fbpx
Wikipedia

Étienne Bonnot de Condillac

Étienne Bonnot de Condillac (UK: /ˌɛtiˈɛn ˈbɒn də ˈkɒndiæk/ ET-ee-EN BON-oh də KON-dee-ak,[citation needed] French: [etjɛn bɔno kɔ̃dijak]; 30 September 1714 – 2 August[1] or 3 August[2][3] 1780) was a French philosopher, epistemologist, and Catholic priest, who studied in such areas as psychology and the philosophy of the mind.

Etienne Bonnot de Condillac
Etienne Bonnot de Condillac
Born(1714-09-30)30 September 1714
Died2 August 1780(1780-08-02) (aged 65)
EraModern philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolEmpiricism
Main interests
Psychology, philosophy of mind, epistemology

Biography edit

He was born at Grenoble into a legal family, the youngest of three brothers. His two older brothers Jean and Gabriel took names associated with one of the family's properties at Mably, Loire, and were each known as "Bonnot de Mably". Étienne identified with another property at Condillac, Drôme, was known as "Bonnot de Condillac". Like his brother Gabriel, Condillac took holy orders (1733–1740) at Saint-Sulpice church in Paris. He was appointed as Abbot of Mureau.[4]

 
Birthplace of de Condillac in 13 Grande Rue à Grenoble

Condillac devoted his whole life, with the exception of an interval as a court-appointed tutor to the court of Parma, to speculative thought. His works are:[4]

  • Essai sur l'origine des connaissances humaines (1746);
  • Traité des systèmes (1749);
  • Traité des sensations (1754);
  • Traité des animaux (1755);
  • a comprehensive Cours d'études (1767–1773) in 13 vols., written for the young Duke Ferdinand of Parma, a grandson of Louis XV;
  • Le Commerce et le gouvernement, considérés relativement l'un a l'autre (1776); and two posthumous works,
  • Logique (1781) and the unfinished Langue des calculs (1798).

In Paris, Condillac was involved with the circle of Denis Diderot, the philosopher who was co-contributor to the Encyclopédie. He developed a friendship with Jean-Jacques Rousseau, which lasted in some measure to the end of his life. It likely started when Rousseau was a tutor to two of his brother Jean's sons in Lyon[5]—Jean Bonnot de Mably was then provost of the police and known as Monsieur de Mably. Together with his brother Gabriel, who became the well-known political writer known as Abbé de Mably, Condillac introduced Rousseau to an intellectual circle.[citation needed]

Condillac's relations with unorthodox philosophers did not injure his career. He had already published several works when the French court sent him to Parma to educate the orphan duke, then a child of seven years.[6]

On his return from Italy, Condillac was elected to the Académie française in 1768. Contrary to the popular idea that he attended only one meeting, he was a frequent attendee until two years before his death. He spent his later years in retirement at Flux, a small property which he had purchased near Beaugency on the river Loire. He died there on 2[6][1] or 3[2][3] August 1780.

Work edit

Condillac is important both as a psychologist and as having established systematically in France the principles of John Locke. Voltaire had made the English philosopher fashionable. Condillac developed his concept of empirical sensationism, and demonstrated "lucidity, brevity, moderation, and an earnest striving after logical method."[6]

His first book, the Essai sur l'origine des connaissances humaines, keeps close to his English master. He accepts with some reluctance Locke's deduction of our knowledge from two sources, sensation and reflection. He uses as his main principle of explanation the association of ideas.[6]

His next book, the Traité des systèmes, is a vigorous criticism of those modern systems which are based upon abstract principles or upon unsound hypotheses. His polemic, which is inspired throughout by Locke, is directed against the innate ideas of the Cartesians, Malebranche's faculty-psychology, Leibniz's monadism and pre-established harmony, and, above all, against the conception of substance set forth in the first part of the Ethics of Baruch Spinoza.[6]

