fbpx
Wikipedia

Euthanasia

Euthanasia (from Greek: εὐθανασία, lit.'good death': εὖ, eu, 'well, good' + θάνατος, thanatos, 'death') is the practice of intentionally ending life to eliminate pain and suffering.[1][2]

Different countries have different euthanasia laws. The British House of Lords select committee on medical ethics defines euthanasia as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, to relieve intractable suffering".[3] In the Netherlands and Belgium, euthanasia is understood as "termination of life by a doctor at the request of a patient".[4] The Dutch law, however, does not use the term 'euthanasia' but includes the concept under the broader definition of "assisted suicide and termination of life on request".[5]

Euthanasia is categorized in different ways, which include voluntary, non-voluntary, or involuntary.[6] Voluntary euthanasia is when a person wills to have their life ended and is legal in a growing number of countries. Non-voluntary euthanasia occurs when a patient's consent is unavailable and is legal in some countries under certain limited conditions, in both active and passive forms. Involuntary euthanasia, which is done without asking for consent or against the patient's will, is illegal in all countries and is usually considered murder.

As of 2006 euthanasia had become the most active area of research in bioethics.[7] In some countries divisive public controversy occurs over the moral, ethical, and legal issues associated with euthanasia. Passive euthanasia (known as "pulling the plug") is legal under some circumstances in many countries. Active euthanasia, however, is legal or de facto legal in only a handful of countries (for example: Belgium, Canada and Switzerland), which limit it to specific circumstances and require the approval of counselors and doctors or other specialists. In some countries—such as Nigeria, Saudi Arabia and Pakistan—support for active euthanasia is almost non-existent.

Definition

Like other terms borrowed from history, "euthanasia" has had different meanings depending on usage. The first apparent usage of the term "euthanasia" belongs to the historian Suetonius, who described how the Emperor Augustus, "dying quickly and without suffering in the arms of his wife, Livia, experienced the 'euthanasia' he had wished for."[8] The word "euthanasia" was first used in a medical context by Francis Bacon in the 17th century, to refer to an easy, painless, happy death, during which it was a "physician's responsibility to alleviate the 'physical sufferings' of the body." Bacon referred to an "outward euthanasia"—the term "outward" he used to distinguish from a spiritual concept—the euthanasia "which regards the preparation of the soul."[9]

In current usage, euthanasia has been defined as the "painless inducement of a quick death".[10] However, it is argued that this approach fails to properly define euthanasia, as it leaves open a number of possible actions which would meet the requirements of the definition, but would not be seen as euthanasia. In particular, these include situations where a person kills another, painlessly, but for no reason beyond that of personal gain; or accidental deaths that are quick and painless, but not intentional.[11][12]

Another approach incorporates the notion of suffering into the definition.[11] The definition offered by the Oxford English Dictionary incorporates suffering as a necessary condition, with "the painless killing of a patient suffering from an incurable and painful disease or in an irreversible coma",[13] This approach is included in Marvin Khol and Paul Kurtz's definition of it as "a mode or act of inducing or permitting death painlessly as a relief from suffering".[14] Counterexamples can be given: such definitions may encompass killing a person suffering from an incurable disease for personal gain (such as to claim an inheritance), and commentators such as Tom Beauchamp and Arnold Davidson have argued that doing so would constitute "murder simpliciter" rather than euthanasia.[11]

The third element incorporated into many definitions is that of intentionality – the death must be intended, rather than being accidental, and the intent of the action must be a "merciful death".[11] Michael Wreen argued that "the principal thing that distinguishes euthanasia from intentional killing simpliciter is the agent's motive: it must be a good motive insofar as the good of the person killed is concerned."[15] Similarly, Heather Draper speaks to the importance of motive, arguing that "the motive forms a crucial part of arguments for euthanasia, because it must be in the best interests of the person on the receiving end."[12] Definitions such as that offered by the House of Lords Select committee on Medical Ethics take this path, where euthanasia is defined as "a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, to relieve intractable suffering."[3] Beauchamp and Davidson also highlight Baruch Brody's "an act of euthanasia is one in which one person ... (A) kills another person (B) for the benefit of the second person, who actually does benefit from being killed".[16]

Draper argued that any definition of euthanasia must incorporate four elements: an agent and a subject; an intention; a causal proximity, such that the actions of the agent lead to the outcome; and an outcome. Based on this, she offered a definition incorporating those elements, stating that euthanasia "must be defined as death that results from the intention of one person to kill another person, using the most gentle and painless means possible, that is motivated solely by the best interests of the person who dies."[17] Prior to Draper, Beauchamp and Davidson had also offered a definition that includes these elements. Their definition specifically discounts fetuses to distinguish between abortions and euthanasia:[18]

In summary, we have argued ... that the death of a human being, A, is an instance of euthanasia if and only if (1) A's death is intended by at least one other human being, B, where B is either the cause of death or a causally relevant feature of the event resulting in death (whether by action or by omission); (2) there is either sufficient current evidence for B to believe that A is acutely suffering or irreversibly comatose, or there is sufficient current evidence related to A's present condition such that one or more known causal laws supports B's belief that A will be in a condition of acute suffering or irreversible comatoseness; (3) (a) B's primary reason for intending A's death is cessation of A's (actual or predicted future) suffering or irreversible comatoseness, where B does not intend A's death for a different primary reason, though there may be other relevant reasons, and (b) there is sufficient current evidence for either A or B that causal means to A's death will not produce any more suffering than would be produced for A if B were not to intervene; (4) the causal means to the event of A's death are chosen by A or B to be as painless as possible, unless either A or B has an overriding reason for a more painful causal means, where the reason for choosing the latter causal means does not conflict with the evidence in 3b; (5) A is a nonfetal organism.[19]

Wreen, in part responding to Beauchamp and Davidson, offered a six-part definition:

Person A committed an act of euthanasia if and only if (1) A killed B or let her die; (2) A intended to kill B; (3) the intention specified in (2) was at least partial cause of the action specified in (1); (4) the causal journey from the intention specified in (2) to the action specified in (1) is more or less in accordance with A's plan of action; (5) A's killing of B is a voluntary action; (6) the motive for the action specified in (1), the motive standing behind the intention specified in (2), is the good of the person killed.[20]

Wreen also considered a seventh requirement: "(7) The good specified in (6) is, or at least includes, the avoidance of evil", although as Wreen noted in the paper, he was not convinced that the restriction was required.[21]

In discussing his definition, Wreen noted the difficulty of justifying euthanasia when faced with the notion of the subject's "right to life". In response, Wreen argued that euthanasia has to be voluntary, and that "involuntary euthanasia is, as such, a great wrong".[21] Other commentators incorporate consent more directly into their definitions. For example, in a discussion of euthanasia presented in 2003 by the European Association of Palliative Care (EPAC) Ethics Task Force, the authors offered: "Medicalized killing of a person without the person's consent, whether nonvoluntary (where the person is unable to consent) or involuntary (against the person's will) is not euthanasia: it is murder. Hence, euthanasia can be voluntary only."[22] Although the EPAC Ethics Task Force argued that both non-voluntary and involuntary euthanasia could not be included in the definition of euthanasia, there is discussion in the literature about excluding one but not the other.[21]

Classification

Euthanasia may be classified into three types, according to whether a person gives informed consent: voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary.[23][24]

There is a debate within the medical and bioethics literature about whether or not the non-voluntary (and by extension, involuntary) killing of patients can be regarded as euthanasia, irrespective of intent or the patient's circumstances. In the definitions offered by Beauchamp and Davidson and, later, by Wreen, consent on the part of the patient was not considered one of their criteria, although it may have been required to justify euthanasia.[11][25] However, others see consent as essential.

Voluntary euthanasia

Voluntary euthanasia is conducted with the consent of the patient. Active voluntary euthanasia is legal in Belgium, Luxembourg and the Netherlands. Passive voluntary euthanasia is legal throughout the US per Cruzan v. Director, Missouri Department of Health. When the patient brings about their own death with the assistance of a physician, the term assisted suicide is often used instead. Assisted suicide is legal in Switzerland and the U.S. states of California, Oregon, Washington, Montana and Vermont.

Non-voluntary euthanasia

Non-voluntary euthanasia is conducted when the consent of the patient is unavailable. Examples include child euthanasia, which is illegal worldwide but decriminalised under certain specific circumstances in the Netherlands under the Groningen Protocol. Passive forms of non-voluntary euthanasia (i.e. withholding treatment) are legal in a number of countries under specified conditions.

Involuntary euthanasia

Involuntary euthanasia is conducted against the will of the patient.

Passive and active euthanasia

Voluntary, non-voluntary and involuntary types can be further divided into passive or active variants.[26] Passive euthanasia entails the withholding treatment necessary for the continuance of life.[3] Active euthanasia entails the use of lethal substances or forces (such as administering a lethal injection), and is more controversial. While some authors consider these terms to be misleading and unhelpful, they are nonetheless commonly used. In some cases, such as the administration of increasingly necessary, but toxic doses of painkillers, there is a debate whether or not to regard the practice as active or passive.[3]

History

 
The Death of Socrates, by Jacques-Louis David (1787), depicting Socrates preparing to drink hemlock, following his conviction for corrupting the youth of Athens

Euthanasia was practiced in Ancient Greece and Rome: for example, hemlock was employed as a means of hastening death on the island of Kea, a technique also employed in Massalia. Euthanasia, in the sense of the deliberate hastening of a person's death, was supported by Socrates, Plato and Seneca the Elder in the ancient world, although Hippocrates appears to have spoken against the practice, writing "I will not prescribe a deadly drug to please someone, nor give advice that may cause his death" (noting there is some debate in the literature about whether or not this was intended to encompass euthanasia).[27][28][29]

Early modern period

The term euthanasia, in the earlier sense of supporting someone as they died, was used for the first time by Francis Bacon. In his work, Euthanasia medica, he chose this ancient Greek word and, in doing so, distinguished between euthanasia interior, the preparation of the soul for death, and euthanasia exterior, which was intended to make the end of life easier and painless, in exceptional circumstances by shortening life. That the ancient meaning of an easy death came to the fore again in the early modern period can be seen from its definition in the 18th century Zedlers Universallexikon:

Euthanasia: a very gentle and quiet death, which happens without painful convulsions. The word comes from ευ, bene, well, and θανατος, mors, death.[30]

The concept of euthanasia in the sense of alleviating the process of death goes back to the medical historian, Karl Friedrich Heinrich Marx, who drew on Bacon's philosophical ideas. According to Marx, a doctor had a moral duty to ease the suffering of death through encouragement, support and mitigation using medication. Such an "alleviation of death" reflected the contemporary zeitgeist, but was brought into the medical canon of responsibility for the first time by Marx. Marx also stressed the distinction between the theological care of the soul of sick people from the physical care and medical treatment by doctors.[31][32]

