fbpx
Wikipedia

Legalism (Chinese philosophy)

Fajia (Chinese: 法家; pinyin: fǎ jiā), often translated as Legalism,[2] is one of Sima Qian's six classical schools of thought in Chinese philosophy. Compared in the West with political realism and even the model-building of Max Weber,[3] the "fa school of thought" represents several branches of what Feng Youlan called "men of methods",[4] who contributed greatly to the construction of the bureaucratic Chinese empire. Although lacking a recognized founder, the earliest persona of the Fajia is often considered Guan Zhong (720–645 BCE),[5] while Chinese historians commonly regard Li Kui (455–395 BCE) as the first Legalist philosopher. The term Fajia was identified in the west by Sinologist Herrlee G. Creel as referring to a combination of administrator Shen Buhai (400–337 BCE) and Legalist Shang Yang (390–338 BCE) as its founding branches, but is noted earlier by K.C. Hsiao.

Legalism
Statue of pivotal reformer Shang Yang
Chinese法家
Literal meaningSchool of Standards/Methods
School of Law [1]: 59 

Sinologist Jacques Gernet considered the "theorists of the state" later christened fajia or "Legalists", to be the most important intellectual tradition of the fourth and third centuries BCE.[6] With the Han dynasty taking over the governmental institutions of the Qin dynasty almost unchanged, the Qin to Tang dynasty were characterized by the "centralizing, statist tendencies" of its tradition. Leon Vandermeersch and Vitaly Rubin would assert not a single state measure throughout Chinese history as having been without Legalist influence.[7]

Dubbed by A. C. Graham the "great synthesizer of 'Legalism'", Han Fei is regarded as their finest writer, if not the greatest statesman in Chinese history (Hu Shi). Early considered the "culminating" or "greatest" of the Legalist texts,[8] the Han Feizi is believed to contain the first commentaries on the Dao De Jing. Sun Tzu's Art of War incorporates both a Daoist philosophy of inaction and impartiality, and a Legalist system of punishment and rewards, recalling Han Fei's use of the concepts of power (勢, shì) and technique (術, shù).[9] Temporarily coming to overt power as an ideology with the ascension of the Qin dynasty,[10]: 82  the First Emperor of Qin and succeeding emperors often followed the template set by Han Fei.[11]

Though the origins of the Chinese administrative system cannot be traced to any one person, prime minister Shen Buhai may have had more influence than any other in the construction of the merit system, and might be considered its founder, if not valuable as a rare pre-modern example of abstract theory of administration. Creel saw in Shen Buhai the "seeds of the civil service examination", and perhaps the first political scientist.[12][13]: 94 

Concerned largely with administrative and sociopolitical innovation, Shang Yang was a leading reformer of his time.[14][10]: 83  His numerous reforms transformed the peripheral Qin state into a militarily powerful and strongly centralized kingdom. Much of Legalism was "the development of certain ideas" that lay behind his reforms, helping lead Qin to ultimate conquest of the other states of China in 221 BCE.[15][16]

Taken as "progressive," the Fajia were "rehabilitated" in the twentieth century, with reformers regarding it as a precedent for their opposition to conservative Confucian forces and religion.[17]

Historical background edit

The Zhou dynasty was divided between the masses and the hereditary noblemen. The latter were placed to obtain office and political power, owing allegiance to the local prince, who owed allegiance to the Son of Heaven.[18] The dynasty operated according to the principles of Li and punishment. The former was applied only to aristocrats, the latter only to commoners.[19]

The earliest Zhou kings kept a firm personal hand on the government, depending on their personal capacities, personal relations between ruler and minister, and upon military might. The technique of centralized government being so little developed, they deputed authority to regional lords, almost exclusively clansmen. When the Zhou kings could no longer grant new fiefs, their power began to decline, vassals began to identify with their own regions. Aristocratic sub-lineages became very important, by virtue of their ancestral prestige wielding great power and proving a divisive force. The political structures late Springs-and-Autumns period (770–453 BCE) progressively disintegrated, with schismatic hostility and "debilitating struggles among rival polities."[20]

In the Spring and Autumn period, rulers began to directly appoint state officials to provide advice and management, leading to the decline of inherited privileges and bringing fundamental structural transformations as a result of what may be termed "social engineering from above".[1]: 59  Most Warring States period thinkers tried to accommodate a "changing with the times" paradigm, and each of the schools of thought sought to provide an answer for the attainment of sociopolitical stability.[14]

Confucianism, commonly considered to be China's ruling ethos, was articulated in opposition to the establishment of legal codes, the earliest of which were inscribed on bronze vessels in the sixth century BCE.[21] For the Confucians, the Classics provided the preconditions for knowledge.[22] Orthodox Confucians tended to consider organizational details beneath both minister and ruler, leaving such matters to underlings,[13]: 107  and furthermore wanted ministers to control or at least admonish the ruler.[23]: 359 

Concerned with "goodness", the Confucians became the most prominent, followed by proto-Daoists and the administrative thought that Sima Tan termed the Fajia. But the Daoists focused on the development of inner powers, with little respect for mundane authority[24][25] and both the Daoists and Confucians held a regressive view of history, that the age was a decline from the era of the Zhou kings.[26]

Mohist predecessors edit

 
Between Mozi's background as an engineer and his pacifist leanings, the Mohists became experts at building fortifications and sieges.
 
Small seal scripts were standardized by Li Si after the First Emperor of China gained control of the country, evolving from the larger seal scripts of previous dynasties.

The 12 characters on this slab of floor brick affirm that it is an auspicious moment for the First Emperor to ascend the throne, as the country is united and no men will be dying along the road.

Compared by the Stanford Encyclopedia with Socrates, the Mohists, of Mozi (470 BC–391 BC) contained the philosophical germs of what Sima Qian would term the "Fa-School", initiating philosophical debate, positing some of ancient China's first theories, and contributing to the political thought of contemporary reformers. Finding the values of tradition and Confucian li (ritual) unconvincing, the Mohists took universal welfare and the elimination of harm as morally right, arguing against nepotism in favor of objective standards (fa) to unify moral judgements, favoring thrift over extravagance, economic wealth, population growth, and social order. Mozi's ruler was intended to act as fa (or example) for the nobles and officials, developing towards political technique. Taking social order as a paramount, universally assumed good, the Mohists advocated a unified, peaceful, utilitarian or consequentialist ethical and political order, with an authoritarian, centralized meritocratic state, led by a virtuous, benevolent sovereign.[27]`

The elimination of harm edit

The elimination of harm is a Mohist doctrine. Although Mohism can involve punishment, the broader Chinese tradition considers punishment only one tool, with people responsive to Confucian education, or in the Mozi, attitudes and just rules themselves. The Book of Lord Shang highlights honor, and regards his broader program of fa or law as a teaching transmitted by the accountable laws officers, aiming to spread knowledge of it; "The multitude of people all know what to avoid and what to strive for; they will avoid calamity and strive for happiness, and so govern themselves."

Aiming at quick results, although reward and punishment is a major emphasis for Shang Yang and Han Fei, Shang Yang repeatedly advocates the abolition of punishment with punishment. Liu Xiang takes Shen Buhai's work as advising that a ruler following his doctrine of (administrative) technique ought to follow after ministers proposals, supervising strictly to abolish punishment. Unlike his predecessor Shen Buhai, Han Fei endorses Shang Yang's fa or 'law' with critique, and punishes violations of ministerial roles. But it was not a primary component of his method.

Although there is old precedent for their roots in Confucianism-Mohism, their own variations on the theme doesn't necessarily make them Mohists as much as it does products of their environment.[28][29][30][31] A quotation from Tao Jiang's exploratory work on justice and humaneness highlights the Qin as more conservative than the Mohists, containing both Confucian and Mohist elements. With a "slightly modified" quotation from the late Qin work, the Lüshi Chunqiu.[32]

The Mohist leader Fu Tun resided in Qin. His son murdered a man. King Hui of Qin said, “You, sir, are too old to have another son, so I have already ordered that the officials not execute him. I hope, sir, that you will abide by my judgment in this matter.”

Fu Tun replied, “The law of the Mohist order says: ‘He who kills another person shall die; he who injures another shall be punished.’ The purpose of this is to prevent the injuring and killing of other people. To prevent the injuring and killing of other people is the most important moral principle in the world. Though your majesty out of kindness has ordered that the officials not execute my son, I cannot but implement the law of the Mohist order.” He would not assent to King Hui’s request and proceeded to kill his own son.

School of names edit

Only termed Fajia later, Sima Qian originally glosses Shang Yang, Shen Buhai and Han Fei under the Xing-Ming doctrine of the school of names,[33] as a family of terms, along with fa, that Shen Buhai and Han Fei actually prominently used. Xing-Ming dealt in the administrative details of names and realities, and word and substance of ministers, with Shen Buhai in his time checking minister's works. Xun Kuang also had a Xing-Ming method, only just behind Han Fei in sophistication. Although its earlier thinkers are, like Shen Buhai, more Confucian, more broadly philosophical than them, and less advanced, words and names are essential for administration.[34] The three rise again in the Three Kingdoms period, and broader 'teaching of names' thinker Xu Gan differs from them but still follows Shang Yang-Han Fei doctrine of reward and punishment, emphasizing consistency over their extremes.[35]

Han Fei connects the 'word and substance' of Shen Buhai's ministers with Shang Yang's doctrine of reward and punishment; while not otherwise going into detail apart from extremes, Han Fei more explicitly executes appropriation of titles, but with punishment in the broader Qin context ultimately tending towards conversion into fines etc.[36]

A sovereign who wants to suppress treachery must examine and match performance (or the form, xing 形) and title (or the name, ming 名). Performance and title refer to the difference between the proposal and the task. The minister lays out his proposal; the ruler assigns him the task according to his proposal, and solely on the basis of the task determines [the minister’s] merit. When the merit matches the task, and the task matches the proposal, [the minister] is rewarded; when the merit does not match the task and the task does not match the proposal, he is penalized. … Thus, when the clear-sighted sovereign nourishes his ministers, the minister should not claim merit by overstepping [the duties of] his office, nor should he present the proposal that does not match [his task]. One who oversteps his office’s [duties] dies; one who[se proposal] does not match [the task] is punished; then the ministers are unable to form cabals and cliques (Pine's Stanford Encyclopedia, Han Feizi 7.2, “Two levers”).

Far from the ministerial center, as a contemporary of Shen Buhai, Shang Yang connects Name with reward and punishment, social status and reputation, as passable to deceased soldier's heirs with Qin limitations. The explicit relation between the school of names and Shang Yang is not currently articulated; translator Pines discusses the broader context of the honor of a name, as a motivator alongside wealth "properly understood and manipulated" towards state ends. Shang Yang says:[37]

Wherever the name and benefit meet, the people will go in this direction; they brave what they consider bitter and perform what they consider dangerous because of the calculation [of a name and benefit]. Thus, in [ordinary] life, the people calculate benefits; [facing] death, they think of a (good) name. One cannot but investigate whence the name and benefit come. When benefits come from land, the people fully utilize their strength; when the name comes from war, the people are ready to die.