By far the most important of his works is the Traité des sensations, in which Condillac treats psychology in his own characteristic way. He questioned Locke's doctrine that the senses give us intuitive knowledge of objects, that the eye, for example, naturally judges shapes, sizes, positions, and distances. He believed it was necessary to study the senses separately, to distinguish precisely what ideas are owed to each sense, to observe how the senses are trained, and how one sense aids another. He believed that the conclusion has to be that all human faculty and knowledge are transformed sensation only, to the exclusion of any other principle, such as reflection.[6]

The author imagines a statue organized inwardly like a man, animated by a soul which has never received an idea, into which no sense-impression has ever penetrated. He unlocks its senses one by one, beginning with smell, as the sense that contributes least to human knowledge. At its first experience of smell, the consciousness of the statue is entirely occupied by it; and this occupancy of consciousness is attention. The statue's smell-experience will produce pleasure or pain; and pleasure and pain will thenceforward be the master-principle which, determining all the operations of its mind, will raise it by degrees to all the knowledge of which it is capable. The next stage is memory, which is the lingering impression of the smell experience upon the attention: "memory is nothing more than a mode of feeling." From memory springs comparison: the statue experiences the smell, say, of a rose, while remembering that of a carnation; and "comparison is nothing more than giving one's attention to two things simultaneously." And "as soon as the statue has comparison it has judgment." Comparisons and judgments become habitual, are stored in the mind and formed into series, and thus arises the powerful principle of the association of ideas. From comparison of past and present experiences in respect of their pleasure-giving quality arises desire; it is desire that determines the operation of our faculties, stimulates the memory and imagination, and gives rise to the passions. The passions, also, are nothing but sensation transformed.[6]

These indications will suffice to show the general course of the argument in the first section of the Traité des sensations. He thoroughly developed this idea through the subsequent chapters: "Of the Ideas of a Man limited to the Sense of Smell," "Of a Man limited to the Sense of Hearing," "Of Smell and Hearing combined," "Of Taste by itself, and of Taste combined with Smell and Hearing," "Of a Man limited to the Sense of Sight."[6]

In the second section of the treatise, Condillac invests his statue with the sense of touch, which first informs it of the existence of external objects. In a very careful and elaborate analysis, he distinguishes the various elements in our tactile experiences-the touching of one's own body, the touching of objects other than one's own body, the experience of movement, the exploration of surfaces by the hands: he traces the growth of the statue's perceptions of extension, distance and shape. The third section deals with the combination of touch with the other senses. The fourth section deals with the desires, activities and ideas of an isolated man who enjoys possession of all the senses; and ends with observations on a "wild boy" who was found living among bears in the forests of Lithuania.[6]

The conclusion of the whole work is that in the natural order of things, everything has its source in sensation, and yet that this source is not equally abundant in all men; men differ greatly in the degree of vividness with which they feel. Finally, he says that man is nothing but what he has acquired; all innate faculties and ideas are to be swept away. Modern theories of evolution and heredity have differed from this.[6]

Condillac's work on politics and history, in his Cours d'études, is considered of less interest. In logic, on which he wrote extensively, he is far less successful than in psychology. He enlarges with much iteration on the supremacy of the analytic method; argues that reasoning consists in the substitution of one proposition for another which is identical with it; and lays it down that science is the same thing as a well-constructed language, a proposition which in his Langue des calculs, he tries to prove by the example of arithmetic. His logic is limited by his study of sensations and lack of knowledge of science other than mathematics. He rejects the medieval apparatus of the syllogism; but is precluded by his standpoint from understanding the active, spiritual character of thought; nor had he that interest in natural science and appreciation of inductive reasoning which form the chief merit of J. S. Mill. Some might claim that Condillac's anti-spiritual psychology, with its explanation of personality as an aggregate of sensations, leads straight to atheism and determinism. However, he denies both these consequences. What he says upon religion is always in harmony with his profession; and he vindicated the freedom of the will in a dissertation that has very little in common with the Traité des sensations to which it is appended. The common reproach of materialism should certainly not be made against him. He always asserts the substantive reality of the soul; and in the opening words of his Essai, "Whether we rise to heaven, or descend to the abyss, we never get outside ourselves—it is always our own thoughts that we perceive," we have the subjectivist principle that forms the starting-point of Berkeley.[6]