Euthanasia in its modern sense has always been strongly opposed in the Judeo-Christian tradition. Thomas Aquinas opposed both and argued that the practice of euthanasia contradicted our natural human instincts of survival,[33] as did Francois Ranchin (1565–1641), a French physician and professor of medicine, and Michael Boudewijns (1601–1681), a physician and teacher.[28]: 208 [29] Other voices argued for euthanasia, such as John Donne in 1624,[34] and euthanasia continued to be practised. In 1678, the publication of Caspar Questel's De pulvinari morientibus non-subtrahend, ("On the pillow of which the dying should not be deprived"), initiated debate on the topic. Questel described various customs which were employed at the time to hasten the death of the dying, (including the sudden removal of a pillow, which was believed to accelerate death), and argued against their use, as doing so was "against the laws of God and Nature".[28]: 209–211  This view was shared by others who followed, including Philipp Jakob Spener, Veit Riedlin and Johann Georg Krünitz.[28]: 211  Despite opposition, euthanasia continued to be practised, involving techniques such as bleeding, suffocation, and removing people from their beds to be placed on the cold ground.[28]: 211–214 

Suicide and euthanasia became more accepted during the Age of Enlightenment.[29] Thomas More wrote of euthanasia in Utopia, although it is not clear if More was intending to endorse the practice.[28]: 208–209  Other cultures have taken different approaches: for example, in Japan suicide has not traditionally been viewed as a sin, as it is used in cases of honor, and accordingly, the perceptions of euthanasia are different from those in other parts of the world.[35]

Beginnings of the contemporary euthanasia debate

In the mid-1800s, the use of morphine to treat "the pains of death" emerged, with John Warren recommending its use in 1848. A similar use of chloroform was revealed by Joseph Bullar in 1866. However, in neither case was it recommended that the use should be to hasten death. In 1870 Samuel Williams, a schoolteacher, initiated the contemporary euthanasia debate through a speech given at the Birmingham Speculative Club in England, which was subsequently published in a one-off publication entitled Essays of the Birmingham Speculative Club, the collected works of a number of members of an amateur philosophical society.[36]: 794  Williams' proposal was to use chloroform to deliberately hasten the death of terminally ill patients:

That in all cases of hopeless and painful illness, it should be the recognized duty of the medical attendant, whenever so desired by the patient, to administer chloroform or such other anaesthetic as may by-and-bye supersede chloroform – so as to destroy consciousness at once, and put the sufferer to a quick and painless death; all needful precautions being adopted to prevent any possible abuse of such duty; and means being taken to establish, beyond the possibility of doubt or question, that the remedy was applied at the express wish of the patient.

— Samuel Williams (1872), Euthanasia Williams and Northgate: London.[36]: 794 

The essay was favourably reviewed in The Saturday Review, but an editorial against the essay appeared in The Spectator.[37] From there it proved to be influential, and other writers came out in support of such views: Lionel Tollemache wrote in favour of euthanasia, as did Annie Besant, the essayist and reformer who later became involved with the National Secular Society, considering it a duty to society to "die voluntarily and painlessly" when one reaches the point of becoming a 'burden'.[37][38] Popular Science analyzed the issue in May 1873, assessing both sides of the argument.[39] Kemp notes that at the time, medical doctors did not participate in the discussion; it was "essentially a philosophical enterprise ... tied inextricably to a number of objections to the Christian doctrine of the sanctity of human life".[37]

Early euthanasia movement in the United States

 
Felix Adler, circa 1913, the first prominent American to argue for permitting suicide in cases of chronic illness

The rise of the euthanasia movement in the United States coincided with the so-called Gilded Age, a time of social and technological change that encompassed an "individualistic conservatism that praised laissez-faire economics, scientific method, and rationalism", along with major depressions, industrialisation and conflict between corporations and labour unions.[36]: 794  It was also the period in which the modern hospital system was developed, which has been seen as a factor in the emergence of the euthanasia debate.[40]

Robert Ingersoll argued for euthanasia, stating in 1894 that where someone is suffering from a terminal illness, such as terminal cancer, they should have a right to end their pain through suicide. Felix Adler offered a similar approach, although, unlike Ingersoll, Adler did not reject religion. In fact, he argued from an Ethical Culture framework. In 1891, Adler argued that those suffering from overwhelming pain should have the right to commit suicide, and, furthermore, that it should be permissible for a doctor to assist – thus making Adler the first "prominent American" to argue for suicide in cases where people were suffering from chronic illness.[41] Both Ingersoll and Adler argued for voluntary euthanasia of adults suffering from terminal ailments.[41] Dowbiggin argues that by breaking down prior moral objections to euthanasia and suicide, Ingersoll and Adler enabled others to stretch the definition of euthanasia.[42]

The first attempt to legalise euthanasia took place in the United States, when Henry Hunt introduced legislation into the General Assembly of Ohio in 1906.[43]: 614  Hunt did so at the behest of Anna Sophina Hall, a wealthy heiress who was a major figure in the euthanasia movement during the early 20th century in the United States. Hall had watched her mother die after an extended battle with liver cancer, and had dedicated herself to ensuring that others would not have to endure the same suffering. Towards this end she engaged in an extensive letter writing campaign, recruited Lurana Sheldon and Maud Ballington Booth, and organised a debate on euthanasia at the annual meeting of the American Humane Association in 1905 – described by Jacob Appel as the first significant public debate on the topic in the 20th century.[43]: 614–616 

Hunt's bill called for the administration of an anesthetic to bring about a patient's death, so long as the person is of lawful age and sound mind, and was suffering from a fatal injury, an irrevocable illness, or great physical pain. It also required that the case be heard by a physician, required informed consent in front of three witnesses, and required the attendance of three physicians who had to agree that the patient's recovery was impossible. A motion to reject the bill outright was voted down, but the bill failed to pass, 79 to 23.[36]: 796 [43]: 618–619 

Along with the Ohio euthanasia proposal, in 1906 Assemblyman Ross Gregory introduced a proposal to permit euthanasia to the Iowa legislature. However, the Iowa legislation was broader in scope than that offered in Ohio. It allowed for the death of any person of at least ten years of age who suffered from an ailment that would prove fatal and cause extreme pain, should they be of sound mind and express a desire to artificially hasten their death. In addition, it allowed for infants to be euthanised if they were sufficiently deformed, and permitted guardians to request euthanasia on behalf of their wards. The proposed legislation also imposed penalties on physicians who refused to perform euthanasia when requested: a 6–12-month prison term and a fine of between $200 and $1,000. The proposal proved to be controversial.[43]: 619–621  It engendered considerable debate and failed to pass, having been withdrawn from consideration after being passed to the Committee on Public Health.[43]: 623 

After 1906 the euthanasia debate reduced in intensity, resurfacing periodically, but not returning to the same level of debate until the 1930s in the United Kingdom.[36]: 796 

Euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin argues that the early membership of the Euthanasia Society of America (ESA) reflected how many perceived euthanasia at the time, often seeing it as a eugenics matter rather than an issue concerning individual rights.[41] Dowbiggin argues that not every eugenist joined the ESA "solely for eugenic reasons", but he postulates that there were clear ideological connections between the eugenics and euthanasia movements.[41]

1930s in Britain

The Voluntary Euthanasia Legalisation Society was founded in 1935 by Charles Killick Millard (now called Dignity in Dying). The movement campaigned for the legalisation of euthanasia in Great Britain.

In January 1936, King George V was given a fatal dose of morphine and cocaine to hasten his death. At the time he was suffering from cardio-respiratory failure, and the decision to end his life was made by his physician, Lord Dawson.[44] Although this event was kept a secret for over 50 years, the death of George V coincided with proposed legislation in the House of Lords to legalise euthanasia.[45]

Nazi Euthanasia Program

 
Hartheim Euthanasia Centre, where over 18,000 people were killed

A 24 July 1939 killing of a severely disabled infant in Nazi Germany was described in a BBC "Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline" as the first "state-sponsored euthanasia".[46] Parties that consented to the killing included Hitler's office, the parents, and the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses.[46] The Telegraph noted that the killing of the disabled infant—whose name was Gerhard Kretschmar, born blind, with missing limbs, subject to convulsions, and reportedly "an idiot"— provided "the rationale for a secret Nazi decree that led to 'mercy killings' of almost 300,000 mentally and physically handicapped people".[47] While Kretchmar's killing received parental consent, most of the 5,000 to 8,000 children killed afterwards were forcibly taken from their parents.[46][47]

The "euthanasia campaign" of mass murder gathered momentum on 14 January 1940 when the "handicapped" were killed with gas vans and at killing centres, eventually leading to the deaths of 70,000 adult Germans.[48] Professor Robert Jay Lifton, author of The Nazi Doctors and a leading authority on the T4 program, contrasts this program with what he considers to be a genuine euthanasia. He explains that the Nazi version of "euthanasia" was based on the work of Adolf Jost, who published The Right to Death (Das Recht auf den Tod) in 1895. Lifton writes:

Jost argued that control over the death of the individual must ultimately belong to the social organism, the state. This concept is in direct opposition to the Anglo-American concept of euthanasia, which emphasizes the individual's 'right to die' or 'right to death' or 'right to his or her own death,' as the ultimate human claim. In contrast, Jost was pointing to the state's right to kill. ... Ultimately the argument was biological: 'The rights to death [are] the key to the fitness of life.' The state must own death—must kill—in order to keep the social organism alive and healthy.[49]

In modern terms, the use of "euthanasia" in the context of Action T4 is seen to be a euphemism to disguise a program of genocide, in which people were killed on the grounds of "disabilities, religious beliefs, and discordant individual values".[50] Compared to the discussions of euthanasia that emerged post-war, the Nazi program may have been worded in terms that appear similar to the modern use of "euthanasia", but there was no "mercy" and the patients were not necessarily terminally ill.[50] Despite these differences, historian and euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin writes that "the origins of Nazi euthanasia, like those of the American euthanasia movement, predate the Third Reich and were intertwined with the history of eugenics and Social Darwinism, and with efforts to discredit traditional morality and ethics."[41]: 65 

1949 New York State Petition for Euthanasia and Catholic opposition

On 6 January 1949, the Euthanasia Society of America presented to the New York State Legislature a petition to legalize euthanasia, signed by 379 leading Protestant and Jewish ministers, the largest group of religious leaders ever to have taken this stance. A similar petition had been sent to the New York Legislature in 1947, signed by approximately 1,000 New York physicians. Roman Catholic religious leaders criticized the petition, saying that such a bill would "legalize a suicide-murder pact" and a "rationalization of the fifth commandment of God, 'Thou Shalt Not Kill.'"[51] The Right Reverend Robert E. McCormick stated that:

The ultimate object of the Euthanasia Society is based on the Totalitarian principle that the state is supreme and that the individual does not have the right to live if his continuance in life is a burden or hindrance to the state. The Nazis followed this principle and compulsory Euthanasia was practiced as a part of their program during the recent war. We American citizens of New York State must ask ourselves this question: "Are we going to finish Hitler's job?"[51]

The petition brought tensions between the American Euthanasia Society and the Catholic Church to a head that contributed to a climate of anti-Catholic sentiment generally, regarding issues such as birth control, eugenics, and population control. However, the petition did not result in any legal changes.[41]

Debate

Historically, the euthanasia debate has tended to focus on a number of key concerns. According to euthanasia opponent Ezekiel Emanuel, proponents of euthanasia have presented four main arguments: a) that people have a right to self-determination, and thus should be allowed to choose their own fate; b) assisting a subject to die might be a better choice than requiring that they continue to suffer; c) the distinction between passive euthanasia, which is often permitted, and active euthanasia, which is not substantive (or that the underlying principle–the doctrine of double effect–is unreasonable or unsound); and d) permitting euthanasia will not necessarily lead to unacceptable consequences. Pro-euthanasia activists often point to countries like the Netherlands and Belgium, and states like Oregon, where euthanasia has been legalized, to argue that it is mostly unproblematic.

