fbpx
Wikipedia

Tarski's axioms

Tarski's axioms, due to Alfred Tarski, are an axiom set for the substantial fragment of Euclidean geometry that is formulable in first-order logic with identity, and requiring no set theory (Tarski 1959) (i.e., that part of Euclidean geometry that is formulable as an elementary theory). Other modern axiomizations of Euclidean geometry are Hilbert's axioms and Birkhoff's axioms.

Overview edit

Early in his career Tarski taught geometry and researched set theory. His coworker Steven Givant (1999) explained Tarski's take-off point:

From Enriques, Tarski learned of the work of Mario Pieri, an Italian geometer who was strongly influenced by Peano. Tarski preferred Pieri's system [of his Point and Sphere memoir], where the logical structure and the complexity of the axioms were more transparent.

Givant then says that "with typical thoroughness" Tarski devised his system:

What was different about Tarski's approach to geometry? First of all, the axiom system was much simpler than any of the axiom systems that existed up to that time. In fact the length of all of Tarski's axioms together is not much more than just one of Pieri's 24 axioms. It was the first system of Euclidean geometry that was simple enough for all axioms to be expressed in terms of the primitive notions only, without the help of defined notions. Of even greater importance, for the first time a clear distinction was made between full geometry and its elementary — that is, its first order — part.

Like other modern axiomatizations of Euclidean geometry, Tarski's employs a formal system consisting of symbol strings, called sentences, whose construction respects formal syntactical rules, and rules of proof that determine the allowed manipulations of the sentences. Unlike some other modern axiomatizations, such as Birkhoff's and Hilbert's, Tarski's axiomatization has no primitive objects other than points, so a variable or constant cannot refer to a line or an angle. Because points are the only primitive objects, and because Tarski's system is a first-order theory, it is not even possible to define lines as sets of points. The only primitive relations (predicates) are "betweenness" and "congruence" among points.

Tarski's axiomatization is shorter than its rivals, in a sense Tarski and Givant (1999) make explicit. It is more concise than Pieri's because Pieri had only two primitive notions while Tarski introduced three: point, betweenness, and congruence. Such economy of primitive and defined notions means that Tarski's system is not very convenient for doing Euclidean geometry. Rather, Tarski designed his system to facilitate its analysis via the tools of mathematical logic, i.e., to facilitate deriving its metamathematical properties. Tarski's system has the unusual property that all sentences can be written in universal-existential form, a special case of the prenex normal form. This form has all universal quantifiers preceding any existential quantifiers, so that all sentences can be recast in the form   This fact allowed Tarski to prove that Euclidean geometry is decidable: there exists an algorithm which can determine the truth or falsity of any sentence. Tarski's axiomatization is also complete. This does not contradict Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, because Tarski's theory lacks the expressive power needed to interpret Robinson arithmetic (Franzén 2005, pp. 25–26).

The axioms edit

Alfred Tarski worked on the axiomatization and metamathematics of Euclidean geometry intermittently from 1926 until his death in 1983, with Tarski (1959) heralding his mature interest in the subject. The work of Tarski and his students on Euclidean geometry culminated in the monograph Schwabhäuser, Szmielew, and Tarski (1983), which set out the 10 axioms and one axiom schema shown below, the associated metamathematics, and a fair bit of the subject. Gupta (1965) made important contributions, and Tarski and Givant (1999) discuss the history.

Fundamental relations edit

These axioms are a more elegant version of a set Tarski devised in the 1920s as part of his investigation of the metamathematical properties of Euclidean plane geometry. This objective required reformulating that geometry as a first-order theory. Tarski did so by positing a universe of points, with lower case letters denoting variables ranging over that universe. Equality is provided by the underlying logic (see First-order logic#Equality and its axioms).[1] Tarski then posited two primitive relations:

  • Betweenness, a triadic relation. The atomic sentence Bxyz or (y)B(x,z) denotes that y is "between" x and z, in other words, that y is a point on the line segment xz. (This relation is interpreted inclusively, so that Bxyz is trivially true whenever x=y or y=z).
  • Congruence (or "equidistance"), a tetradic relation. The atomic sentence Cwxyz or (w,x)C(y,z) or commonly wxyz can be interpreted as wx is congruent to yz, in other words, that the length of the line segment wx is equal to the length of the line segment yz.