On the Qin edit

While broader, Shang Yang, Shen Buhai and Han Fei include important principles that can be found in the Qin empire's administration, with Shang Yang influential on ancient China's unification and law. Emperors and reformers would refer back to them and the broader milieu of their methods. Han Fei presented the two as the opposite components of his doctrine, but was, like his predecessor Shen Buhai, primarily bureaucratic. With the Qin dynasty more reasonable than might be expected of the Book of Lord Shang, the milder, more administrative Shen Buhai's policies compliment Shang Yang in this sense.[38]

The Qin empire's laws were primarily administrative, with fa referring primarily to standards, models and norms. Only including penal law alongside li ritual, fa as comparative model manuals in the Qin empire guided penal legal procedure and application based on real-life situations, with publicly named wrongs linked to punishments. While some Qin penal laws deal with infanticide or other unsanctioned harm of children, it primarily concerned theft; it does not much deal with murder. By contrast, detailed rules and "endless paperwork" tightly regulate grain, weights, measures, and official documents.[39]

Although not discarding all his reforms, the Qin had already abandoned Shang Yang's reforms focusing on agriculture and heavy punishment by the time of the Qin dynasty.[40] The First Emperor declares himself to be "benevolent and righteous."[41] Regardless, in the Qin and early Han, criminals may be given amnesties, and then only punished if they did it again.[42]

Penal law actually develops more in the Han dynasty. The Qin often expelled criminals to the new colonies, or pardoned them in exchange for fines, labor, or one to several aristocratic ranks, even up to the death penalty. While the penal laws would still be considered harsh compared to the modern day, they were not harsh for their time, and often not actually enacted.[43] Villainizing the first Emperor while adopting Qin administration,[44] a "confused revulsion" against the Qin occurs in the Han dynasty, centering on Shang Yang and Han Fei as espousing rigorous law and punishment. The Han dynasty ultimately takes the Qin dynasty as having practiced these.[45]

Sima Qian's Fajia edit

Fajia was invented by Sima Tan.[46] Although most figures later called Fajia were influential, they were probably never an organized or self-aware movement in the sense of the Mohists and Confucians. Creel in his time took Shang Yang as the Fajia's Legalist school, with Shen Buhai its administrative wing, but only in the sense of their prominence, influence, and reform recollection. Or, they were schools in that their works could not have been written by one person.[47] But no one ever called himself a Fajia,[48] It does does not exist as a Warring States period category,[49] its figures could never have used the term, and does not represent a unified category of ideology between their texts. With some similarities, their 'emphases' are different. The "typical canon" includes Shen Buhai and Shen Dao only because they are part of Han Fei's lineage.[50]

Sima Qian lauds their capacity to “clearly distinguish offices so that no one can overstep [his responsibilities]”, while also promoting it as a "one-time policy that could not be constantly applied."[33] Sima Qian says:[51]

The fajia are strict and have little kindness, but their alignment of the divisions between lord and subject, superior and inferior, cannot be improved upon. … Fajia do not distinguish between kin and stranger or differentiate between noble and base; all are judged as one by their fa. Thus they sunder the kindnesses of treating one's kin as kin and honoring the honorable. It is a policy that could be practiced for a time, but not applied for long; thus I say: “they are strict and have little kindness.” But as for honoring rulers and derogating subjects, and clarifying social divisions and offices so that no one is able to overstep them—none of the Hundred Schools could improve upon this.

Creel explains Fajia, coming to mean something like Legalism, as a Han dynasty slur targeting regulation of the vassals and ministers, despite the predominant "Shen Buhai branch" reformers commonly opposing punishment.[52] Sima Qian does not name anyone under the schools;[53] rather, Shen Buhai-Han Fei and their administrative method shift towards association with Shang Yang and punishment over the Han dynasty.[54] With Shang Yang as the most 'Legalist' of them, its figures are not, in critical academia, characterized as Legalist modernly, unless Shen Buhai's ministerial labor contracts or Han Fei's addendum of punishment count as Legalism. Shen Buhai's method does not require a legal code,[55] and has even been criticized for it in Chinese scholarship.[56] Legalism has only still been used by some in recent years conventionally.[50]

Credited by Creel as syncretic precedent for their later association within the Fajia, Chapter 43 of the Han Feizi says:[57]

Now Shen Buhai spoke about the need of Shu (fa-shu "Method" or "Technique") and Shang Yang practices the use of Fa ("Standards" as including law). What is called Shu is to create posts according to responsibilities, hold actual services accountable according to official titles, exercise the power over life and death, and examine into the abilities of all his ministers; these are the things that the ruler keeps in his own hand. Fa includes mandates and ordinances promulgated to the government offices, penalties that are definite in the mind of the people, rewards that are due to the careful observers of standards, and punishments that are inflicted upon those who violate orders. It is what the subjects and ministers take as a model. If the ruler is without Shu he will be overshadowed; if the subjects and ministers lack Fa they will be insubordinate. Thus, neither can be dispensed with: both are implements of emperors and kings.

As Han Fei discusses in chapter 43, Shen Buhai only had disorganized law in his comparatively new Hann state.[58] As with Han Fei after him, he was concerned primarily with ministers and administration.[59] Based on his own reading of the Hanshu, Homer H. Dubs considered Shen Buhai the best ruler of the Hann state.[60] Shen Buhai is likely in the Fajia rather than then the school of names due to opposition and presence in the Han Feizi.[61]

Mentioned in the Outer Zhuangzi and with a potential influence in Daoism,[62] scholar Shen Dao would remembered for his secondary subject of shih or "situational authority", of which he is spoken in Chapter 40 of the Han Feizi and incorporated into The Art of War. He only uses the term twice in the his fragments.[63] Xun Kuang calls Shen Dao "beclouded with fa", instead naming Shen Buhai for the doctrine of position.[64] He is earlier taken as having a group based on the chapter,[65] but although known by some in his time, has no record of any notable activity, and is only mentioned in the shiji in a stub with the claim that, along with the others, he had incompletely studied Sima Qian's own Huang-Lao ideology.[66][67]

With Shu as Han Fei's distinctive, although Han Fei and Shen Dao make some use of fa akin to law, with reward and punishment, they both generally use fa similarly to Shen Buhai, as an impersonal administrative technique. With a quotation from Han Fei as example:[68]

An enlightened ruler employs fa to pick his men; he does not select them himself. He employs fa to weigh their merit; he does not fathom it himself. Thus ability cannot be obscured nor failure prettified. If those who are [falsely] glorified cannot advance, and likewise those who are maligned cannot be set back, then there will be clear distinctions between lord and subject, and order will be easily [attained]. Thus the ruler can only use fa.

The early Han dynasty kings who used Xing-Ming made capital punishment rare. After the death of Gongsun Hong the chancellery becomes ineffective, with only two not executed. Serving as a secondary historical moniker for the fajia, Xing-Ming's meaning ultimately narrows into the "names of punishments", becomes a term for criminal law, and is given to ministers in charge of criminal affairs.[69] Along with departments for the other schools, Liu Xin assigns the Fajia a fictional origin in an ancient ministry of criminal justice for his imperial library classification system,[70] while the school of names were already considered disputers in the Warring States period. Hence, Pines explains the term Fajia as a cataloguing label for 'intellectually related texts'. While its earliest usage is unknown, it was already termed Legalism dating to the 1939 translation of the Han Feizi, with a decreasing usage over the decades.[33]

Philosophical introduction edit

Systems administration edit

 
The key figure in the late imperial bureaucracy was the district magistrate, a combination of a mayor, chief of police, judge, and even military commander.[71] He obtained the position by passing the examination for the civil service and performance at a lower level. He had a staff, some who moved with him, some permanently located in the district. Any penalty more serious than bambooing had to be approved by higher officials, any decision not based on statute required approval from Peking.[72]
Drawing by William Alexander, draughtsman of the Macartney Embassy to China in 1793.

Although Han Fei does not necessarily try to "establish any kind of general theory of state",[73] he still seems "closer in spirit to certain 19th- and 20th-century social-scientific 'model builders'", with Shen Buhai's 'model' of bureaucratic organization "much closer to Weber's modern ideal-type than to any notion of patrimonial bureaucracy." Contrary to comparisons with the art of Machiavelli, Shen Buhai and Han Fei have been compared more with science of politics, and even the model building of Max Weber.[74]

In practical terms, the ruler's authority means that he ought to hold the power to reward and punish, which Han Fei advises. However, his power is simply institutional. Both the Book of Lord Shang and Han Feizi consider their rulers "shortsighted", "mediocre" and "muddle headed." Hence, fa thinkers do not actually make much discussion of such factors as charisma that might enhance the ruler's personal power. Han Fei has tactics in later chapters, but primarily attempts to convince the ruler that a do-nothing role of paper checking and rubber stamping will be the best thing for him.[75][excessive citations] Han Fei says:[76]

If the sovereign personally inspects his hundred officials, the whole day will not be enough; his power will not suffice. Moreover, when the superior uses his eyesight, the underlings embellish what he sees; when he uses his hearing, the underlings embellish what he hears; when he uses his contemplation, the underlings multiply their words. The former kings considered these three [methods] as insufficient: hence they cast away personal abilities and relied on laws and [administrative] methods examining rewards and punishments.

Han Fei has, like other ancient thinkers, been considered a defender of monarchy. But his critics have not necessarily considered him anti-people, but anti-ministerial, with Han Fei more concerned with bureaucracy. Some have considered Shang Yang noting more than a defender of state power, but while the Book of Lord Shang in particular has been taken as anti-people, with a broader program of agriculture and war, ordinary people "have an interest in the security against arbitrary punishment" by controlling penal officials, which Shang Yang's fa "penal law" and Han Fei's Shu "managerial technique" regulate. If they are taken as only serving the ruler, it is only by discarding the people from the equation.[77]

Enlightened Absolutism edit

Not expecting that monstrous tyrants can be accommodated, although Han Fei frequently addresses the enlightened ruler, what Pines terms the fa tradition must aim to accommodate mediocrities on the throne. Characterized as akin to "social engineers", they aim at "perfectly designed", "foolproof", "self-regulating", "mechanically reliable institutions."[78][excessive citations] Xuezhi Guo's Ideal Chinese Political Leader contrasts the Confucian "Humane ruler" with the 'Legalists' as "intending to create a truly 'enlightened ruler'". He quotes Benjamin I. Schwartz as describing the features of a truly Legalist "enlightened ruler":[79]

He must be anything but an arbitrary despot if one means by a despot a tyrant who follows all his impulses, whims and passions. Once the systems which maintain the entire structure are in place, he must not interfere with their operation. He may use the entire system as a means to the achievement of his national and international ambitions, but to do so he must not disrupt its impersonal workings. He must at all times be able to maintain an iron wall between his private life and public role. Concubines, friends, flatterers and charismatic saints must have no influence whatsoever on the course of policy, and he must never relax his suspicions of the motives of those who surround him.

