fbpx
Wikipedia

Johann Gottlieb Fichte

Johann Gottlieb Fichte (/ˈfɪktə/;[11] German: [ˈjoːhan ˈɡɔtliːp ˈfɪçtə];[12][13][14] 19 May 1762 – 29 January 1814) was a German philosopher who became a founding figure of the philosophical movement known as German idealism, which developed from the theoretical and ethical writings of Immanuel Kant. Recently, philosophers and scholars have begun to appreciate Fichte as an important philosopher in his own right due to his original insights into the nature of self-consciousness or self-awareness.[15] Fichte was also the originator of thesis–antithesis–synthesis,[2] an idea that is often erroneously attributed to Hegel.[16] Like Descartes and Kant before him, Fichte was motivated by the problem of subjectivity and consciousness. Fichte also wrote works of political philosophy; he has a reputation as one of the fathers of German nationalism.

Johann Gottlieb Fichte
Born(1762-05-19)19 May 1762
Died29 January 1814(1814-01-29) (aged 51)
NationalityGerman
EducationSchulpforta
University of Jena
(1780; no degree)
Leipzig University
(1781–1784; no degree)
Era18th-century philosophy
SchoolGerman idealism
InstitutionsUniversity of Jena
University of Erlangen
University of Berlin
Main interests
Self-consciousness, moral philosophy, political philosophy
Notable ideas
List
Signature

Biography Edit

Origins Edit

Fichte was born in Rammenau, Upper Lusatia, and baptized a Lutheran.[17] The son of a ribbon weaver,[18] Fichte was born into a pious family that had lived in the region for generations. Christian Fichte, Johann Gottlieb's father, married somewhat above his class. It has been suggested that a certain impatience which Fichte himself displayed throughout his life was an inheritance from his mother.[19]

He received a rudimentary education from his father. He showed remarkable ability from an early age, and it was owing to his reputation among the villagers that he gained the opportunity for a better education than he otherwise would have received. The story runs that the Freiherr von Miltitz, a country landowner, arrived too late to hear the local pastor preach. He was, however, informed that a lad in the neighborhood would be able to repeat the sermon almost verbatim. As a result, the baron took Fichte into his protection and paid for his tuition.[19]

Early schooling Edit

Fichte was placed in the family of Pastor Krebel at Niederau near Meissen, and there received a thorough grounding in the classics. From this time onward, Fichte saw little of his parents. In October 1774, he attended the celebrated foundation-school at Pforta near Naumburg. Freiherr von Miltitz continued to support him, but died in 1774. The Pforta school is associated with the names of Novalis, August Wilhelm Schlegel, Friedrich Schlegel, and Nietzsche. The spirit of the institution was semi-monastic and, while the education was excellent, it is doubtful whether there was enough social life and contact with the world for Fichte.[19]

Theological studies and private tutoring Edit

In 1780, Fichte began study at the University of Jena's Lutheran[20] theology seminary. He was transferred a year later to study at the Leipzig University. Fichte seems to have supported himself during this period of poverty and struggle.[19] Without the financial support by von Miltitz, Fichte had to end his studies without completing his degree.[21]

From 1784 to 1788, Fichte precariously supported himself as tutor for various Saxon families.[18] In early 1788, he returned to Leipzig in the hope of finding a better employment, but eventually he had to settle for a less promising position with the family of an innkeeper in Zurich.[22] He lived in Zurich for the next two years (1788–1790), where he met his future wife, Johanna Rahn,[19][23] and Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi. He also became, in 1793, a member of the Freemasonry lodge "Modestia cum Libertate", with which Johann Wolfgang Goethe was also connected.[24][25] In the spring of 1790, he became engaged to Johanna.[26] Fichte began to study the works of Kant in the summer of 1790. This occurred initially because one of Fichte's students wanted to know about Kant's writings.[27] They had a lasting effect on his life and thought. However, while Fichte was studying Kantian philosophy, the Rahn family suffered financial reverses. His impending marriage had to be postponed.[19]

Kant Edit

From Zurich, Fichte returned to Leipzig in May 1790.[26] In early 1791, he obtained a tutorship in Warsaw in the house of a Polish nobleman. The situation, however, quickly proved disagreeable and he was released. He then got a chance to see Kant at Königsberg. After a disappointing interview on 4 July of the same year,[28] he shut himself in his lodgings and threw all his energies into the composition of an essay which would attract Kant's attention and interest. This essay, completed in five weeks, was the Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung [sic] (Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation, 1792).[19] In this book, according to Dieter Henrich, Fichte investigated the connections between divine revelation and Kant's critical philosophy. The first edition was published without Kant's or Fichte's knowledge and without Fichte's name or signed preface. It was thus believed by the public to be a new work by Kant.[29]

When Kant cleared the confusion and openly praised the work and author, Fichte's reputation skyrocketed. In a letter to Karl Reinhold, Jens Baggeson wrote that it was "...the most shocking and astonishing news... [since] nobody but Kant could have written this book. This amazing news of a third sun in the philosophical heavens has set me into such confusion".[30] Kant waited seven years to make public statement about the incident; after considerable external pressure he dissociated himself from Fichte. In his statement, he inscribed, "May God protect us from our friends. From our enemies, we can try to protect ourselves."[31]

Jena Edit

In October 1793, Fichte was married in Zurich, where he remained the rest of the year. Stirred by the events and principles of the French Revolution, he wrote and anonymously published two pamphlets which led to him to be seen as a devoted defender of liberty of thought and action and an advocate of political changes. In December of the same year, he received an invitation to fill the position of extraordinary professor of philosophy at the University of Jena.[32] He accepted and began his lectures in May 1794. With extraordinary zeal, he expounded his system of "transcendental idealism". His success was immediate. He excelled as a lecturer due to the earnestness and force of his personality. These lectures were later published under the title The Vocation of the Scholar (Einige Vorlesungen über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten). He gave himself up to intense production, and a succession of works soon appeared.[18][19]

Atheism dispute Edit

Fichte was dismissed from the University of Jena in 1799 for atheism. He had been accused of this in 1798 after publishing the essay "Ueber den Grund unsers Glaubens an eine göttliche Weltregierung" ("On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World-Governance"), written in response to Friedrich Karl Forberg's essay "Development of the Concept of Religion", in his Philosophical Journal. For Fichte, God should be conceived primarily in moral terms: "The living and efficaciously acting moral order is itself God. We require no other God, nor can we grasp any other" ("On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World-Governance"). Fichte's intemperate "Appeal to the Public" ("Appellation an das Publikum", 1799) provoked F. H. Jacobi to publish an open letter in which he equated philosophy in general and Fichte's transcendental philosophy in particular with nihilism.[33]

Berlin Edit

Since all the German states except Prussia had joined in the cry against Fichte, he was forced to go to Berlin. There he associated himself with Friedrich and August Wilhelm Schlegel, Schleiermacher, Schelling, and Tieck.[19] In April 1800, through the introduction of Hungarian writer Ignaz Aurelius Fessler, he was initiated into Freemasonry in the Lodge Pythagoras of the Blazing Star, where he was elected minor warden. At first Fichte was a warm admirer of Fessler, and was disposed to aid him in his proposed Masonic reform. But later he became Fessler's bitter opponent. Their controversy attracted much attention among Freemasons.[34] Fichte presented two lectures on the philosophy of Masonry during the same period as part of his work on the development of various higher degrees for the lodge in Berlin.[35] Johann Karl Christian Fischer, a high official of the Grand Orient, published those lectures in 1802/03 in two volumes under the title Philosophy of Freemasonry: Letters to Konstant (Philosophie der Maurerei. Briefe an Konstant), where "Konstant" referred to a fictitious non-Mason.[35]

In November 1800, Fichte published The Closed Commercial State: A Philosophical Sketch as an Appendix to the Doctrine of Right and an Example of a Future Politics (Der geschlossene Handelsstaat. Ein philosophischer Entwurf als Anhang zur Rechtslehre und Probe einer künftig zu liefernden Politik), a philosophical statement of his property theory, a historical analysis of European economic relations, and a political proposal for reforming them.[36] In 1805, he was appointed to a professorship at the University of Erlangen. The Battle of Jena-Auerstedt in 1806, in which Napoleon defeated the Prussian army, drove him to Königsberg for a time, but he returned to Berlin in 1807 and continued his literary activity.[18][19]

Fichte wrote On Machiavelli, as an Author, and Passages from His Writings in June 1807. ("Über Machiavell, als Schriftsteller, und Stellen aus seinen Schriften" ). Karl Clausewitz wrote a Letter to Fichte (1809) about his book on Machiavelli.

After the collapse of the Holy Roman Empire, when German southern principalities resigned as member states and became part of a French protectorship, Fichte delivered the famous Addresses to the German Nation (Reden an die deutsche Nation, 1807-1808), which attempted to define the German Nation and guided the uprising against Napoleon.[37][38] He became a professor at the new University of Berlin, founded in 1810. By the votes of his colleagues Fichte was unanimously elected its rector in the succeeding year. But, once more, his temperament led to friction, and he resigned in 1812. The campaign against Napoleon began, and the hospitals at Berlin were soon full of patients. Fichte's wife devoted herself to nursing and caught a virulent fever. Just as she was recovering, he became sick with typhus and died in 1814 at the age of 51.[18][19]

His son, Immanuel Hermann Fichte (18 July 1796 – 8 August 1879), also made contributions to philosophy.

Philosophical work Edit

Fichte's critics argued that his mimicry of Kant's difficult style produced works that were barely intelligible.[39] On the other hand, Fichte acknowledged the difficulty, but argued that his works were clear and transparent to those who made the effort to think without preconceptions and prejudices.[citation needed]

Fichte did not endorse Kant's argument for the existence of "things in themselves", the supra-sensible reality beyond direct human perception. Fichte saw the rigorous and systematic separation of "things in themselves" and things "as they appear to us" (phenomena) as an invitation to skepticism. Rather than invite skepticism, Fichte made the radical suggestion that we should throw out the notion of a world-in-itself and accept that consciousness does not have a grounding. In fact, Fichte achieved fame for originating the argument that consciousness is not grounded in anything outside of itself. The phenomenal world as such, arises from consciousness, the activity of the I, and moral awareness.

