fbpx
Wikipedia

Mermin's device

In physics, Mermin's device[1][2] or Mermin's machine[3] is a thought experiment intended to illustrate the non-classical features of nature without making a direct reference to quantum mechanics. The challenge is to reproduce the results of the thought experiment in terms of classical physics. The input of the experiment are particles, starting from a common origin, that reach detectors of a device that are independent from each other, the output are the lights of the device that turn on following a specific set of statistics depending on the configuration of the device.

The results of the thought experiment are constructed in such a way to reproduce the result of a Bell test using quantum entangled particles, which demonstrate how quantum mechanics cannot be explained using a local hidden variable theory. In this way Mermin's device is a pedagogical tool to introduce the unconventional features of quantum mechanics to a larger public.

History edit

The original version with two particles and three settings per detector, was first devised in a paper called "Bringing home the atomic world: Quantum mysteries for anybody" authored by the physicist N. David Mermin in 1981.[4] Richard Feynman told Mermin that it was "One of the most beautiful papers in physics".[5] Mermin later described this accolade as "the finest reward of my entire career in physics". Ed Purcell shared Mermin's article with Willard Van Orman Quine, who then asked Mermin to write a version intended for philosophers, which he then produced.[6][7]

Mermin also published a second version of the thought experiment in 1990 based on the GHZ experiment, with three particles and detectors with only two configurations.[8] In 1993, Lucien Hardy devised a paradox that can be made into a Mermin-device-type thought experiment with two detectors and two settings.[9][10]

Original device edit

Assumptions edit

 
Mermin's original device consist of a source of two particles and two detectors that can be set to settings 1, 2 or 3 each. A single bulb per detector will flash when particles reach the detectors.

In Mermin's original thought experiment, he considers a device consisting of three parts: two detectors A and B, and a source C.[4] The source emits two particles whenever a button is pushed, one particle reaches detector A and the other reaches detector B. The three parts A, B and C are isolated from each other (no connecting pipes, no wires, no antennas) in such a way that the detectors are not signaled when the button of the source has been pushed nor when the other detector has received a particle.

Each detector (A and B) has a switch with three configurations labeled (1,2 and 3) and a red and a green light bulb. Either the green or the red light will turn on (never both) when a particle enters the device after a given period of time. The light bulbs only emit light in the direction of the observer working on the device.

Additional barriers or instrument can be put in place to check that there is no interference between the three parts (A,B,C), as the parts should remain as independent as possible. Only allowing for a single particle to go from C to A and a single particle from C to B, and nothing else between A and B (no vibrations, no electromagnetic radiation).

The experiment runs in the following way. The button of the source C is pushed, particles take some time to travel to the detectors and the detectors flash a light with a color determined by the switch configuration. There are nine total possible configuration of the switches (three for A, three for B).

The switches can be changed at any moment during the experiment, even if the particles are still traveling to reach the detectors, but not after the detectors flash a light. The distance between the detectors can be changed so that the detectors flash a light at the same time or at different times. If detector A is set to flash a light first, the configuration of the switch of detector B can be changed after A has already flashed (similarly if B set to flash first, the settings of A can be change before A flashes).

Results edit

The results of the experiment are given in this table in percentages:[4]

Table 1
Setting of detector 1 Setting of detector 2 Flash the same colors (%) Flash opposite colors (%)
1 1 100 0
2 2
3 3
1 2 25 75
1 3
2 1
2 3
3 1
3 2

Every time the detectors are set to the same setting, the bulbs in each detector always flash same colors (either A and B flash red, or A and B flash green) and never opposite colors (A red B green, or A green B red). Every time the detectors are at different setting, the detectors flash the same color a quarter of the time and opposite colors 3/4 of the time. The challenge consists in finding a device that can reproduce these statistics.

Hidden variables and classical mechanics edit

In order to make sense of the data using classical mechanics, one can consider the existence of three variables per particle that are measured by the detectors and follow the percentages above.[4] Particle that goes into detector A has variables   and the particle that goes into detector B has variables  . These variables determine which color will flash for a specific setting (1,2 and 3). For example, if the particle that goes in A has variables (R,G,G), then if the detector A is set to 1 it will flash red (labelled R), set to 2 or 3 it will flash green (labelled G).

We have 8 possible states:

   
(G,G,G) (G,G,G)
(G,G,R) (G,G,R)
(G,R,G) (G,R,G)
(G,R,R) (G,R,R)
(R,G,G) (R,G,G)
(R,G,R) (R,G,R)
(R,R,G) (R,R,G)
(R,R,R) (R,R,R)

where   in order to reproduce the results of table 1 when selecting the same setting for both detectors.

For any given configuration, if the detector settings were chosen randomly, when the settings of the devices are different (12,13,21,23,31,32), the color of their lights would agree 100% of the time for the states (GGG) and (RRR) and for the other states the results would agree 1/3 of the time.