As easily as mediocre carpenters can draw circles by employing a compass, anyone can employ the system Han Fei envisions.[80] The enlightened ruler restricts his desires and refrains from displays of personal ability or input in policy. Capability is not dismissed, but the ability to use talent will allow the ruler greater power if he can utilize others with the given expertise.[81] Laws and regulations allow him to utilize his power to the utmost. Adhering unwaveringly to legal and institutional arrangements, the average monarch is numinous.[82][83] Graham writes:

[Han Fei's] ruler, empty of thoughts, desires, partialities of his own, concerned with nothing in the situation but the 'facts', selects his ministers by objectively comparing their abilities with the demands of the offices. Inactive, doing nothing, he awaits their proposals, compares the project with the results, and rewards or punishes. His own knowledge, ability, moral worth, warrior spirit, such as they may be, are wholly irrelevant; he simply performs his function in the impersonal mechanism of the state.[84]: 288 

Pines recalls Graham's provocative conclusion that the ruler in Han Fei's system “has no functions which could not be performed by an elementary computer", questioning whether it is not in fact the ministers who do the ruling. Resting empty, Han Fei's ruler simply checking "shapes" against "names" and dispenses rewards and punishments accordingly, concertizing the Dao as standards for right and wrong. Submerged by the system he supposedly runs, the alleged despot disappears from the scene.[85][excessive citations]

Huang-Lao appropriation edit

 
Sima Qian

Sima Qian claims Shen Dao, Shen Buhai, and Han Fei as having studied the teachings of his own faction, "the Teachings of the Yellow Emperor and Lao-tzu" (Huang-Lao), synonymous with daojia ('school of Dao', early Daoism). Although modernly included under early Daoism, it would not have meant Daoism as understood modernly. With pre-Han Daoists also more an informal network than an organized school or movement, Daojia first appears in the Records, and is also taken as retrospective. Associated with the much earlier Guan Zhong, the Guanzi, with its proto-daoist texts, was classed as Daoist in the Han bibliography, with the texts commonly classed Guan Zhong and Shen Dao under Daojia before Fajia.

Given its precedent, with formal similarities between the texts and Daoism as including Han Fei's advocacy of wu wei (so-called "effortless action") or reduced activity by the ruler, the theorists were often supposed by the Chinese and early scholarship to have studied Daoism. Modern scholarship does not take the Daodejing to be as ancient. Incomplete versions date back to the fourth century B.C., while the earliest complete written editions of the Daodejing only date back to the early Han dynasty. No pre-Han records discuss it.[citation needed]

By Creel's time, few critical scholars believed Laozi to have been a contemporary of Confucius. Although incomplete versions of the Daodejing may have been contemporary to Shen Buhai's time, Creel did not find Shen Buhai, as Han Fei's predecessor and prior prime minister of their native Hann state, to be influenced by Daoist ideas, lacking metaphysical content. Shen Buhai quotes the Analects of Confucius, in which Wu Wei can also be seen as an idea.[citation needed]

As had generally already been accepted by scholarship at the time, Creel did not find the Han Feizi's Daodejing commentary to have been written by Han Fei. A.C. Graham would reiterate that Han Fei does not appear to make effective use of it. The Han Feizi is most similar to the Shen Buhai fragments. Evidences for Daoist influence on the Han Feizi remain lacking outside of a few tertiary chapters. The final chapter of the Zhuangzi does not regard Laozi and Zhuangzi as having been part of a Daoist school. The Outer Zhuangzi's history includes Confucians, Mohists, Shendao, Laozi, and Zhuangzi, effectively leaving out a Legalist school, with the Mohists as a primary influence.[citation needed]

However, while others of the Fajia are left out, the Zhuangzi takes Shen Dao as Daoistic, preceding both Laozi and Zhuangzi. With precedent in Creel, Schwarz and Graham, Hansen of the Standford's Daoism would take Daoist theory as beginning in the relativist discussions of Shen Dao. He still considers Shen Dao's theory foundational for a Daoist favoring of Dao, as meaning guide, over Heaven, a narrative shared with the late Mohists in that an appeal to Heaven justifies thieves as well as sages.[citation needed]

Although modernly more often given to contrast and comparison with the Mohists, comparison and attempts to root the Han Feizi in proto-Daoist attitudes or naturalism can be still seen within scholarship. Creel did not exclude the possibility that Daoist ideas influenced the fajia before they were written down in the Zhuangzi and Daodejing, or for instance influence by Yang Zhu and the Yangists, but his evidences suggested Huang-Lao as not existing during Shen Buhai's time. Writing at the turn of its discussion, John Makeham (1990) still considered some of the Han Feizi's most typifying chapters as being of distinctly Daoist quality, not considering, at least, the dividing line between the two as having ever been particularly clear.[86][excessive citations][87][excessive citations][88][excessive citations]

Appendix edit

Notes edit

Creel's branches of the Fajia
Creel's basic lense for the subject would be reiterated by K. C. Hsiao (1979), Michael Loewe (1986) of the Cambridge History of China, A.C. Graham (1989), and S.Y. Hsieh (1995). With his prior What is Taoism? as relevant, Creel's Shen Pu-Hai: A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B. C. remains the only major publication on Shen Buhai. Tao Jiang would modernly reiterate its view as having superseded that of Feng Youlan (1948). Emphasizing Creel's heavy utilization of other works, Tao Jiang still takes him as still "very useful for understanding fajia thought more generally."[89]

Tao Jiang mentions Korean scholar Soon-Ja Yang as the only opposition, with a more Legalist Shen Buhai as going against the general history[citation needed]