Central theory Edit

In Foundations of Natural Right (1797), Fichte argued that self-consciousness is a social phenomenon. For Fichte, a necessary condition of every subject's self-awareness is the existence of other rational subjects. These others call or summon (fordern auf) the subject or self out of its unconsciousness and into an awareness of itself as a free individual.[40]

Fichte proceeds from the general principle that the I (das Ich) must posit itself as an individual in order to posit (setzen) itself at all, and that in order to posit itself as an individual, it must recognize itself to a calling or summons (Aufforderung) by other free individual(s) — called to limit its own freedom out of respect for the freedom of the others. The same condition applies to the others in development. Mutual recognition (gegenseitig anerkennen) of rational individuals is a condition necessary for the individual I.[41][42] The argument for intersubjectivity is central to the conception of selfhood developed in the Foundations of the Science of Knowledge[43] (Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, 1794/1795).

According to Fichte, consciousness of the self depends upon resistance or a check by something that is not self, yet is not immediately ascribable to a particular sensory perception. In his later 1796–99 lectures (his Nova methodo), Fichte incorporated this into his revised presentation of the foundations of his system, where the summons takes its place alongside original feeling, which takes the place of the earlier Anstoss (see below) as a limit on the absolute freedom and a condition for the positing of the I.

The I posits this situation for itself. To posit does not mean to 'create' the objects of consciousness. The principle in question simply states that the essence of an I lies in the assertion of self-identity; that is, consciousness presupposes self-consciousness. Such immediate self-identity cannot be understood as a psychological fact, or an act or accident of some previously existing substance or being. It is an action of the I, but one that is identical with the very existence of this same I. In Fichte's technical terminology, the original unity of self-consciousness is an action and the product of the same I, as a "fact and/or act" (Thathandlung; Modern German: Tathandlung), a unity that is presupposed by and contained within every fact and every act of empirical consciousness, although it never appears as such.[citation needed]

The I can posit itself only as limited. It cannot even posit its own limitations, in the sense of producing or creating these limits. The finite I cannot be the ground of its own passivity. Instead, for Fichte, if the I is to posit itself, it must simply discover itself to be limited, a discovery that Fichte characterizes as an "impulse,"[44] "repulse,"[45] or "resistance"[46] (Anstoss; Modern German: Anstoß) to the free practical activity of the I. Such an original limitation of the I is, however, a limit for the I only insofar as the I posits it as a limit. The I does this, according to Fichte's analysis, by positing its own limitation, first, as only a feeling, then as a sensation, next as an intuition of a thing, and finally as a summons of another person.

The Anstoss thus provides the essential impetus that first posits in motion the entire complex train of activities that finally result in our conscious experience both of ourselves and others as empirical individuals and of the world around us. Although Anstoss plays a similar role as the thing in itself does in Kantian philosophy, unlike Kant, Fichte's Anstoss is not something foreign to the I. Instead, it denotes the original encounter of the I with its own finitude. Rather than claim that the not-I (das Nicht-Ich) is the cause or ground of the Anstoss, Fichte argues that not-I is posited by the I in order to explain to itself the Anstoss in order to become conscious of Anstoss. The Wissenschaftslehre demonstrates that Anstoss must occur if self-consciousness is to come about but is unable to explain the actual occurrence of Anstoss. There are limits to what can be expected from an a priori deduction of experience, and this, for Fichte, equally applies to Kant's transcendental philosophy.[citation needed] According to Fichte, transcendental philosophy can explain that the world must have space, time, and causality, but it can never explain why objects have the particular sensible properties they happen to have or why I am this determinate individual rather than another. This is something that the I simply has to discover at the same time that it discovers its own freedom, and indeed, is a condition for the latter.[citation needed]

Dieter Henrich (1966) proposed that Fichte was able to move beyond a "reflective theory of consciousness". According to Fichte, the self must already have some prior acquaintance with itself, independent of the act of reflection ("no object comes to consciousness except under the condition that I am aware of myself, the conscious subject").[47] This idea is what Henrich called Fichte's original insight.[15]

Nationalism Edit

Between December 1807 and March 1808, Fichte gave a series of lectures concerning the "German nation" and its culture and language, projecting the kind of national education he hoped would raise it from the humiliation of its defeat at the hands of the French.[48] Having been a supporter of Revolutionary France, Fichte became disenchanted by 1804 as Napoleon's armies advanced through Europe, occupying German territories, stripping them of their raw materials and subjugating them to foreign rule. He came to believe Germany would be responsible for carrying the virtues of the French Revolution into the future. Disappointed in the French, he turned to the German nation as the instrument of fulfilling it.[49]

These lectures, entitled the Addresses to the German Nation, coincided with a period of reform in the Prussian government under the chancellorship of Baron vom Stein. The Addresses display Fichte's interest during that period in language and culture as vehicles of human spiritual development. Fichte built upon earlier ideas of Johann Gottfried Herder and attempted to unite them with his approach. The aim of the German nation, according to Fichte, was to "found an empire of spirit and reason, and to annihilate completely the crude physical force that rules of the world."[50] Like Herder's German nationalism, Fichte's was cultural, and grounded in aesthetic, literary, and moral principles.[48]

The nationalism propounded by Fichte in the Addresses would be used over a century later by the Nazi Party in Germany, which saw in Fichte a forerunner to its own nationalist ideology. Like Nietzsche, the association of Fichte with the Nazi regime came to color readings of Fichte in the post-war period.[51] This reading of Fichte was often bolstered through reference to an unpublished letter from 1793, Contributions to the Correction of the Public's Judgment concerning the French Revolution, in which Fichte expressed anti-Semitic sentiments, such as arguing against extending civil rights to Jews and calling them a "state within a state" that could "undermine" the German nation.[52]

However, attached to the letter is a footnote in which Fichte provides an impassioned plea for permitting Jews to practice their religion without hindrance. Furthermore, the final act of Fichte's academic career was to resign as rector of the University of Berlin in protest when his colleagues refused to punish the harassment of Jewish students.[53] While recent scholarship has sought to dissociate Fichte's writings on nationalism with their adoption by the Nazi Party, the association continues to blight his legacy,[54] although Fichte, as if to exclude all ground of doubt, clearly and distinctly prohibits,  in his reworked version of The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge (see § Final period in Berlin) genocide and other crimes against humanity:

If you say that it is your conscience's command to exterminate peoples for their sins, [...] we can confidently tell you that you are wrong; for such things can never be commanded against the free and moral force.[55]

Economics Edit

Fichte's 1800 economic treatise The Closed Commercial State had a profound influence on the economic theories of German Romanticism. In it, Fichte argues the need for the strictest, purely guild-like regulation of industry.

The "exemplary rational state" (Vernunftstaat), Fichte argues, should not allow any of its "subjects" to engage in this or that production, failing to pass the preliminary test, not certifying government agents in their professional skills and agility.[56] According to Vladimir Mikhailovich Shulyatikov, "this kind of demand was typical of Mittelstund, the German petty middle class, the class of artisans, hoping by creating artificial barriers to stop the victorious march of big capital and thus save themselves from inevitable death. The same demand was imposed on the state, as is evident from Fichte's treatise, by the German "factory" (Fabrike), more precisely, the manufacture of the early 19th century".[57]

Fichte opposed free trade[58] and unrestrained capitalist industrial growth, stating: "There is an endless war of all against all ... And this war is becoming more fierce, unjust, more dangerous in its consequences, the more the world's population grows, the more acquisitions the trading state makes, the more production and art (industry) develops and, together with thus, the number of circulating goods increases, and with them the needs become more and more diversified."[56]

The only means that could save the modern world, which would destroy evil at the root, is, according to Fichte, to split the "world state" (the global market) into separate self-sufficient bodies. Each such body, each "closed trading state" will be able to regulate its internal economic relations. It will be able to both extract and process everything that is needed to meet the needs of its citizens. It will carry out the ideal organization of production.[57] Fichte argued for government regulation of industrial growth, writing "Only by limitation does a certain industry become the property of the class that deals with it".[56]

Women Edit

Fichte believed that "active citizenship, civic freedom and even property rights should be withheld from women, whose calling was to subject themselves utterly to the authority of their fathers and husbands."[59]

Final period in Berlin Edit

 
Tombs of Johann Gottlieb Fichte and his wife Johanna Marie, Dorotheenstaedtischer Friedhof (cemetery), Berlin

Fichte gave a wide range of public and private lectures in Berlin in the last decade of his life. These form some of his best-known work, and are the basis of a revived German-speaking scholarly interest in his work.[33]

The lectures include two works from 1806. In The Characteristics of the Present Age (Die Grundzüge des gegenwärtigen Zeitalters), Fichte outlines his theory of different historical and cultural epochs. His mystic work The Way Towards the Blessed Life (Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben oder auch die Religionslehre) gave his fullest thoughts on religion. In 1807-1808 he gave a series of speeches in French-occupied Berlin, Addresses to the German Nation.[60]

In 1810, the new University of Berlin was established, designed along ideas put forward by Wilhelm von Humboldt. Fichte was made its rector and also the first Chair of Philosophy. This was in part because of educational themes in the Addresses, and in part because of his earlier work at Jena University.

Fichte lectured on further versions of his Wissenschaftslehre. Of these, he only published a brief work from 1810, The Science of Knowledge in its General Outline (Die Wissenschaftslehre, in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt; also translated as Outline of the Doctrine of Knowledge). His son published some of these thirty years after his death.[citation needed] Most only became public in the last decades of the twentieth century, in his collected works.[61] This included reworked versions of the Doctrine of Science (Wissenschaftslehre, 1810–1813), The Science of Rights (Das System der Rechtslehre, 1812), and The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge (Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre, 1812; 1st ed. 1798).

Bibliography Edit

Selected works in German Edit

Wissenschaftslehre Edit

  • Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre oder der sogenannten Philosophie (1794)
  • Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre (1794/1795)
  • Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo (1796–1799: "Halle Nachschrift," 1796/1797 and "Krause Nachschrift," 1798/1799)
  • Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre (1797/1798)
  • Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre (1801)
  • Die Wissenschaftslehre (1804, 1812, 1813)
  • Die Wissenschaftslehre, in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt (1810)

Other works in German Edit

  • Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung (1792)
  • Beitrag zur Berichtigung der Urteile des Publikums über die französische Revolution (1793)
  • Einige Vorlesungen über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten (1794)
  • Grundlage des Naturrechts (1796)
  • Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre (1798)
  • "Ueber den Grund unsers Glaubens an eine göttliche Weltregierung" (1798)
  • "Appellation an das Publikum über die durch Churf. Sächs. Confiscationsrescript ihm beigemessenen atheistischen Aeußerungen. Eine Schrift, die man zu lesen bittet, ehe man sie confsicirt" (1799)
  • Der geschlossene Handelsstaat. Ein philosophischer Entwurf als Anhang zur Rechtslehre und Probe einer künftig zu liefernden Politik (1800)
  • Die Bestimmung des Menschen (1800)
  • Friedrich Nicolais Leben und sonderbare Meinungen[62] (1801)
  • Philosophie der Maurerei. Briefe an Konstant (1802/03)
  • Die Grundzüge des gegenwärtigen Zeitalters (1806)
  • Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben oder auch die Religionslehre (1806)
  • Reden an die deutsche Nation (1807/1808)
  • Das System der Rechtslehre (1812)

Correspondence Edit

  • Jacobi an Fichte, German Text (1799/1816), with Introduction and Critical Apparatus by Marco Ivaldo and Ariberto Acerbi (Introduction, German Text, Italian Translation, 3 Appendices with Jacobi's and Fichte's complementary Texts, Philological Notes, Commentary, Bibliography, Index): Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici Press, Naples 2011, ISBN 978-88-905957-5-2.