Betweenness captures the affine aspect (such as the parallelism of lines) of Euclidean geometry; congruence, its metric aspect (such as angles and distances). The background logic includes identity, a binary relation. The axioms invoke identity (or its negation) on five occasions.

The axioms below are grouped by the types of relation they invoke, then sorted, first by the number of existential quantifiers, then by the number of atomic sentences. The axioms should be read as universal closures; hence any free variables should be taken as tacitly universally quantified.

Congruence axioms edit

Reflexivity of Congruence
 
Identity of Congruence
 
Transitivity of Congruence
 

Commentary edit

While the congruence relation   is, formally, a 4-way relation among points, it may also be thought of, informally, as a binary relation between two line segments   and  . The "Reflexivity" and "Transitivity" axioms above, combined, prove both:

  • that this binary relation is in fact an equivalence relation
    • it is reflexive:  .
    • it is symmetric  .
    • it is transitive  .
  • and that the order in which the points of a line segment are specified is irrelevant.
    •  .
    •  .
    •  .

The "transitivity" axiom asserts that congruence is Euclidean, in that it respects the first of Euclid's "common notions".

The "Identity of Congruence" axiom states, intuitively, that if xy is congruent with a segment that begins and ends at the same point, x and y are the same point. This is closely related to the notion of reflexivity for binary relations.

Betweenness axioms edit

 
Pasch's axiom
Identity of Betweenness
 

The only point on the line segment   is   itself.

Axiom of Pasch
 
 
Continuity: φ and ψ divide the ray into two halves and the axiom asserts the existence of a point b dividing those two halves
Axiom schema of Continuity

Let φ(x) and ψ(y) be first-order formulae containing no free instances of either a or b. Let there also be no free instances of x in ψ(y) or of y in φ(x). Then all instances of the following schema are axioms:

 

Let r be a ray with endpoint a. Let the first order formulae φ and ψ define subsets X and Y of r, such that every point in Y is to the right of every point of X (with respect to a). Then there exists a point b in r lying between X and Y. This is essentially the Dedekind cut construction, carried out in a way that avoids quantification over sets.

Lower Dimension
 

There exist three noncollinear points. Without this axiom, the theory could be modeled by the one-dimensional real line, a single point, or even the empty set.

Congruence and betweenness edit

 
Upper dimension
Upper Dimension
 

Three points equidistant from two distinct points form a line. Without this axiom, the theory could be modeled by three-dimensional or higher-dimensional space.

Axiom of Euclid

Each of the three variants of this axiom, all equivalent over the remaining Tarski's axioms to Euclid's parallel postulate, has an advantage over the others:

  • A dispenses with existential quantifiers;
  • B has the fewest variables and atomic sentences;
  • C requires but one primitive notion, betweenness. This variant is the usual one given in the literature.
A:  

Let a line segment join the midpoint of two sides of a given triangle. That line segment will be half as long as the third side. This is equivalent to the interior angles of any triangle summing to two right angles.

B:  

Given any triangle, there exists a circle that includes all of its vertices.

 
Axiom of Euclid: C
C:  

Given any angle and any point v in its interior, there exists a line segment including v, with an endpoint on each side of the angle.

Five Segment
 
Five segment
 

Begin with two triangles, xuz and x'u'z'. Draw the line segments yu and y'u', connecting a vertex of each triangle to a point on the side opposite to the vertex. The result is two divided triangles, each made up of five segments. If four segments of one triangle are each congruent to a segment in the other triangle, then the fifth segments in both triangles must be congruent.

This is equivalent to the side-angle-side rule for determining that two triangles are congruent; if the angles uxz and u'x'z' are congruent (there exist congruent triangles xuz and x'u'z'), and the two pairs of incident sides are congruent (xu ≡ x'u' and xz ≡ x'z'), then the remaining pair of sides is also congruent (uz ≡ u'z').

Segment Construction
 

For any point y, it is possible to draw in any direction (determined by x) a line congruent to any segment ab.

Discussion edit

Starting from two primitive relations whose fields are a dense universe of points, Tarski built a geometry of line segments. According to Tarski and Givant (1999: 192-93), none of the above axioms are fundamentally new. The first four axioms establish some elementary properties of the two primitive relations. For instance, Reflexivity and Transitivity of Congruence establish that congruence is an equivalence relation over line segments. The Identity of Congruence and of Betweenness govern the trivial case when those relations are applied to nondistinct points. The theorem xyzzx=yBxyx extends these Identity axioms.