Similarly, Emanuel argues that there are four major arguments presented by opponents of euthanasia: a) not all deaths are painful; b) alternatives, such as cessation of active treatment, combined with the use of effective pain relief, are available; c) the distinction between active and passive euthanasia is morally significant; and d) legalising euthanasia will place society on a slippery slope,[52] which will lead to unacceptable consequences.[36]: 797–8  In fact, in Oregon, in 2013, pain was not one of the top five reasons people sought euthanasia. Top reasons were a loss of dignity, and a fear of burdening others.[53]

In the United States in 2013, 47% nationwide supported doctor-assisted suicide. This included 32% of Latinos, 29% of African-Americans, and almost nobody with disabilities.[53]

A 2015 Populus poll in the United Kingdom found broad public support for assisted dying. 82% of people supported the introduction of assisted dying laws, including 86% of people with disabilities.[54]

An alternative approach to the question is seen in the hospice movement which promotes palliative care for the dying and terminally ill. This has pioneered the use of pain-relieving drugs in a holistic atmosphere in which the patient's spiritual care ranks alongside physical care. It 'intends neither to hasten nor postpone death'.[55]

Legal status

 
Current status of euthanasia around the world:
  Active voluntary euthanasia legal (Belgium, Canada, Colombia, Luxembourg, the Netherlands, New Zealand, Spain and the Australian states of New South Wales, Queensland, South Australia, Tasmania, Victoria and Western Australia)
  Passive euthanasia legal (refusal of treatment / withdrawal of life support)
  Active euthanasia illegal, passive euthanasia not legislated or regulated
  All forms of euthanasia illegal

West's Encyclopedia of American Law states that "a 'mercy killing' or euthanasia is generally considered to be a criminal homicide" and is normally used as a synonym of homicide committed at a request made by the patient.[56][57]

The judicial sense of the term "homicide" includes any intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life, even to relieve intractable suffering.[58][57][59] Not all homicide is unlawful.[60] Two designations of homicide that carry no criminal punishment are justifiable and excusable homicide.[60] In most countries this is not the status of euthanasia. The term "euthanasia" is usually confined to the active variety; the University of Washington website states that "euthanasia generally means that the physician would act directly, for instance by giving a lethal injection, to end the patient's life".[61] Physician-assisted suicide is thus not classified as euthanasia by the US State of Oregon, where it is legal under the Oregon Death with Dignity Act, and despite its name, it is not legally classified as suicide either.[62] Unlike physician-assisted suicide, withholding or withdrawing life-sustaining treatments with patient consent (voluntary) is almost unanimously considered, at least in the United States, to be legal.[63] The use of pain medication to relieve suffering, even if it hastens death, has been held as legal in several court decisions.[61]

Some governments around the world have legalized voluntary euthanasia but most commonly it is still considered to be criminal homicide. In the Netherlands and Belgium, where euthanasia has been legalized, it still remains homicide although it is not prosecuted and not punishable if the perpetrator (the doctor) meets certain legal conditions.[64][65][66][67]

In a historic judgment, the Supreme court of India legalized passive euthanasia. The apex court remarked in the judgment that the Constitution of India values liberty, dignity, autonomy, and privacy. A bench headed by Chief Justice Dipak Misra delivered a unanimous judgment.[68]

Health professionals' sentiment

A 2010 survey in the United States of more than 10,000 physicians found that 16.3% of physicians would consider halting life-sustaining therapy because the family demanded it, even if they believed that it was premature. Approximately 54.5% would not, and the remaining 29.2% responded "it depends".[69] The study also found that 45.8% of physicians agreed that physician-assisted suicide should be allowed in some cases; 40.7% did not, and the remaining 13.5% felt it depended.[69]

In the United Kingdom, the assisted dying campaign group Dignity in Dying cites research in which 54% of general practitioners support or are neutral towards a law change on assisted dying.[70] Similarly, a 2017 Doctors.net.uk poll reported in the British Medical Journal stated that 55% of doctors believe assisted dying, in defined circumstances, should be legalised in the UK.[71]

Religious views

Christianity

Broadly against

The Roman Catholic Church condemns euthanasia and assisted suicide as morally wrong. It states that, "intentional euthanasia, whatever its forms or motives, is murder. It is gravely contrary to the dignity of the human person and to the respect due to the living God, his Creator". Because of this, the practice is unacceptable within the Church.[citation needed] The Orthodox Church in America, along with other Eastern Orthodox Churches, also opposes euthanasia stating that "euthanasia is the deliberate cessation of human life, and, as such, must be condemned as murder."[72]

Many non-Catholic churches in the United States take a stance against euthanasia. Among Protestant denominations, the Episcopal Church passed a resolution in 1991 opposing euthanasia and assisted suicide stating that it is "morally wrong and unacceptable to take a human life to relieve the suffering caused by incurable illnesses."[72] Protestant and other non-Catholic churches which oppose euthanasia include:

Partially in favor of

The Church of England accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is strongly against active euthanasia, and has led opposition against recent attempts to legalise it.[82] The United Church of Canada accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances, but is in general against active euthanasia, with growing acceptance now that active euthanasia has been partly legalised in Canada.[83]

Islam

Euthanasia is a complex issue in Islamic theology; however, in general it is considered contrary to Islamic law and holy texts. Among interpretations of the Qur'an and Hadith, the early termination of life is a crime, be it by suicide or helping one commit suicide. The various positions on the cessation of medical treatment are mixed and considered a different class of action than direct termination of life, especially if the patient is suffering. Suicide and euthanasia are both crimes in almost all Muslim majority countries.[84]

Judaism

There is much debate on the topic of euthanasia in Judaic theology, ethics, and general opinion (especially in Israel and the United States). Passive euthanasia was declared legal by Israel's highest court under certain conditions and has reached some level of acceptance. Active euthanasia remains illegal, however the topic is actively under debate with no clear consensus through legal, ethical, theological and spiritual perspectives.[85]