References edit

  1. ^ a b Garfield, Jay L.; Edelglass, William (9 June 2011). The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy. OUP USA. ISBN 9780195328998 – via Google Books.
  2. ^
    • Pines, Yuri (2023), "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-legalism/
    • Tao Jiang 2021. p238. Origins of Moral-Political Philosophy in Early China
    https://books.google.com/books?id=qXo_EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA238
    • Goldin, Paul R. (March 2011). "Persistent misconceptions about Chinese 'Legalism'"
    • Creel, Herrlee Glessner.1970,1982. p93,119-120. What Is Taoism?
  3. ^ A.C. Graham 1989. p269 https://books.google.com/books?id=QBzyCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA269
  4. ^ Feng Youlan 1948. p.37. A short history of Chinese philosophy
    • Chen, Jianfu (1999). Chinese Law: Towards an Understanding of Chinese Law, Its Nature and Development. The Hague: Kluwer Law International. p. 12. ISBN 9041111867.
  5. ^ Schwarz 1985 p325 (regarded as a forefather by Han literature)
    • Eno, Robert (2010), Legalism and Huang-Lao Thought (PDF), Indiana University, Early Chinese Thought Course Readings
    https://chinatxt.sitehost.iu.edu/Thought/Legalism.pdf
  6. ^ Jacques Gernet 1982. p. 90. A History of Chinese Civilization. https://books.google.com/books?id=jqb7L-pKCV8C&pg=PA90
  7. ^ Jay L. Garfield, William Edelglass 2011, p. 60 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy https://books.google.com/books?id=I0iMBtaSlHYC&pg=PA60
    • Creel, Herrlee Glessner (15 September 1982). p103. What Is Taoism?: And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 9780226120478 – via Google Books
    • Hengy Chye Kiang 1999. p. 44. Cities of Aristocrats and Bureaucrats. https://books.google.com/books?id=BIgS4p8NykYC&pg=PA44
    • Rubin, Vitaliĭ, 1976. p55. Individual and state in ancient China : essays on four Chinese philosophers
  8. ^ * Yu-lan Fung 1948. p. 157. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. https://books.google.com/books?id=HZU0YKnpTH0C&pg=PA157
  9. ^ Chen, Chao Chuan and Yueh-Ting Lee 2008 p. 12. Leadership and Management in China
  10. ^ a b Bishop, Donald H. (27 September 1995). Chinese Thought: An Introduction. Motilal Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 9788120811393.
  11. ^ Kenneth Winston p. 315. Singapore Journal of Legal Studies [2005] 313–347. The Internal Morality of Chinese Legalism. http://law.nus.edu.sg/sjls/articles/SJLS-2005-313.pdf
  12. ^ Graham, A. C. 1989/2015. p283. Disputers of the Tao.
    • Creel, 1974. p4–5. Shen Pu-hai: A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B.C.
  13. ^ a b Creel, Herrlee Glessner (15 September 1982). What Is Taoism?: And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History. University of Chicago Press. ISBN 9780226120478 – via Google Books.
  14. ^ a b Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), 1.2 Historical Context. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/chinese-legalism/
  15. ^ Eno (2010), p. 1.
  16. ^ Chad Hansen, University of Hong Kong. Lord Shang. http://www.philosophy.hku.hk/ch/Lord%20Shang.htm
  17. ^ Charles Holcombe 2011 p. 42. A History of East Asia. https://books.google.com/books?id=rHeb7wQu0xIC&pg=PA42
  18. ^ K. K. Lee, 1975 p. 24. Legalist School and Legal Positivism, Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 2.
  19. ^ Yu-lan Fung 1948. p. 155. A Short History of Chinese Philosophy. https://books.google.com/books?id=HZU0YKnpTH0C&pg=PA155
  20. ^ Herrlee G. Creel, 1974 p. 124. Shen Pu-Hai: A Secular Philosopher of Administration, Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1
    firm hand, devolution, aristocratic lineages:
    • Edward L. Shaughnessy. China Empire and Civilization p26
    rise of regional powers
    • Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", 1.2 Historical Context.
    disintegration and struggle
  21. ^ David K Schneider May/June 2016 p. 20. China's New Legalism
  22. ^ Knoblox Xunzi 148
  23. ^ Hansen, Chad (17 August 2000). A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought: A Philosophical Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780195350760 – via Google Books.
  24. ^ K. K. Lee, 1975 p. 26. Legalist School and Legal Positivism, Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 2.
  25. ^ Waley, Arthur (1939). Three Ways of Thought in Ancient China. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. p. 194.
  26. ^ Huang, Ray, China A Macro History. p.20.
    Daoists little respect for mundane authority.
    • Jay L. Garfield, William Edelglass 2011, p. 65 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy
    Daoists and Confucians regressive view of history
  27. ^ Fa concept
  28. ^
    • Goldin 2011. p10 Persistent Misconceptions
    • Makeham 1994. p70. Name and Actuality
    https://books.google.com/books?id=GId_ASbEI2YC&pg=PA70
    • Hansen 1992 p359,367
    https://books.google.com/books?id=QybpAAAAIAAJ&pg=367
  29. ^ Creel 1970 p101. What is Taoism? https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA101 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/101/modee/2up
  30. ^ Pines 2009. p110. Envisioning Eternal Empire https://books.google.com/books?id=zhpLJgHZMTQC&pg=PA110
    • Creel 1974 Shen Pu-Hai p126 A Secular Philosopher
    • Creel 1970 p101. What is Taoism?
    https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA101 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/101/modee/2up
    • An emphasis for punishment has never been demonstrated, and barely argued, for the tactful Shen Buhai; 47. Benjamin Schwartz cites "the fact that the two handles of punishment and reward are clearly part of shu in rebuttal of Creel's insistence that Shen Buhai was not a Legalist", but his reputation belies him actually blatantly using punishment.
  31. ^ Schwarz 1985. p334 https://books.google.com/books?id=AT_pAAAAIAAJ&
  32. ^ Tao Jiang 2021 p40
    • Knoblock and Riegel 2000 trans., 75,
  33. ^ a b c Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/chinese-legalism/
  34. ^
    • Creel 1970 p101. What is Taoism?
    https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA79 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/79/modee/2up
  35. ^ *Makeham p265 Balanced Discourses: A Bilingual Edition https://books.google.com/books?id=O9OPW7TKip8C&pg=PA265
  36. ^ Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/chinese-legalism/#MoniOffiTechRule
    • Makeham 1990.p95-96 THE LEGALIST CONCEPT OF HSING-MING
  37. ^
    • Pines, Yuri (2023), "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-legalism/#HumaNatu
    • Pines 2017 p51 Abridged Book of Lord Shang
  38. ^
    • Michael Loewe 1999 p973, The Cambridge History of Ancient China: From the Origins of Civilization to 221 B.C
    https://books.google.com/books?id=cHA7Ey0-pbEC&pg=PA973
    • Michael Loewe 1978-1986 574. The Cambridge History of China Volume I: Ch'in and Han Empires, 221 B.C. -- A.D. 220.
    https://books.google.com/books?id=A2HKxK5N2sAC&pg=PA74
    • Creel 1970 p92. What is Taoism?
    https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA92 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/92/modee/2up
  39. ^
    • Michael Loewe 1978/1986 539-540. The Cambridge History of China Volume I: Ch'in and Han Empires, 221 B.C. -- A.D. 220.
    https://books.google.com/books?id=A2HKxK5N2sAC&pg=PA539
    • Bo Mou 2009. p208. Routledge History of Chinese Philosophy
  40. ^ Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/chinese-legalism/
  41. ^ Pines 2014 Birth of an Empire. p267 https://books.google.com/books?id=_aowDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA267
    • Pines 2013. p267. The Messianic Emperor
  42. ^ Pines 2014 Birth of an Empire. p213 https://books.google.com/books?id=_aowDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA213
  43. ^
    • Michael Loewe 1978/1986 74,526,534-535. The Cambridge History of China Volume I: Ch'in and Han Empires, 221 B.C. -- A.D. 220.
    https://books.google.com/books?id=A2HKxK5N2sAC&pg=PA534
  44. ^
    • Mark Edward Lewis 2007. p42,72. The Early Chinese Empires: Qin and Han
    https://books.google.com/books?id=JyEsEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA72
    • Pines 2009. p110. Envisioning Eternal Empire
    https://books.google.com/books?id=zhpLJgHZMTQC&pg=PA110
  45. ^ Michael Loewe 1999 p1008, The Cambridge History of Ancient China: From the Origins of Civilization to 221 B.C https://books.google.com/books?id=cHA7Ey0-pbEC&pg=PA1008
    • Creel 1970 p92. What is Taoism?
    https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA92 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/92/mode/2up
  46. ^ Goldin 2011. p3-4 Persistent Misconceptions Kidder Smith. 2003 p141-144. Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism
  47. ^ Creel 1970 p92. What is Taoism? https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA92
    • Kidder Smith. 2003 p141-144. Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism
  48. ^ Goldin 2011. p5 Persistent Misconceptions
  49. ^ Thomas A. Metzger 1976. p19
  50. ^ a b Vincent S. Leung. 2019. P103 The Politics of the Past in Early China https://books.google.com/books?id=1DCdDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA103
    • Pines 2017 p85 Abridged Book of Lord Shang
  51. ^ Goldin 2011. p3-4 Persistent Misconceptions
    • Kidder Smith. 2003 p141-144. Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism
  52. ^ Creel 1970 p113,119. What is Taoism? https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA113 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/113/modee/2up
  53. ^ Kidder Smith. 2003 p141-144. Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism
  54. ^ Pines, Yuri, "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/chinese-legalism/ https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/79/mode/2up
    • Makeham 1990.p95-96 THE LEGALIST CONCEPT OF HSING-MING
  55. ^ Goldin 2011. p8,10 Persistent Misconceptions
  56. ^ Lü Peng 2023 p44. A History of China in the 20th Century https://www.google.com/books?id=gRLREAAAQBAJ&pg=PA44
  57. ^ https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/94/mode/2up
  58. ^ Kenneth Winston
  59. ^ Pines 2017. Abridged Book of Lord Shang p70
  60. ^ Creel 1970 p115. What is Taoism? https://books.google.com/books?id=5p6EBnx4_W0C&pg=PA115 https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/115/mode/2up
  61. ^ https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/117/mode/2up
  62. ^ Hansen, Chad, "Daoism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2020 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2020/entries/daoism
  63. ^ YANG Soon-ja 2011. SHEN Dao’s Own Voice
  64. ^ * Graham 1989. 268 https://books.google.com/books?id=QBzyCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA268
  65. ^
    • Yuri Pines. 2019. p689. Worth Vs. Power: Han Fei's “Objection to Positional Power” Revisited
  66. ^ Huang Kejian 2016 p166,180
  67. ^ * Vitali Rubin, "Shen Tao and Fa-chia" Journal of the American Oriental Society, 94.3 1974,pp. 337-46
    • Bishop, Donald H. (September 27, 1995). P,81,93 Chinese Thought: An Introduction. Motilal Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 9788120811393
    • Pending sorting
  68. ^ Goldin 2011. p8,10 Persistent Misconceptions
  69. ^ https://archive.org/details/whatistaoismothe0000cree/page/93/mode/2up
    • Luke Habberstad p201. Forming the Early Chinese Court: Rituals, Spaces, Roles
    https://books.google.com/books?id=wjVKDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA201
  70. ^ Feng Youlan 1948. p33. A short history of Chinese philosophy https://archive.org/details/in.ernet.dli.2015.260423/page/n55/mode/2up
  71. ^ Yang Zhong 2003 p. 26. Local Government and Politics in China: Challenges from Below. https://books.google.com/books?id=yuW3BgAAQBAJ&pg=PA26
  72. ^ "Chinese Law". daviddfriedman.com. Retrieved 17 September 2023.
  73. ^ Goldin 2011. Persistent Misconceptions
  74. ^ https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-legalism/#Rule * A.C. Graham 1989. p269 https://books.google.com/books?id=QBzyCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA269
  75. ^ Characterization
    • Pines 2013. p77. Submerged by Absolute Power
    https://books.google.com/books?id=ow5EY_upzRkC&pg=PA87
  76. ^ Pines 2013. p77. Submerged by Absolute Power https://books.google.com/books?id=ow5EY_upzRkC&pg=PA77
  77. ^
  78. ^ Institutions https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2023/entries/chinese-legalism/
  79. ^ Xuezhi Guo 2002 p241. Ideal Chinese Political Leader
  80. ^ Eirik Lang Harris 2013 pp. 1,5 Constraining the Ruler
  81. ^ Chen, Chao Chuan and Yueh-Ting Lee 2008 p. 115. Leadership and Management in China
  82. ^ Yuri Pines 2003 pp. 78,81. Submerged by Absolute Power
  83. ^ Chen Qiyou 2000: 18.48.1049; 20.54.1176; 2.6.111; 17.45.998
  84. ^ Graham, A. C. (15 December 2015). Disputers of the Tao: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China. Open Court. ISBN 9780812699425 – via Google Books.
  85. ^ Enlightened Absolutism
  86. ^ Huang-Lao Daojia
    • Jay L. Garfield, William Edelglass 2011. p47. Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy
    • Graham, A. C. 1989/2015. Disputers of the Tao.
    p268. Guanzi was classed as Daoist in the Han bibliography. p374. Daodejing. 376. Zhuangzi. p377. No one is named.
    • Hansen, Chad 1992/2000. p345,350,401. A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought: A Philosophical Interpretation
    • ✓ Paul R. Goldin 2011. p2. Persistent Misconceptions about Chinese Legalism.
    • Herrlee G. Creel, 1974. p123-124. Shen Pu-Hai: A Secular Philosopher of Administration, Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1.
    • Creel, Herrlee Glessner 1970. What Is Taoism?
    p10-11. Huanglao Shiji. p48. Lao Tzu. p51. Huangdi. p71-72. xingming zhuangzi. 95,99 Analects. 99. Not a Daoist
  87. ^ Daojia and Daoist references
    • Cao, F. (2017). Introduction: On the Huang-Lao Tradition of Daoist Thought. In: Daoism in Early China. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55094-1_1
    • ✓ Benjamin Schwarz. The World of Thought in Ancient China p.237.
    • Daniel Coyle 1999. Guiguzi: On the Cosmological Axes of Chinese Persuasion. p.114.
    Shendao/Guanzhong Fajia/Daojia.
  88. ^ Arguments for Daoist influence Earlier based in Kayrn Lai (2008), Pines still does not regard Daoism as evidential outside a few chapters.
    • Yuri Pines (2022) Han Feizi and the Earliest Exegesis of Zuozhuan, Monumenta Serica, 70:2, 341-365, DOI: 10.1080/02549948.2022.2131797

    Moody represents a disciplined comparison without assumption of Daoist influence. Referencing moody, Mingjun argues for natural-law Daoism in the Han Feizi that would typically be associated with the Han dynasty Huainanzi.
    • Peter R. Moody 2011. Han Fei in his Context: Legalism on the Eve of the Qin conquest. John Wiley and Sons; Wiley (Blackwell Publishing); Blackwell Publishing Inc.; Wiley; Brill (ISSN 0301-8121), Journal of Chinese Philosophy, #1, 38, pages 14-30, 2011 feb 24
    • Mingjun Lu 2016. p.344. "Implications of Han Fei's Philosophy". Journal of Chinese Political Science.

    a disciplinary rejection of assumed daoist influence does not appear to necessarily be shared by the Chinese, or otherwise at any rate by persons prior the Oxford. Prior represented in Creel, its discipline is rooted in Graham 1989/Hansen 1992 as represented in the Oxford 2011.

    Professor Xing-Lu (1998), based in the west although prior the Oxford, references their work, but either doesn't agree with their conclusions or ignores them in terms of Daoism and Fa as requiring no connection to punishment. Peng He, located in Beijing, simply references Sima Qian out of hand for theory of Daoist origin, despite otherwise quality content.

    • Xing Lu 1998. p264. Rhetoric in Ancient China, Fifth to Third Century, B.C.E.

    https://books.google.com/books?id=Lw9hEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA264

    • Peng He 2014. p. 69. Chinese Lawmaking: From Non-communicative to Communicative.
    • Kejian, Huang 2016. p180. From Destiny to Dao: A Survey of Pre-Qin Philosophy in China.
  89. ^ Notes. Creel's branches
    • Michael Loewe 1978/1986. p74. Cambridge History of China Volume I
    https://books.google.com/books?id=A2HKxK5N2sAC&pg=PA74
    • Bishop, Donald H. (September 27, 1995). P,81,93 Chinese Thought: An Introduction. Motilal Banarsidass Publ. ISBN 9788120811393.'
    • Yuri Pines. 2019. p689. Worth Vs. Power: Han Fei's “Objection to Positional Power” Revisited


Sources and further reading edit

  • Pines, Yuri (2023), "Legalism in Chinese Philosophy", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 28 January 2022
  • Lai, Karyn L. (2008), An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-1-139-47171-8.
  • Creel, Herrlee Glessner. What Is Taoism?: And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History (1982)
  • Creel, Herrlee Glessner. Shen Pu-hai: A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B.C. (1974)
  • Goldin, Paul R. (March 2011). "Persistent misconceptions about Chinese 'Legalism'". Journal of Chinese Philosophy. 38 (1): 88–104. doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2010.01629.x. See also
    • Goldin, Paul R. (2011), "Response to editor", Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 38 (2): 328–329, doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2011.01654.x.
    • Cheng, Chung-ying (2011), "Editor's discussion", Journal of Chinese Philosophy, 38 (2): 330, doi:10.1111/j.1540-6253.2011.01655.x.
  • Schwartz, Benjamin I. (1985), The World of Thought in Ancient China, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, ISBN 978-0-674-96191-3.
  • Creel, Herrlee Glessner, 1974 Shen Pu-Hai: A Secular Philosopher of Administration, Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1.
  • Makeham, John (1994) Name and Actuality in Early Chinese Thought
  • Bodde, Derk (1986). "The State and Empire of Ch'in". In Twitchett, Denis; Loewe, Michael (eds.). The Cambridge History of China Volume I: Ch'in and Han Empires, 221 B.C. — A.D. 220. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521243278.
  • Graham, A.C., Disputers of the TAO: Philosophical Argument in Ancient China (Open Court 1993). ISBN 0-8126-9087-7
  • Hansen, Chad. Philosophy East & West. Jul94, Vol. 44 Issue 3. Fa (standards: laws) and meaning changes in Chinese philosophy
  • Barbieri-Low, Anthony, trans. The Standard Measure of Shang Yang (344 B.C.) (2006)
  • Eno, Robert (2010), Legalism and Huang-Lao Thought (PDF), Indiana University, Early Chinese Thought Course Readings