Collected works in German Edit

The new standard edition of Fichte's works in German, which supersedes all previous editions, is the Gesamtausgabe ("Collected Works" or "Complete Edition", commonly abbreviated as GA), prepared by the Bavarian Academy of Sciences: Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, 42 volumes, edited by Reinhard Lauth [de], Hans Gliwitzky, Erich Fuchs and Peter Schneider, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann-Holzboog, 1962–2012.

It is organized into four parts:

  • Part I: Published Works
  • Part II: Unpublished Writings
  • Part III: Correspondence
  • Part IV: Lecture Transcripts

Fichte's works are quoted and cited from GA, followed by a combination of Roman and Arabic numbers, indicating the series and volume, respectively, and the page number(s). Another edition is Johann Gottlieb Fichtes sämmtliche Werke (abbrev. SW), ed. I. H. Fichte. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1971.

Selected works in English Edit

  • Concerning the Conception of the Science of Knowledge Generally (Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre oder der sogenannten Philosophie, 1794), translated by Adolph Ernst Kroeger. In The Science of Knowledge, pp. 331–336. Philadelphia: J.B. Lippincott & Co., 1868. Rpt., London: Trübner & Co., 1889.
  • Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation. Trans. Garrett Green. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978. (Translation of Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung, 1st ed. 1792, 2nd ed. 1793.)
  • Early Philosophical Writings. Trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1988. (Contains Selections from Fichte's Writings and Correspondence from the Jena period, 1794–1799).
  • Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge. Translation of: Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre (1794/95, 2nd ed. 1802), Fichte's first major exposition of the Wissenschaftlehre. In: Heath, Peter; Lachs, John, eds. (1982). The Science of Knowledge. With the First and Second Introductions (reissued; first published by Meredith Corporation 1970). Texts in German Philosophy. Translated by Heath, Peter; Lachs, John. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-27050-2.
  • Foundations of Natural Right. Trans. Michael Baur. Ed. Frederick Neuhouser. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000. (Translation of Grundlage des Naturrechts, 1796/97.)
  • Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy (Wissenschaftslehre) Nova Methodo [FTP]. Trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1992. (Translation of Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo, 1796–1799.)
  • The System of Ethics according to the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre (translation of Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre, 1798). Ed. and trans. Daniel Breazeale and Günter Zöller. Cambridge University Press, 2005.
  • Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings. Trans. and ed. Daniel Breazeale. Indianapolis, and Cambridge: Hackett, 1994. (Contains mostly writings from the late Jena period, 1797–1799.)
  • The Vocation of Man, 1848. Trans. Peter Preuss. Indianapolis. (Translation of Die Bestimmung des Menschen, 1800.)
  • The Vocation of the Scholar, 1847. (Translation of Einige Vorlesungen über die Bestimmung des Gelehrten, 1794.)
  • The Closed Commercial State: J G Fichte (with an interpretive essay by the translator, and with a German-English glossary). SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Translated by Adler, Anthony Curtis. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press. 2013. ISBN 978-1-4384-4021-7.
  • A Crystal Clear Report to the General Public Concerning the Actual Essence of the Newest Philosophy: An Attempt to Force the Reader to Understand. Trans. John Botterman and William Rash. In: Philosophy of German Idealism, pp. 39–115. (Translation of Sonnenklarer Bericht an das grössere Publikum über das Wesen der neuesten Philosophie, 1801.)
  • The Science of Knowing: J.G. Fichte's 1804 Lectures on the Wissenschaftslehre (with an introduction by the translator and a German-English glossary). SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy. Translated by Wright, Walter E. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press. 2005. ISBN 978-0-7914-6449-6.
  • Outline of the Doctrine of Knowledge, 1810 (Translation of Die Wissenschaftslehre, in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt published in From The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte, Trubner and Co., 1889; trans. William Smith.)
  • On the Nature of the Scholar, 1845 (Translation of Ueber das Wesen des Gelehrten, 1806.)
  • Characteristics of the Present Age (Die Grundzüge des gegenwärtigen Zeitalters, 1806). In: The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte, 2 vols., trans. and ed. William Smith. London: Chapman, 1848/49. Reprint, London: Thoemmes Press, 1999.
  • Addresses to the German Nation (Reden an die deutsche Nation, 1808), ed. and trans. Gregory Moore. Cambridge University Press, 2008.
  • The Philosophical Rupture Between Fichte and Schelling: Selected Texts and Correspondence (1800–1802). Trans. and eds. Michael G. Vater and David W. Wood. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 2012. Includes the following texts by Johann Gottlieb Fichte: Correspondence with F.W.J. Schelling (1800–1802); "Announcement" (1800); extract from "New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre" (1800); "Commentaries on Schelling's System of Transcendental Idealism and Presentation of My System of Philosophy" (1800–1801).

Works online in English Edit

  • J.G. Fichte. "The Wissenschaftslehre is Mathematics" ("Announcement", 1800/1801). * [1]
  • Addresses to the German Nation (1922). (Trs. R. F. Jones and G. H. Turnbull.) IA (UToronto)
  • The Destination of Man (1846). Alternative translation of The Vocation of Man. (Tr. Mrs. Percy Sinnett.) IA (UToronto)
  • Doctrine de la science (Paris, 1843). French translation of Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge. Google (Harvard) Google (Oxford) Google (UMich) (in French)
  • Johann Gottlieb Fichte's Popular Works (1873). (Tr. William Smith.) IA (UToronto)
  • New Exposition of the Science of Knowledge (1869). Translation of Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre. (Tr. A. E. Kroeger.) Google (Harvard) Google (NYPL) IA (UToronto)
  • On the Nature of the Scholar (1845). Alternative translation of The Vocation of the Scholar. (Tr. William Smith.) IA (UToronto)
  • The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1848–49). (Tr. William Smith.)
    • Volume 1, 1848. Google (Oxford) IA (UToronto) 4th ed., 1889. IA (UIllinois) IA (UToronto)
    • Volume 2, 1849. IA (UToronto) 4th ed., 1889. Google (Stanford) IA (UIllinois) IA (UToronto)
  • The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge (1897). (Tr. A. E. Kroeger.) Google (UMich) IA (UToronto)
  • The Science of Knowledge (1889). Alternative translation of Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge. (Tr. A. E. Kroeger.) IA (UToronto)
  • The Science of Rights (1889). (Tr. A. E. Kroeger.) IA (UCal)
  • (German) Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung (Königsberg, 1792; 2nd ed. 1793). Gallica Google (Oxford) Google (Oxford)
  • The Vocation of Man (1848). (Tr. William Smith.) Google (Oxford) 1910. Google (UCal)
  • The Vocation of the Scholar (1847). (Tr. William Smith.) IA (UCal)
  • The Way Towards the Blessed Life (1849). (Tr. William Smith.) Google (Oxford)
  • ; alternative translation of "On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World-Governance" (trans. anon. n.d.).