Language edit

Condillac considered language as the vehicle by which senses and emotions were transformed into higher mental faculties. He believed that the structure of language reflects the structure of thought, and compared ideas to the sounds of a harpsichord. His theories had a major effect on the development of linguistics.[citation needed]

Condillac promoted "sensationalism," a theory that says all knowledge comes from the senses and there are no innate ideas. Condillac promoted an expressionist theory of linguistic creation that anticipates the prime features of later thoughts about language by German theorist Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803).[7]

Economics edit

Condillac's 'Le Commerce et le Gouvernement' (published in 1776, the same year as Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations) attempted to place economics in a coherent logical framework. He was a friend of François Quesnay – leader of the Physiocrats. Much of Condillac's work reflected mainstream Physiocrats, particularly his analysis of the structure of taxation and proposals for the revival of the economy, but he also proposed another line of argument, claiming that producers work to obtain utility. Most physiocrats rejected utility and the idea was ignored until his 'rediscovery' by Stanley Jevons and Carl Menger in 1871.[citation needed]

In his theory of "vrai prix" [true price], Condillac proposed a theory of human history divided into two phases: progress and decline. Progress is marked by a rational development and use of resources; decline is precipitated by bad behavior from the upper classes that then trickles down to the workers, encouraging excess, luxury, and false prices that harm the masses. Condillac saw the remedy to this as "vrai prix," a true price created by the unimpeded interaction of supply and demand, to be achieved by complete deregulation. People would be taught to work toward their best interest in an open market through a reshaping of their perceptions. By advocating of a free market economy in contrast to the prevailing contemporary policy of state control in France, Condillac influenced classical liberal economics.[8]

History edit

Condillac's Histoire ancienne and Histoire moderne (1758–1767) demonstrated how the experience and observation of the past aided man. History was not a mere retelling of the past, but a source of information and inspiration as well. Reason and critical thinking can improve man's lot and destroy superstition and fanaticism. History thus served as a moral, political, and philosophical textbook which taught man to live better. Thus the two histories present the basic program of the Enlightenment in crystallized form.[citation needed]

Legacy edit

As was fitting to a disciple of Locke, Condillac's ideas have had most importance in their effect upon English thought. In matters connected with the association of ideas, the supremacy of pleasure and pain, and the general explanation of all mental contents as sensations or transformed sensations, his influence can be traced upon the Mills and upon Bain and Herbert Spencer. And, apart from any definite propositions, Condillac did a notable work in the direction of making psychology a science; it is a great step from the desultory, genial observation of Locke to the rigorous analysis of Condillac, short-sighted and defective as that analysis may seem to us in the light of fuller knowledge.[9]

His method, however, of imaginative reconstruction was by no means suited to English ways of thinking. In spite of his protests against abstraction, hypothesis and synthesis, his allegory of the statue is in the highest degree abstract, hypothetical and synthetic. James Mill, who stood more by the study of concrete realities, put Condillac into the hands of his youthful son with the warning that here was an example of what to avoid in the method of psychology. A modern historian has compared[10] Condillac with Scottish Enlightenment philosopher and pre-evolutionary thinker Lord Monboddo, who had a similar fascination with abstraction and ideas. In France Condillac's doctrine, so congenial to the tone of 18th century philosophism, reigned in the schools for over fifty years, challenged only by a few who, like Maine de Biran, saw that it gave no sufficient account of volitional experience. Early in the 19th century, the romantic awakening of Germany had spread to France, and sensationism was displaced by the eclectic spiritualism of Victor Cousin.[11]