See also

References

  1. ^ "Euthanasia". Worldrtd.net. from the original on 5 August 2017. Retrieved 6 July 2017. Philosopher Helga Kuhse: "'Euthanasia' is a compound of two Greek words – eu and thanatos meaning, literally, 'a good death'. Today, 'euthanasia' is generally understood to mean the bringing about of a good death – 'mercy killing,' where one person, A, ends the life of another person, B, for the sake of B."
  2. ^ "Voluntary Euthanasia". Voluntary Euthanasia (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). Plato.stanford.edu. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018. Retrieved 7 May 2019. When a person performs an act of euthanasia, she brings about the death of another person because she believes the latter's present existence is so bad that he would be better off dead, or believes that unless she intervenes and ends his life, his life will very soon become so bad that he would be better off dead.
  3. ^ a b c d Harris, NM. (October 2001). "The euthanasia debate". J R Army Med Corps. 147 (3): 367–70. doi:10.1136/jramc-147-03-22. PMID 11766225.
  4. ^ Euthanasia and assisted suicide 19 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC. Last reviewed June 2011. Accessed 25 July 2011. Archived from the original
  5. ^ Carr, Claudia (2014). Unlocking Medical Law and Ethics (2nd ed.). Routledge. p. 374. ISBN 9781317743514. Retrieved 2 February 2018.
  6. ^ Voluntary and involuntary euthanasia 5 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 12 February 2012. Archived from the original
  7. ^ Borry P, Schotsmans P, Dierickx K (April 2006). "Empirical research in bioethical journals. A quantitative analysis". J Med Ethics. 32 (4): 240–45. doi:10.1136/jme.2004.011478. PMC 2565792. PMID 16574880.
  8. ^ Philippe Letellier, chapter: History and Definition of a Word, in Euthanasia: Ethical and Human Aspects By Council of Europe
  9. ^ Francis Bacon: The Major Works by Francis Bacon, edited by Brian Vickers, p. 630.
  10. ^ Kohl, Marvin (1974). The Morality of Killing. New York: Humanities Press. p. 94. ISBN 9780391001954., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 294. A similar definition is offered by Blackburn (1994) with "the action of causing the quick and painless death of a person, or not acting to prevent it when prevention was within the agent's powers."
  11. ^ a b c d e Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 294–312. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  12. ^ a b Draper, Heather (1998). "Euthanasia". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics. Vol. 2. Academic Press.
  13. ^ . Oxford Dictionaries. Oxford University Press. April 2010. Archived from the original on 21 August 2011. Retrieved 26 April 2011.
  14. ^ Kohl, Marvin; Kurtz, Paul (1975). "A Plea for Beneficient Euthanasia". In Kohl, Marvin (ed.). Beneficient Euthanasia. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. p. 94., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.
  15. ^ Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53 [639]. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  16. ^ Brody, Baruch (1975). "Voluntary Euthanasia and the Law". In Kohl, Marvin (ed.). Beneficient Euthanasia. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. p. 94., quoted in Beauchamp & Davidson (1979), p 295.
  17. ^ Draper, Heather (1998). "Euthanasia". In Chadwick, Ruth (ed.). Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics. Vol. 2. Academic Press. p. 176.
  18. ^ Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 303. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  19. ^ Beauchamp, Tom L.; Davidson, Arnold I. (1979). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Journal of Medicine and Philosophy. 4 (3): 304. doi:10.1093/jmp/4.3.294. PMID 501249.
  20. ^ Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–40. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  21. ^ a b c Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53 [645]. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  22. ^ Materstvedt, Lars Johan; Clark, David; Ellershaw, John; Førde, Reidun; Boeck Gravgaard, Anne-Marie; Müller-Busch, Christof; Porta i Sales, Josep; Rapin, Charles-Henri (2003). "Euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide: a view from an EAPC Ethics Task Force". Palliative Medicine. 17 (2): 97–101. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.514.5064. doi:10.1191/0269216303pm673oa. PMID 12701848. S2CID 1498250.
  23. ^ Perrett RW (October 1996). "Buddhism, euthanasia and the sanctity of life". J Med Ethics. 22 (5): 309–13. doi:10.1136/jme.22.5.309. PMC 1377066. PMID 8910785.
  24. ^ LaFollette, Hugh (2002). Ethics in practice: an anthology. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 25–26. ISBN 978-0-631-22834-9.
  25. ^ Wreen, Michael (1988). "The Definition of Euthanasia". Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 48 (4): 637–53. doi:10.2307/2108012. JSTOR 2108012. PMID 11652547.
  26. ^ Rachels J (January 1975). "Active and passive euthanasia". N. Engl. J. Med. 292 (2): 78–80. doi:10.1056/NEJM197501092920206. PMID 1109443. S2CID 46465710.
  27. ^ Mystakidou, Kyriaki; Parpa, Efi; Tsilika, Eleni; Katsouda, Emanuela; Vlahos, Lambros (2005). "The Evolution of Euthanasia and Its Perceptions in Greek Culture and Civilization". Perspectives in Biology and Medicine. 48 (1): 97–98. doi:10.1353/pbm.2005.0013. PMID 15681882. S2CID 44600176.
  28. ^ a b c d e f Stolberg, Michael (2007). "Active Euthanasia in Pre-ModernSociety, 1500–1800: Learned Debates and Popular Practices". Social History of Medicine. 20 (2): 206–07. doi:10.1093/shm/hkm034. PMID 18605325. S2CID 6150428.
  29. ^ a b c Gesundheit, Benjamin; Steinberg, Avraham; Glick, Shimon; Or, Reuven; Jotkovitz, Alan (2006). "Euthanasia: An Overview and the Jewish Perspective". Cancer Investigation. 24 (6): 621–9. doi:10.1080/07357900600894898. PMID 16982468. S2CID 8906449.
  30. ^ Zedlers Universallexikon, Vol. 08, p. 1150, published 1732–54.
  31. ^ Markwart Michler (1990), "Marx, Karl, Mediziner", Neue Deutsche Biographie (in German), vol. 16, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp. 327–328; (full text online)
  32. ^ Helge Dvorak: Biographisches Lexikon der Deutschen Burschenschaft. Vol. I, Sub-vol. 4, Heidelberg, 2000, pp. 40–41.
  33. ^ "Historical Timeline: History of Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide," Archived 5 July 2012 at the Library of Congress Web Archives Euthanasia – ProCon.org. Last updated on: 23 July 2013. Retrieved 4 May 2014.
  34. ^ Mannes, Marya (1975). "Euthanasia vs. the Right to Life". Baylor Law Review. 27: 69.
  35. ^ Otani, Izumi (2010). ""Good Manner of Dying" as a Normative Concept: "Autocide", "Granny Dumping" and Discussions on Euthanasia/Death with Dignity in Japan". International Journal of Japanese Sociology. 19 (1): 49–63. doi:10.1111/j.1475-6781.2010.01136.x.
  36. ^ a b c d e f Emanuel, Ezekiel (1994). "The history of euthanasia debates in the United States and Britain". Annals of Internal Medicine. 121 (10): 796. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.732.724. doi:10.7326/0003-4819-121-10-199411150-00010. PMID 7944057. S2CID 20754659.
  37. ^ a b c Nick Kemp (7 September 2002). Merciful Release. Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-0-7190-6124-0. OL 10531689M. 0719061245.
  38. ^ Ian Dowbiggin (March 2007). A Concise History of Euthanasia: Life, Death, God, and Medicine. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 51, 62–64. ISBN 978-0-7425-3111-6.
  39. ^ Corporation, Bonnier (May 1873). "Popular Science". {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  40. ^ Pappas, Demetra (1996). "Recent historical perspectives regarding medical euthanasia and physician assisted suicide". British Medical Bulletin. 52 (2): 386–87. doi:10.1093/oxfordjournals.bmb.a011554. PMID 8759237.
  41. ^ a b c d e f Dowbiggin, Ian (2003). A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America. Oxford University Press. pp. 10–13. ISBN 978-0-19-515443-6.
  42. ^ Dowbiggin, Ian (2003). A merciful end: the euthanasia movement in modern America. Oxford University Press. p. 13. ISBN 978-0-19-515443-6.
  43. ^ a b c d e Appel, Jacob (2004). "A Duty to Kill? A Duty to Die? Rethinking the Euthanasia Controversy of 1906". Bulletin of the History of Medicine. 78 (3): 610–34. doi:10.1353/bhm.2004.0106. PMID 15356372. S2CID 24991992.
  44. ^ Ramsay, J H R (28 May 2011). "A king, a doctor, and a convenient death". British Medical Journal. 308 (1445): 1445. doi:10.1136/bmj.308.6941.1445. PMC 2540387. PMID 11644545.
  45. ^ Gurney, Edward (1972). "Is There a Right to Die – A Study of the Law of Euthanasia". Cumberland-Samford Law Review. 3: 237.
  46. ^ a b c Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline: 24 July 1939 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The first state-sanctioned euthanasia is carried out, after Hitler receives a petition from a child's parents, asking for the life of their severely disabled infant to be ended. This happens after the case has been considered by Hitler's office and by the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses, whose 'experts' have laid down the basis for the removal of disabled children to special 'paediatric clinics'. Here they can be either starved to death or given lethal injections. At least 5,200 infants will eventually be killed through this programme".
  47. ^ a b Irene Zoech (11 October 2003). "Named: the baby boy who was Nazis' first euthanasia victim". Telegraph.co.uk. from the original on 8 September 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  48. ^ Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline: 14 January 1940 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011. Quotation: "The 'euthanasia campaign' gathers momentum in Germany, as six special killing centres and gas vans, under an organisation code-named T4, are used in the murder of 'handicapped' adults. Over 70,000 Germans will eventually be killed in this act of mass murder – it is the first time poison bas will be used for such a purpose".
  49. ^ Basic Books 1986, 46
  50. ^ a b Michalsen A, Reinhart K (September 2006). ""Euthanasia": A confusing term, abused under the Nazi regime and misused in present end-of-life debate". Intensive Care Med. 32 (9): 1304–10. doi:10.1007/s00134-006-0256-9. PMID 16826394. S2CID 21032497.
  51. ^ a b The Moncton Transcript. "Ministers Ask Mercy Killing." 6 January 1949.
  52. ^ Wesley J. Smith (1997). Forced Exit (Forced exit ed.). New York: Times Books. ISBN 978-0-8129-2790-0. OL 1006883M. 0812927907.
  53. ^ a b "The vulnerable will be the victims: Opposing view". Usatoday.com. from the original on 9 September 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  54. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 November 2016. Retrieved 4 August 2018.
  55. ^ "Position statement on hospice care and assisted dying (assisted suicide) and recommendations" (PDF). Hospice UK. Retrieved 11 March 2021.
  56. ^ West's Encyclopedia of American Law, Vol. 4. West Publishing Company. 1998. p. 24. ISBN 9780314201577.
  57. ^ a b Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997
  58. ^ Harris, N. (1 October 2001). "The Euthanasia Debate". Journal of the Royal Army Medical Corps. 147 (3): 367–370. doi:10.1136/jramc-147-03-22. PMID 11766225. S2CID 298551.
  59. ^ Manoj Kumar Mohanty (August 2004). "Variants of homicide: a review". Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine. 11 (4): 214–18. doi:10.1016/j.jcfm.2004.04.006. PMID 15363757.
  60. ^ a b "the definition of homicide". Dictionary.com. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  61. ^ a b "Physician-Assisted Suicide: Ethical Topic in Medicine". depts.washington.edu. from the original on 13 April 2017. Retrieved 4 July 2017.
  62. ^ Taylor, Bill (7 July 2017). (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 December 2004. Retrieved 7 July 2017.
  63. ^ "Legal Aspects of Withholding and Withdrawing Life Support from Critically Ill Patients in the United States and Providing Palliative Care to Them", Am. J. Respir. Crit. Care Med., Volume 162, Number 6, December 2000. 13 August 2003 at the Wayback Machine
  64. ^ Oluyemisi Bamgbose (2004). "Euthanasia: Another Face of Murder". International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology. 48 (1): 111–21. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.631.618. doi:10.1177/0306624X03256662. PMID 14969121. S2CID 32664881.
  65. ^ Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee : Netherlands. 27 August 2001
  66. ^ Carmen Tomás Y Valiente, La regulación de la eutanasia en Holanda, Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales – Núm. L, Enero 1997
  67. ^ R Cohen-Almagor (2009). "Belgian euthanasia law: a critical analysis". J. Med. Ethics. 35 (7): 436–39. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.508.6943. doi:10.1136/jme.2008.026799. PMID 19567694. S2CID 44968015.
  68. ^ "Euthanasia and beyond: on the Supreme Court's verdict SC Constitution Bench holds passive euthanasia, living wills permissible". The Hindu. Karnataka. 9 March 2018. from the original on 5 June 2018. Retrieved 9 March 2018.
  69. ^ a b Leslie Kane, MA. "Exclusive Ethics Survey Results: Doctors Struggle With Tougher-Than-Ever Dilemmas". Medscape.com. from the original on 14 August 2017. Retrieved 6 July 2017.
  70. ^ "Public opinion – Dignity in Dying". Retrieved 3 August 2018.
  71. ^ "Assisted dying case 'stronger than ever' with majority of doctors now in support". 7 February 2018. Retrieved 3 August 2018.
  72. ^ a b c "The Orthodox Christian view on Euthanasia". www.orthodoxchristian.info. from the original on 12 August 2017.
  73. ^ a b "Assemblies of God (USA) Official Web Site – Medical: Euthanasia, and Extraordinary Support to Sustain Life". ag.org. from the original on 14 August 2017.
  74. ^ "21. Selected Church Policies and Guidelines". ChurchofJesusChrist.org.
  75. ^ "The Church of the Nazarene, Doctrinal and Ethical Positions". www.crivoice.org. from the original on 8 November 2017.
  76. ^ "Error" (PDF). (PDF) from the original on 18 April 2016. Retrieved 28 March 2018.
  77. ^ "What Are Christian Perspectives on Euthanasia and Physician-Assisted Suicide? - Euthanasia - ProCon.org". euthanasia.procon.org. from the original on 15 August 2017.
  78. ^ "LCMS Views – Frequently Asked Questions – The Lutheran Church—Missouri Synod". www.lcms.org. from the original on 14 August 2017.
  79. ^ "General Synod Statements: Physician-Assisted Suicide – Reformed Church in America". www.rca.org. from the original on 19 March 2017.
  80. ^ "The Salvation Army International – Positional Statement: Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide". www.salvationarmy.org. from the original on 14 August 2017.
  81. ^ "Southern Baptist Convention > Resolution on Euthanasia And Assisted Suicide". www.sbc.net. from the original on 9 October 2017.
  82. ^ Why the Church of England Supports the Current Law on Assisted Suicide. Dr Brendan McCarthy Archbishops' Council Church House, London 2015
  83. ^ Submission to The Special Joint Committee on Physician-Assisted Dying. Rev. Jordan Cantwell Moderator of The United Church of Canada. 2016
  84. ^ Islamic Perspectives, Euthanasia (Qatl al-raḥma). Abulfadl Mohsin Ebrahim. Journal of the Islamic Medical Association of North America 2007 Volume 4.
  85. ^ Death and Euthanasia in Jewish Law: Essays and Responses. W Jacob and M. Zemer. Pitsburg and Tel Aviv. Rodef Shalom Press. 1995

