell J S 1971 Introduction to the hidden variable question Proceedings of the International School of Physics Enrico Fermi Course IL Foundations of Quantum Mechanics pp 171 81 Bell J S 2004 Bertlmann s Socks and the Nature of Reality Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics Cambridge University Press pp 139 158 D Espagnat B 1979 The Quantum Theory and Reality PDF Scientific American 241 5 158 181 Bibcode 1979SciAm 241e 158D doi 10 1038 scientificamerican1179 158 Archived PDF from the original on 2009 03 27 Retrieved 2009 03 18 Fry E S Walther T Li S 1995 Proposal for a loophole free test of the Bell inequalities PDF Phys Rev A 52 6 4381 4395 Bibcode 1995PhRvA 52 4381F doi 10 1103 physreva 52 4381 hdl 1969 1 126533 PMID 9912775 Archived from the original on 2021 12 29 Retrieved 2018 03 19 Fry E S Walther T 2002 Atom based tests of the Bell Inequalities the legacy of John Bell continues In Bertlmann R A Zeilinger A eds Quantum Un speakables Berlin Heidelberg New York Springer pp 103 117 Goldstein Sheldon et al 2011 Bell s theorem Scholarpedia 6 10 8378 Bibcode 2011SchpJ 6 8378G doi 10 4249 scholarpedia 8378 Griffiths R B 2001 Consistent Quantum Theory Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 80349 6 OCLC 1180958776 Hardy L 1993 Nonlocality for 2 particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states Physical Review Letters 71 11 1665 1668 Bibcode 1993PhRvL 71 1665H doi 10 1103 physrevlett 71 1665 PMID 10054467 S2CID 11839894 Matsukevich D N Maunz P Moehring D L Olmschenk S Monroe C 2008 Bell Inequality Violation with Two Remote Atomic Qubits Phys Rev Lett 100 15 150404 arXiv 0801 2184 Bibcode 2008PhRvL 100o0404M doi 10 1103 physrevlett 100 150404 PMID 18518088 S2CID 11536757 Rieffel Eleanor G Polak Wolfgang H 4 March 2011 4 4 EPR Paradox and Bell s Theorem Quantum Computing A Gentle Introduction MIT Press pp 60 65 ISBN 978 0 262 01506 6 Sulcs S 2003 The Nature of Light and Twentieth Century Experimental Physics Foundations of Science 8 4 365 391 doi 10 1023 A 1026323203487 S2CID 118769677 van Fraassen B C 1991 Quantum Mechanics An Empiricist View Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 198 24861 3 OCLC 22906474 External links edit nbsp Wikibooks has a book on the topic of Quantum Mechanics nbsp Wikiversity has learning resources about Bell s theorem nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Bell s theorem Mermin Spooky Actions At A Distance Oppenheimer Lecture Bell s theorem Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Bell inequalities Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Bell 27s theorem amp oldid 1212395088, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.