External links edit

  • The Han Feizi
  • Book of Lord Shang
  • The Shenzi

legalism, chinese, philosophy, other, uses, legalism, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, this, article, confusing, unclear, readers, please, help, clarify,. For other uses see Legalism This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article may be confusing or unclear to readers Please help clarify the article There might be a discussion about this on the talk page November 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article may contain an excessive amount of intricate detail that may interest only a particular audience Please help by spinning off or relocating any relevant information and removing excessive detail that may be against Wikipedia s inclusion policy December 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message Fajia Chinese 法家 pinyin fǎ jia often translated as Legalism 2 is one of Sima Qian s six classical schools of thought in Chinese philosophy Compared in the West with political realism and even the model building of Max Weber 3 the fa school of thought represents several branches of what Feng Youlan called men of methods 4 who contributed greatly to the construction of the bureaucratic Chinese empire Although lacking a recognized founder the earliest persona of the Fajia is often considered Guan Zhong 720 645 BCE 5 while Chinese historians commonly regard Li Kui 455 395 BCE as the first Legalist philosopher The term Fajia was identified in the west by Sinologist Herrlee G Creel as referring to a combination of administrator Shen Buhai 400 337 BCE and Legalist Shang Yang 390 338 BCE as its founding branches but is noted earlier by K C Hsiao LegalismStatue of pivotal reformer Shang YangChinese法家Literal meaningSchool of Standards MethodsSchool of Law 1 59 TranscriptionsStandard MandarinHanyu PinyinFǎjiaGwoyeu RomatzyhFaajiaWade GilesFa3 chia1IPA fa tɕja WuRomanizationFat平 ka平Yue CantoneseYale RomanizationFaatgaaJyutpingFaat3 gaa1IPA faːt kaː Southern MinTai loHuat kaSinologist Jacques Gernet considered the theorists of the state later christened fajia or Legalists to be the most important intellectual tradition of the fourth and third centuries BCE 6 With the Han dynasty taking over the governmental institutions of the Qin dynasty almost unchanged the Qin to Tang dynasty were characterized by the centralizing statist tendencies of its tradition Leon Vandermeersch and Vitaly Rubin would assert not a single state measure throughout Chinese history as having been without Legalist influence 7 Dubbed by A C Graham the great synthesizer of Legalism Han Fei is regarded as their finest writer if not the greatest statesman in Chinese history Hu Shi Early considered the culminating or greatest of the Legalist texts 8 the Han Feizi is believed to contain the first commentaries on the Dao De Jing Sun Tzu s Art of War incorporates both a Daoist philosophy of inaction and impartiality and a Legalist system of punishment and rewards recalling Han Fei s use of the concepts of power 勢 shi and technique 術 shu 9 Temporarily coming to overt power as an ideology with the ascension of the Qin dynasty 10 82 the First Emperor of Qin and succeeding emperors often followed the template set by Han Fei 11 Though the origins of the Chinese administrative system cannot be traced to any one person prime minister Shen Buhai may have had more influence than any other in the construction of the merit system and might be considered its founder if not valuable as a rare pre modern example of abstract theory of administration Creel saw in Shen Buhai the seeds of the civil service examination and perhaps the first political scientist 12 13 94 Concerned largely with administrative and sociopolitical innovation Shang Yang was a leading reformer of his time 14 10 83 His numerous reforms transformed the peripheral Qin state into a militarily powerful and strongly centralized kingdom Much of Legalism was the development of certain ideas that lay behind his reforms helping lead Qin to ultimate conquest of the other states of China in 221 BCE 15 16 Taken as progressive the Fajia were rehabilitated in the twentieth century with reformers regarding it as a precedent for their opposition to conservative Confucian forces and religion 17 Contents 1 Historical background 2 Mohist predecessors 2 1 The elimination of harm 2 2 School of names 3 On the Qin 4 Sima Qian s Fajia 5 Philosophical introduction 5 1 Systems administration 5 2 Enlightened Absolutism 6 Huang Lao appropriation 7 Appendix 8 Notes 9 References 10 Sources and further reading 11 External linksHistorical background editFurther information Warring States period The Zhou dynasty was divided between the masses and the hereditary noblemen The latter were placed to obtain office and political power owing allegiance to the local prince who owed allegiance to the Son of Heaven 18 The dynasty operated according to the principles of Li and punishment The former was applied only to aristocrats the latter only to commoners 19 The earliest Zhou kings kept a firm personal hand on the government depending on their personal capacities personal relations between ruler and minister and upon military might The technique of centralized government being so little developed they deputed authority to regional lords almost exclusively clansmen When the Zhou kings could no longer grant new fiefs their power began to decline vassals began to identify with their own regions Aristocratic sub lineages became very important by virtue of their ancestral prestige wielding great power and proving a divisive force The political structures late Springs and Autumns period 770 453 BCE progressively disintegrated with schismatic hostility and debilitating struggles among rival polities 20 In the Spring and Autumn period rulers began to directly appoint state officials to provide advice and management leading to the decline of inherited privileges and bringing fundamental structural transformations as a result of what may be termed social engineering from above 1 59 Most Warring States period thinkers tried to accommodate a changing with the times paradigm and each of the schools of thought sought to provide an answer for the attainment of sociopolitical stability 14 Confucianism commonly considered to be China s ruling ethos was articulated in opposition to the establishment of legal codes the earliest of which were inscribed on bronze vessels in the sixth century BCE 21 For the Confucians the Classics provided the preconditions for knowledge 22 Orthodox Confucians tended to consider organizational details beneath both minister and ruler leaving such matters to underlings 13 107 and furthermore wanted ministers to control or at least admonish the ruler 23 359 Concerned with goodness the Confucians became the most prominent followed by proto Daoists and the administrative thought that Sima Tan termed the Fajia But the Daoists focused on the development of inner powers with little respect for mundane authority 24 25 and both the Daoists and Confucians held a regressive view of history that the age was a decline from the era of the Zhou kings 26 Mohist predecessors edit nbsp Between Mozi s background as an engineer and his pacifist leanings the Mohists became experts at building fortifications and sieges nbsp Small seal scripts were standardized by Li Si after the First Emperor of China gained control of the country evolving from the larger seal scripts of previous dynasties The 12 characters on this slab of floor brick affirm that it is an auspicious moment for the First Emperor to ascend the throne as the country is united and no men will be dying along the road Compared by the Stanford Encyclopedia with Socrates the Mohists of Mozi 470 BC 391 BC contained the philosophical germs of what Sima Qian would term the Fa School initiating philosophical debate positing some of ancient China s first theories and contributing to the political thought of contemporary reformers Finding the values of tradition and Confucian li ritual unconvincing the Mohists took universal welfare and the elimination of harm as morally right arguing against nepotism in favor of objective standards fa to unify moral judgements favoring thrift over extravagance economic wealth population growth and social order Mozi s ruler was intended to act as fa or example for the nobles and officials developing towards political technique Taking social order as a paramount universally assumed good the Mohists advocated a unified peaceful utilitarian or consequentialist ethical and political order with an authoritarian centralized meritocratic state led by a virtuous benevolent sovereign 27 The elimination of harm edit The elimination of harm is a Mohist doctrine Although Mohism can involve punishment the broader Chinese tradition considers punishment only one tool with people responsive to Confucian education or in the Mozi attitudes and just rules themselves The Book of Lord Shang highlights honor and regards his broader program of fa or law as a teaching transmitted by the accountable laws officers aiming to spread knowledge of it The multitude of people all know what to avoid and what to strive for they will avoid calamity and strive for happiness and so govern themselves Aiming at quick results although reward and punishment is a major emphasis for Shang Yang and Han Fei Shang Yang repeatedly advocates the abolition of punishment with punishment Liu Xiang takes Shen Buhai s work as advising that a ruler following his doctrine of administrative technique ought to follow after ministers proposals supervising strictly to abolish punishment Unlike his predecessor Shen Buhai Han Fei endorses Shang Yang s fa or law with critique and punishes violations of ministerial roles But it was not a primary component of his method Although there is old precedent for their roots in Confucianism Mohism their own variations on the theme doesn t necessarily make them Mohists as much as it does products of their environment 28 29 30 31 A quotation from Tao Jiang s exploratory work on justice and humaneness highlights the Qin as more conservative than the Mohists containing both Confucian and Mohist elements With a slightly modified quotation from the late Qin work the Lushi Chunqiu 32 The Mohist leader Fu Tun resided in Qin His son murdered a man King Hui of Qin said You sir are too old to have another son so I have already ordered that the officials not execute him I hope sir that you will abide by my judgment in this matter Fu Tun replied The law of the Mohist order says He who kills another person shall die he who injures another shall be punished The purpose of this is to prevent the injuring and killing of other people To prevent the injuring and killing of other people is the most important moral principle in the world Though your majesty out of kindness has ordered that the officials not execute my son I cannot but implement the law of the Mohist order He would not assent to King Hui s request and proceeded to kill his own son School of names edit Only termed Fajia later Sima Qian originally glosses Shang Yang Shen Buhai and Han Fei under the Xing Ming doctrine of the school of names 33 as a family of terms along with fa that Shen Buhai and Han Fei actually prominently used Xing Ming dealt in the administrative details of names and realities and word and substance of ministers with Shen Buhai in his time checking minister s works Xun Kuang also had a Xing Ming method only just behind Han Fei in sophistication Although its earlier thinkers are like Shen Buhai more Confucian more broadly philosophical than them and less advanced words and names are essential for administration 34 The three rise again in the Three Kingdoms period and broader teaching of names thinker Xu Gan differs from them but still follows Shang Yang Han Fei doctrine of reward and punishment emphasizing consistency over their extremes 35 Han Fei connects the word and substance of Shen Buhai s ministers with Shang Yang s doctrine of reward and punishment while not otherwise going into detail apart from extremes Han Fei more explicitly executes appropriation of titles but with punishment in the broader Qin context ultimately tending towards conversion into fines etc 36 A sovereign who wants to suppress treachery must examine and match performance or the form xing 形 and title or the name ming 名 Performance and title refer to the difference between the proposal and the task The minister lays out his proposal the ruler assigns him the task according to his proposal and solely on the basis of the task determines the minister s merit When the merit matches the task and the task matches the proposal the minister is rewarded when the merit does not match the task and the task does not match the proposal he is penalized Thus when the clear sighted sovereign nourishes his ministers the minister should not claim merit by overstepping the duties of his office nor should he present the proposal that does not match his task One who oversteps his office s duties dies one who se proposal does not match the task is punished then the ministers are unable to form cabals and cliques Pine s Stanford