Notes Edit

  1. ^ "Fichte in Berlin to Schelling in Jena, May 31–August 7[8?], 1801," in: Michael Vater and David W. Wood (eds. and trs.), The Philosophical Rupture between Fichte and Schelling: Selected Texts and Correspondence (1800-1802), SUNY Press, 2012, p. 56.
  2. ^ a b "Review of Aenesidemus" ("Rezension des Aenesidemus", Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung, 11–12 February 1794). Trans. Daniel Breazeale. In Breazeale, Daniel; Fichte, Johann (1993). Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Cornell University Press. p. 63. (See also: FTP, p. 46; Breazeale 1980–81, pp. 545–68; Breazeale and Rockmore 1994, p. 19; Breazeale 2013, pp. 36–37; Waibel, Breazeale, Rockmore 2010, p. 157: "Fichte believes that the I must be grasped as the unity of synthesis and analysis.")
  3. ^ Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, 1794/1795, p. 274.
  4. ^ Breazeale 2013, pp. 305 and 308 n. 24.
  5. ^ Gesamtausgabe I/2: 364–65; Daniel Breazeale, "Fichte's Conception of Philosophy as a "Pragmatic History of the Human Mind" and the Contributions of Kant, Platner, and Maimon," Journal of the History of Ideas, 62(4), Oct. 2001, pp. 685–703; Zöller 1998, p. 130 n. 30; Sedgwick 2007, p. 144 n. 33; Breazeale and Rockmore 2010, p. 50 n. 27: "Α »history of the human mind« is a genetic account of the self-constitution of the I in the form of an ordered description of the various acts of thinking that are presupposed by the act of thinking the I"; Posesorski 2012, p. 81: "Pragmatische Geschichte des menschlichen Geistes designates reason's timeless course of production of the different levels of the a priori system of all knowledge, which are exclusively uncovered and portrayed genetically by personal self-conscious reflection"; Breazeale 2013, p. 72.
  6. ^ The principle of reciprocal determination (der Satz der Wechselbestimmbarkeit) is the principle that, according to Fichte (Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo, "Halle Nachschrift," 1796/1797), explicitly guides all philosophical reflection; it is derived from the reciprocally determinable relationship between the finite I and its other. In a similar way, Fichte had derived in his Foundations of the Science of Knowledge (publ. 1794/1795, paras. 1–2) the logical laws of identity and non-contradiction from the original positing and counter-positing of the I. (See Breazeale 2013, pp. 54–5.)
  7. ^ Gesamtausgabe II/3: 24–25; Breazeale 2013, p. 198.
  8. ^ Fichte, J. G., "Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre" ("Second Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre"; 1797); Rocío Zambrana, Hegel's Theory of Intelligibility, University of Chicago Press, 2015, p. 151 n. 15.
  9. ^ FTP, p. 365; Waibel, Breazeale, Rockmore 2010, p. 157; Breazeale 2013, pp. 354 and 404–439.
  10. ^ Cf. KpV A219.
  11. ^ "Fichte". Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary.
  12. ^ "Duden | Johann | Rechtschreibung, Bedeutung, Definition". Duden (in German). Retrieved 20 October 2018. Johann
  13. ^ "Duden | Gottlieb | Rechtschreibung, Bedeutung, Definition". Duden (in German). Retrieved 20 October 2018. Gọttlieb
  14. ^ "Duden | Fichte | Rechtschreibung, Bedeutung, Definition". Duden (in German). Retrieved 20 October 2018. Fịchte
  15. ^ a b Dieter Henrich, "Fichte's Original Insight", Contemporary German Philosophy 1 (1982 [1966]), ed. by Darrel E. Christensen et al., pp. 15–52 (translation of Henrich, Dieter (1966), "Fichtes ursprüngliche Einsicht", in: Subjektivität und Metaphysik. Festschrift für Wolfgang Cramer edited by D. Henrich und H. Wagner, Frankfurt/M., pp. 188–232). Henrich's article is an analysis of the following three presentations of the Wissenschaftslehre: Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre (Foundations of the Science of Knowledge, 1794/1795), Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre (An Attempt a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre, 1797/1798), and Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre (Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre, 1801).
  16. ^ Robert C. Solomon, In the Spirit of Hegel, Oxford University Press, p. 23.
  17. ^ Verkamp, B.J. (2008). Encyclopedia of Philosophers on Religion. McFarland & Company, Incorporated, Publishers. ISBN 978-0-7864-3286-8. Retrieved 2 November 2022.
  18. ^ a b c d e Gilman, D. C.; Peck, H. T.; Colby, F. M., eds. (1905). "Fichte, Johann Gottlieb" . New International Encyclopedia (1st ed.). New York: Dodd, Mead.
  19. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Rines, George Edwin, ed. (1920). "Fichte, Johann Gottlieb" . Encyclopedia Americana.
  20. ^ Wood, Allen W. (21 April 2016). Fichte's Ethical Thought. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-107950-4.
  21. ^ Breazeale, Daniel; Fichte, Johann (1993). Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Cornell University Press. p. 2.
  22. ^ Anthony J. La Vopa, Fichte: The Self and the Calling of Philosophy, 1762-1799, Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 26.
  23. ^ She was the niece of the famous poet F. G. Klopstock.
  24. ^ Imhof, Gottlieb (1959). Kleine Werklehre der Freimaurerei. I. Das Buch des Lehrlings. 5th ed. Lausanne: Alpina, p. 42.
  25. ^ Lawatsch, Hans-Helmut (1991). "Fichte und die hermetische Demokratie der Freimaurer." In: Hammacher, Klaus, Schottky, Richard, Schrader, Wolfgang H. and Daniel Breazeale (eds.). Sozialphilosophie. Fichte-Studien, Vol. 3. Amsterdam-Atlanta: Editions Rodopi, p. 204, ISBN 978-90-5183-236-5.
  26. ^ a b Anthony J. La Vopa, Fichte: The Self and the Calling of Philosophy, 1762-1799, Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 151.
  27. ^ Breazeale, Daniel; Fichte, Johann (1993). Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Cornell University Press. p. 4.
  28. ^ Breazeale, Daniel; Fichte, Johann (1993). Fichte: Early Philosophical Writings. Cornell University Press. p. 7.
  29. ^ It is unknown if the omission was an accident or a deliberate attempt by the publisher to sell copies. In either case, Fichte had not planned it and only heard about it much later. He wrote to his fiancée: "Why did I have to have such utterly strange, excellent, unheard-of good luck?" See Garrett Green's Introduction to Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978.
  30. ^ Letter from Jens Baggeson to Karl Reinhold. Quoted in Editor's Introduction to Fichte, Early Philosophical Writings. London: Cornell University Press, 1988.
  31. ^ Popper, Karl. "The Open Society and Its Enemies." Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994. Vol 2, p. 266.
  32. ^ On the role of Freemasonry in Fichte's call to Jena, see Klaus Hammacher, Fichte und die Freimaurerei', in Fichte-Studien 2/1990, pp. 138-159; Hans-Helmut Lawatsch, Fichte und die hermetische Demokratie der Freimaurei', in Fichte-Studien, 3/1991, pp. 204-218. As quoted in (in Italian) Marco Rampazzo Bazzan, Il prisma "Rousseau". Lo sguardo di Fichte sulla politica tra Staatsrecht e Rivoluzione francese. Franco Angeli Edizioni, 2017, p. 38, ISBN 9788891757531
  33. ^ a b Breazeale, Dan, "Johann Gottlieb Fichte", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed).
  34. ^ Albert G. Mackey, ed. (2003). Fichte as a Freemason: October 1872 to September 1873. p. 430. ISBN 978-0-7661-5717-0. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  35. ^ a b Glenn Alexander Magee, Hegel and the Hermetic Tradition, Cornell University Press, 2008, p. 55.
  36. ^ Isaac Nakhimovsky, The Closed Commercial State: Perpetual Peace and Commercial Society from Rousseau to Fichte, Princeton University Press, 2011, p. 6.
  37. ^ Kurt F. Reinhardt, Germany: 2000 Years (1950; rpt. New York: Frederick Ungar, 1961), I, pp. 322-26. Louis Snyder, Basic History of Modern Germany (Princeton, N.J.: Van Nostrand, 1957), pp. 23-6. (The end of the nominal Holy Roman Empire was an important factor advancing the cause of German nationalists by eliminating the last vestiges of that apparent German union, clearing the way for a German nation to emerge in its place.)
  38. ^ Michael D. McGuire (1976). Rhetoric, philosophy and the volk: Johann Gottlieb Fichte's addresses to the German nation. Quarterly Journal of Speech, 62:2, 135-144.
  39. ^ Robert Blakely, History of the Philosophy of Mind, Vol. IV, p. 114, London: Longmans, 1850
  40. ^ "Foundations of Natural Right". Scribd. Retrieved 18 January 2018.
  41. ^ Fichte, J. G. (2000), Foundations of Natural Right, according to the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre, ed. F. Neuhouser, trans. M. Baur. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 42.
  42. ^ Allen W. Wood, The Free Development of Each: Studies on Reason, Right, and Ethics in Classical German Philosophy, Oxford University Press, 2014, p. 207: "The whole point of the summons, in fact, is that it is what first makes our individuality possible for us, through presenting us with the concept of our own individual free action in the form of an object of our consciousness."
  43. ^ Also translated as Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge.
  44. ^ Breazeale 2013, p. vii.
  45. ^ Nicholas Adams, George Pattison, Graham Ward (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Theology and Modern European Thought, Oxford University Press, 2013, p. 129.
  46. ^ Jeffrey Reid, The Anti-Romantic: Hegel Against Ironic Romanticism, A&C Black, 2014, p. 26.
  47. ^ Fichte, J. G., Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre (1797/1798): II.2; Gesamtausgabe I/4:274–275.
  48. ^ a b Wood, Allen (2016). Fichte's Ethical Thought. Oxford University Press. p. 25.
  49. ^ Anderson, Eugene (1966). Nationalism and the Culture Crisis in Prussia: 1806-1815. Octagon Press. p. 29.
  50. ^ Fichte, Johann Gottlieb (2008). Addresses to the German Nation. Cambridge University Press. p. 496.
  51. ^ Butler, Rohan (1941). The Roots of National Socialism. Faber & Faber. pp. 38–39.
  52. ^ Gesamtausgabe, I/1, pp. 292–93
  53. ^ Wood, Allen (2016). Fichte's Ethical Thought. Oxford University Press. p. 27.
  54. ^ Wood, Allen (2016). Fichte's Ethical Thought. Oxford University Press. p. 26.
  55. ^ Lauth, Reinhard (2003). "8. Moses" (PDF). Abraham und die Kinder seines Bundes mit Gott [Abraham and the children of his Covenant with God] (in German). München: Christian Jerrentrup Verlag. pp. 243–292, here: p. 273. (PDF) from the original on 19 November 2004. Retrieved 14 September 2018. Wenn du sagtest, es sei dir durch dein Gewissen geboten, Völker zur Strafe für ihre Sünden auszurotten, [...] so können wir dir mit Zuversicht sagen, daß du dich täuschest; denn dergleichen kann der freien und sittlichen Kraft nie geboten werden', schrieb Fichte 1812 (SL 1812; Akad.-Ausg. II, 13, S. 368). Heger, Christoph. "Reinhard Lauth" (in German). from the original on 14 September 2018. Retrieved 14 September 2018. ISBN 3-935990-14-6 (paperback), ISBN 3-935990-15-4 (hardback).
  56. ^ a b c Fichte, Johann Gottlieb (1800). The Closed Commercial State. Translated by Blunden, Andy.
  57. ^ a b Shulyatikov, Vladimir Mikhailovich (1908). "Фихте, Шеллинг, Гегель.". Оправдание капитализма в западноевропейской философии. Moscow.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  58. ^ Suesse, Marvin, ed. (2023), "The Birth of the National Economy in Europe, 1789–1860", The Nationalist Dilemma: A Global History of Economic Nationalism, 1776–Present, Cambridge University Press, pp. 44–75, doi:10.1017/9781108917087.003, ISBN 978-1-108-83138-3
  59. ^ Christopher M. Clark, Iron Kingdom: The Rise and Downfall of Prussia, 1600-1947 (Harvard University Press, 2006: ISBN 978-0-674-02385-7), p. 377.
  60. ^ Fichte, J. G., JONES, R. F., & TURNBULL, G. H. (1922). Addresses to the German Nation. Translated by RF Jones... and GH Turnbull. Chicago & London; Edinburgh printed. p. xxii
  61. ^ Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, approx. 40 volumes. Edited by Reinhard Lauth [de], Erich Fuchs, Hans Gliwitzky, Ives Radrizzani, Günter Zöller, et al., Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt 1962.
  62. ^ English translation: Friedrich Nicolai's Life and Strange Opinions.

References Edit

  • Daniel Breazeale. "Fichte's Aenesidemus Review and the Transformation of German Idealism" The Review of Metaphysics, 34 (1980–81): 545–68.
  • Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (eds.). Fichte: Historical Contexts/Contemporary Controversies. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1994.
  • Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore (eds.), Fichte, German Idealism, and Early Romanticism, Rodopi, 2010.
  • Daniel Breazeale. Thinking Through the Wissenschaftslehre: Themes from Fichte's Early Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013.
  • Ezequiel L. Posesorski. Between Reinhold and Fichte: August Ludwig Hülsen's Contribution to the Emergence of German Idealism. Karlsruhe: Karlsruher Institut Für Technologie, 2012.
  • Sally Sedgwick. The Reception of Kant's Critical Philosophy: Fichte, Schelling, and Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007.
  • Violetta L. Waibel, Daniel Breazeale, Tom Rockmore (eds.), Fichte and the Phenomenological Tradition, Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 2010.
  • Günter Zöller. Fichte's Transcendental Philosophy: The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998.