A number of other properties of Betweenness are derivable as theorems[citation needed] including:

The last two properties totally order the points making up a line segment.

Upper and Lower Dimension together require that any model of these axioms have a specific finite dimensionality. Suitable changes in these axioms yield axiom sets for Euclidean geometry for dimensions 0, 1, and greater than 2 (Tarski and Givant 1999: Axioms 8(1), 8(n), 9(0), 9(1), 9(n) ). Note that solid geometry requires no new axioms, unlike the case with Hilbert's axioms. Moreover, Lower Dimension for n dimensions is simply the negation of Upper Dimension for n - 1 dimensions.

When the number of dimensions is greater than 1, Betweenness can be defined in terms of congruence (Tarski and Givant, 1999). First define the relation "≤" (where   is interpreted "the length of line segment   is less than or equal to the length of line segment  "):

 

In the case of two dimensions, the intuition is as follows: For any line segment xy, consider the possible range of lengths of xv, where v is any point on the perpendicular bisector of xy. It is apparent that while there is no upper bound to the length of xv, there is a lower bound, which occurs when v is the midpoint of xy. So if xy is shorter than or equal to zu, then the range of possible lengths of xv will be a superset of the range of possible lengths of zw, where w is any point on the perpendicular bisector of zu.

Betweenness can then be defined by using the intuition that the shortest distance between any two points is a straight line:

 

The Axiom Schema of Continuity assures that the ordering of points on a line is complete (with respect to first-order definable properties). The Axioms of Pasch and Euclid are well known. Remarkably, Euclidean geometry requires just the following further axioms:

Let wff stand for a well-formed formula (or syntactically correct formula) of elementary geometry. Tarski and Givant (1999: 175) proved that elementary geometry is:

Gupta (1965) proved the above axioms independent, Pasch and Reflexivity of Congruence excepted.

Negating the Axiom of Euclid yields hyperbolic geometry, while eliminating it outright yields absolute geometry. Full (as opposed to elementary) Euclidean geometry requires giving up a first order axiomatization: replace φ(x) and ψ(y) in the axiom schema of Continuity with xA and yB, where A and B are universally quantified variables ranging over sets of points.

Comparison with Hilbert edit

Hilbert's axioms for plane geometry number 16, and include Transitivity of Congruence and a variant of the Axiom of Pasch. The only notion from intuitive geometry invoked in the remarks to Tarski's axioms is triangle. (Versions B and C of the Axiom of Euclid refer to "circle" and "angle," respectively.) Hilbert's axioms also require "ray," "angle," and the notion of a triangle "including" an angle. In addition to betweenness and congruence, Hilbert's axioms require a primitive binary relation "on," linking a point and a line. The Axiom schema of Continuity plays a role similar to Hilbert's two axioms of Continuity. This schema is indispensable; Euclidean geometry in Tarski's (or equivalent) language cannot be finitely axiomatized as a first-order theory. Hilbert's axioms do not constitute a first-order theory because his continuity axioms require second-order logic.

The first four groups of axioms of Hilbert's axioms for plane geometry are bi-interpretable with Tarski's axioms minus continuity.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Tarski and Givant, 1999, page 177

References edit

  • Franzén, Torkel (2005), Gödel's Theorem: An Incomplete Guide to Its Use and Abuse, A K Peters, ISBN 1-56881-238-8
  • Givant, Steven (1 December 1999). "Unifying threads in Alfred Tarski's Work". The Mathematical Intelligencer. 21 (1): 47–58. doi:10.1007/BF03024832. ISSN 1866-7414. S2CID 119716413.
  • Gupta, H. N. (1965). Contributions to the Axiomatic Foundations of Geometry (Ph.D. thesis). University of California-Berkeley.
  • Tarski, Alfred (1959), "What is elementary geometry?", in Leon Henkin, Patrick Suppes and Alfred Tarski (ed.), The axiomatic method. With special reference to geometry and physics. Proceedings of an International Symposium held at the Univ. of Calif., Berkeley, Dec. 26, 1957-Jan. 4, 1958, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 16–29, MR 0106185.
  • Tarski, Alfred; Givant, Steven (1999), "Tarski's system of geometry", The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic, 5 (2): 175–214, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.27.9012, doi:10.2307/421089, ISSN 1079-8986, JSTOR 421089, MR 1791303, S2CID 18551419
  • Schwabhäuser, W.; Szmielew, W.; Tarski, Alfred (1983). Metamathematische Methoden in der Geometrie. Springer-Verlag.
  • Szczerba, L. W. (1986). "Tarski and Geometry". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 51 (4): 907–12. doi:10.2307/2273904. JSTOR 2273904. S2CID 35275962.