Further reading

External links

  •   Media related to Euthanasia at Wikimedia Commons
  •   The dictionary definition of euthanasia at Wiktionary
  •   Quotations related to Euthanasia at Wikiquote
  • Physician assisted death from The Hastings Center

euthanasia, this, article, about, euthanasia, humans, mercy, killings, performed, other, animals, animal, euthanasia, killing, mortally, wounded, animals, humans, coup, grâce, megadeth, album, youthanasia, from, greek, εὐθανασία, good, death, εὖ, well, good, θ. This article is about euthanasia of humans For mercy killings performed on other animals see Animal euthanasia For the killing of mortally wounded animals or humans see Coup de grace For the Megadeth album see Youthanasia Euthanasia from Greek eὐ8anasia lit good death eὖ eu well good 8anatos thanatos death is the practice of intentionally ending life to eliminate pain and suffering 1 2 Different countries have different euthanasia laws The British House of Lords select committee on medical ethics defines euthanasia as a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life to relieve intractable suffering 3 In the Netherlands and Belgium euthanasia is understood as termination of life by a doctor at the request of a patient 4 The Dutch law however does not use the term euthanasia but includes the concept under the broader definition of assisted suicide and termination of life on request 5 Euthanasia is categorized in different ways which include voluntary non voluntary or involuntary 6 Voluntary euthanasia is when a person wills to have their life ended and is legal in a growing number of countries Non voluntary euthanasia occurs when a patient s consent is unavailable and is legal in some countries under certain limited conditions in both active and passive forms Involuntary euthanasia which is done without asking for consent or against the patient s will is illegal in all countries and is usually considered murder As of 2006 update euthanasia had become the most active area of research in bioethics 7 In some countries divisive public controversy occurs over the moral ethical and legal issues associated with euthanasia Passive euthanasia known as pulling the plug is legal under some circumstances in many countries Active euthanasia however is legal or de facto legal in only a handful of countries for example Belgium Canada and Switzerland which limit it to specific circumstances and require the approval of counselors and doctors or other specialists In some countries such as Nigeria Saudi Arabia and Pakistan support for active euthanasia is almost non existent Contents 1 Definition 2 Classification 2 1 Voluntary euthanasia 2 2 Non voluntary euthanasia 2 3 Involuntary euthanasia 2 4 Passive and active euthanasia 3 History 3 1 Early modern period 3 2 Beginnings of the contemporary euthanasia debate 3 3 Early euthanasia movement in the United States 3 4 1930s in Britain 3 5 Nazi Euthanasia Program 3 6 1949 New York State Petition for Euthanasia and Catholic opposition 4 Debate 5 Legal status 6 Health professionals sentiment 7 Religious views 7 1 Christianity 7 1 1 Broadly against 7 1 2 Partially in favor of 7 2 Islam 7 3 Judaism 8 See also 9 References 10 Further reading 11 External linksDefinitionLike other terms borrowed from history euthanasia has had different meanings depending on usage The first apparent usage of the term euthanasia belongs to the historian Suetonius who described how the Emperor Augustus dying quickly and without suffering in the arms of his wife Livia experienced the euthanasia he had wished for 8 The word euthanasia was first used in a medical context by Francis Bacon in the 17th century to refer to an easy painless happy death during which it was a physician s responsibility to alleviate the physical sufferings of the body Bacon referred to an outward euthanasia the term outward he used to distinguish from a spiritual concept the euthanasia which regards the preparation of the soul 9 In current usage euthanasia has been defined as the painless inducement of a quick death 10 However it is argued that this approach fails to properly define euthanasia as it leaves open a number of possible actions which would meet the requirements of the definition but would not be seen as euthanasia In particular these include situations where a person kills another painlessly but for no reason beyond that of personal gain or accidental deaths that are quick and painless but not intentional 11 12 Another approach incorporates the notion of suffering into the definition 11 The definition offered by the Oxford English Dictionary incorporates suffering as a necessary condition with the painless killing of a patient suffering from an incurable and painful disease or in an irreversible coma 13 This approach is included in Marvin Khol and Paul Kurtz s definition of it as a mode or act of inducing or permitting death painlessly as a relief from suffering 14 Counterexamples can be given such definitions may encompass killing a person suffering from an incurable disease for personal gain such as to claim an inheritance and commentators such as Tom Beauchamp and Arnold Davidson have argued that doing so would constitute murder simpliciter rather than euthanasia 11 The third element incorporated into many definitions is that of intentionality the death must be intended rather than being accidental and the intent of the action must be a merciful death 11 Michael Wreen argued that the principal thing that distinguishes euthanasia from intentional killing simpliciter is the agent s motive it must be a good motive insofar as the good of the person killed is concerned 15 Similarly Heather Draper speaks to the importance of motive arguing that the motive forms a crucial part of arguments for euthanasia because it must be in the best interests of the person on the receiving end 12 Definitions such as that offered by the House of Lords Select committee on Medical Ethics take this path where euthanasia is defined as a deliberate intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life to relieve intractable suffering 3 Beauchamp and Davidson also highlight Baruch Brody s an act of euthanasia is one in which one person A kills another person B for the benefit of the second person who actually does benefit from being killed 16 Draper argued that any definition of euthanasia must incorporate four elements an agent and a subject an intention a causal proximity such that the actions of the agent lead to the outcome and an outcome Based on this she offered a definition incorporating those elements stating that euthanasia must be defined as death that results from the intention of one person to kill another person using the most gentle and painless means possible that is motivated solely by the best interests of the person who dies 17 Prior to Draper Beauchamp and Davidson had also offered a definition that includes these elements Their definition specifically discounts fetuses to distinguish between abortions and euthanasia 18 In summary we have argued that the death of a human being A is an instance of euthanasia if and only if 1 A s death is intended by at least one other human being B where B is either the cause of death or a causally relevant feature of the event resulting in death whether by action or by omission 2 there is either sufficient current evidence for B to believe that A is acutely suffering or irreversibly comatose or there is sufficient current evidence related to A s present condition such that one or more known causal laws supports B s belief that A will be in a condition of acute suffering or irreversible comatoseness 3 a B s primary reason for intending A s death is cessation of A s actual or predicted future suffering or irreversible comatoseness where B does not intend A s death for a different primary reason though there may be other relevant reasons and b there is sufficient current evidence for either A or B that causal means to A s death will not produce any more suffering than would be produced for A if B were not to intervene 4 the causal means to the event of A s death are chosen by A or B to be as painless as possible unless either A or B has an overriding reason for a more painful causal means where the reason for choosing the latter causal means does not conflict with the evidence in 3b 5 A is a nonfetal organism 19 Wreen in part responding to Beauchamp and Davidson offered a six part definition Person A committed an act of euthanasia if and only if 1 A killed B or let her die 2 A intended to kill B 3 the intention specified in 2 was at least partial cause of the action specified in 1 4 the causal journey from the intention specified in 2 to the action specified in 1 is more or less in accordance with A s plan of action 5 A s killing of B is a voluntary action 6 the motive for the action specified in 1 the motive standing behind the intention specified in 2 is the good of the person killed 20 Wreen also considered a seventh requirement 7 The good specified in 6 is or at least includes the avoidance of evil although as Wreen noted in the paper he was not convinced that the restriction was required 21 In discussing his definition Wreen noted the difficulty of justifying euthanasia when faced with the notion of the subject s right to life In response Wreen argued that euthanasia has to be voluntary and that involuntary euthanasia is as such a great wrong 21 Other commentators incorporate consent more directly into their definitions For example in a discussion of euthanasia presented in 2003 by the European Association of Palliative Care EPAC Ethics Task Force the authors offered Medicalized killing of a person without the person s consent whether nonvoluntary where the person is unable to consent or involuntary against the person s will is not euthanasia it is murder Hence euthanasia can be voluntary only 22 Although the EPAC Ethics Task Force argued that both non voluntary and involuntary euthanasia could not be included in the definition of euthanasia there is discussion in the literature about excluding one but not the other 21 ClassificationEuthanasia may be classified into three types according to whether a person gives informed consent voluntary non voluntary and involuntary 23 24 There is a debate within the medical and bioethics literature about whether or not the non voluntary and by extension involuntary killing of patients can be regarded as euthanasia irrespective of intent or the patient s circumstances In the definitions offered by Beauchamp and Davidson and later by Wreen consent on the part of the patient was not considered one of their criteria although it may have been required to justify euthanasia 11 25 However others see consent as essential Voluntary euthanasia See also Right to die Voluntary euthanasia is conducted with the consent of the patient Active voluntary euthanasia is legal in Belgium Luxembourg and the Netherlands Passive voluntary euthanasia is legal throughout the US per Cruzan v Director Missouri Department of Health When the patient brings about their own death with the assistance of a physician the term assisted suicide is often used instead Assisted suicide is legal in Switzerland and the U S states of California Oregon Washington Montana and Vermont Non voluntary euthanasia Non voluntary euthanasia is conducted when the consent of the patient is unavailable Examples include child euthanasia which is illegal worldwide but decriminalised under certain specific circumstances in the Netherlands under the Groningen Protocol Passive forms of non voluntary euthanasia i e withholding treatment are legal in a number of countries under specified conditions Involuntary euthanasia Involuntary euthanasia is conducted against the will of the patient Passive and active euthanasia Voluntary non voluntary and involuntary types can be further divided into passive or active variants 26 Passive euthanasia entails the withholding treatment necessary for the continuance of life 3 Active euthanasia entails the use of lethal substances or forces such as administering a lethal injection and is more controversial While some authors consider these terms to be misleading and unhelpful they are nonetheless commonly used In some cases such as the administration of increasingly necessary but toxic doses of painkillers there is a debate whether or not to regard the practice as active or passive 3 History The Death of Socrates by Jacques Louis David 1787 depicting Socrates preparing to drink hemlock following his conviction for corrupting the youth of Athens Euthanasia was practiced in Ancient Greece and Rome for example hemlock was employed as a means of hastening death on the island of Kea a technique also employed in Massalia Euthanasia in the sense of the deliberate hastening of a person s death was supported by Socrates Plato and Seneca the Elder in the ancient world although Hippocrates appears to have spoken against the practice writing I will not prescribe a deadly drug to please someone nor give advice that may cause his death noting