Condillac's collected works were published in 1798 (23 vols.) and two or three times subsequently; the last edition (1822) has an introductory dissertation by A. F. Théry. The Encyclopédie méthodique has a very long article on Condillac by Naigeon. Biographical details and criticism of the Traité des systèmes in J. P. Damiron's Mémoires pour servir a l'histoire de to philosophie au dixhuitieme siècle, tome iii.; a full criticism in V Cousin's Cours de l'histoire de la philosophie moderne, ser. i. tome iii. Consult also F Rethoré, Condillac ou l'empirisme et le rationalisme (1864); L Dewaule, Condillac et la psychologie anglaise contemporaine (1891); histories of philosophy.[11]

In Condillac's statue, a chapter in A Mind So Rare: The evolution of human consciousness, psychologist and cognitive neuroscientist Merlin Donald argues that Condillac was the first constructivist.[12]

In the short story "Condillac's Statue, or Wrens in his Head", science fiction writer R. A. Lafferty brings the allegory of Condillac's statue to life, having Condillac build the statue in a park in the French countryside, and then slowly turning the statue's senses on one at a time.

Works edit

  • M. l'Abbé de Condillac (1786). Le commerce et le gouvernement considérés relativement l'un à l'autre (in French). Amsterdam: Jombert & Cellot. Retrieved 5 March 2015.
  • M. l'Abbé de Condillac (1780). La logique, ou Les premiers développements de l'art de penser (in French). Paris. Retrieved 5 March 2015.
  • Condillac (1947–1951). Le Roy, Georges (ed.). Œuvres philosophiques de Condillac. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
  • Etienne Bonnot, Abbé de Condillac (1987). Philosophical Writings of Etienne Bonnot, Abbé de Condillac. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum.

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b "Étienne Bonnot de Condillac (1714-1780)". data.bnf.fr.
  2. ^ a b "CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Etienne Bonnot de Condillac". www.newadvent.org. Retrieved 2 August 2020.
  3. ^ a b Falkenstein, Lorne; Grandi, Giovanni (2017). "Étienne Bonnot de Condillac". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 2 August 2020.
  4. ^ a b Sturt 1911, p. 849.
  5. ^ Sturt 1911, pp. 849–850.
  6. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Sturt 1911, p. 850.
  7. ^ George Albert Wells, The Origin of Language: Aspects of the Discussion from Condillac to Wundt (1987)
  8. ^ Orain (2006)
  9. ^ Sturt 1911, pp. 850–851.
  10. ^ Hobbs, Catherine, Rhetoric on the Margin of Modernity, Vico, Condillac, Monboddo, Southern Illinois University Press, Carbondale, Illinois (2002)
  11. ^ a b Sturt 1911, p. 851.
  12. ^ Donald, Merlin (2002). A mind so rare : the evolution of human consciousness. New York: Norton. ISBN 978-0-393-32319-1. OCLC 53438156.

References edit

Further reading edit

  • Hine, Ellen McNiven (1979). A Critical Study of Condillac's Traité des Systèmes. Dordrecht: Springer. ISBN 978-94-009-9291-7.
  • Knight, Isabel F. (1968). The Geometric Spirit: The Abbe de Condillac and the French Enlightenment. New Haven: Yale University Press.
  • Orain, Arnaud. "Directing or Reforming Behaviors? A Discussion of Condillac's Theory of 'Vrai Prix'." History of Political Economy 2006 38(3): 497–530.