Encyclopedia Han Feizi 7 2 Two levers Far from the ministerial center as a contemporary of Shen Buhai Shang Yang connects Name with reward and punishment social status and reputation as passable to deceased soldier s heirs with Qin limitations The explicit relation between the school of names and Shang Yang is not currently articulated translator Pines discusses the broader context of the honor of a name as a motivator alongside wealth properly understood and manipulated towards state ends Shang Yang says 37 Wherever the name and benefit meet the people will go in this direction they brave what they consider bitter and perform what they consider dangerous because of the calculation of a name and benefit Thus in ordinary life the people calculate benefits facing death they think of a good name One cannot but investigate whence the name and benefit come When benefits come from land the people fully utilize their strength when the name comes from war the people are ready to die On the Qin editWhile broader Shang Yang Shen Buhai and Han Fei include important principles that can be found in the Qin empire s administration with Shang Yang influential on ancient China s unification and law Emperors and reformers would refer back to them and the broader milieu of their methods Han Fei presented the two as the opposite components of his doctrine but was like his predecessor Shen Buhai primarily bureaucratic With the Qin dynasty more reasonable than might be expected of the Book of Lord Shang the milder more administrative Shen Buhai s policies compliment Shang Yang in this sense 38 The Qin empire s laws were primarily administrative with fa referring primarily to standards models and norms Only including penal law alongside li ritual fa as comparative model manuals in the Qin empire guided penal legal procedure and application based on real life situations with publicly named wrongs linked to punishments While some Qin penal laws deal with infanticide or other unsanctioned harm of children it primarily concerned theft it does not much deal with murder By contrast detailed rules and endless paperwork tightly regulate grain weights measures and official documents 39 Although not discarding all his reforms the Qin had already abandoned Shang Yang s reforms focusing on agriculture and heavy punishment by the time of the Qin dynasty 40 The First Emperor declares himself to be benevolent and righteous 41 Regardless in the Qin and early Han criminals may be given amnesties and then only punished if they did it again 42 Penal law actually develops more in the Han dynasty The Qin often expelled criminals to the new colonies or pardoned them in exchange for fines labor or one to several aristocratic ranks even up to the death penalty While the penal laws would still be considered harsh compared to the modern day they were not harsh for their time and often not actually enacted 43 Villainizing the first Emperor while adopting Qin administration 44 a confused revulsion against the Qin occurs in the Han dynasty centering on Shang Yang and Han Fei as espousing rigorous law and punishment The Han dynasty ultimately takes the Qin dynasty as having practiced these 45 Sima Qian s Fajia editFajia was invented by Sima Tan 46 Although most figures later called Fajia were influential they were probably never an organized or self aware movement in the sense of the Mohists and Confucians Creel in his time took Shang Yang as the Fajia s Legalist school with Shen Buhai its administrative wing but only in the sense of their prominence influence and reform recollection Or they were schools in that their works could not have been written by one person 47 But no one ever called himself a Fajia 48 It does does not exist as a Warring States period category 49 its figures could never have used the term and does not represent a unified category of ideology between their texts With some similarities their emphases are different The typical canon includes Shen Buhai and Shen Dao only because they are part of Han Fei s lineage 50 Sima Qian lauds their capacity to clearly distinguish offices so that no one can overstep his responsibilities while also promoting it as a one time policy that could not be constantly applied 33 Sima Qian says 51 The fajia are strict and have little kindness but their alignment of the divisions between lord and subject superior and inferior cannot be improved upon Fajia do not distinguish between kin and stranger or differentiate between noble and base all are judged as one by their fa Thus they sunder the kindnesses of treating one s kin as kin and honoring the honorable It is a policy that could be practiced for a time but not applied for long thus I say they are strict and have little kindness But as for honoring rulers and derogating subjects and clarifying social divisions and offices so that no one is able to overstep them none of the Hundred Schools could improve upon this Creel explains Fajia coming to mean something like Legalism as a Han dynasty slur targeting regulation of the vassals and ministers despite the predominant Shen Buhai branch reformers commonly opposing punishment 52 Sima Qian does not name anyone under the schools 53 rather Shen Buhai Han Fei and their administrative method shift towards association with Shang Yang and punishment over the Han dynasty 54 With Shang Yang as the most Legalist of them its figures are not in critical academia characterized as Legalist modernly unless Shen Buhai s ministerial labor contracts or Han Fei s addendum of punishment count as Legalism Shen Buhai s method does not require a legal code 55 and has even been criticized for it in Chinese scholarship 56 Legalism has only still been used by some in recent years conventionally 50 Credited by Creel as syncretic precedent for their later association within the Fajia Chapter 43 of the Han Feizi says 57 Now Shen Buhai spoke about the need of Shu fa shu Method or Technique and Shang Yang practices the use of Fa Standards as including law What is called Shu is to create posts according to responsibilities hold actual services accountable according to official titles exercise the power over life and death and examine into the abilities of all his ministers these are the things that the ruler keeps in his own hand Fa includes mandates and ordinances promulgated to the government offices penalties that are definite in the mind of the people rewards that are due to the careful observers of standards and punishments that are inflicted upon those who violate orders It is what the subjects and ministers take as a model If the ruler is without Shu he will be overshadowed if the subjects and ministers lack Fa they will be insubordinate Thus neither can be dispensed with both are implements of emperors and kings As Han Fei discusses in chapter 43 Shen Buhai only had disorganized law in his comparatively new Hann state 58 As with Han Fei after him he was concerned primarily with ministers and administration 59 Based on his own reading of the Hanshu Homer H Dubs considered Shen Buhai the best ruler of the Hann state 60 Shen Buhai is likely in the Fajia rather than then the school of names due to opposition and presence in the Han Feizi 61 Mentioned in the Outer Zhuangzi and with a potential influence in Daoism 62 scholar Shen Dao would remembered for his secondary subject of shih or situational authority of which he is spoken in Chapter 40 of the Han Feizi and incorporated into The Art of War He only uses the term twice in the his fragments 63 Xun Kuang calls Shen Dao beclouded with fa instead naming Shen Buhai for the doctrine of position 64 He is earlier taken as having a group based on the chapter 65 but although known by some in his time has no record of any notable activity and is only mentioned in the shiji in a stub with the claim that along with the others he had incompletely studied Sima Qian s own Huang Lao ideology 66 67 With Shu as Han Fei s distinctive although Han Fei and Shen Dao make some use of fa akin to law with reward and punishment they both generally use fa similarly to Shen Buhai as an impersonal administrative technique With a quotation from Han Fei as example 68 An enlightened ruler employs fa to pick his men he does not select them himself He employs fa to weigh their merit he does not fathom it himself Thus ability cannot be obscured nor failure prettified If those who are falsely glorified cannot advance and likewise those who are maligned cannot be set back then there will be clear distinctions between lord and subject and order will be easily attained Thus the ruler can only use fa The early Han dynasty kings who used Xing Ming made capital punishment rare After the death of Gongsun Hong the chancellery becomes ineffective with only two not executed Serving as a secondary historical moniker for the fajia Xing Ming s meaning ultimately narrows into the names of punishments becomes a term for criminal law and is given to ministers in charge of criminal affairs 69 Along with departments for the other schools Liu Xin assigns the Fajia a fictional origin in an ancient ministry of criminal justice for his imperial library classification system 70 while the school of names were already considered disputers in the Warring States period Hence Pines explains the term Fajia as a cataloguing label for intellectually related texts While its earliest usage is unknown it was already termed Legalism dating to the 1939 translation of the Han Feizi with a decreasing usage over the decades 33 Philosophical introduction editSystems administration edit nbsp The key figure in the late imperial bureaucracy was the district magistrate a combination of a mayor chief of police judge and even military commander 71 He obtained the position by passing the examination for the civil service and performance at a lower level He had a staff some who moved with him some permanently located in the district Any penalty more serious than bambooing had to be approved by higher officials any decision not based on statute required approval from Peking 72 Drawing by William Alexander draughtsman of the Macartney Embassy to China in 1793 Although Han Fei does not necessarily try to establish any kind of general theory of state 73 he still seems closer in spirit to certain 19th and 20th century social scientific model builders with Shen Buhai s model of bureaucratic organization much closer to Weber s modern ideal type than to any notion of patrimonial bureaucracy Contrary to comparisons with the art of Machiavelli Shen Buhai and Han Fei have been compared more with science of politics and even the model building of Max Weber 74 In practical terms the ruler s authority means that he ought to hold the power to reward and punish which Han Fei advises However his power is simply institutional Both the Book of Lord Shang and Han Feizi consider their rulers shortsighted mediocre and muddle headed Hence fa thinkers do not actually make much discussion of such factors as charisma that might enhance the ruler s personal power Han Fei has tactics in later chapters but primarily attempts to convince the ruler that a do nothing role of paper checking and rubber stamping will be the best thing for him 75 excessive citations Han Fei says 76 If the sovereign personally inspects his hundred officials the whole day will not be enough his power will not suffice Moreover when the superior uses his eyesight the underlings embellish what he sees when he uses his hearing the underlings embellish what he hears when he uses his contemplation the underlings multiply their words The former kings considered these three methods as insufficient hence they cast away personal abilities and relied on laws and administrative methods examining rewards and punishments Han Fei has like other ancient thinkers been considered a defender of monarchy But his critics have not necessarily considered him anti people but anti ministerial with Han Fei more concerned with bureaucracy Some have considered Shang Yang noting more than a defender of state power but while the Book of Lord Shang in particular has been taken as anti people with a broader program of agriculture and war ordinary people have an interest in the security against arbitrary punishment by controlling penal officials which Shang Yang s fa penal law and Han Fei s Shu managerial technique regulate If they are taken as only serving the ruler it is only by discarding the people from the equation 77 Enlightened Absolutism edit Not expecting that monstrous tyrants can be accommodated although Han Fei frequently addresses the enlightened ruler what Pines terms the fa tradition must aim to accommodate mediocrities on the throne Characterized as akin to social engineers they aim at perfectly designed foolproof self regulating mechanically reliable institutions 78 excessive citations Xuezhi Guo s Ideal Chinese Political Leader contrasts the Confucian Humane ruler with the Legalists as intending to create a truly enlightened ruler He quotes Benjamin I Schwartz as describing the features of a truly Legalist enlightened ruler 79 He must be anything but an arbitrary despot if one means by a despot a tyrant who follows all his impulses whims and