External links Edit

johann, gottlieb, fichte, fichte, redirects, here, other, uses, fichte, disambiguation, german, ˈjoːhan, ˈɡɔtliːp, ˈfɪçtə, 1762, january, 1814, german, philosopher, became, founding, figure, philosophical, movement, known, german, idealism, which, developed, f. Fichte redirects here For other uses see Fichte disambiguation Johann Gottlieb Fichte ˈ f ɪ k t e 11 German ˈjoːhan ˈɡɔtliːp ˈfɪcte 12 13 14 19 May 1762 29 January 1814 was a German philosopher who became a founding figure of the philosophical movement known as German idealism which developed from the theoretical and ethical writings of Immanuel Kant Recently philosophers and scholars have begun to appreciate Fichte as an important philosopher in his own right due to his original insights into the nature of self consciousness or self awareness 15 Fichte was also the originator of thesis antithesis synthesis 2 an idea that is often erroneously attributed to Hegel 16 Like Descartes and Kant before him Fichte was motivated by the problem of subjectivity and consciousness Fichte also wrote works of political philosophy he has a reputation as one of the fathers of German nationalism Johann Gottlieb FichteBorn 1762 05 19 19 May 1762Rammenau Saxony Holy Roman EmpireDied29 January 1814 1814 01 29 aged 51 Berlin Brandenburg Prussia German ConfederationNationalityGermanEducationSchulpfortaUniversity of Jena 1780 no degree Leipzig University 1781 1784 no degree Era18th century philosophySchoolGerman idealismInstitutionsUniversity of JenaUniversity of ErlangenUniversity of BerlinMain interestsSelf consciousness moral philosophy political philosophyNotable ideasList Das absolute Bewusstsein the absolute consciousness 1 Thesis antithesis synthesis 2 Das Nicht Ich the not I Das Streben striving Wissenschaftslehre Doctrine of Science as Real Idealismus Ideal Realismus real idealism ideal realism 3 4 Philosophy as pragmatic history of the human spirit 5 Gegenseitig anerkennen mutual recognition Principle of reciprocal determination 6 Anstoss impulse Tathandlung fact and or act Aufforderung calling summons Philosophical reflection as intellectual intuition 7 The primacy of the practical Handeln 8 9 10 Urtrieb original drive Signature Contents 1 Biography 1 1 Origins 1 2 Early schooling 1 3 Theological studies and private tutoring 1 4 Kant 1 5 Jena 1 6 Atheism dispute 1 7 Berlin 2 Philosophical work 2 1 Central theory 2 2 Nationalism 2 3 Economics 2 4 Women 3 Final period in Berlin 4 Bibliography 4 1 Selected works in German 4 1 1 Wissenschaftslehre 4 1 2 Other works in German 4 1 3 Correspondence 4 2 Collected works in German 4 3 Selected works in English 4 4 Works online in English 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksBiography EditOrigins Edit Fichte was born in Rammenau Upper Lusatia and baptized a Lutheran 17 The son of a ribbon weaver 18 Fichte was born into a pious family that had lived in the region for generations Christian Fichte Johann Gottlieb s father married somewhat above his class It has been suggested that a certain impatience which Fichte himself displayed throughout his life was an inheritance from his mother 19 He received a rudimentary education from his father He showed remarkable ability from an early age and it was owing to his reputation among the villagers that he gained the opportunity for a better education than he otherwise would have received The story runs that the Freiherr von Miltitz a country landowner arrived too late to hear the local pastor preach He was however informed that a lad in the neighborhood would be able to repeat the sermon almost verbatim As a result the baron took Fichte into his protection and paid for his tuition 19 Early schooling Edit Fichte was placed in the family of Pastor Krebel at Niederau near Meissen and there received a thorough grounding in the classics From this time onward Fichte saw little of his parents In October 1774 he attended the celebrated foundation school at Pforta near Naumburg Freiherr von Miltitz continued to support him but died in 1774 The Pforta school is associated with the names of Novalis August Wilhelm Schlegel Friedrich Schlegel and Nietzsche The spirit of the institution was semi monastic and while the education was excellent it is doubtful whether there was enough social life and contact with the world for Fichte 19 Theological studies and private tutoring Edit In 1780 Fichte began study at the University of Jena s Lutheran 20 theology seminary He was transferred a year later to study at the Leipzig University Fichte seems to have supported himself during this period of poverty and struggle 19 Without the financial support by von Miltitz Fichte had to end his studies without completing his degree 21 From 1784 to 1788 Fichte precariously supported himself as tutor for various Saxon families 18 In early 1788 he returned to Leipzig in the hope of finding a better employment but eventually he had to settle for a less promising position with the family of an innkeeper in Zurich 22 He lived in Zurich for the next two years 1788 1790 where he met his future wife Johanna Rahn 19 23 and Johann Heinrich Pestalozzi He also became in 1793 a member of the Freemasonry lodge Modestia cum Libertate with which Johann Wolfgang Goethe was also connected 24 25 In the spring of 1790 he became engaged to Johanna 26 Fichte began to study the works of Kant in the summer of 1790 This occurred initially because one of Fichte s students wanted to know about Kant s writings 27 They had a lasting effect on his life and thought However while Fichte was studying Kantian philosophy the Rahn family suffered financial reverses His impending marriage had to be postponed 19 Kant Edit From Zurich Fichte returned to Leipzig in May 1790 26 In early 1791 he obtained a tutorship in Warsaw in the house of a Polish nobleman The situation however quickly proved disagreeable and he was released He then got a chance to see Kant at Konigsberg After a disappointing interview on 4 July of the same year 28 he shut himself in his lodgings and threw all his energies into the composition of an essay which would attract Kant s attention and interest This essay completed in five weeks was the Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung sic Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation 1792 19 In this book according to Dieter Henrich Fichte investigated the connections between divine revelation and Kant s critical philosophy The first edition was published without Kant s or Fichte s knowledge and without Fichte s name or signed preface It was thus believed by the public to be a new work by Kant 29 When Kant cleared the confusion and openly praised the work and author Fichte s reputation skyrocketed In a letter to Karl Reinhold Jens Baggeson wrote that it was the most shocking and astonishing news since nobody but Kant could have written this book This amazing news of a third sun in the philosophical heavens has set me into such confusion 30 Kant waited seven years to make public statement about the incident after considerable external pressure he dissociated himself from Fichte In his statement he inscribed May God protect us from our friends From our enemies we can try to protect ourselves 31 Jena Edit In October 1793 Fichte was married in Zurich where he remained the rest of the year Stirred by the events and principles of the French Revolution he wrote and anonymously published two pamphlets which led to him to be seen as a devoted defender of liberty of thought and action and an advocate of political changes In December of the same year he received an invitation to fill the position of extraordinary professor of philosophy at the University of Jena 32 He accepted and began his lectures in May 1794 With extraordinary zeal he expounded his system of transcendental idealism His success was immediate He excelled as a lecturer due to the earnestness and force of his personality These lectures were later published under the title The Vocation of the Scholar Einige Vorlesungen uber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten He gave himself up to intense production and a succession of works soon appeared 18 19 Atheism dispute Edit Main article Atheism dispute Fichte was dismissed from the University of Jena in 1799 for atheism He had been accused of this in 1798 after publishing the essay Ueber den Grund unsers Glaubens an eine gottliche Weltregierung On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World Governance written in response to Friedrich Karl Forberg s essay Development of the Concept of Religion in his Philosophical Journal For Fichte God should be conceived primarily in moral terms The living and efficaciously acting moral order is itself God We require no other God nor can we grasp any other On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World Governance Fichte s intemperate Appeal to the Public Appellation an das Publikum 1799 provoked F H Jacobi to publish an open letter in which he equated philosophy in general and Fichte s transcendental philosophy in particular with nihilism 33 Berlin Edit Since all the German states except Prussia had joined in the cry against Fichte he was forced to go to Berlin There he associated himself with Friedrich and August Wilhelm Schlegel Schleiermacher Schelling and Tieck 19 In April 1800 through the introduction of Hungarian writer Ignaz Aurelius Fessler he was initiated into Freemasonry in the Lodge Pythagoras of the Blazing Star where he was elected minor warden At first Fichte was a warm admirer of Fessler and was disposed to aid him in his proposed Masonic reform But later he became Fessler s bitter opponent Their controversy attracted much attention among Freemasons 34 Fichte presented two lectures on the philosophy of Masonry during the same period as part of his work on the development of various higher degrees for the lodge in Berlin 35 Johann Karl Christian Fischer a high official of the Grand Orient published those lectures in 1802 03 in two volumes under the title Philosophy of Freemasonry Letters to Konstant Philosophie der Maurerei Briefe an Konstant where Konstant referred to a fictitious non Mason 35 In November 1800 Fichte published The Closed Commercial State A Philosophical Sketch as an Appendix to the Doctrine of Right and an Example of a Future Politics Der geschlossene Handelsstaat Ein philosophischer Entwurf als Anhang zur Rechtslehre und Probe einer kunftig zu liefernden Politik a philosophical statement of his property theory a historical analysis of European economic relations and a political proposal for reforming them 36 In 1805 he was appointed to a professorship at the University of Erlangen The Battle of Jena Auerstedt in 1806 in which Napoleon defeated the Prussian army drove him to Konigsberg for a time but he returned to Berlin in 1807 and continued his literary activity 18 19 Fichte wrote On Machiavelli as an Author and Passages from His Writings in June 1807 Uber Machiavell als Schriftsteller und Stellen aus seinen Schriften Karl Clausewitz wrote a Letter to Fichte 1809 about his book on Machiavelli After the collapse of the Holy Roman Empire when German southern principalities resigned as member states and became part of a French protectorship Fichte delivered the famous Addresses to the German Nation Reden an die deutsche Nation 1807 1808 which attempted to define the German Nation and guided the uprising against Napoleon 37 38 He became a professor at the new University of Berlin founded in 1810 By the votes of his colleagues Fichte was unanimously elected its rector in the succeeding year But once more his temperament led to friction and he resigned in 1812 The campaign against Napoleon began and the hospitals at Berlin were soon full of patients Fichte s wife devoted herself to nursing and caught a virulent fever Just as she was recovering he became sick with typhus and died in 1814 at the age of 51 18 19 His son Immanuel