Thus we reach an impossibility: there is no possible distribution of these states that would allow for the system to flash the same colors 1/4 of the time when the settings are not the same. Thereby, it is not possible to reproduce the results provided in Table 1.

Quantum mechanics edit

 
Stern-Gerlach device, a charged spin 1/2 particle enters into an inhomogeneous magnetic field. Only two possible outcomes are possible, the particle is deviated up or down.
 
Aspect's experiment with an entangled photon source S and polarizers P1 and P2 at angles α and β.

Table 1 can be reproduced using quantum mechanics using quantum entanglement.[4] Mermin reveals a possible construction of his device based on David Bohm's version of the Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox.

One can set two spin-1/2 particles in the maximally entangled singlet Bell state:

 ,

to leave the experiment, where   ( ) is the state where the projection of the spin of particle 1 is aligned (anti-aligned) with a given axis and particle 2 is anti-aligned (aligned) to the same axis. The measurement devices can be replaced with Stern–Gerlach devices, that measure the spin in a given direction. The three different settings determine whether the detectors are vertical or at ±120° to the vertical in the plane of perpendicular to the line of flight of the particles. Detector A flashes green when the spin of the measured particle is aligned with the detector's magnetic field and flashes red when anti-aligned. Detector B has the opposite color scheme with respect to A. Detector B flashes red when the spin of the measured particle is aligned and flashes green when anti-aligned. Another possibility is to use photons that have two possible polarizations, using polarizers as detectors, as in Aspect's experiment.

Quantum mechanics predicts a probability of measuring opposite spin projections given by

 

where   is the relative angle between settings of the detectors. For   and   the system reproduces the result of table 1 keeping all the assumptions.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Ross, Robert (June 2020). "Computer simulation of Mermin's quantum device". American Journal of Physics. 88 (6): 483–489. Bibcode:2020AmJPh..88..483R. doi:10.1119/10.0000833. ISSN 0002-9505. S2CID 219514634.
  2. ^ Stuckey, W. M.; Silberstein, Michael; McDevitt, Timothy; Le, T. D. (2020-09-25). "Answering Mermin's challenge with conservation per no preferred reference frame". Scientific Reports. 10 (1): 15771. Bibcode:2020NatSR..1015771S. doi:10.1038/s41598-020-72817-7. ISSN 2045-2322. PMC 7519099. PMID 32978499.
  3. ^ Mullin, William J. (2017). Quantum weirdness. Oxford, United Kingdom. ISBN 978-0-19-251434-9. OCLC 975487260.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  4. ^ a b c d e Mermin, N. D. (1981). "Bringing home the atomic world: Quantum mysteries for anybody". American Journal of Physics. 49 (10): 940–943. Bibcode:1981AmJPh..49..940M. doi:10.1119/1.12594. ISSN 0002-9505.
  5. ^ Feynman, Richard P. (2008-08-01). Perfectly Reasonable Deviations from the Beaten Track: The Letters of Richard P. Feynman. Basic Books. ISBN 978-0-7867-2242-6.
  6. ^ Mermin, N. David (1990-03-15). Boojums All the Way Through: Communicating Science in a Prosaic Age. Cambridge University Press. pp. xv. ISBN 978-0-521-38880-1.
  7. ^ Mermin, N. David (July 1981). "Quantum Mysteries for Anyone". The Journal of Philosophy. 78 (7): 397–408. doi:10.2307/2026482. JSTOR 2026482.
  8. ^ Mermin, N. David (1990-08-01). "Quantum mysteries revisited". American Journal of Physics. 58 (8): 731–734. Bibcode:1990AmJPh..58..731M. doi:10.1119/1.16503. ISSN 0002-9505.
  9. ^ Hardy, Lucien (1993). "Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states". Physical Review Letters. 71 (11): 1665–1668. Bibcode:1993PhRvL..71.1665H. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.71.1665. PMID 10054467.
  10. ^ Mermin, N. David (1994-10-01). "Quantum mysteries refined". American Journal of Physics. 62 (10): 880–887. Bibcode:1994AmJPh..62..880M. doi:10.1119/1.17733. ISSN 0002-9505.