External links edit

  • Falkenstein, Lorne; Grandi, Giovanni. "Étienne Bonnot de Condillac". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • "Etienne Bonnot de Condillac" . Catholic Encyclopedia. 1913.
  • Étienne Bonnot de Condillac, An Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge, Being a Supplement to Mr. Locke's Essay on the Human Understanding, Translated by Thomas Nugent (London: J. Nourse, 1756). Facsimile ed., introd. Robert G. Weyant, 1971, Scholars' Facsimiles & Reprints, ISBN 978-0-8201-1090-5.
  • Traité de l'art d'écrire correctement la langue française (Paris: Dufart, 1812)
  •   Media related to Étienne Bonnot de Condillac at Wikimedia Commons

Étienne, bonnot, condillac, citation, needed, french, etjɛn, bɔno, dijak, september, 1714, august, august, 1780, french, philosopher, epistemologist, catholic, priest, studied, such, areas, psychology, philosophy, mind, etienne, bonnot, condillacetienne, bonno. Etienne Bonnot de Condillac UK ˌ ɛ t i ˈ ɛ n ˈ b ɒ n oʊ d e ˈ k ɒ n d i ae k ET ee EN BON oh de KON dee ak citation needed French etjɛn bɔno de kɔ dijak 30 September 1714 2 August 1 or 3 August 2 3 1780 was a French philosopher epistemologist and Catholic priest who studied in such areas as psychology and the philosophy of the mind Etienne Bonnot de CondillacEtienne Bonnot de CondillacBorn 1714 09 30 30 September 1714Grenoble Kingdom of FranceDied2 August 1780 1780 08 02 aged 65 Lailly en Val Kingdom of FranceEraModern philosophy Age of EnlightenmentRegionWestern philosophy French philosophySchoolEmpiricismMain interestsPsychology philosophy of mind epistemology Contents 1 Biography 2 Work 3 Language 4 Economics 5 History 6 Legacy 7 Works 8 Notes 9 References 10 Further reading 11 External linksBiography editHe was born at Grenoble into a legal family the youngest of three brothers His two older brothers Jean and Gabriel took names associated with one of the family s properties at Mably Loire and were each known as Bonnot de Mably Etienne identified with another property at Condillac Drome was known as Bonnot de Condillac Like his brother Gabriel Condillac took holy orders 1733 1740 at Saint Sulpice church in Paris He was appointed as Abbot of Mureau 4 nbsp Birthplace of de Condillac in 13 Grande Rue a Grenoble Condillac devoted his whole life with the exception of an interval as a court appointed tutor to the court of Parma to speculative thought His works are 4 Essai sur l origine des connaissances humaines 1746 Traite des systemes 1749 Traite des sensations 1754 Traite des animaux 1755 a comprehensive Cours d etudes 1767 1773 in 13 vols written for the young Duke Ferdinand of Parma a grandson of Louis XV Le Commerce et le gouvernement consideres relativement l un a l autre 1776 and two posthumous works Logique 1781 and the unfinished Langue des calculs 1798 In Paris Condillac was involved with the circle of Denis Diderot the philosopher who was co contributor to the Encyclopedie He developed a friendship with Jean Jacques Rousseau which lasted in some measure to the end of his life It likely started when Rousseau was a tutor to two of his brother Jean s sons in Lyon 5 Jean Bonnot de Mably was then provost of the police and known as Monsieur de Mably Together with his brother Gabriel who became the well known political writer known as Abbe de Mably Condillac introduced Rousseau to an intellectual circle citation needed Condillac s relations with unorthodox philosophers did not injure his career He had already published several works when the French court sent him to Parma to educate the orphan duke then a child of seven years 6 On his return from Italy Condillac was elected to the Academie francaise in 1768 Contrary to the popular idea that he attended only one meeting he was a frequent attendee until two years before his death He spent his later years in retirement at Flux a small property which he had purchased near Beaugency on the river Loire He died there on 2 6 1 or 3 2 3 August 1780 Work editCondillac is important both as a psychologist and as having established systematically in France the principles of John Locke Voltaire had made the English philosopher fashionable Condillac developed his concept of empirical sensationism and demonstrated lucidity brevity moderation and an earnest striving after logical method 6 His first book the Essai sur l origine des connaissances humaines keeps close to his English master He accepts with some reluctance Locke s deduction of our knowledge from two sources sensation and reflection He uses as his main principle of explanation the association of ideas 6 His next book the Traite des systemes is a vigorous criticism of those modern systems which are based upon abstract