Hermann Fichte 18 July 1796 8 August 1879 also made contributions to philosophy Philosophical work EditFichte s critics argued that his mimicry of Kant s difficult style produced works that were barely intelligible 39 On the other hand Fichte acknowledged the difficulty but argued that his works were clear and transparent to those who made the effort to think without preconceptions and prejudices citation needed Fichte did not endorse Kant s argument for the existence of things in themselves the supra sensible reality beyond direct human perception Fichte saw the rigorous and systematic separation of things in themselves and things as they appear to us phenomena as an invitation to skepticism Rather than invite skepticism Fichte made the radical suggestion that we should throw out the notion of a world in itself and accept that consciousness does not have a grounding In fact Fichte achieved fame for originating the argument that consciousness is not grounded in anything outside of itself The phenomenal world as such arises from consciousness the activity of the I and moral awareness Central theory Edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Johann Gottlieb Fichte news newspapers books scholar JSTOR May 2017 Learn how and when to remove this template message In Foundations of Natural Right 1797 Fichte argued that self consciousness is a social phenomenon For Fichte a necessary condition of every subject s self awareness is the existence of other rational subjects These others call or summon fordern auf the subject or self out of its unconsciousness and into an awareness of itself as a free individual 40 Fichte proceeds from the general principle that the I das Ich must posit itself as an individual in order to posit setzen itself at all and that in order to posit itself as an individual it must recognize itself to a calling or summons Aufforderung by other free individual s called to limit its own freedom out of respect for the freedom of the others The same condition applies to the others in development Mutual recognition gegenseitig anerkennen of rational individuals is a condition necessary for the individual I 41 42 The argument for intersubjectivity is central to the conception of selfhood developed in the Foundations of the Science of Knowledge 43 Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre 1794 1795 According to Fichte consciousness of the self depends upon resistance or a check by something that is not self yet is not immediately ascribable to a particular sensory perception In his later 1796 99 lectures his Nova methodo Fichte incorporated this into his revised presentation of the foundations of his system where the summons takes its place alongside original feeling which takes the place of the earlier Anstoss see below as a limit on the absolute freedom and a condition for the positing of the I The I posits this situation for itself To posit does not mean to create the objects of consciousness The principle in question simply states that the essence of an I lies in the assertion of self identity that is consciousness presupposes self consciousness Such immediate self identity cannot be understood as a psychological fact or an act or accident of some previously existing substance or being It is an action of the I but one that is identical with the very existence of this same I In Fichte s technical terminology the original unity of self consciousness is an action and the product of the same I as a fact and or act Thathandlung Modern German Tathandlung a unity that is presupposed by and contained within every fact and every act of empirical consciousness although it never appears as such citation needed The I can posit itself only as limited It cannot even posit its own limitations in the sense of producing or creating these limits The finite I cannot be the ground of its own passivity Instead for Fichte if the I is to posit itself it must simply discover itself to be limited a discovery that Fichte characterizes as an impulse 44 repulse 45 or resistance 46 Anstoss Modern German Anstoss to the free practical activity of the I Such an original limitation of the I is however a limit for the I only insofar as the I posits it as a limit The I does this according to Fichte s analysis by positing its own limitation first as only a feeling then as a sensation next as an intuition of a thing and finally as a summons of another person The Anstoss thus provides the essential impetus that first posits in motion the entire complex train of activities that finally result in our conscious experience both of ourselves and others as empirical individuals and of the world around us Although Anstoss plays a similar role as the thing in itself does in Kantian philosophy unlike Kant Fichte s Anstoss is not something foreign to the I Instead it denotes the original encounter of the I with its own finitude Rather than claim that the not I das Nicht Ich is the cause or ground of the Anstoss Fichte argues that not I is posited by the I in order to explain to itself the Anstoss in order to become conscious of Anstoss The Wissenschaftslehre demonstrates that Anstoss must occur if self consciousness is to come about but is unable to explain the actual occurrence of Anstoss There are limits to what can be expected from an a priori deduction of experience and this for Fichte equally applies to Kant s transcendental philosophy citation needed According to Fichte transcendental philosophy can explain that the world must have space time and causality but it can never explain why objects have the particular sensible properties they happen to have or why I am this determinate individual rather than another This is something that the I simply has to discover at the same time that it discovers its own freedom and indeed is a condition for the latter citation needed Dieter Henrich 1966 proposed that Fichte was able to move beyond a reflective theory of consciousness According to Fichte the self must already have some prior acquaintance with itself independent of the act of reflection no object comes to consciousness except under the condition that I am aware of myself the conscious subject 47 This idea is what Henrich called Fichte s original insight 15 Nationalism Edit This section possibly contains synthesis of material which does not verifiably mention or relate to the main topic Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page March 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Between December 1807 and March 1808 Fichte gave a series of lectures concerning the German nation and its culture and language projecting the kind of national education he hoped would raise it from the humiliation of its defeat at the hands of the French 48 Having been a supporter of Revolutionary France Fichte became disenchanted by 1804 as Napoleon s armies advanced through Europe occupying German territories stripping them of their raw materials and subjugating them to foreign rule He came to believe Germany would be responsible for carrying the virtues of the French Revolution into the future Disappointed in the French he turned to the German nation as the instrument of fulfilling it 49 These lectures entitled the Addresses to the German Nation coincided with a period of reform in the Prussian government under the chancellorship of Baron vom Stein The Addresses display Fichte s interest during that period in language and culture as vehicles of human spiritual development Fichte built upon earlier ideas of Johann Gottfried Herder and attempted to unite them with his approach The aim of the German nation according to Fichte was to found an empire of spirit and reason and to annihilate completely the crude physical force that rules of the world 50 Like Herder s German nationalism Fichte s was cultural and grounded in aesthetic literary and moral principles 48 The nationalism propounded by Fichte in the Addresses would be used over a century later by the Nazi Party in Germany which saw in Fichte a forerunner to its own nationalist ideology Like Nietzsche the association of Fichte with the Nazi regime came to color readings of Fichte in the post war period 51 This reading of Fichte was often bolstered through reference to an unpublished letter from 1793 Contributions to the Correction of the Public s Judgment concerning the French Revolution in which Fichte expressed anti Semitic sentiments such as arguing against extending civil rights to Jews and calling them a state within a state that could undermine the German nation 52 However attached to the letter is a footnote in which Fichte provides an impassioned plea for permitting Jews to practice their religion without hindrance Furthermore the final act of Fichte s academic career was to resign as rector of the University of Berlin in protest when his colleagues refused to punish the harassment of Jewish students 53 While recent scholarship has sought to dissociate Fichte s writings on nationalism with their adoption by the Nazi Party the association continues to blight his legacy 54 although Fichte as if to exclude all ground of doubt clearly and distinctly prohibits in his reworked version of The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge see Final period in Berlin genocide and other crimes against humanity If you say that it is your conscience s command to exterminate peoples for their sins we can confidently tell you that you are wrong for such things can never be commanded against the free and moral force 55 Economics Edit Fichte s 1800 economic treatise The Closed Commercial State had a profound influence on the economic theories of German Romanticism In it Fichte argues the need for the strictest purely guild like regulation of industry The exemplary rational state Vernunftstaat Fichte argues should not allow any of its subjects to engage in this or that production failing to pass the preliminary test not certifying government agents in their professional skills and agility 56 According to Vladimir Mikhailovich Shulyatikov this kind of demand was typical of Mittelstund the German petty middle class the class of artisans hoping by creating artificial barriers to stop the victorious march of big capital and thus save themselves from inevitable death The same demand was imposed on the state as is evident from Fichte s treatise by the German factory Fabrike more precisely the manufacture of the early 19th century 57 Fichte opposed free trade 58 and unrestrained capitalist industrial growth stating There is an endless war of all against all And this war is becoming more fierce unjust more dangerous in its consequences the more the world s population grows the more acquisitions the trading state makes the more production and art industry develops and together with thus the number of circulating goods increases and with them the needs become more and more diversified 56 The only means that could save the modern world which would destroy evil at the root is according to Fichte to split the world state the global market into separate self sufficient bodies Each such body each closed trading state will be able to regulate its internal economic relations It will be able to both extract and process everything that is needed to meet the needs of its citizens It will carry out the ideal organization of production 57 Fichte argued for government regulation of industrial growth writing Only by limitation does a certain industry become the property of the class that deals with it 56 Women Edit Fichte believed that active citizenship civic freedom and even property rights should be withheld from women whose calling was to subject themselves utterly to the authority of their fathers and husbands 59 Final period in Berlin EditThis section relies largely or entirely on a single source Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page Please help improve this article by introducing citations to additional sources Find sources Johann