there is some debate in the literature about whether or not this was intended to encompass euthanasia 27 28 29 Early modern period The term euthanasia in the earlier sense of supporting someone as they died was used for the first time by Francis Bacon In his work Euthanasia medica he chose this ancient Greek word and in doing so distinguished between euthanasia interior the preparation of the soul for death and euthanasia exterior which was intended to make the end of life easier and painless in exceptional circumstances by shortening life That the ancient meaning of an easy death came to the fore again in the early modern period can be seen from its definition in the 18th century Zedlers Universallexikon Euthanasia a very gentle and quiet death which happens without painful convulsions The word comes from ey bene well and 8anatos mors death 30 The concept of euthanasia in the sense of alleviating the process of death goes back to the medical historian Karl Friedrich Heinrich Marx who drew on Bacon s philosophical ideas According to Marx a doctor had a moral duty to ease the suffering of death through encouragement support and mitigation using medication Such an alleviation of death reflected the contemporary zeitgeist but was brought into the medical canon of responsibility for the first time by Marx Marx also stressed the distinction between the theological care of the soul of sick people from the physical care and medical treatment by doctors 31 32 Euthanasia in its modern sense has always been strongly opposed in the Judeo Christian tradition Thomas Aquinas opposed both and argued that the practice of euthanasia contradicted our natural human instincts of survival 33 as did Francois Ranchin 1565 1641 a French physician and professor of medicine and Michael Boudewijns 1601 1681 a physician and teacher 28 208 29 Other voices argued for euthanasia such as John Donne in 1624 34 and euthanasia continued to be practised In 1678 the publication of Caspar Questel s De pulvinari morientibus non subtrahend On the pillow of which the dying should not be deprived initiated debate on the topic Questel described various customs which were employed at the time to hasten the death of the dying including the sudden removal of a pillow which was believed to accelerate death and argued against their use as doing so was against the laws of God and Nature 28 209 211 This view was shared by others who followed including Philipp Jakob Spener Veit Riedlin and Johann Georg Krunitz 28 211 Despite opposition euthanasia continued to be practised involving techniques such as bleeding suffocation and removing people from their beds to be placed on the cold ground 28 211 214 Suicide and euthanasia became more accepted during the Age of Enlightenment 29 Thomas More wrote of euthanasia in Utopia although it is not clear if More was intending to endorse the practice 28 208 209 Other cultures have taken different approaches for example in Japan suicide has not traditionally been viewed as a sin as it is used in cases of honor and accordingly the perceptions of euthanasia are different from those in other parts of the world 35 Beginnings of the contemporary euthanasia debate In the mid 1800s the use of morphine to treat the pains of death emerged with John Warren recommending its use in 1848 A similar use of chloroform was revealed by Joseph Bullar in 1866 However in neither case was it recommended that the use should be to hasten death In 1870 Samuel Williams a schoolteacher initiated the contemporary euthanasia debate through a speech given at the Birmingham Speculative Club in England which was subsequently published in a one off publication entitled Essays of the Birmingham Speculative Club the collected works of a number of members of an amateur philosophical society 36 794 Williams proposal was to use chloroform to deliberately hasten the death of terminally ill patients That in all cases of hopeless and painful illness it should be the recognized duty of the medical attendant whenever so desired by the patient to administer chloroform or such other anaesthetic as may by and bye supersede chloroform so as to destroy consciousness at once and put the sufferer to a quick and painless death all needful precautions being adopted to prevent any possible abuse of such duty and means being taken to establish beyond the possibility of doubt or question that the remedy was applied at the express wish of the patient Samuel Williams 1872 Euthanasia Williams and Northgate London 36 794 The essay was favourably reviewed in The Saturday Review but an editorial against the essay appeared in The Spectator 37 From there it proved to be influential and other writers came out in support of such views Lionel Tollemache wrote in favour of euthanasia as did Annie Besant the essayist and reformer who later became involved with the National Secular Society considering it a duty to society to die voluntarily and painlessly when one reaches the point of becoming a burden 37 38 Popular Science analyzed the issue in May 1873 assessing both sides of the argument 39 Kemp notes that at the time medical doctors did not participate in the discussion it was essentially a philosophical enterprise tied inextricably to a number of objections to the Christian doctrine of the sanctity of human life 37 Early euthanasia movement in the United States Main article Euthanasia in the United States Felix Adler circa 1913 the first prominent American to argue for permitting suicide in cases of chronic illness The rise of the euthanasia movement in the United States coincided with the so called Gilded Age a time of social and technological change that encompassed an individualistic conservatism that praised laissez faire economics scientific method and rationalism along with major depressions industrialisation and conflict between corporations and labour unions 36 794 It was also the period in which the modern hospital system was developed which has been seen as a factor in the emergence of the euthanasia debate 40 Robert Ingersoll argued for euthanasia stating in 1894 that where someone is suffering from a terminal illness such as terminal cancer they should have a right to end their pain through suicide Felix Adler offered a similar approach although unlike Ingersoll Adler did not reject religion In fact he argued from an Ethical Culture framework In 1891 Adler argued that those suffering from overwhelming pain should have the right to commit suicide and furthermore that it should be permissible for a doctor to assist thus making Adler the first prominent American to argue for suicide in cases where people were suffering from chronic illness 41 Both Ingersoll and Adler argued for voluntary euthanasia of adults suffering from terminal ailments 41 Dowbiggin argues that by breaking down prior moral objections to euthanasia and suicide Ingersoll and Adler enabled others to stretch the definition of euthanasia 42 The first attempt to legalise euthanasia took place in the United States when Henry Hunt introduced legislation into the General Assembly of Ohio in 1906 43 614 Hunt did so at the behest of Anna Sophina Hall a wealthy heiress who was a major figure in the euthanasia movement during the early 20th century in the United States Hall had watched her mother die after an extended battle with liver cancer and had dedicated herself to ensuring that others would not have to endure the same suffering Towards this end she engaged in an extensive letter writing campaign recruited Lurana Sheldon and Maud Ballington Booth and organised a debate on euthanasia at the annual meeting of the American Humane Association in 1905 described by Jacob Appel as the first significant public debate on the topic in the 20th century 43 614 616 Hunt s bill called for the administration of an anesthetic to bring about a patient s death so long as the person is of lawful age and sound mind and was suffering from a fatal injury an irrevocable illness or great physical pain It also required that the case be heard by a physician required informed consent in front of three witnesses and required the attendance of three physicians who had to agree that the patient s recovery was impossible A motion to reject the bill outright was voted down but the bill failed to pass 79 to 23 36 796 43 618 619 Along with the Ohio euthanasia proposal in 1906 Assemblyman Ross Gregory introduced a proposal to permit euthanasia to the Iowa legislature However the Iowa legislation was broader in scope than that offered in Ohio It allowed for the death of any person of at least ten years of age who suffered from an ailment that would prove fatal and cause extreme pain should they be of sound mind and express a desire to artificially hasten their death In addition it allowed for infants to be euthanised if they were sufficiently deformed and permitted guardians to request euthanasia on behalf of their wards The proposed legislation also imposed penalties on physicians who refused to perform euthanasia when requested a 6 12 month prison term and a fine of between 200 and 1 000 The proposal proved to be controversial 43 619 621 It engendered considerable debate and failed to pass having been withdrawn from consideration after being passed to the Committee on Public Health 43 623 After 1906 the euthanasia debate reduced in intensity resurfacing periodically but not returning to the same level of debate until the 1930s in the United Kingdom 36 796 Euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin argues that the early membership of the Euthanasia Society of America ESA reflected how many perceived euthanasia at the time often seeing it as a eugenics matter rather than an issue concerning individual rights 41 Dowbiggin argues that not every eugenist joined the ESA solely for eugenic reasons but he postulates that there were clear ideological connections between the eugenics and euthanasia movements 41 1930s in Britain The Voluntary Euthanasia Legalisation Society was founded in 1935 by Charles Killick Millard now called Dignity in Dying The movement campaigned for the legalisation of euthanasia in Great Britain In January 1936 King George V was given a fatal dose of morphine and cocaine to hasten his death At the time he was suffering from cardio respiratory failure and the decision to end his life was made by his physician Lord Dawson 44 Although this event was kept a secret for over 50 years the death of George V coincided with proposed legislation in the House of Lords to legalise euthanasia 45 Nazi Euthanasia Program Main article Action T4 Hartheim Euthanasia Centre where over 18 000 people were killed A 24 July 1939 killing of a severely disabled infant in Nazi Germany was described in a BBC Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline as the first state sponsored euthanasia 46 Parties that consented to the killing included Hitler s office the parents and the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses 46 The Telegraph noted that the killing of the disabled infant whose name was Gerhard Kretschmar born blind with missing limbs subject to convulsions and reportedly an idiot provided the rationale for a secret Nazi decree that led to mercy killings of almost 300 000 mentally and physically handicapped people 47 While Kretchmar s killing received parental consent most of the 5 000 to 8 000 children killed afterwards were forcibly taken from their parents 46 47 The euthanasia campaign of mass murder gathered momentum on 14 January 1940 when the handicapped were killed with gas vans and at killing centres eventually leading to the deaths of 70 000 adult Germans 48 Professor Robert Jay Lifton author of The Nazi Doctors and a leading authority on the T4 program contrasts this program with what he considers to be a genuine euthanasia He explains that the Nazi version of euthanasia was based on the work of Adolf Jost who published The Right to Death Das Recht auf den Tod in 1895 Lifton writes Jost argued that control over the death of the individual must ultimately belong to the social organism the state This concept is in direct opposition to the Anglo American concept of euthanasia which emphasizes the individual s right to die or right to death or right to his or her own death as the ultimate human claim In contrast Jost was pointing to the state s right to kill Ultimately the argument was biological The rights to death are the key to the fitness of life The state must own death must kill in order to keep the social organism alive and healthy 49 In modern terms the use of euthanasia in the context of Action T4 is seen to be a euphemism to disguise a program of genocide in which people were killed on the grounds of disabilities religious beliefs and discordant individual values 50 Compared to the discussions of euthanasia that emerged post war the Nazi program may have been worded in terms that appear similar to the modern use of euthanasia but there was no mercy and the patients were not necessarily terminally ill 50 Despite these differences historian and euthanasia