principles or upon unsound hypotheses His polemic which is inspired throughout by Locke is directed against the innate ideas of the Cartesians Malebranche s faculty psychology Leibniz s monadism and pre established harmony and above all against the conception of substance set forth in the first part of the Ethics of Baruch Spinoza 6 By far the most important of his works is the Traite des sensations in which Condillac treats psychology in his own characteristic way He questioned Locke s doctrine that the senses give us intuitive knowledge of objects that the eye for example naturally judges shapes sizes positions and distances He believed it was necessary to study the senses separately to distinguish precisely what ideas are owed to each sense to observe how the senses are trained and how one sense aids another He believed that the conclusion has to be that all human faculty and knowledge are transformed sensation only to the exclusion of any other principle such as reflection 6 The author imagines a statue organized inwardly like a man animated by a soul which has never received an idea into which no sense impression has ever penetrated He unlocks its senses one by one beginning with smell as the sense that contributes least to human knowledge At its first experience of smell the consciousness of the statue is entirely occupied by it and this occupancy of consciousness is attention The statue s smell experience will produce pleasure or pain and pleasure and pain will thenceforward be the master principle which determining all the operations of its mind will raise it by degrees to all the knowledge of which it is capable The next stage is memory which is the lingering impression of the smell experience upon the attention memory is nothing more than a mode of feeling From memory springs comparison the statue experiences the smell say of a rose while remembering that of a carnation and comparison is nothing more than giving one s attention to two things simultaneously And as soon as the statue has comparison it has judgment Comparisons and judgments become habitual are stored in the mind and formed into series and thus arises the powerful principle of the association of ideas From comparison of past and present experiences in respect of their pleasure giving quality arises desire it is desire that determines the operation of our faculties stimulates the memory and imagination and gives rise to the passions The passions also are nothing but sensation transformed 6 These indications will suffice to show the general course of the argument in the first section of the Traite des sensations He thoroughly developed this idea through the subsequent chapters Of the Ideas of a Man limited to the Sense of Smell Of a Man limited to the Sense of Hearing Of Smell and Hearing combined Of Taste by itself and of Taste combined with Smell and Hearing Of a Man limited to the Sense of Sight 6 In the second section of the treatise Condillac invests his statue with the sense of touch which first informs it of the existence of external objects In a very careful and elaborate analysis he distinguishes the various elements in our tactile experiences the touching of one s own body the touching of objects other than one s own body the experience of movement the exploration of surfaces by the hands he traces the growth of the statue s perceptions of extension distance and shape The third section deals with the combination of touch with the other senses The fourth section deals with the desires activities and ideas of an isolated man who enjoys possession of all the senses and ends with observations on a wild boy who was found living among bears in the forests of Lithuania 6 The conclusion of the whole work is that in the natural order of things everything has its source in sensation and yet that this source is not equally abundant in all men men differ greatly in the degree of vividness with which they feel Finally he says that man is nothing but what he has acquired all innate faculties and ideas are to be swept away Modern theories of evolution and heredity have differed from this 6 Condillac s work on politics and history in his Cours d etudes is considered of less interest In logic on which he wrote extensively he is far less successful than in psychology He enlarges with much iteration on the supremacy of the analytic method argues that reasoning consists in the substitution of one proposition for another which is identical with it and lays it down that science is the same thing as a well constructed language a proposition which in his Langue des calculs he tries to prove by the example of arithmetic His logic is limited by his study of sensations and lack of knowledge