Additional references edit

  • "David Mermin". The Information Philosopher. Retrieved 2023-03-22.
  • Greenstein, George; Zajonc, Arthur (2006). The Quantum Challenge: Modern Research on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-0-7637-2470-2.
  • Blumel, Reinhold (2010). Foundations of Quantum Mechanics: From Photons to Quantum Computers. Jones & Bartlett Learning. ISBN 978-0-7637-7628-2.

mermin, device, physics, mermin, machine, thought, experiment, intended, illustrate, classical, features, nature, without, making, direct, reference, quantum, mechanics, challenge, reproduce, results, thought, experiment, terms, classical, physics, input, expe. In physics Mermin s device 1 2 or Mermin s machine 3 is a thought experiment intended to illustrate the non classical features of nature without making a direct reference to quantum mechanics The challenge is to reproduce the results of the thought experiment in terms of classical physics The input of the experiment are particles starting from a common origin that reach detectors of a device that are independent from each other the output are the lights of the device that turn on following a specific set of statistics depending on the configuration of the device The results of the thought experiment are constructed in such a way to reproduce the result of a Bell test using quantum entangled particles which demonstrate how quantum mechanics cannot be explained using a local hidden variable theory In this way Mermin s device is a pedagogical tool to introduce the unconventional features of quantum mechanics to a larger public Contents 1 History 2 Original device 2 1 Assumptions 2 2 Results 2 3 Hidden variables and classical mechanics 2 4 Quantum mechanics 3 See also 4 References 4 1 Additional referencesHistory editThe original version with two particles and three settings per detector was first devised in a paper called Bringing home the atomic world Quantum mysteries for anybody authored by the physicist N David Mermin in 1981 4 Richard Feynman told Mermin that it was One of the most beautiful papers in physics 5 Mermin later described this accolade as the finest reward of my entire career in physics Ed Purcell shared Mermin s article with Willard Van Orman Quine who then asked Mermin to write a version intended for philosophers which he then produced 6 7 Mermin also published a second version of the thought experiment in 1990 based on the GHZ experiment with three particles and detectors with only two configurations 8 In 1993 Lucien Hardy devised a paradox that can be made into a Mermin device type thought experiment with two detectors and two settings 9 10 Original device editAssumptions edit nbsp Mermin s original device consist of a source of two particles and two detectors that can be set to settings 1 2 or 3 each A single bulb per detector will flash when particles reach the detectors In Mermin s original thought experiment he considers a device consisting of three parts two detectors A and B and a source C 4 The source emits two particles whenever a button is pushed one particle reaches detector A and the other reaches detector B The three parts A B and C are isolated from each other no connecting pipes no wires no antennas in such a way that the detectors are not signaled when the button of the source has been pushed nor when the other detector has received a particle Each detector A and B has a switch with three configurations labeled 1 2 and 3 and a red and a green light bulb Either the green or the red light will turn on never both when a particle enters the device after a given period of time The light bulbs only emit light in the direction of the observer working on the device Additional barriers or instrument can be put in place to check that there is no interference between the three parts A B C as the parts should remain as independent as possible Only allowing for a single particle to go from C to A and a single particle from C to B and nothing else between A and B no vibrations no electromagnetic radiation The experiment runs in the following way The button of the source C is pushed particles take some time to travel to the detectors and the detectors flash a light with a color determined by the switch configuration There are nine total possible configuration of the switches three for A three for B The switches can be changed at any moment during the experiment even if the particles are still traveling to reach the detectors but not after the detectors flash a light The distance between the detectors can be changed so that the detectors flash a light at the same time or at different times If detector A is set to flash a light first the configuration of the switch of detector B can be changed after A has already flashed similarly if B set to flash first the settings of A can be change before A flashes Results edit The results of the experiment are given in this table in percentages 4 Table 1 Setting of detector 1 Setting of detector 2 Flash the same colors Flash opposite colors 1 1 100 02 23 31 2 25 751 32 12 33 13 2Every time the detectors are set to the same setting the bulbs in each detector always flash same colors either A and B flash red or A and B flash green and never opposite colors A red B green or A green B red Every time the detectors are at different setting the detectors flash the same color a quarter of the time and opposite colors 3 4 of the time The challenge consists in finding a device that can reproduce these statistics Hidden variables and classical mechanics edit In order to make sense of the data using classical mechanics one can consider the existence of three variables per particle that are measured by the detectors and follow the percentages above 4 Particle that goes into detector A