fbpx
Wikipedia

Gorgias

Gorgias (/ˈɡɔːriəs/;[1] Greek: Γοργίας; 483–375 BC)[2] was an ancient Greek sophist, pre-Socratic philosopher, and rhetorician who was a native of Leontinoi in Sicily. Along with Protagoras, he forms the first generation of Sophists. Several doxographers report that he was a pupil of Empedocles, although he would only have been a few years younger. W. K. C. Guthrie writes that "Like other Sophists, he was an itinerant that practiced in various cities and giving public exhibitions of his skill at the great pan-Hellenic centers of Olympia and Delphi, and charged fees for his instruction and performances. A special feature of his displays was to ask miscellaneous questions from the audience and give impromptu replies."[3] He has been called "Gorgias the Nihilist" although the degree to which this epithet adequately describes his philosophy is controversial.[4][5][6][7]

Gorgias
Born483 BC
Leontinoi, Sicily
(today Lentini, Italy)
Died375 BC
EraPre-Socratic philosophy
RegionWestern philosophy
SchoolSophists
Main interests
Ontology, epistemology, rhetoric, moral relativism

Prominent among his claims to recognition is that he transplanted rhetoric from his native Sicily to Attica, and contributed to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose.[8]

Life edit

class=notpageimage|
Map of the Mediterranean showing locations associated with Gorgias

Gorgias was born c. 483 BC in Leontinoi, a Chalcidian colony in eastern Sicily that was allied with Athens.[9] His father's name was Charmantides.[9] He had a brother named Herodicus, who was a physician, and sometimes accompanied him during his travels.[10] He also had a sister, whose name is not known, but whose grandson dedicated a golden statue to his great uncle at Delphi.[11] It is not known whether Gorgias married or had children.[11] Gorgias is said to have studied under the Sicilian philosopher Empedocles of Acragas (c. 490 – c. 430 BC), but it is not known when, where, for how long, or in what capacity.[11] He may have also studied under the rhetoricians Corax of Syracuse and Tisias,[11] but very little is known about either of these men, nor is anything known about their relationship with Gorgias.[11]

It is not known what kind of role Gorgias may have played in the politics in his native Leontinoi,[11] but it is known that, in 427 BC, when he was around sixty years old, he was sent to Athens by his fellow-citizens as the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of the Syracusans.[11] After 427 BC, Gorgias appears to have settled in mainland Greece, living at various points in a number of city-states, including Athens and Larisa.[11] He was well known for delivering orations at Panhellenic Festivals and is described as having been "conspicuous" at Olympia.[11] There is no surviving record of any role he might have played in organizing the festivals themselves.[11]

Gorgias's primary occupation was as a teacher of rhetoric.[11] According to Aristotle, his students included Isocrates.[12] (Other students are named in later traditions; the Suda adds Pericles, Polus, and Alcidamas,[13] Diogenes Laërtius mentions Antisthenes,[14] and according to Philostratus, "I understand that he attracted the attention of the most admired men, Critias and Alcibiades who were young, and Thucydides and Pericles who were already old. Agathon too, the tragic poet, whom Comedy regards as wise and eloquent, often Gorgianizes in his iambic verse").[15] Additionally, although they are not described as his students, Gorgias is widely thought to have influenced the styles of the historian Thucydides, the tragic playwright Agathon, the doctor Hippocrates, the rhetorician Alcidamas, and the poet and commentator Lycophron.[11]

Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be one hundred and eight years old (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He won admiration for his ability to speak on any subject (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He accumulated considerable wealth; enough to commission a gold statue of himself for a public temple.[16] After his Pythian Oration, the Greeks installed a solid gold statue of him in the temple of Apollo at Delphi (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). He died at Larissa in Thessaly.