of science other than mathematics He rejects the medieval apparatus of the syllogism but is precluded by his standpoint from understanding the active spiritual character of thought nor had he that interest in natural science and appreciation of inductive reasoning which form the chief merit of J S Mill Some might claim that Condillac s anti spiritual psychology with its explanation of personality as an aggregate of sensations leads straight to atheism and determinism However he denies both these consequences What he says upon religion is always in harmony with his profession and he vindicated the freedom of the will in a dissertation that has very little in common with the Traite des sensations to which it is appended The common reproach of materialism should certainly not be made against him He always asserts the substantive reality of the soul and in the opening words of his Essai Whether we rise to heaven or descend to the abyss we never get outside ourselves it is always our own thoughts that we perceive we have the subjectivist principle that forms the starting point of Berkeley 6 Language editCondillac considered language as the vehicle by which senses and emotions were transformed into higher mental faculties He believed that the structure of language reflects the structure of thought and compared ideas to the sounds of a harpsichord His theories had a major effect on the development of linguistics citation needed Condillac promoted sensationalism a theory that says all knowledge comes from the senses and there are no innate ideas Condillac promoted an expressionist theory of linguistic creation that anticipates the prime features of later thoughts about language by German theorist Johann Gottfried Herder 1744 1803 7 Economics editCondillac s Le Commerce et le Gouvernement published in 1776 the same year as Adam Smith s Wealth of Nations attempted to place economics in a coherent logical framework He was a friend of Francois Quesnay leader of the Physiocrats Much of Condillac s work reflected mainstream Physiocrats particularly his analysis of the structure of taxation and proposals for the revival of the economy but he also proposed another line of argument claiming that producers work to obtain utility Most physiocrats rejected utility and the idea was ignored until his rediscovery by Stanley Jevons and Carl Menger in 1871 citation needed In his theory of vrai prix true price Condillac proposed a theory of human history divided into two phases progress and decline Progress is marked by a rational development and use of resources decline is precipitated by bad behavior from the upper classes that then trickles down to the workers encouraging excess luxury and false prices that harm the masses Condillac saw the remedy to this as vrai prix a true price created by the unimpeded interaction of supply and demand to be achieved by complete deregulation People would be taught to work toward their best interest in an open market through a reshaping of their perceptions By advocating of a free market economy in contrast to the prevailing contemporary policy of state control in France Condillac influenced classical liberal economics 8 History editCondillac s Histoire ancienne and Histoire moderne 1758 1767 demonstrated how the experience and observation of the past aided man History was not a mere retelling of the past but a source of information and inspiration as well Reason and critical thinking can improve man s lot and destroy superstition and fanaticism History thus served as a moral political and philosophical textbook which taught man to live better Thus the two histories present the basic program of the Enlightenment in crystallized form citation needed Legacy editAs was fitting to a disciple of Locke Condillac s ideas have had most importance in their effect upon English thought In matters connected with the association of ideas the supremacy of pleasure and pain and the general explanation of all mental contents as sensations or transformed sensations his influence can be traced upon the Mills and upon Bain and Herbert Spencer And apart from any definite propositions Condillac did a notable work in the direction of making psychology a science it is a great step from the desultory genial observation of Locke to the rigorous analysis of Condillac short sighted and defective as that analysis may seem to us in the light of fuller knowledge 9 His method however of imaginative reconstruction was by no means suited to English ways of thinking In spite of his protests against abstraction hypothesis and synthesis his allegory of the statue is in the highest degree abstract hypothetical and synthetic James Mill who stood more by the study of