has variables a 1 a 2 a 3 displaystyle a 1 a 2 a 3 nbsp and the particle that goes into detector B has variables b 1 b 2 b 3 displaystyle b 1 b 2 b 3 nbsp These variables determine which color will flash for a specific setting 1 2 and 3 For example if the particle that goes in A has variables R G G then if the detector A is set to 1 it will flash red labelled R set to 2 or 3 it will flash green labelled G We have 8 possible states a 1 a 2 a 3 displaystyle a 1 a 2 a 3 nbsp b 1 b 2 b 3 displaystyle b 1 b 2 b 3 nbsp G G G G G G G G R G G R G R G G R G G R R G R R R G G R G G R G R R G R R R G R R G R R R R R R where b 1 b 2 b 3 a 1 a 2 a 3 displaystyle b 1 b 2 b 3 a 1 a 2 a 3 nbsp in order to reproduce the results of table 1 when selecting the same setting for both detectors For any given configuration if the detector settings were chosen randomly when the settings of the devices are different 12 13 21 23 31 32 the color of their lights would agree 100 of the time for the states GGG and RRR and for the other states the results would agree 1 3 of the time Thus we reach an impossibility there is no possible distribution of these states that would allow for the system to flash the same colors 1 4 of the time when the settings are not the same Thereby it is not possible to reproduce the results provided in Table 1 Quantum mechanics edit nbsp Stern Gerlach device a charged spin 1 2 particle enters into an inhomogeneous magnetic field Only two possible outcomes are possible the particle is deviated up or down nbsp Aspect s experiment with an entangled photon source S and polarizers P1 and P2 at angles a and b Table 1 can be reproduced using quantum mechanics using quantum entanglement 4 Mermin reveals a possible construction of his device based on David Bohm s version of the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox One can set two spin 1 2 particles in the maximally entangled singlet Bell state PS 2 displaystyle Psi rangle frac uparrow downarrow rangle downarrow uparrow rangle sqrt 2 nbsp to leave the experiment where displaystyle uparrow downarrow rangle nbsp displaystyle downarrow uparrow rangle nbsp is the state where the projection of the spin of particle 1 is aligned anti aligned with a given axis and particle 2 is anti aligned aligned to the same axis The measurement devices can be replaced with Stern Gerlach devices that measure the spin in a given direction The three different settings determine whether the detectors are vertical or at 120 to the vertical in the plane of perpendicular to the line of flight of the particles Detector A flashes green when the spin of the measured particle is aligned with the detector s magnetic field and flashes red when anti aligned Detector B has the opposite color scheme with respect to A Detector B flashes red when the spin of the measured particle is aligned and flashes green when anti aligned Another possibility is to use photons that have two possible polarizations using polarizers as detectors as in Aspect s experiment Quantum mechanics predicts a probability of measuring opposite spin projections given by P 8 cos 2 8 2 displaystyle P theta cos 2 theta 2 nbsp where 8 displaystyle theta nbsp is the relative angle between settings of the detectors For 8 0 displaystyle theta 0 nbsp and 8 120 displaystyle theta pm 120 circ nbsp the system reproduces the result of table 1 keeping all the assumptions See also editQuantum pseudo telepathyReferences edit Ross Robert June 2020 Computer simulation of Mermin s quantum device American Journal of Physics 88 6 483 489 Bibcode 2020AmJPh 88 483R doi 10 1119 10 0000833 ISSN 0002 9505 S2CID 219514634 Stuckey W M Silberstein Michael McDevitt Timothy Le T D 2020 09 25 Answering Mermin s challenge with conservation per no preferred reference frame Scientific Reports 10 1 15771 Bibcode 2020NatSR 1015771S doi 10 1038 s41598 020 72817 7 ISSN 2045 2322 PMC 7519099 PMID 32978499 Mullin William J 2017 Quantum weirdness Oxford United Kingdom ISBN 978 0 19 251434 9 OCLC 975487260 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link a b c d e Mermin N D 1981 Bringing home the atomic world Quantum mysteries for anybody American Journal of Physics 49 10 940 943 Bibcode 1981AmJPh 49 940M doi 10 1119 1 12594 ISSN 0002 9505 Feynman Richard P 2008 08 01 Perfectly Reasonable Deviations from the Beaten Track The Letters of Richard P Feynman Basic Books ISBN 978 0 7867 2242 6 Mermin N David 1990 03 15 Boojums All the Way Through Communicating Science in a Prosaic Age Cambridge University Press pp xv ISBN 978 0 521 38880 1 Mermin N David July 1981 Quantum Mysteries for Anyone The Journal of Philosophy 78 7 397 408 doi 10 2307 2026482 JSTOR 2026482 Mermin N David 1990 08 01 Quantum mysteries revisited American Journal of Physics 58 8 731 734 Bibcode 1990AmJPh 58 731M doi 10 1119 1 16503 ISSN 0002 9505 Hardy Lucien 1993 Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states Physical Review Letters 71 11 1665 1668 Bibcode 1993PhRvL 71 1665H doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 71 1665 PMID 10054467 Mermin N David 1994 10 01 Quantum mysteries refined American Journal of Physics 62 10 880 887 Bibcode 1994AmJPh 62 880M doi 10 1119 1 17733 ISSN 0002 9505 Additional references edit David Mermin The Information Philosopher Retrieved 2023 03 22 Greenstein George Zajonc Arthur 2006 The Quantum Challenge Modern Research on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Jones amp Bartlett Learning ISBN 978 0 7637 2470 2 Blumel Reinhold 2010 Foundations of Quantum Mechanics From Photons to Quantum Computers Jones amp Bartlett Learning ISBN 978 0 7637 7628 2 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Mermin 27s device amp oldid 1181628366, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.