passions Once the systems which maintain the entire structure are in place he must not interfere with their operation He may use the entire system as a means to the achievement of his national and international ambitions but to do so he must not disrupt its impersonal workings He must at all times be able to maintain an iron wall between his private life and public role Concubines friends flatterers and charismatic saints must have no influence whatsoever on the course of policy and he must never relax his suspicions of the motives of those who surround him As easily as mediocre carpenters can draw circles by employing a compass anyone can employ the system Han Fei envisions 80 The enlightened ruler restricts his desires and refrains from displays of personal ability or input in policy Capability is not dismissed but the ability to use talent will allow the ruler greater power if he can utilize others with the given expertise 81 Laws and regulations allow him to utilize his power to the utmost Adhering unwaveringly to legal and institutional arrangements the average monarch is numinous 82 83 Graham writes Han Fei s ruler empty of thoughts desires partialities of his own concerned with nothing in the situation but the facts selects his ministers by objectively comparing their abilities with the demands of the offices Inactive doing nothing he awaits their proposals compares the project with the results and rewards or punishes His own knowledge ability moral worth warrior spirit such as they may be are wholly irrelevant he simply performs his function in the impersonal mechanism of the state 84 288 Pines recalls Graham s provocative conclusion that the ruler in Han Fei s system has no functions which could not be performed by an elementary computer questioning whether it is not in fact the ministers who do the ruling Resting empty Han Fei s ruler simply checking shapes against names and dispenses rewards and punishments accordingly concertizing the Dao as standards for right and wrong Submerged by the system he supposedly runs the alleged despot disappears from the scene 85 excessive citations Huang Lao appropriation edit nbsp Sima QianSima Qian claims Shen Dao Shen Buhai and Han Fei as having studied the teachings of his own faction the Teachings of the Yellow Emperor and Lao tzu Huang Lao synonymous with daojia school of Dao early Daoism Although modernly included under early Daoism it would not have meant Daoism as understood modernly With pre Han Daoists also more an informal network than an organized school or movement Daojia first appears in the Records and is also taken as retrospective Associated with the much earlier Guan Zhong the Guanzi with its proto daoist texts was classed as Daoist in the Han bibliography with the texts commonly classed Guan Zhong and Shen Dao under Daojia before Fajia Given its precedent with formal similarities between the texts and Daoism as including Han Fei s advocacy of wu wei so called effortless action or reduced activity by the ruler the theorists were often supposed by the Chinese and early scholarship to have studied Daoism Modern scholarship does not take the Daodejing to be as ancient Incomplete versions date back to the fourth century B C while the earliest complete written editions of the Daodejing only date back to the early Han dynasty No pre Han records discuss it citation needed By Creel s time few critical scholars believed Laozi to have been a contemporary of Confucius Although incomplete versions of the Daodejing may have been contemporary to Shen Buhai s time Creel did not find Shen Buhai as Han Fei s predecessor and prior prime minister of their native Hann state to be influenced by Daoist ideas lacking metaphysical content Shen Buhai quotes the Analects of Confucius in which Wu Wei can also be seen as an idea citation needed As had generally already been accepted by scholarship at the time Creel did not find the Han Feizi s Daodejing commentary to have been written by Han Fei A C Graham would reiterate that Han Fei does not appear to make effective use of it The Han Feizi is most similar to the Shen Buhai fragments Evidences for Daoist influence on the Han Feizi remain lacking outside of a few tertiary chapters The final chapter of the Zhuangzi does not regard Laozi and Zhuangzi as having been part of a Daoist school The Outer Zhuangzi s history includes Confucians Mohists Shendao Laozi and Zhuangzi effectively leaving out a Legalist school with the Mohists as a primary influence citation needed However while others of the Fajia are left out the Zhuangzi takes Shen Dao as Daoistic preceding both Laozi and Zhuangzi With precedent in Creel Schwarz and Graham Hansen of the Standford s Daoism would take Daoist theory as beginning in the relativist discussions of Shen Dao He still considers Shen Dao s theory foundational for a Daoist favoring of Dao as meaning guide over Heaven a narrative shared with the late Mohists in that an appeal to Heaven justifies thieves as well as sages citation needed Although modernly more often given to contrast and comparison with the Mohists comparison and attempts to root the Han Feizi in proto Daoist attitudes or naturalism can be still seen within scholarship Creel did not exclude the possibility that Daoist ideas influenced the fajia before they were written down in the Zhuangzi and Daodejing or for instance influence by Yang Zhu and the Yangists but his evidences suggested Huang Lao as not existing during Shen Buhai s time Writing at the turn of its discussion John Makeham 1990 still considered some of the Han Feizi s most typifying chapters as being of distinctly Daoist quality not considering at least the dividing line between the two as having ever been particularly clear 86 excessive citations 87 excessive citations 88 excessive citations Appendix editThis section is empty You can help by adding to it February 2024 Notes editCreel s branches of the Fajia Creel s basic lense for the subject would be reiterated by K C Hsiao 1979 Michael Loewe 1986 of the Cambridge History of China A C Graham 1989 and S Y Hsieh 1995 With his prior What is Taoism as relevant Creel s Shen Pu Hai A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B C remains the only major publication on Shen Buhai Tao Jiang would modernly reiterate its view as having superseded that of Feng Youlan 1948 Emphasizing Creel s heavy utilization of other works Tao Jiang still takes him as still very useful for understanding fajia thought more generally 89 Tao Jiang mentions Korean scholar Soon Ja Yang as the only opposition with a more Legalist Shen Buhai as going against the general history citation needed References editThis section has an unclear citation style The references used may be made clearer with a different or consistent style of citation and footnoting February 2024 Learn how and when to remove this template message a b Garfield Jay L Edelglass William 9 June 2011 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy OUP USA ISBN 9780195328998 via Google Books Pines Yuri 2023 Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps plato stanford edu entries chinese legalism Tao Jiang 2021 p238 Origins of Moral Political Philosophy in Early Chinahttps books google com books id qXo EAAAQBAJ amp pg PA238 Goldin Paul R March 2011 Persistent misconceptions about Chinese Legalism Creel Herrlee Glessner 1970 1982 p93 119 120 What Is Taoism A C Graham 1989 p269 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA269 Feng Youlan 1948 p 37 A short history of Chinese philosophy Chen Jianfu 1999 Chinese Law Towards an Understanding of Chinese Law Its Nature and Development The Hague Kluwer Law International p 12 ISBN 9041111867 Schwarz 1985 p325 regarded as a forefather by Han literature Eno Robert 2010 Legalism and Huang Lao Thought PDF Indiana University Early Chinese Thought Course Readingshttps chinatxt sitehost iu edu Thought Legalism pdf Jay L Garfield William Edelglass 2011 p 63 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy https books google com books id I0iMBtaSlHYC amp pg PA63 Jacques Gernet 1982 p 90 A History of Chinese Civilization https books google com books id jqb7L pKCV8C amp pg PA90 Jay L Garfield William Edelglass 2011 p 60 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy https books google com books id I0iMBtaSlHYC amp pg PA60 Creel Herrlee Glessner 15 September 1982 p103 What Is Taoism And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History University of Chicago Press ISBN 9780226120478 via Google Books Hengy Chye Kiang 1999 p 44 Cities of Aristocrats and Bureaucrats https books google com books id BIgS4p8NykYC amp pg PA44 Rubin Vitaliĭ 1976 p55 Individual and state in ancient China essays on four Chinese philosophers Yu lan Fung 1948 p 157 A Short History of Chinese Philosophy https books google com books id HZU0YKnpTH0C amp pg PA157 Graham 1989 p268 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA268 Chen Chao Chuan and Yueh Ting Lee 2008 p 12 Leadership and Management in China a b Bishop Donald H 27 September 1995 Chinese Thought An Introduction Motilal Banarsidass Publ ISBN 9788120811393 Kenneth Winston p 315 Singapore Journal of Legal Studies 2005 313 347 The Internal Morality of Chinese Legalism http law nus edu sg sjls articles SJLS 2005 313 pdf Graham A C 1989 2015 p283 Disputers of the Tao Creel 1974 p4 5 Shen Pu hai A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B C a b Creel Herrlee Glessner 15 September 1982 What Is Taoism And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History University of Chicago Press ISBN 9780226120478 via Google Books a b Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2014 Edition Edward N Zalta ed 1 2 Historical Context http plato stanford edu archives win2014 entries chinese legalism Eno 2010 p 1 Chad Hansen University of Hong Kong Lord Shang http www philosophy hku hk ch Lord 20Shang htm Charles Holcombe 2011 p 42 A History of East Asia https books google com books id rHeb7wQu0xIC amp pg PA42 K K Lee 1975 p 24 Legalist School and Legal Positivism Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 2 Yu lan Fung 1948 p 155 A Short History of Chinese Philosophy https books google com books id HZU0YKnpTH0C amp pg PA155 Herrlee G Creel 1974 p 124 Shen Pu Hai A Secular Philosopher of Administration Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1 firm hand devolution aristocratic lineages Edward L Shaughnessy China Empire and Civilization p26 rise of regional powers Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy 1 2 Historical Context disintegration and struggle David K Schneider May June 2016 p 20 China s New Legalism Knoblox Xunzi 148 Hansen Chad 17 August 2000 A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought A Philosophical Interpretation Oxford University Press ISBN 9780195350760 via Google Books K K Lee 1975 p 26 Legalist School and Legal Positivism Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 2 Waley Arthur 1939 Three Ways of Thought in Ancient China London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd p 194 Huang Ray China A Macro History p 20 Daoists little respect for mundane authority Jay L Garfield William Edelglass 2011 p 65 The Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy Daoists and Confucians regressive view of history Fa concept Fraser Chris Mohism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives fall2023 entries mohism Schwarz 1985 p321 322 329 World of thought Goldin 2011 p10 Persistent Misconceptions Makeham 1994 p70 Name and Actualityhttps books google com books id GId ASbEI2YC amp pg PA70 Hansen 1992 p359 367https books google com books id QybpAAAAIAAJ amp pg 367 Creel 1970 p101 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA101 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 101 modee 2up Pines 2009 p110 Envisioning Eternal Empire https books google com books id zhpLJgHZMTQC amp pg PA110 Creel 1974 Shen Pu Hai p126 A Secular Philosopher Creel 1970 p101 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA101 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 101 modee 2up An emphasis for punishment has never been demonstrated and barely argued for the tactful Shen Buhai 47 Benjamin Schwartz cites the fact that the two handles of punishment and reward are clearly part of shu in rebuttal of Creel s insistence that Shen Buhai was not a Legalist but his reputation belies him actually blatantly using punishment Schwarz 1985 p334 https books google com books id AT pAAAAIAAJ amp Tao Jiang 2021 p40 Knoblock and Riegel 2000 trans 75 a b c Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Creel 1970 p101 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA79 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 79 modee 2up Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Makeham 1994 p70 100 https books google com books id GId ASbEI2YC amp pg PA100 Encyclopedia of Chinese Philosophy p492 https books google com books id yTv AQAAQBAJ amp pg PA492 Makeham p265 Balanced Discourses A Bilingual Edition https books google com books id O9OPW7TKip8C amp pg PA265 Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism MoniOffiTechRule Makeham 1990 p95 96 THE LEGALIST