concrete realities put Condillac into the hands of his youthful son with the warning that here was an example of what to avoid in the method of psychology A modern historian has compared 10 Condillac with Scottish Enlightenment philosopher and pre evolutionary thinker Lord Monboddo who had a similar fascination with abstraction and ideas In France Condillac s doctrine so congenial to the tone of 18th century philosophism reigned in the schools for over fifty years challenged only by a few who like Maine de Biran saw that it gave no sufficient account of volitional experience Early in the 19th century the romantic awakening of Germany had spread to France and sensationism was displaced by the eclectic spiritualism of Victor Cousin 11 Condillac s collected works were published in 1798 23 vols and two or three times subsequently the last edition 1822 has an introductory dissertation by A F Thery The Encyclopedie methodique has a very long article on Condillac by Naigeon Biographical details and criticism of the Traite des systemes in J P Damiron s Memoires pour servir a l histoire de to philosophie au dixhuitieme siecle tome iii a full criticism in V Cousin s Cours de l histoire de la philosophie moderne ser i tome iii Consult also F Rethore Condillac ou l empirisme et le rationalisme 1864 L Dewaule Condillac et la psychologie anglaise contemporaine 1891 histories of philosophy 11 In Condillac s statue a chapter in A Mind So Rare The evolution of human consciousness psychologist and cognitive neuroscientist Merlin Donald argues that Condillac was the first constructivist 12 In the short story Condillac s Statue or Wrens in his Head science fiction writer R A Lafferty brings the allegory of Condillac s statue to life having Condillac build the statue in a park in the French countryside and then slowly turning the statue s senses on one at a time Works editM l Abbe de Condillac 1786 Le commerce et le gouvernement consideres relativement l un a l autre in French Amsterdam Jombert amp Cellot Retrieved 5 March 2015 M l Abbe de Condillac 1780 La logique ou Les premiers developpements de l art de penser in French Paris Retrieved 5 March 2015 Condillac 1947 1951 Le Roy Georges ed Œuvres philosophiques de Condillac Paris Presses Universitaires de France Etienne Bonnot Abbe de Condillac 1987 Philosophical Writings of Etienne Bonnot Abbe de Condillac Hillsdale Lawrence Erlbaum Notes edit a b Etienne Bonnot de Condillac 1714 1780 data bnf fr a b CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA Etienne Bonnot de Condillac www newadvent org Retrieved 2 August 2020 a b Falkenstein Lorne Grandi Giovanni 2017 Etienne Bonnot de Condillac The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Retrieved 2 August 2020 a b Sturt 1911 p 849 Sturt 1911 pp 849 850 a b c d e f g h i j k Sturt 1911 p 850 George Albert Wells The Origin of Language Aspects of the Discussion from Condillac to Wundt 1987 Orain 2006 Sturt 1911 pp 850 851 Hobbs Catherine Rhetoric on the Margin of Modernity Vico Condillac Monboddo Southern Illinois University Press Carbondale Illinois 2002 a b Sturt 1911 p 851 Donald Merlin 2002 A mind so rare the evolution of human consciousness New York Norton ISBN 978 0 393 32319 1 OCLC 53438156 References edit nbsp This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Sturt Henry 1911 Condillac Etienne Bonnot de In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 6 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 849 851 Further reading editHine Ellen McNiven 1979 A Critical Study of Condillac s Traite des Systemes Dordrecht Springer ISBN 978 94 009 9291 7 Knight Isabel F 1968 The Geometric Spirit The Abbe de Condillac and the French Enlightenment New Haven Yale University Press Orain Arnaud Directing or Reforming Behaviors A Discussion of Condillac s Theory of Vrai Prix History of Political Economy 2006 38 3 497 530 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Etienne Bonnot de Condillac Falkenstein Lorne Grandi Giovanni Etienne Bonnot de Condillac In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Etienne Bonnot de Condillac Catholic Encyclopedia 1913 Etienne Bonnot de Condillac An Essay on the Origin of Human Knowledge Being a Supplement to Mr Locke s Essay on the Human Understanding Translated by Thomas Nugent London J Nourse 1756 Facsimile ed introd Robert G Weyant 1971 Scholars Facsimiles amp Reprints ISBN 978 0 8201 1090 5 Traite de l art d ecrire correctement la langue francaise Paris Dufart 1812 nbsp Media related to Etienne Bonnot de Condillac at Wikimedia Commons Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Etienne Bonnot de Condillac amp oldid 1219336636, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.