opponent Ian Dowbiggin writes that the origins of Nazi euthanasia like those of the American euthanasia movement predate the Third Reich and were intertwined with the history of eugenics and Social Darwinism and with efforts to discredit traditional morality and ethics 41 65 1949 New York State Petition for Euthanasia and Catholic opposition On 6 January 1949 the Euthanasia Society of America presented to the New York State Legislature a petition to legalize euthanasia signed by 379 leading Protestant and Jewish ministers the largest group of religious leaders ever to have taken this stance A similar petition had been sent to the New York Legislature in 1947 signed by approximately 1 000 New York physicians Roman Catholic religious leaders criticized the petition saying that such a bill would legalize a suicide murder pact and a rationalization of the fifth commandment of God Thou Shalt Not Kill 51 The Right Reverend Robert E McCormick stated that The ultimate object of the Euthanasia Society is based on the Totalitarian principle that the state is supreme and that the individual does not have the right to live if his continuance in life is a burden or hindrance to the state The Nazis followed this principle and compulsory Euthanasia was practiced as a part of their program during the recent war We American citizens of New York State must ask ourselves this question Are we going to finish Hitler s job 51 The petition brought tensions between the American Euthanasia Society and the Catholic Church to a head that contributed to a climate of anti Catholic sentiment generally regarding issues such as birth control eugenics and population control However the petition did not result in any legal changes 41 DebateHistorically the euthanasia debate has tended to focus on a number of key concerns According to euthanasia opponent Ezekiel Emanuel proponents of euthanasia have presented four main arguments a that people have a right to self determination and thus should be allowed to choose their own fate b assisting a subject to die might be a better choice than requiring that they continue to suffer c the distinction between passive euthanasia which is often permitted and active euthanasia which is not substantive or that the underlying principle the doctrine of double effect is unreasonable or unsound and d permitting euthanasia will not necessarily lead to unacceptable consequences Pro euthanasia activists often point to countries like the Netherlands and Belgium and states like Oregon where euthanasia has been legalized to argue that it is mostly unproblematic Similarly Emanuel argues that there are four major arguments presented by opponents of euthanasia a not all deaths are painful b alternatives such as cessation of active treatment combined with the use of effective pain relief are available c the distinction between active and passive euthanasia is morally significant and d legalising euthanasia will place society on a slippery slope 52 which will lead to unacceptable consequences 36 797 8 In fact in Oregon in 2013 pain was not one of the top five reasons people sought euthanasia Top reasons were a loss of dignity and a fear of burdening others 53 In the United States in 2013 47 nationwide supported doctor assisted suicide This included 32 of Latinos 29 of African Americans and almost nobody with disabilities 53 A 2015 Populus poll in the United Kingdom found broad public support for assisted dying 82 of people supported the introduction of assisted dying laws including 86 of people with disabilities 54 An alternative approach to the question is seen in the hospice movement which promotes palliative care for the dying and terminally ill This has pioneered the use of pain relieving drugs in a holistic atmosphere in which the patient s spiritual care ranks alongside physical care It intends neither to hasten nor postpone death 55 Legal statusThe examples and perspective in this section may not represent a worldwide view of the subject You may improve this section discuss the issue on the talk page or create a new section as appropriate November 2011 Learn how and when to remove this template message Main article Legality of euthanasia Current status of euthanasia around the world Active voluntary euthanasia legal Belgium Canada Colombia Luxembourg the Netherlands New Zealand Spain and the Australian states of New South Wales Queensland South Australia Tasmania Victoria and Western Australia Passive euthanasia legal refusal of treatment withdrawal of life support Active euthanasia illegal passive euthanasia not legislated or regulated All forms of euthanasia illegal West s Encyclopedia of American Law states that a mercy killing or euthanasia is generally considered to be a criminal homicide and is normally used as a synonym of homicide committed at a request made by the patient 56 57 The judicial sense of the term homicide includes any intervention undertaken with the express intention of ending a life even to relieve intractable suffering 58 57 59 Not all homicide is unlawful 60 Two designations of homicide that carry no criminal punishment are justifiable and excusable homicide 60 In most countries this is not the status of euthanasia The term euthanasia is usually confined to the active variety the University of Washington website states that euthanasia generally means that the physician would act directly for instance by giving a lethal injection to end the patient s life 61 Physician assisted suicide is thus not classified as euthanasia by the US State of Oregon where it is legal under the Oregon Death with Dignity Act and despite its name it is not legally classified as suicide either 62 Unlike physician assisted suicide withholding or withdrawing life sustaining treatments with patient consent voluntary is almost unanimously considered at least in the United States to be legal 63 The use of pain medication to relieve suffering even if it hastens death has been held as legal in several court decisions 61 Some governments around the world have legalized voluntary euthanasia but most commonly it is still considered to be criminal homicide In the Netherlands and Belgium where euthanasia has been legalized it still remains homicide although it is not prosecuted and not punishable if the perpetrator the doctor meets certain legal conditions 64 65 66 67 In a historic judgment the Supreme court of India legalized passive euthanasia The apex court remarked in the judgment that the Constitution of India values liberty dignity autonomy and privacy A bench headed by Chief Justice Dipak Misra delivered a unanimous judgment 68 Health professionals sentimentA 2010 survey in the United States of more than 10 000 physicians found that 16 3 of physicians would consider halting life sustaining therapy because the family demanded it even if they believed that it was premature Approximately 54 5 would not and the remaining 29 2 responded it depends 69 The study also found that 45 8 of physicians agreed that physician assisted suicide should be allowed in some cases 40 7 did not and the remaining 13 5 felt it depended 69 In the United Kingdom the assisted dying campaign group Dignity in Dying cites research in which 54 of general practitioners support or are neutral towards a law change on assisted dying 70 Similarly a 2017 Doctors net uk poll reported in the British Medical Journal stated that 55 of doctors believe assisted dying in defined circumstances should be legalised in the UK 71 Religious viewsMain article Religious views on euthanasia Christianity Broadly against The Roman Catholic Church condemns euthanasia and assisted suicide as morally wrong It states that intentional euthanasia whatever its forms or motives is murder It is gravely contrary to the dignity of the human person and to the respect due to the living God his Creator Because of this the practice is unacceptable within the Church citation needed The Orthodox Church in America along with other Eastern Orthodox Churches also opposes euthanasia stating that euthanasia is the deliberate cessation of human life and as such must be condemned as murder 72 Many non Catholic churches in the United States take a stance against euthanasia Among Protestant denominations the Episcopal Church passed a resolution in 1991 opposing euthanasia and assisted suicide stating that it is morally wrong and unacceptable to take a human life to relieve the suffering caused by incurable illnesses 72 Protestant and other non Catholic churches which oppose euthanasia include Assemblies of God 73 The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter day Saints 74 Church of the Nazarene 75 Evangelical Lutheran Church in America 76 Presbyterian Church in America 77 Lutheran Church Missouri Synod 78 Reformed Church in America 79 Salvation Army 80 Seventh day Adventist Church 73 Southern Baptist Convention 81 United Methodist Church 72 Partially in favor of The Church of England accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances but is strongly against active euthanasia and has led opposition against recent attempts to legalise it 82 The United Church of Canada accepts passive euthanasia under some circumstances but is in general against active euthanasia with growing acceptance now that active euthanasia has been partly legalised in Canada 83 Islam Euthanasia is a complex issue in Islamic theology however in general it is considered contrary to Islamic law and holy texts Among interpretations of the Qur an and Hadith the early termination of life is a crime be it by suicide or helping one commit suicide The various positions on the cessation of medical treatment are mixed and considered a different class of action than direct termination of life especially if the patient is suffering Suicide and euthanasia are both crimes in almost all Muslim majority countries 84 Judaism There is much debate on the topic of euthanasia in Judaic theology ethics and general opinion especially in Israel and the United States Passive euthanasia was declared legal by Israel s highest court under certain conditions and has reached some level of acceptance Active euthanasia remains illegal however the topic is actively under debate with no clear consensus through legal ethical theological and spiritual perspectives 85 See alsoAll pages with titles beginning with Euthanasia in lists many countries with notable positions All pages with titles beginning with Assisted suicide in lists some countries with notable positions List of deaths from legal euthanasia and assisted suicideAdvance healthcare directive Aruna Shanbaug case Terri Schiavo case Child euthanasia in Nazi Germany Coup de grace Dysthanasia Euthanasia and the slippery slope Euthanasia device Medical law Palliative sedation Principle of double effect Sarco podReferences Euthanasia Worldrtd net Archived from the original on 5 August 2017 Retrieved 6 July 2017 Philosopher Helga Kuhse Euthanasia is a compound of two Greek words eu and thanatos meaning literally a good death Today euthanasia is generally understood to mean the bringing about of a good death mercy killing where one person A ends the life of another person B for the sake of B Voluntary Euthanasia Voluntary Euthanasia Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Plato stanford edu Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 Retrieved 7 May 2019 When a person performs an act of euthanasia she brings about the death of another person because she believes the latter s present existence is so bad that he would be better off dead or believes that unless she intervenes and ends his life his life will very soon become so bad that he would be better off dead a b c d Harris NM October 2001 The euthanasia debate J R Army Med Corps 147 3 367 70 doi 10 1136 jramc 147 03 22 PMID 11766225 Euthanasia and assisted suicide Archived 19 July 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Last reviewed June 2011 Accessed 25 July 2011 Archived from the original Carr Claudia 2014 Unlocking Medical Law and Ethics 2nd ed Routledge p 374 ISBN 9781317743514 Retrieved 2 February 2018 Voluntary and involuntary euthanasia Archived 5 September 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 12 February 2012 Archived from the original Borry P Schotsmans P Dierickx K April 2006 Empirical research in bioethical journals A quantitative analysis J Med Ethics 32 4 240 45 doi 10 1136 jme 2004 011478 PMC 2565792 PMID 16574880 Philippe Letellier chapter History and Definition of a Word in Euthanasia Ethical and Human Aspects By Council of Europe Francis Bacon The Major Works by Francis Bacon edited by Brian Vickers p 630 Kohl Marvin 1974 The Morality of Killing New York Humanities Press p 94 ISBN 9780391001954 quoted in Beauchamp amp Davidson 1979 p 294 A similar definition is offered by Blackburn 1994 with the action of causing the quick and painless death of a person or not acting to prevent it when prevention was within the agent s powers a b c d e Beauchamp Tom L Davidson Arnold I 1979 The Definition of Euthanasia Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 