tarski, axioms, this, article, about, axioms, euclidean, geometry, real, numbers, tarski, axiomatization, reals, theory, tarski, grothendieck, theory, alfred, tarski, axiom, substantial, fragment, euclidean, geometry, that, formulable, first, order, logic, wit. This article is about axioms for Euclidean geometry For Tarski s axioms for the real numbers see Tarski s axiomatization of the reals For Tarski s axioms for set theory see Tarski Grothendieck set theory Tarski s axioms due to Alfred Tarski are an axiom set for the substantial fragment of Euclidean geometry that is formulable in first order logic with identity and requiring no set theory Tarski 1959 i e that part of Euclidean geometry that is formulable as an elementary theory Other modern axiomizations of Euclidean geometry are Hilbert s axioms and Birkhoff s axioms Contents 1 Overview 2 The axioms 2 1 Fundamental relations 2 2 Congruence axioms 2 2 1 Commentary 2 3 Betweenness axioms 2 4 Congruence and betweenness 3 Discussion 4 Comparison with Hilbert 5 See also 6 Notes 7 ReferencesOverview editEarly in his career Tarski taught geometry and researched set theory His coworker Steven Givant 1999 explained Tarski s take off point From Enriques Tarski learned of the work of Mario Pieri an Italian geometer who was strongly influenced by Peano Tarski preferred Pieri s system of his Point and Sphere memoir where the logical structure and the complexity of the axioms were more transparent Givant then says that with typical thoroughness Tarski devised his system What was different about Tarski s approach to geometry First of all the axiom system was much simpler than any of the axiom systems that existed up to that time In fact the length of all of Tarski s axioms together is not much more than just one of Pieri s 24 axioms It was the first system of Euclidean geometry that was simple enough for all axioms to be expressed in terms of the primitive notions only without the help of defined notions Of even greater importance for the first time a clear distinction was made between full geometry and its elementary that is its first order part Like other modern axiomatizations of Euclidean geometry Tarski s employs a formal system consisting of symbol strings called sentences whose construction respects formal syntactical rules and rules of proof that determine the allowed manipulations of the sentences Unlike some other modern axiomatizations such as Birkhoff s and Hilbert s Tarski s axiomatization has no primitive objects other than points so a variable or constant cannot refer to a line or an angle Because points are the only primitive objects and because Tarski s system is a first order theory it is not even possible to define lines as sets of points The only primitive relations predicates are betweenness and congruence among points Tarski s axiomatization is shorter than its rivals in a sense Tarski and Givant 1999 make explicit It is more concise than Pieri s because Pieri had only two primitive notions while Tarski introduced three point betweenness and congruence Such economy of primitive and defined notions means that Tarski s system is not very convenient for doing Euclidean geometry Rather Tarski designed his system to facilitate its analysis via the tools of mathematical logic i e to facilitate deriving its metamathematical properties Tarski s system has the unusual property that all sentences can be written in universal existential form a special case of the prenex normal form This form has all universal quantifiers preceding any existential quantifiers so that all sentences can be recast in the form u v a b displaystyle forall u forall v ldots exists a exists b dots nbsp This fact allowed Tarski to prove that Euclidean geometry is decidable there exists an algorithm which can determine the truth or falsity of any sentence Tarski s axiomatization is also complete This does not contradict Godel s first incompleteness theorem because Tarski s theory lacks the expressive power needed to interpret Robinson arithmetic Franzen 2005 pp 25 26 The axioms editAlfred Tarski worked on the axiomatization and metamathematics of Euclidean geometry intermittently from 1926 until his death in 1983 with Tarski 1959 heralding his mature interest in the subject The work of Tarski and his students on Euclidean geometry culminated in the monograph Schwabhauser Szmielew and Tarski 1983 which set out the 10 axioms and one axiom schema shown below the associated metamathematics and a fair bit of the subject Gupta 1965 made important contributions and Tarski and Givant 1999 discuss the history Fundamental relations edit These axioms are a more elegant version of