Gottlieb Fichte news newspapers books scholar JSTOR January 2019 nbsp Tombs of Johann Gottlieb Fichte and his wife Johanna Marie Dorotheenstaedtischer Friedhof cemetery BerlinFichte gave a wide range of public and private lectures in Berlin in the last decade of his life These form some of his best known work and are the basis of a revived German speaking scholarly interest in his work 33 The lectures include two works from 1806 In The Characteristics of the Present Age Die Grundzuge des gegenwartigen Zeitalters Fichte outlines his theory of different historical and cultural epochs His mystic work The Way Towards the Blessed Life Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben oder auch die Religionslehre gave his fullest thoughts on religion In 1807 1808 he gave a series of speeches in French occupied Berlin Addresses to the German Nation 60 In 1810 the new University of Berlin was established designed along ideas put forward by Wilhelm von Humboldt Fichte was made its rector and also the first Chair of Philosophy This was in part because of educational themes in the Addresses and in part because of his earlier work at Jena University Fichte lectured on further versions of his Wissenschaftslehre Of these he only published a brief work from 1810 The Science of Knowledge in its General Outline Die Wissenschaftslehre in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt also translated as Outline of the Doctrine of Knowledge His son published some of these thirty years after his death citation needed Most only became public in the last decades of the twentieth century in his collected works 61 This included reworked versions of the Doctrine of Science Wissenschaftslehre 1810 1813 The Science of Rights Das System der Rechtslehre 1812 and The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre 1812 1st ed 1798 Bibliography EditSelected works in German Edit Wissenschaftslehre Edit Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre oder der sogenannten Philosophie 1794 Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre 1794 1795 Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo 1796 1799 Halle Nachschrift 1796 1797 and Krause Nachschrift 1798 1799 Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre 1797 1798 Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre 1801 Die Wissenschaftslehre 1804 1812 1813 Die Wissenschaftslehre in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt 1810 Other works in German Edit Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung 1792 Beitrag zur Berichtigung der Urteile des Publikums uber die franzosische Revolution 1793 Einige Vorlesungen uber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten 1794 Grundlage des Naturrechts 1796 Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre 1798 Ueber den Grund unsers Glaubens an eine gottliche Weltregierung 1798 Appellation an das Publikum uber die durch Churf Sachs Confiscationsrescript ihm beigemessenen atheistischen Aeusserungen Eine Schrift die man zu lesen bittet ehe man sie confsicirt 1799 Der geschlossene Handelsstaat Ein philosophischer Entwurf als Anhang zur Rechtslehre und Probe einer kunftig zu liefernden Politik 1800 Die Bestimmung des Menschen 1800 Friedrich Nicolais Leben und sonderbare Meinungen 62 1801 Philosophie der Maurerei Briefe an Konstant 1802 03 Die Grundzuge des gegenwartigen Zeitalters 1806 Die Anweisung zum seligen Leben oder auch die Religionslehre 1806 Reden an die deutsche Nation 1807 1808 Das System der Rechtslehre 1812 Correspondence Edit Jacobi an Fichte German Text 1799 1816 with Introduction and Critical Apparatus by Marco Ivaldo and Ariberto Acerbi Introduction German Text Italian Translation 3 Appendices with Jacobi s and Fichte s complementary Texts Philological Notes Commentary Bibliography Index Istituto Italiano per gli Studi Filosofici Press Naples 2011 ISBN 978 88 905957 5 2 Collected works in German Edit The new standard edition of Fichte s works in German which supersedes all previous editions is the Gesamtausgabe Collected Works or Complete Edition commonly abbreviated as GA prepared by the Bavarian Academy of Sciences Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften 42 volumes edited by Reinhard Lauth de Hans Gliwitzky Erich Fuchs and Peter Schneider Stuttgart Bad Cannstatt Frommann Holzboog 1962 2012 It is organized into four parts Part I Published Works Part II Unpublished Writings Part III Correspondence Part IV Lecture TranscriptsFichte s works are quoted and cited from GA followed by a combination of Roman and Arabic numbers indicating the series and volume respectively and the page number s Another edition is Johann Gottlieb Fichtes sammtliche Werke abbrev SW ed I H Fichte Berlin de Gruyter 1971 Selected works in English Edit Concerning the Conception of the Science of Knowledge Generally Ueber den Begriff der Wissenschaftslehre oder der sogenannten Philosophie 1794 translated by Adolph Ernst Kroeger In The Science of Knowledge pp 331 336 Philadelphia J B Lippincott amp Co 1868 Rpt London Trubner amp Co 1889 Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation Trans Garrett Green New York Cambridge University Press 1978 Translation of Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung 1st ed 1792 2nd ed 1793 Early Philosophical Writings Trans and ed Daniel Breazeale Ithaca Cornell University Press 1988 Contains Selections from Fichte s Writings and Correspondence from the Jena period 1794 1799 Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge Translation of Grundlage der gesammten Wissenschaftslehre 1794 95 2nd ed 1802 Fichte s first major exposition of the Wissenschaftlehre In Heath Peter Lachs John eds 1982 The Science of Knowledge With the First and Second Introductions reissued first published by Meredith Corporation 1970 Texts in German Philosophy Translated by Heath Peter Lachs John Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 27050 2 Foundations of Natural Right Trans Michael Baur Ed Frederick Neuhouser Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2000 Translation of Grundlage des Naturrechts 1796 97 Foundations of Transcendental Philosophy Wissenschaftslehre Nova Methodo FTP Trans and ed Daniel Breazeale Ithaca NY Cornell University Press 1992 Translation of Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo 1796 1799 The System of Ethics according to the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre translation of Das System der Sittenlehre nach den Principien der Wissenschaftslehre 1798 Ed and trans Daniel Breazeale and Gunter Zoller Cambridge University Press 2005 Introductions to the Wissenschaftslehre and Other Writings Trans and ed Daniel Breazeale Indianapolis and Cambridge Hackett 1994 Contains mostly writings from the late Jena period 1797 1799 The Vocation of Man 1848 Trans Peter Preuss Indianapolis Translation of Die Bestimmung des Menschen 1800 The Vocation of the Scholar 1847 Translation of Einige Vorlesungen uber die Bestimmung des Gelehrten 1794 The Closed Commercial State J G Fichte with an interpretive essay by the translator and with a German English glossary SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy Translated by Adler Anthony Curtis Albany New York State University of New York Press 2013 ISBN 978 1 4384 4021 7 A Crystal Clear Report to the General Public Concerning the Actual Essence of the Newest Philosophy An Attempt to Force the Reader to Understand Trans John Botterman and William Rash In Philosophy of German Idealism pp 39 115 Translation of Sonnenklarer Bericht an das grossere Publikum uber das Wesen der neuesten Philosophie 1801 The Science of Knowing J G Fichte s 1804 Lectures on the Wissenschaftslehre with an introduction by the translator and a German English glossary SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy Translated by Wright Walter E Albany New York State University of New York Press 2005 ISBN 978 0 7914 6449 6 Outline of the Doctrine of Knowledge 1810 Translation of Die Wissenschaftslehre in ihrem allgemeinen Umrisse dargestellt published in From The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte Trubner and Co 1889 trans William Smith On the Nature of the Scholar 1845 Translation of Ueber das Wesen des Gelehrten 1806 Characteristics of the Present Age Die Grundzuge des gegenwartigen Zeitalters 1806 In The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte 2 vols trans and ed William Smith London Chapman 1848 49 Reprint London Thoemmes Press 1999 Addresses to the German Nation Reden an die deutsche Nation 1808 ed and trans Gregory Moore Cambridge University Press 2008 The Philosophical Rupture Between Fichte and Schelling Selected Texts and Correspondence 1800 1802 Trans and eds Michael G Vater and David W Wood Albany NY State University of New York Press 2012 Includes the following texts by Johann Gottlieb Fichte Correspondence with F W J Schelling 1800 1802 Announcement 1800 extract from New Version of the Wissenschaftslehre 1800 Commentaries on Schelling s System of Transcendental Idealism and Presentation of My System of Philosophy 1800 1801 Works online in English Edit J G Fichte The Wissenschaftslehre is Mathematics Announcement 1800 1801 1 Addresses to the German Nation 1922 Trs R F Jones and G H Turnbull IA UToronto The Destination of Man 1846 Alternative translation of The Vocation of Man Tr Mrs Percy Sinnett IA UToronto Doctrine de la science Paris 1843 French translation of Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge Google Harvard Google Oxford Google UMich in French Johann Gottlieb Fichte s Popular Works 1873 Tr William Smith IA UToronto New Exposition of the Science of Knowledge 1869 Translation of Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre Tr A E Kroeger Google Harvard Google NYPL IA UToronto On the Nature of the Scholar 1845 Alternative translation of The Vocation of the Scholar Tr William Smith IA UToronto The Popular Works of Johann Gottlieb Fichte 1848 49 Tr William Smith Volume 1 1848 Google Oxford IA UToronto 4th ed 1889 IA UIllinois IA UToronto Volume 2 1849 IA UToronto 4th ed 1889 Google Stanford IA UIllinois IA UToronto The Science of Ethics as Based on the Science of Knowledge 1897 Tr A E Kroeger Google UMich IA UToronto The Science of Knowledge 1889 Alternative translation of Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge Tr A E Kroeger IA UToronto The Science of Rights 1889 Tr A E Kroeger IA UCal German Versuch einer Critik aller Offenbarung Konigsberg 1792 2nd ed 1793 Gallica Google Oxford Google Oxford The Vocation of Man 1848 Tr William Smith Google Oxford 1910 Google UCal The Vocation of the Scholar 1847 Tr William Smith IA UCal The Way Towards the Blessed Life 1849 Tr William Smith Google Oxford On the Foundation of Our Belief in a Divine Government of the Universe alternative translation of On the Ground of Our Belief in a Divine World Governance trans anon n d Notes Edit Fichte in Berlin to Schelling in Jena May 31 August 7 8 1801 in Michael Vater and David W Wood eds and trs The Philosophical Rupture between Fichte and Schelling Selected Texts and Correspondence 1800 1802 SUNY Press 2012 p 56 a b Review of Aenesidemus Rezension des Aenesidemus Allgemeine Literatur Zeitung 11 12 February 1794 Trans Daniel Breazeale In Breazeale Daniel Fichte Johann 1993 Fichte Early Philosophical Writings Cornell University Press p 63 See also FTP p 46 Breazeale 1980 81 pp 545 68 Breazeale and Rockmore 1994 p 19 Breazeale 2013 pp 36 37 Waibel Breazeale Rockmore 2010 p 157 Fichte believes that the I must be grasped as the unity of synthesis and analysis Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre 1794 1795 p 274 Breazeale 2013 pp 305 and 308 n 24 Gesamtausgabe I 2 364 65 Daniel Breazeale Fichte s Conception of Philosophy as a Pragmatic History of the Human Mind and the Contributions of Kant Platner and Maimon Journal of the History of Ideas 62 4 Oct 2001 pp 685 703 Zoller 1998 p 130 n 30 Sedgwick 2007 p 144 n 