CONCEPT OF HSING MING Pines Yuri 2023 Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps plato stanford edu entries chinese legalism HumaNatu Pines 2017 p51 Abridged Book of Lord Shang Michael Loewe 1999 p973 The Cambridge History of Ancient China From the Origins of Civilization to 221 B Chttps books google com books id cHA7Ey0 pbEC amp pg PA973 Michael Loewe 1978 1986 574 The Cambridge History of China Volume I Ch in and Han Empires 221 B C A D 220 https books google com books id A2HKxK5N2sAC amp pg PA74 Creel 1970 p92 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA92 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 92 modee 2up Michael Loewe 1978 1986 539 540 The Cambridge History of China Volume I Ch in and Han Empires 221 B C A D 220 https books google com books id A2HKxK5N2sAC amp pg PA539 Bo Mou 2009 p208 Routledge History of Chinese Philosophy Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Pines 2014 Birth of an Empire p267 https books google com books id aowDwAAQBAJ amp pg PA267 Pines 2013 p267 The Messianic Emperor Pines 2014 Birth of an Empire p213 https books google com books id aowDwAAQBAJ amp pg PA213 Michael Loewe 1978 1986 74 526 534 535 The Cambridge History of China Volume I Ch in and Han Empires 221 B C A D 220 https books google com books id A2HKxK5N2sAC amp pg PA534 Mark Edward Lewis 2007 p42 72 The Early Chinese Empires Qin and Hanhttps books google com books id JyEsEAAAQBAJ amp pg PA72 Pines 2009 p110 Envisioning Eternal Empirehttps books google com books id zhpLJgHZMTQC amp pg PA110 Michael Loewe 1999 p1008 The Cambridge History of Ancient China From the Origins of Civilization to 221 B C https books google com books id cHA7Ey0 pbEC amp pg PA1008 Creel 1970 p92 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA92 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 92 mode 2up Goldin 2011 p3 4 Persistent Misconceptions Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Creel 1970 p92 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA92 Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Goldin 2011 p5 Persistent Misconceptions Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Thomas A Metzger 1976 p19 a b Vincent S Leung 2019 P103 The Politics of the Past in Early China https books google com books id 1DCdDwAAQBAJ amp pg PA103 Pines 2017 p85 Abridged Book of Lord Shang Goldin 2011 p3 4 Persistent Misconceptions Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Creel 1970 p113 119 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA113 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 113 modee 2up Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Creel 1970 p79 92 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA79https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 79 mode 2up Makeham 1990 p95 96 THE LEGALIST CONCEPT OF HSING MING Goldin 2011 p8 10 Persistent Misconceptions Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism MoniOffiTechRule Lu Peng 2023 p44 A History of China in the 20th Century https www google com books id gRLREAAAQBAJ amp pg PA44 Creel 1970 p94 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA94https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 94 mode 2up Makeham 1994 p68 https books google com books id GId ASbEI2YC amp pg PA68 A C Graham 1989 p269 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA269 Kenneth Winston Pines 2017 Abridged Book of Lord Shang p70 Creel 1970 p115 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA115 https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 115 mode 2up Kidder Smith 2003 p141 144 Sima Tan and the Invention of Daoism Creel 1970 p113 129 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA117https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 117 mode 2up Hansen Chad Daoism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 Edition Edward N Zalta ed https plato stanford edu archives spr2020 entries daoism Hansen 1992 p345 Benjamin I Schwarz 1985 p 247 https books google com books id kA0c1hl3CXUC amp pg PA247 YANG Soon ja 2011 SHEN Dao s Own Voice Graham 1989 268 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA268 Yuri Pines 2019 p689 Worth Vs Power Han Fei s Objection to Positional Power Revisited Huang Kejian 2016 p166 180 Vitali Rubin Shen Tao and Fa chia Journal of the American Oriental Society 94 3 1974 pp 337 46 Bishop Donald H September 27 1995 P 81 93 Chinese Thought An Introduction Motilal Banarsidass Publ ISBN 9788120811393 Pending sorting Goldin 2011 p8 10 Persistent Misconceptions Makeham 1990 THE LEGALIST CONCEPT OF HSING MING Creel 1970 p79 92 What is Taoism https books google com books id 5p6EBnx4 W0C amp pg PA79https archive org details whatistaoismothe0000cree page 93 mode 2up Luke Habberstad p201 Forming the Early Chinese Court Rituals Spaces Roleshttps books google com books id wjVKDwAAQBAJ amp pg PA201 Feng Youlan 1948 p33 A short history of Chinese philosophy https archive org details in ernet dli 2015 260423 page n55 mode 2up Yang Zhong 2003 p 26 Local Government and Politics in China Challenges from Below https books google com books id yuW3BgAAQBAJ amp pg PA26 Chinese Law daviddfriedman com Retrieved 17 September 2023 Goldin 2011 Persistent Misconceptions https plato stanford edu entries chinese legalism Rule Benajamin Schwarz 1985 p337 341 348 https books google com books id kA0c1hl3CXUC amp pg PA337 A C Graham 1989 p269 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA269 Characterization Pines 2013 p77 Submerged by Absolute Powerhttps books google com books id ow5EY upzRkC amp pg PA87 Graham 1989 p268 269 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA290 Goldin 2011 p10 persistent misconceptions Tao Jiang 2021 p237 239 Creel 1974 p4 44 55 Pines 2013 p77 Submerged by Absolute Power https books google com books id ow5EY upzRkC amp pg PA77 Hansen 1992 daoist theory p347 358 359 364 368 375 Pines Yuri Legalism in Chinese Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Summer 2023 Edition Edward N Zalta amp Uri Nodelman eds https plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Graham 1989 p290 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA290 While accurate the defense of Shang Yang is actually by an old critic of the tradition Hansen Institutions Roger T Ames 1983 p 50 Art of Rulership The https books google com books id OkTurZP qAC amp pg PA50 Graham 1989 p268 269 https books google com books id QBzyCgAAQBAJ amp pg PA290 Jay L Garfield William Edelglass 2011 p59 Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy https books google com books id I0iMBtaSlHYC amp pg PA59 Pines Yuri 2023 Legalism in Chinese Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophyhttps plato stanford edu archives sum2023 entries chinese legalism Xuezhi Guo 2002 p241 Ideal Chinese Political Leader Eirik Lang Harris 2013 pp 1 5 Constraining the Ruler Chen Chao Chuan and Yueh Ting Lee 2008 p 115 Leadership and Management in China Yuri Pines 2003 pp 78 81 Submerged by Absolute Power Chen Qiyou 2000 18 48 1049 20 54 1176 2 6 111 17 45 998 Graham A C 15 December 2015 Disputers of the Tao Philosophical Argument in Ancient China Open Court ISBN 9780812699425 via Google Books Enlightened Absolutism Tao Jiang 2021 p242 Creel 1974 p6 Xuezhi Guo p 141 The Ideal Chinese Political Leader https books google com books id 6vG MROnr7IC amp pg PA141 Benjanmin I Schwartz p 345 The World of Thought in Ancient China https plato stanford edu entries chinese legalism Graham 1989 291 Xing Lu 1998 Rhetoric in Ancient China Fifth to Third Century B C E p 264 https books google com books id 72QURrAppzkC amp pg PA258 Yuri Pines 2003 p 81 Submerged by Absolute Power Huang Lao Daojia Jay L Garfield William Edelglass 2011 p47 Oxford Handbook of World Philosophy Graham A C 1989 2015 Disputers of the Tao p268 Guanzi was classed as Daoist in the Han bibliography p374 Daodejing 376 Zhuangzi p377 No one is named Hansen Chad 1992 2000 p345 350 401 A Daoist Theory of Chinese Thought A Philosophical Interpretation Paul R Goldin 2011 p2 Persistent Misconceptions about Chinese Legalism Herrlee G Creel 1974 p123 124 Shen Pu Hai A Secular Philosopher of Administration Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1 Creel Herrlee Glessner 1970 What Is Taoism p10 11 Huanglao Shiji p48 Lao Tzu p51 Huangdi p71 72 xingming zhuangzi 95 99 Analects 99 Not a Daoist Thomas Michael Religions 2022 The Original Text of the Daodejing https www mdpi com 2077 1444 13 4 325 Daojia and Daoist references Cao F 2017 Introduction On the Huang Lao Tradition of Daoist Thought In Daoism in Early China Palgrave Macmillan New York https doi org 10 1057 978 1 137 55094 1 1 Benjamin Schwarz The World of Thought in Ancient China p 237 Daniel Coyle 1999 Guiguzi On the Cosmological Axes of Chinese Persuasion p 114 Shendao Guanzhong Fajia Daojia Allyn Ricket 2001 p19 Guanzi Volume 1 p19 Shendao Hansen Chad Daoism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2020 Edition Edward N Zalta ed https plato stanford edu archives spr2020 entries daoism Arguments for Daoist influence Earlier based in Kayrn Lai 2008 Pines still does not regard Daoism as evidential outside a few chapters Yuri Pines 2022 Han Feizi and the Earliest Exegesis of Zuozhuan Monumenta Serica 70 2 341 365 DOI 10 1080 02549948 2022 2131797Moody represents a disciplined comparison without assumption of Daoist influence Referencing moody Mingjun argues for natural law Daoism in the Han Feizi that would typically be associated with the Han dynasty Huainanzi Peter R Moody 2011 Han Fei in his Context Legalism on the Eve of the Qin conquest John Wiley and Sons Wiley Blackwell Publishing Blackwell Publishing Inc Wiley Brill ISSN 0301 8121 Journal of Chinese Philosophy 1 38 pages 14 30 2011 feb 24 Mingjun Lu 2016 p 344 Implications of Han Fei s Philosophy Journal of Chinese Political Science a disciplinary rejection of assumed daoist influence does not appear to necessarily be shared by the Chinese or otherwise at any rate by persons prior the Oxford Prior represented in Creel its discipline is rooted in Graham 1989 Hansen 1992 as represented in the Oxford 2011 Professor Xing Lu 1998 based in the west although prior the Oxford references their work but either doesn t agree with their conclusions or ignores them in terms of Daoism and Fa as requiring no connection to punishment Peng He located in Beijing simply references Sima Qian out of hand for theory of Daoist origin despite otherwise quality content Xing Lu 1998 p264 Rhetoric in Ancient China Fifth to Third Century B C E https books google com books id Lw9hEAAAQBAJ amp pg PA264 Peng He 2014 p 69 Chinese Lawmaking From Non communicative to Communicative Kejian Huang 2016 p180 From Destiny to Dao A Survey of Pre Qin Philosophy in China Notes Creel s branches Michael Loewe 1978 1986 p74 Cambridge History of China Volume Ihttps books google com books id A2HKxK5N2sAC amp pg PA74 Bishop Donald H September 27 1995 P 81 93 Chinese Thought An Introduction Motilal Banarsidass Publ ISBN 9788120811393 Yuri Pines 2019 p689 Worth Vs Power Han Fei s Objection to Positional Power RevisitedSources and further reading editPines Yuri 2023 Legalism in Chinese Philosophy in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 28 January 2022 Lai Karyn L 2008 An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 139 47171 8 Creel Herrlee Glessner What Is Taoism And Other Studies in Chinese Cultural History 1982 Creel Herrlee Glessner Shen Pu hai A Chinese Political Philosopher of the Fourth Century B C 1974 Goldin Paul R March 2011 Persistent misconceptions about Chinese Legalism Journal of Chinese Philosophy 38 1 88 104 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 2010 01629 x See also Goldin Paul R 2011 Response to editor Journal of Chinese Philosophy 38 2 328 329 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 2011 01654 x Cheng Chung ying 2011 Editor s discussion Journal of Chinese Philosophy 38 2 330 doi 10 1111 j 1540 6253 2011 01655 x Schwartz Benjamin I 1985 The World of Thought in Ancient China Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 96191 3 Creel Herrlee Glessner 1974 Shen Pu Hai A Secular Philosopher of Administration Journal of Chinese Philosophy Volume 1 Makeham John 1994 Name and Actuality in Early Chinese Thought Bodde Derk 1986 The State and Empire of Ch in In Twitchett Denis Loewe Michael eds The Cambridge History of China Volume I Ch in and Han Empires 221 B C A D 220 Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521243278 Graham A C Disputers of the TAO Philosophical Argument in Ancient China Open Court 1993 ISBN 0 8126 9087 7 Hansen Chad Philosophy East amp West Jul94 Vol 44 Issue 3 Fa standards laws and meaning changes in Chinese philosophy Barbieri Low Anthony trans The Standard Measure of Shang Yang 344 B C 2006 Eno Robert 2010 Legalism and Huang Lao Thought PDF Indiana University Early Chinese Thought Course ReadingsExternal links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Legalism Chinese philosophy The Han Feizi Book of Lord Shang The Shenzi Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Legalism Chinese philosophy amp oldid 1207837469, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.