a set Tarski devised in the 1920s as part of his investigation of the metamathematical properties of Euclidean plane geometry This objective required reformulating that geometry as a first order theory Tarski did so by positing a universe of points with lower case letters denoting variables ranging over that universe Equality is provided by the underlying logic see First order logic Equality and its axioms 1 Tarski then posited two primitive relations Betweenness a triadic relation The atomic sentence Bxyz or y B x z denotes that y is between x and z in other words that y is a point on the line segment xz This relation is interpreted inclusively so that Bxyz is trivially true whenever x y or y z Congruence or equidistance a tetradic relation The atomic sentence Cwxyz or w x C y z or commonly wx yz can be interpreted as wx is congruent to yz in other words that the length of the line segment wx is equal to the length of the line segment yz Betweenness captures the affine aspect such as the parallelism of lines of Euclidean geometry congruence its metric aspect such as angles and distances The background logic includes identity a binary relation The axioms invoke identity or its negation on five occasions The axioms below are grouped by the types of relation they invoke then sorted first by the number of existential quantifiers then by the number of atomic sentences The axioms should be read as universal closures hence any free variables should be taken as tacitly universally quantified Congruence axioms edit Reflexivity of Congruence x y y x displaystyle xy equiv yx nbsp Identity of Congruence x y z z x y displaystyle xy equiv zz rightarrow x y nbsp Transitivity of Congruence x y z u x y v w z u v w displaystyle xy equiv zu land xy equiv vw rightarrow zu equiv vw nbsp Commentary edit While the congruence relation x y z w displaystyle xy equiv zw nbsp is formally a 4 way relation among points it may also be thought of informally as a binary relation between two line segments x y displaystyle xy nbsp and z w displaystyle zw nbsp The Reflexivity and Transitivity axioms above combined prove both that this binary relation is in fact an equivalence relation it is reflexive x y x y displaystyle xy equiv xy nbsp it is symmetric x y z w z w x y displaystyle xy equiv zw rightarrow zw equiv xy nbsp it is transitive x y z u z u v w x y v w displaystyle xy equiv zu land zu equiv vw rightarrow xy equiv vw nbsp and that the order in which the points of a line segment are specified is irrelevant x y z w x y w z displaystyle xy equiv zw rightarrow xy equiv wz nbsp x y z w y x z w displaystyle xy equiv zw rightarrow yx equiv zw nbsp x y z w y x w z displaystyle xy equiv zw rightarrow yx equiv wz nbsp The transitivity axiom asserts that congruence is Euclidean in that it respects the first of Euclid s common notions The Identity of Congruence axiom states intuitively that if xy is congruent with a segment that begins and ends at the same point x and y are the same point This is closely related to the notion of reflexivity for binary relations Betweenness axioms edit nbsp Pasch s axiomIdentity of Betweenness B x y x x y displaystyle Bxyx rightarrow x y nbsp The only point on the line segment x x displaystyle xx nbsp is x displaystyle x nbsp itself Axiom of Pasch B x u z B y v z a B u a y B v a x displaystyle Bxuz land Byvz rightarrow exists a Buay land Bvax nbsp nbsp Continuity f and ps divide the ray into two halves and the axiom asserts the existence of a point b dividing those two halvesAxiom schema of ContinuityLet f x and ps y be first order formulae containing no free instances of either a or b Let there also be no free instances of x in ps y or of y in f x Then all instances of the following schema are axioms a x y ϕ x ps y B a x y b x y ϕ x ps y B x b y displaystyle exists a forall x forall y phi x land psi y rightarrow Baxy rightarrow exists b forall x forall y phi x land psi y rightarrow Bxby nbsp Let r be a ray with endpoint a Let the first order formulae f and ps define subsets X and Y of r such that every point in Y is to the right of every point of X with respect to a Then there exists a point b in r lying between X and Y This is essentially the Dedekind cut construction carried out in a way that avoids quantification over sets Lower Dimension a b c B a b c B b c a B c a b displaystyle exists a exists b exists c neg Babc land neg Bbca land neg Bcab nbsp There exist three noncollinear points Without this axiom the theory could be modeled by the one dimensional real line a single point or even the empty set Congruence and betweenness edit nbsp Upper dimensionUpper Dimension x u x v y u y v z u z v u v B