33 Breazeale and Rockmore 2010 p 50 n 27 A history of the human mind is a genetic account of the self constitution of the I in the form of an ordered description of the various acts of thinking that are presupposed by the act of thinking the I Posesorski 2012 p 81 Pragmatische Geschichte des menschlichen Geistes designates reason s timeless course of production of the different levels of the a priori system of all knowledge which are exclusively uncovered and portrayed genetically by personal self conscious reflection Breazeale 2013 p 72 The principle of reciprocal determination der Satz der Wechselbestimmbarkeit is the principle that according to Fichte Wissenschaftslehre nova methodo Halle Nachschrift 1796 1797 explicitly guides all philosophical reflection it is derived from the reciprocally determinable relationship between the finite I and its other In a similar way Fichte had derived in his Foundations of the Science of Knowledge publ 1794 1795 paras 1 2 the logical laws of identity and non contradiction from the original positing and counter positing of the I See Breazeale 2013 pp 54 5 Gesamtausgabe II 3 24 25 Breazeale 2013 p 198 Fichte J G Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre Second Introduction to the Wissenschaftslehre 1797 Rocio Zambrana Hegel s Theory of Intelligibility University of Chicago Press 2015 p 151 n 15 FTP p 365 Waibel Breazeale Rockmore 2010 p 157 Breazeale 2013 pp 354 and 404 439 Cf KpV A219 Fichte Random House Webster s Unabridged Dictionary Duden Johann Rechtschreibung Bedeutung Definition Duden in German Retrieved 20 October 2018 Johann Duden Gottlieb Rechtschreibung Bedeutung Definition Duden in German Retrieved 20 October 2018 Gọttlieb Duden Fichte Rechtschreibung Bedeutung Definition Duden in German Retrieved 20 October 2018 Fịchte a b Dieter Henrich Fichte s Original Insight Contemporary German Philosophy 1 1982 1966 ed by Darrel E Christensen et al pp 15 52 translation of Henrich Dieter 1966 Fichtes ursprungliche Einsicht in Subjektivitat und Metaphysik Festschrift fur Wolfgang Cramer edited by D Henrich und H Wagner Frankfurt M pp 188 232 Henrich s article is an analysis of the following three presentations of the Wissenschaftslehre Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre Foundations of the Science of Knowledge 1794 1795 Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre An Attempt a New Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre 1797 1798 and Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre Presentation of the Wissenschaftslehre 1801 Robert C Solomon In the Spirit of Hegel Oxford University Press p 23 Verkamp B J 2008 Encyclopedia of Philosophers on Religion McFarland amp Company Incorporated Publishers ISBN 978 0 7864 3286 8 Retrieved 2 November 2022 a b c d e Gilman D C Peck H T Colby F M eds 1905 Fichte Johann Gottlieb New International Encyclopedia 1st ed New York Dodd Mead a b c d e f g h i j k Rines George Edwin ed 1920 Fichte Johann Gottlieb Encyclopedia Americana Wood Allen W 21 April 2016 Fichte s Ethical Thought Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 107950 4 Breazeale Daniel Fichte Johann 1993 Fichte Early Philosophical Writings Cornell University Press p 2 Anthony J La Vopa Fichte The Self and the Calling of Philosophy 1762 1799 Cambridge University Press 2001 p 26 She was the niece of the famous poet F G Klopstock Imhof Gottlieb 1959 Kleine Werklehre der Freimaurerei I Das Buch des Lehrlings 5th ed Lausanne Alpina p 42 Lawatsch Hans Helmut 1991 Fichte und die hermetische Demokratie der Freimaurer In Hammacher Klaus Schottky Richard Schrader Wolfgang H and Daniel Breazeale eds Sozialphilosophie Fichte Studien Vol 3 Amsterdam Atlanta Editions Rodopi p 204 ISBN 978 90 5183 236 5 a b Anthony J La Vopa Fichte The Self and the Calling of Philosophy 1762 1799 Cambridge University Press 2001 p 151 Breazeale Daniel Fichte Johann 1993 Fichte Early Philosophical Writings Cornell University Press p 4 Breazeale Daniel Fichte Johann 1993 Fichte Early Philosophical Writings Cornell University Press p 7 It is unknown if the omission was an accident or a deliberate attempt by the publisher to sell copies In either case Fichte had not planned it and only heard about it much later He wrote to his fiancee Why did I have to have such utterly strange excellent unheard of good luck See Garrett Green s Introduction to Attempt at a Critique of All Revelation Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1978 Letter from Jens Baggeson to Karl Reinhold Quoted in Editor s Introduction to Fichte Early Philosophical Writings London Cornell University Press 1988 Popper Karl The Open Society and Its Enemies Princeton Princeton University Press 1994 Vol 2 p 266 On the role of Freemasonry in Fichte s call to Jena see Klaus Hammacher Fichte und die Freimaurerei inFichte Studien2 1990 pp 138 159 Hans Helmut Lawatsch Fichte und die hermetische Demokratie der Freimaurei in Fichte Studien 3 1991 pp 204 218 As quoted in in Italian Marco Rampazzo Bazzan Il prisma Rousseau Lo sguardo di Fichte sulla politica tra Staatsrecht e Rivoluzione francese Franco Angeli Edizioni 2017 p 38 ISBN 9788891757531 a b Breazeale Dan Johann Gottlieb Fichte The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2012 Edition Edward N Zalta ed Albert G Mackey ed 2003 Fichte as a Freemason October 1872 to September 1873 p 430 ISBN 978 0 7661 5717 0 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help a b Glenn Alexander Magee Hegel and the Hermetic Tradition Cornell University Press 2008 p 55 Isaac Nakhimovsky The Closed Commercial State Perpetual Peace and Commercial Society from Rousseau to Fichte Princeton University Press 2011 p 6 Kurt F Reinhardt Germany 2000 Years 1950 rpt New York Frederick Ungar 1961 I pp 322 26 Louis Snyder Basic History of Modern Germany Princeton N J Van Nostrand 1957 pp 23 6 The end of the nominal Holy Roman Empire was an important factor advancing the cause of German nationalists by eliminating the last vestiges of that apparent German union clearing the way for a German nation to emerge in its place Michael D McGuire 1976 Rhetoric philosophy and the volk Johann Gottlieb Fichte s addresses to the German nation Quarterly Journal of Speech 62 2 135 144 Robert Blakely History of the Philosophy of Mind Vol IV p 114 London Longmans 1850 Foundations of Natural Right Scribd Retrieved 18 January 2018 Fichte J G 2000 Foundations of Natural Right according to the Principles of the Wissenschaftslehre ed F Neuhouser trans M Baur Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 42 Allen W Wood The Free Development of Each Studies on Reason Right and Ethics in Classical German Philosophy Oxford University Press 2014 p 207 The whole point of the summons in fact is that it is what first makes our individuality possible for us through presenting us with the concept of our own individual free action in the form of an object of our consciousness Also translated as Foundations of the Entire Science of Knowledge Breazeale 2013 p vii Nicholas Adams George Pattison Graham Ward eds The Oxford Handbook of Theology and Modern European Thought Oxford University Press 2013 p 129 Jeffrey Reid The Anti Romantic Hegel Against Ironic Romanticism A amp C Black 2014 p 26 Fichte J G Versuch einer neuen Darstellung der Wissenschaftslehre 1797 1798 II 2 Gesamtausgabe I 4 274 275 a b Wood Allen 2016 Fichte s Ethical Thought Oxford University Press p 25 Anderson Eugene 1966 Nationalism and the Culture Crisis in Prussia 1806 1815 Octagon Press p 29 Fichte Johann Gottlieb 2008 Addresses to the German Nation Cambridge University Press p 496 Butler Rohan 1941 The Roots of National Socialism Faber amp Faber pp 38 39 Gesamtausgabe I 1 pp 292 93 Wood Allen 2016 Fichte s Ethical Thought Oxford University Press p 27 Wood Allen 2016 Fichte s Ethical Thought Oxford University Press p 26 Lauth Reinhard 2003 8 Moses PDF Abraham und die Kinder seines Bundes mit Gott Abraham and the children of his Covenant with God in German Munchen Christian Jerrentrup Verlag pp 243 292 here p 273 Archived PDF from the original on 19 November 2004 Retrieved 14 September 2018 Wenn du sagtest es sei dir durch dein Gewissen geboten Volker zur Strafe fur ihre Sunden auszurotten so konnen wir dir mit Zuversicht sagen dass du dich tauschest denn dergleichen kann der freien und sittlichen Kraft nie geboten werden schrieb Fichte 1812 SL 1812 Akad Ausg II 13 S 368 Heger Christoph Reinhard Lauth in German Archived from the original on 14 September 2018 Retrieved 14 September 2018 ISBN 3 935990 14 6 paperback ISBN 3 935990 15 4 hardback a b c Fichte Johann Gottlieb 1800 The Closed Commercial State Translated by Blunden Andy a b Shulyatikov Vladimir Mikhailovich 1908 Fihte Shelling Gegel Opravdanie kapitalizma v zapadnoevropejskoj filosofii Moscow a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Suesse Marvin ed 2023 The Birth of the National Economy in Europe 1789 1860 The Nationalist Dilemma A Global History of Economic Nationalism 1776 Present Cambridge University Press pp 44 75 doi 10 1017 9781108917087 003 ISBN 978 1 108 83138 3 Christopher M Clark Iron Kingdom The Rise and Downfall of Prussia 1600 1947 Harvard University Press 2006 ISBN 978 0 674 02385 7 p 377 Fichte J G JONES R F amp TURNBULL G H 1922 Addresses to the German Nation Translated by RF Jones and GH Turnbull Chicago amp London Edinburgh printed p xxii Gesamtausgabe der Bayerischen Akademie der Wissenschaften approx 40 volumes Edited by Reinhard Lauth de Erich Fuchs Hans Gliwitzky Ives Radrizzani Gunter Zoller et al Stuttgart Bad Cannstatt 1962 English translation Friedrich Nicolai s Life and Strange Opinions References EditDaniel Breazeale Fichte s Aenesidemus Review and the Transformation of German Idealism The Review of Metaphysics 34 1980 81 545 68 Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore eds Fichte Historical Contexts Contemporary Controversies Atlantic Highlands Humanities Press 1994 Daniel Breazeale and Tom Rockmore eds Fichte German Idealism and Early Romanticism Rodopi 2010 Daniel Breazeale Thinking Through the Wissenschaftslehre Themes from Fichte s Early Philosophy Oxford Oxford University Press 2013 Ezequiel L Posesorski Between Reinhold and Fichte August Ludwig Hulsen s Contribution to the Emergence of German Idealism Karlsruhe Karlsruher Institut Fur Technologie 2012 Sally Sedgwick The Reception of Kant s Critical Philosophy Fichte Schelling and Hegel Cambridge Cambridge University Press 2007 Violetta L Waibel Daniel Breazeale Tom Rockmore eds Fichte and the Phenomenological Tradition Berlin Walter de Gruyter 2010 Gunter Zoller Fichte s Transcendental Philosophy The Original Duplicity of Intelligence and Will Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1998 External links Edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Johann Gottlieb Fichte nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Johann Gottlieb Fichte nbsp Wikisource has original works by or about Johann Gottlieb Fichte Works by Johann Gottlieb Fichte at Project Gutenberg Works by or about Johann Gottlieb Fichte at Internet Archive Works by Johann Gottlieb Fichte at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Outlines of the Doctrine of Knowledge Zalta Edward N ed Johann Gottlieb Fichte Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The North American Fichte Society Fichte s Works in English Translation Works by Fichte original German texts Internationale Johann Gottlieb Fichte Gesellschaft Adamson Robert 1911 Fichte Johann Gottlieb Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 10 11th ed pp 313 317 KULTUR amp KONGRESSWERK fichte Archived 1 August 2015 at the Wayback Machine Event location in Magdeburg named after Johann Gottlieb Fichte A Case Study in Ad Hominem Arguments Fichte s Science of Knowledge Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Johann Gottlieb Fichte amp oldid 1179463081, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.