4 3 294 312 doi 10 1093 jmp 4 3 294 PMID 501249 a b Draper Heather 1998 Euthanasia In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol 2 Academic Press euthanasia Oxford Dictionaries Oxford University Press April 2010 Archived from the original on 21 August 2011 Retrieved 26 April 2011 Kohl Marvin Kurtz Paul 1975 A Plea for Beneficient Euthanasia In Kohl Marvin ed Beneficient Euthanasia Buffalo New York Prometheus Books p 94 quoted in Beauchamp amp Davidson 1979 p 295 Wreen Michael 1988 The Definition of Euthanasia Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 4 637 53 639 doi 10 2307 2108012 JSTOR 2108012 PMID 11652547 Brody Baruch 1975 Voluntary Euthanasia and the Law In Kohl Marvin ed Beneficient Euthanasia Buffalo New York Prometheus Books p 94 quoted in Beauchamp amp Davidson 1979 p 295 Draper Heather 1998 Euthanasia In Chadwick Ruth ed Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics Vol 2 Academic Press p 176 Beauchamp Tom L Davidson Arnold I 1979 The Definition of Euthanasia Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 4 3 303 doi 10 1093 jmp 4 3 294 PMID 501249 Beauchamp Tom L Davidson Arnold I 1979 The Definition of Euthanasia Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 4 3 304 doi 10 1093 jmp 4 3 294 PMID 501249 Wreen Michael 1988 The Definition of Euthanasia Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 4 637 40 doi 10 2307 2108012 JSTOR 2108012 PMID 11652547 a b c Wreen Michael 1988 The Definition of Euthanasia Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 4 637 53 645 doi 10 2307 2108012 JSTOR 2108012 PMID 11652547 Materstvedt Lars Johan Clark David Ellershaw John Forde Reidun Boeck Gravgaard Anne Marie Muller Busch Christof Porta i Sales Josep Rapin Charles Henri 2003 Euthanasia and physician assisted suicide a view from an EAPC Ethics Task Force Palliative Medicine 17 2 97 101 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 514 5064 doi 10 1191 0269216303pm673oa PMID 12701848 S2CID 1498250 Perrett RW October 1996 Buddhism euthanasia and the sanctity of life J Med Ethics 22 5 309 13 doi 10 1136 jme 22 5 309 PMC 1377066 PMID 8910785 LaFollette Hugh 2002 Ethics in practice an anthology Oxford Blackwell pp 25 26 ISBN 978 0 631 22834 9 Wreen Michael 1988 The Definition of Euthanasia Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48 4 637 53 doi 10 2307 2108012 JSTOR 2108012 PMID 11652547 Rachels J January 1975 Active and passive euthanasia N Engl J Med 292 2 78 80 doi 10 1056 NEJM197501092920206 PMID 1109443 S2CID 46465710 Mystakidou Kyriaki Parpa Efi Tsilika Eleni Katsouda Emanuela Vlahos Lambros 2005 The Evolution of Euthanasia and Its Perceptions in Greek Culture and Civilization Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 48 1 97 98 doi 10 1353 pbm 2005 0013 PMID 15681882 S2CID 44600176 a b c d e f Stolberg Michael 2007 Active Euthanasia in Pre ModernSociety 1500 1800 Learned Debates and Popular Practices Social History of Medicine 20 2 206 07 doi 10 1093 shm hkm034 PMID 18605325 S2CID 6150428 a b c Gesundheit Benjamin Steinberg Avraham Glick Shimon Or Reuven Jotkovitz Alan 2006 Euthanasia An Overview and the Jewish Perspective Cancer Investigation 24 6 621 9 doi 10 1080 07357900600894898 PMID 16982468 S2CID 8906449 Zedlers Universallexikon Vol 08 p 1150 published 1732 54 Markwart Michler 1990 Marx Karl Mediziner Neue Deutsche Biographie in German vol 16 Berlin Duncker amp Humblot pp 327 328 full text online Helge Dvorak Biographisches Lexikon der Deutschen Burschenschaft Vol I Sub vol 4 Heidelberg 2000 pp 40 41 Historical Timeline History of Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide Archived 5 July 2012 at the Library of Congress Web Archives Euthanasia ProCon org Last updated on 23 July 2013 Retrieved 4 May 2014 Mannes Marya 1975 Euthanasia vs the Right to Life Baylor Law Review 27 69 Otani Izumi 2010 Good Manner of Dying as a Normative Concept Autocide Granny Dumping and Discussions on Euthanasia Death with Dignity in Japan International Journal of Japanese Sociology 19 1 49 63 doi 10 1111 j 1475 6781 2010 01136 x a b c d e f Emanuel Ezekiel 1994 The history of euthanasia debates in the United States and Britain Annals of Internal Medicine 121 10 796 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 732 724 doi 10 7326 0003 4819 121 10 199411150 00010 PMID 7944057 S2CID 20754659 a b c Nick Kemp 7 September 2002 Merciful Release Manchester University Press ISBN 978 0 7190 6124 0 OL 10531689M 0719061245 Ian Dowbiggin March 2007 A Concise History of Euthanasia Life Death God and Medicine Rowman amp Littlefield pp 51 62 64 ISBN 978 0 7425 3111 6 Corporation Bonnier May 1873 Popular Science a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help Pappas Demetra 1996 Recent historical perspectives regarding medical euthanasia and physician assisted suicide British Medical Bulletin 52 2 386 87 doi 10 1093 oxfordjournals bmb a011554 PMID 8759237 a b c d e f Dowbiggin Ian 2003 A merciful end the euthanasia movement in modern America Oxford University Press pp 10 13 ISBN 978 0 19 515443 6 Dowbiggin Ian 2003 A merciful end the euthanasia movement in modern America Oxford University Press p 13 ISBN 978 0 19 515443 6 a b c d e Appel Jacob 2004 A Duty to Kill A Duty to Die Rethinking the Euthanasia Controversy of 1906 Bulletin of the History of Medicine 78 3 610 34 doi 10 1353 bhm 2004 0106 PMID 15356372 S2CID 24991992 Ramsay J H R 28 May 2011 A king a doctor and a convenient death British Medical Journal 308 1445 1445 doi 10 1136 bmj 308 6941 1445 PMC 2540387 PMID 11644545 Gurney Edward 1972 Is There a Right to Die A Study of the Law of Euthanasia Cumberland Samford Law Review 3 237 a b c Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline 24 July 1939 Archived 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011 Quotation The first state sanctioned euthanasia is carried out after Hitler receives a petition from a child s parents asking for the life of their severely disabled infant to be ended This happens after the case has been considered by Hitler s office and by the Reich Committee for the Scientific Registration of Serious and Congenitally Based Illnesses whose experts have laid down the basis for the removal of disabled children to special paediatric clinics Here they can be either starved to death or given lethal injections At least 5 200 infants will eventually be killed through this programme a b Irene Zoech 11 October 2003 Named the baby boy who was Nazis first euthanasia victim Telegraph co uk Archived from the original on 8 September 2017 Retrieved 4 July 2017 Genocide Under the Nazis Timeline 14 January 1940 Archived 5 August 2011 at the Wayback Machine BBC Accessed 23 July 2011 Quotation The euthanasia campaign gathers momentum in Germany as six special killing centres and gas vans under an organisation code named T4 are used in the murder of handicapped adults Over 70 000 Germans will eventually be killed in this act of mass murder it is the first time poison bas will be used for such a purpose Basic Books 1986 46 a b Michalsen A Reinhart K September 2006 Euthanasia A confusing term abused under the Nazi regime and misused in present end of life debate Intensive Care Med 32 9 1304 10 doi 10 1007 s00134 006 0256 9 PMID 16826394 S2CID 21032497 a b The Moncton Transcript Ministers Ask Mercy Killing 6 January 1949 Wesley J Smith 1997 Forced Exit Forced exit ed New York Times Books ISBN 978 0 8129 2790 0 OL 1006883M 0812927907 a b The vulnerable will be the victims Opposing view Usatoday com Archived from the original on 9 September 2017 Retrieved 4 July 2017 Dignity in Dying Poll Populous PDF Archived from the original PDF on 8 November 2016 Retrieved 4 August 2018 Position statement on hospice care and assisted dying assisted suicide and recommendations PDF Hospice UK Retrieved 11 March 2021 West s Encyclopedia of American Law Vol 4 West Publishing Company 1998 p 24 ISBN 9780314201577 a b Carmen Tomas Y Valiente La regulacion de la eutanasia en Holanda Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales Num L Enero 1997 Harris N 1 October 2001 The Euthanasia Debate Journal of the Royal Army Medical Corps 147 3 367 370 doi 10 1136 jramc 147 03 22 PMID 11766225 S2CID 298551 Manoj Kumar Mohanty August 2004 Variants of homicide a review Journal of Clinical Forensic Medicine 11 4 214 18 doi 10 1016 j jcfm 2004 04 006 PMID 15363757 a b the definition of homicide Dictionary com Retrieved 4 July 2017 a b Physician Assisted Suicide Ethical Topic in Medicine depts washington edu Archived from the original on 13 April 2017 Retrieved 4 July 2017 Taylor Bill 7 July 2017 Physician Assisted Suicide PDF Archived from the original PDF on 4 December 2004 Retrieved 7 July 2017 Legal Aspects of Withholding and Withdrawing Life Support from Critically Ill Patients in the United States and Providing Palliative Care to Them Am J Respir Crit Care Med Volume 162 Number 6 December 2000 Archived 13 August 2003 at the Wayback Machine Oluyemisi Bamgbose 2004 Euthanasia Another Face of Murder International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology 48 1 111 21 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 631 618 doi 10 1177 0306624X03256662 PMID 14969121 S2CID 32664881 Concluding observations of the Human Rights Committee Netherlands 27 August 2001 Carmen Tomas Y Valiente La regulacion de la eutanasia en Holanda Anuario de Derecho Penal y Ciencias Penales Num L Enero 1997 R Cohen Almagor 2009 Belgian euthanasia law a critical analysis J Med Ethics 35 7 436 39 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 508 6943 doi 10 1136 jme 2008 026799 PMID 19567694 S2CID 44968015 Euthanasia and beyond on the Supreme Court s verdict SC Constitution Bench holds passive euthanasia living wills permissible The Hindu Karnataka 9 March 2018 Archived from the original on 5 June 2018 Retrieved 9 March 2018 a b Leslie Kane MA Exclusive Ethics Survey Results Doctors Struggle With Tougher Than Ever Dilemmas Medscape com Archived from the original on 14 August 2017 Retrieved 6 July 2017 Public opinion Dignity in Dying Retrieved 3 August 2018 Assisted dying case stronger than ever with majority of doctors now in support 7 February 2018 Retrieved 3 August 2018 a b c The Orthodox Christian view on Euthanasia www orthodoxchristian info Archived from the original on 12 August 2017 a b Assemblies of God USA Official Web Site Medical Euthanasia and Extraordinary Support to Sustain Life ag org Archived from the original on 14 August 2017 21 Selected Church Policies and Guidelines ChurchofJesusChrist org The Church of the Nazarene Doctrinal and Ethical Positions www crivoice org Archived from the original on 8 November 2017 Error PDF Archived PDF from the original on 18 April 2016 Retrieved 28 March 2018 What Are Christian Perspectives on Euthanasia and Physician Assisted Suicide Euthanasia ProCon org euthanasia procon org Archived from the original on 15 August 2017 LCMS Views Frequently Asked Questions The Lutheran Church Missouri Synod www lcms org Archived from the original on 14 August 2017 General Synod Statements Physician Assisted Suicide Reformed Church in America www rca org Archived from the original on 19 March 2017 The Salvation Army International Positional Statement Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide www salvationarmy org Archived from the original on 14 August 2017 Southern Baptist Convention gt Resolution on Euthanasia And Assisted Suicide www sbc net Archived from the original on 9 October 2017 Why the Church of England Supports the Current Law on Assisted Suicide Dr Brendan McCarthy Archbishops Council Church House London 2015 Submission to The Special Joint Committee on Physician Assisted Dying Rev Jordan Cantwell Moderator of The United Church of Canada 2016 Islamic Perspectives Euthanasia Qatl al raḥma Abulfadl Mohsin Ebrahim Journal of the Islamic Medical Association of North America 2007 Volume 4 Death and Euthanasia in Jewish Law Essays and Responses W Jacob and M Zemer Pitsburg and Tel Aviv Rodef Shalom Press 1995Further readingFry Revere Sigrid 2008 Euthanasia In Hamowy Ronald ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA SAGE Publications Cato Institute pp 156 58 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 n98 ISBN 978 1412965804 LCCN 2008009151 OCLC 750831024 Nitschke Philip Fiona Stewart Philip Nitschke Fiona Stewart 2006 The Peaceful Pill Handbook Exit International US Ltd ISBN 978 0 9788788 0 1 Rachels James 1986 The end of life Euthanasia and Morality Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 286070 5 Torr James D 2000 Euthanasia opposing viewpoints San Diego Greenhaven Press ISBN 978 0 7377 0127 2 External links Wikinews has news related to Euthanasia Media related to Euthanasia at Wikimedia Commons The dictionary definition of euthanasia at Wiktionary Quotations related to Euthanasia at Wikiquote Physician assisted death from The Hastings Center Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Euthanasia amp oldid 1143161277, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.