x y z B y z x B z x y displaystyle xu equiv xv land yu equiv yv land zu equiv zv land u neq v rightarrow Bxyz lor Byzx lor Bzxy nbsp Three points equidistant from two distinct points form a line Without this axiom the theory could be modeled by three dimensional or higher dimensional space Axiom of EuclidEach of the three variants of this axiom all equivalent over the remaining Tarski s axioms to Euclid s parallel postulate has an advantage over the others A dispenses with existential quantifiers B has the fewest variables and atomic sentences C requires but one primitive notion betweenness This variant is the usual one given in the literature A B x y w x y y w B x u v x u u v B y u z y u u z y z v w displaystyle Bxyw land xy equiv yw land Bxuv land xu equiv uv land Byuz land yu equiv uz rightarrow yz equiv vw nbsp Let a line segment join the midpoint of two sides of a given triangle That line segment will be half as long as the third side This is equivalent to the interior angles of any triangle summing to two right angles B B x y z B y z x B z x y a x a y a x a z a displaystyle Bxyz lor Byzx lor Bzxy lor exists a xa equiv ya land xa equiv za nbsp Given any triangle there exists a circle that includes all of its vertices nbsp Axiom of Euclid CC B x u v B y u z x u a b B x y a B x z b B a v b displaystyle Bxuv land Byuz land x neq u rightarrow exists a exists b Bxya land Bxzb land Bavb nbsp Given any angle and any point v in its interior there exists a line segment including v with an endpoint on each side of the angle Five Segment nbsp Five segment x y B x y z B x y z x y x y y z y z x u x u y u y u z u z u displaystyle x neq y land Bxyz land Bx y z land xy equiv x y land yz equiv y z land xu equiv x u land yu equiv y u rightarrow zu equiv z u nbsp Begin with two triangles xuz and x u z Draw the line segments yu and y u connecting a vertex of each triangle to a point on the side opposite to the vertex The result is two divided triangles each made up of five segments If four segments of one triangle are each congruent to a segment in the other triangle then the fifth segments in both triangles must be congruent This is equivalent to the side angle side rule for determining that two triangles are congruent if the angles uxz and u x z are congruent there exist congruent triangles xuz and x u z and the two pairs of incident sides are congruent xu x u and xz x z then the remaining pair of sides is also congruent uz u z Segment Construction z B x y z y z a b displaystyle exists z Bxyz land yz equiv ab nbsp For any point y it is possible to draw in any direction determined by x a line congruent to any segment ab Discussion editStarting from two primitive relations whose fields are a dense universe of points Tarski built a geometry of line segments According to Tarski and Givant 1999 192 93 none of the above axioms are fundamentally new The first four axioms establish some elementary properties of the two primitive relations For instance Reflexivity and Transitivity of Congruence establish that congruence is an equivalence relation over line segments The Identity of Congruence and of Betweenness govern the trivial case when those relations are applied to nondistinct points The theorem xy zz x y Bxyx extends these Identity axioms A number of other properties of Betweenness are derivable as theorems citation needed including Reflexivity Bxxy Symmetry Bxyz Bzyx Transitivity Bxyw Byzw Bxyz Connectivity Bxyw Bxzw Bxyz Bxzy The last two properties totally order the points making up a line segment Upper and Lower Dimension together require that any model of these axioms have a specific finite dimensionality Suitable changes in these axioms yield axiom sets for Euclidean geometry for dimensions 0 1 and greater than 2 Tarski and Givant 1999 Axioms 8 1 8 n 9 0 9 1 9 n Note that solid geometry requires no new axioms unlike the case with Hilbert s axioms Moreover Lower Dimension for n dimensions is simply the negation of Upper Dimension for n 1 dimensions When the number of dimensions is greater than 1 Betweenness can be defined in terms of congruence Tarski and Givant 1999 First define the relation where a b c d displaystyle ab leq cd nbsp is interpreted the length of line segment a b displaystyle ab nbsp is less than or equal to the length of line segment c d displaystyle cd nbsp x y z u v z v u v w x w y w y w u v displaystyle xy leq zu leftrightarrow forall v zv equiv uv rightarrow exists w xw equiv yw land yw equiv uv nbsp In the case of two dimensions the intuition is as follows For any line segment xy consider the possible range of lengths of xv where v is any point on the perpendicular bisector of xy It is apparent that while there is no upper bound to the length of xv there is a lower bound which occurs when v is the midpoint of xy So if xy is shorter than or equal to zu then the range of possible lengths of xv will be a superset of the range of possible lengths of zw where w is any point on the perpendicular bisector of zu Betweenness can then be defined by using the intuition that the shortest distance between any two points is a straight line B x y z u u x x y u z z y u y displaystyle Bxyz leftrightarrow forall u ux leq xy land uz leq zy rightarrow u y nbsp The Axiom Schema of Continuity assures that the ordering of points on a line is complete with respect to first order definable properties The Axioms of Pasch and Euclid are well known Remarkably Euclidean geometry requires just the following further axioms Segment Construction This axiom makes measurement and the Cartesian coordinate system possible simply assign the real number of 1 to some arbitrary non empty line segment clarification needed Let wff stand for a well formed formula or syntactically correct formula of elementary geometry Tarski and Givant 1999 175 proved that elementary geometry is Consistent There is no wff such that it and its negation are both theorems Complete Every sentence or its negation is a theorem provable from the axioms Decidable There exists an algorithm that assigns a truth value to every sentence This follows from Tarski s Decision procedure for the real closed field which he found by quantifier elimination the Tarski Seidenberg theorem Axioms admitting of a multi dimensional faithful interpretation as a real closed field Gupta 1965 proved the above axioms independent Pasch and Reflexivity of Congruence excepted Negating the Axiom of Euclid yields hyperbolic geometry while eliminating it outright yields absolute geometry Full as opposed to elementary Euclidean geometry requires giving up a first order axiomatization replace f x and ps y in the axiom schema of Continuity with x A and y B where A and B are universally quantified variables ranging over sets of points Comparison with Hilbert editHilbert s axioms for plane geometry number 16 and include Transitivity of Congruence and a variant of the Axiom of Pasch The only notion from intuitive geometry invoked in the remarks to Tarski s axioms is triangle Versions B and C of the Axiom of Euclid refer to circle and angle respectively Hilbert s axioms also require ray angle and the notion of a triangle including an angle In addition to betweenness and congruence Hilbert s axioms require a primitive binary relation on linking a point and a line The Axiom schema of Continuity plays a role similar to Hilbert s two axioms of Continuity This schema is indispensable Euclidean geometry in Tarski s or equivalent language cannot be finitely axiomatized as a first order theory Hilbert s axioms do not constitute a first order theory because his continuity axioms require second order logic The first four groups of axioms of Hilbert s axioms for plane geometry are bi interpretable with Tarski s axioms minus continuity See also editEuclidean geometry Euclidean spaceNotes edit Tarski and Givant 1999 page 177References editFranzen Torkel 2005 Godel s Theorem An Incomplete Guide to Its Use and Abuse A K Peters ISBN 1 56881 238 8 Givant Steven 1 December 1999 Unifying threads in Alfred Tarski s Work The Mathematical Intelligencer 21 1 47 58 doi 10 1007 BF03024832 ISSN 1866 7414 S2CID 119716413 Gupta H N 1965 Contributions to the Axiomatic Foundations of Geometry Ph D thesis University of California Berkeley Tarski Alfred 1959 What is elementary geometry in Leon Henkin Patrick Suppes and Alfred Tarski ed The axiomatic method With special reference to geometry and physics Proceedings of an International Symposium held at the Univ of Calif Berkeley Dec 26 1957 Jan 4 1958 Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics Amsterdam North Holland pp 16 29 MR 0106185 Available as a 2007 reprint Brouwer Press ISBN 1 4437 2812 8 Tarski Alfred Givant Steven 1999 Tarski s system of geometry The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 5 2 175 214 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 27 9012 doi 10 2307 421089 ISSN 1079 8986 JSTOR 421089 MR 1791303 S2CID 18551419 Schwabhauser W Szmielew W Tarski Alfred 1983 Metamathematische Methoden in der Geometrie Springer Verlag Szczerba L W 1986 Tarski and Geometry Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 4 907 12 doi 10 2307 2273904 JSTOR 2273904 S2CID 35275962 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Tarski 27s axioms amp oldid 1172686544, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.