Philosophy edit

The philosophies of the pre-Socratic Greek Sophists are controversial among scholars in general, due to their highly subtle and ambiguous writings and also to the fact that they are best known as characters in Plato's dialogues.[17][18] Gorgias, however, is particularly frustrating for modern scholars to attempt to understand.[17] While scholars debate the precise subtleties of the teachings of Protagoras, Hippias, and Prodicus, they generally agree on the basic frameworks of what these thinkers believed.[19] With Gorgias, however, scholars widely disagree on even the most basic framework of his ideas, including over whether or not that framework even existed at all.[19] The greatest hindrance to scholarly understanding of Gorgias's philosophy is that the vast majority of his writings have been lost[20] and those that have survived have suffered considerable alteration by later copyists.[21]

These difficulties are further compounded by the fact that Gorgias's rhetoric is frequently elusive and confusing;[22] he makes many of his most important points using elaborate, but highly ambiguous, metaphors, similes, and puns.[23] Many of Gorgias's propositions are also thought to be sarcastic, playful, or satirical.[9] In his treatise On Rhetoric, Aristotle characterizes Gorgias's style of oratory as "pervasively ironic" and states that Gorgias recommended responding to seriousness with jests and to jests with seriousness.[9] Gorgias frequently blurs the lines between serious philosophical discourse and satire,[9] which makes it extremely difficult for scholars to tell when he is being serious and when he is merely joking.[17] Gorgias frequently contradicts his own statements and adopts inconsistent perspectives on different issues.[19] As a result of all these factors, Scott Porter Consigny calls him "perhaps the most elusive of the polytropic quarry hunted in Plato's Sophist.[19]

Gorgias has been labelled "The Nihilist"[4][5][6][24][25] because some scholars have interpreted his thesis on "the non-existent" to be an argument against the existence of anything that is straightforwardly endorsed by Gorgias himself.[26] According to Alan Pratt, nihilism is "the belief that all values are baseless and that nothing can be known or communicated." It is associated with pessimism and a radical skepticism that condemns existence.[27]

Gorgias presented his nihilist arguments in On Non-Existence; however, the original text is no longer extant. We only know his arguments through commentary by Sextus Empiricus and Pseudo-Aristotle's De Melisso, Xenophane, Gorgia.[28] Ostensibly Gorgias developed three sequential arguments: first, that nothing exists; second, that even if existence exists, it is inapprehensible to humans; and third, that even if existence is apprehensible, it certainly cannot be communicated or interpreted to one's neighbors.

That being said, there is consensus in late 20th century and early 21st century scholarship that the label 'nihilist' is misleading, in part because if his argument were genuinely meant to support nihilism it would be self-undermining. The argument, of course, is itself something, and has pretensions to communicate knowledge, in conflict with its explicit pronouncement that there is nothing and that it can't be known or communicated. Gisela Striker argues: "I find it hard to believe that anyone should ever have thought that Gorgias seriously advocated the view that nothing is and that he was, therefore, a 'nihilist.'[29] Similarly Caston states: "Gorgias would have to be not merely disconsolate, but quite dull-witted, to have missed the conflict between his presentation and its content".[30] Finally, Wardy says, "This sadly mistaken reading overlooks the most obvious consequence of Gorgias' paradoxologia (παραδοξολογία): his message refutes itself, and in consequence, so far from constituting a theory of logos, it confronts us with a picture of what language cannot be, with what it cannot be assumed to aspire to be."[31] Gigon and Newiger make similar points.[32][33]

Rhetorical innovation edit

Gorgias ushered in rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation, and he introduced paradoxologia – the idea of paradoxical thought and paradoxical expression. For these advancements, Gorgias has been labeled the "father of sophistry" (Wardy 6). Gorgias is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the Attic Greek dialect as the language of literary prose.[8] Gorgias was the first orator known to develop and teach a "distinctive style of speaking" (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33).

Gorgias' extant rhetorical works – Encomium of Helen (Ἑλένης ἐγκώμιον), Defense of Palamedes (Ὑπέρ Παλαμήδους ἀπολογία), On Non-Existence (Περὶ τοῦ μὴ ὄντος ἢ Περὶ φύσεως), and Epitaphios (Επιτάφιος) – come to us via a work entitled Technai (Τέχναι), a manual of rhetorical instruction, which may have consisted of models to be memorized and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice (Leitch, et al. 29). Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements, the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up-and-coming theory and art (technē) of rhetoric (McComiskey 32). Of Gorgias' surviving works, only the Encomium and the Defense are believed to exist in their entirety. Meanwhile, there are his own speeches, rhetorical, political, or other. A number of these are referred to and quoted by Aristotle, including a speech on Hellenic unity, a funeral oration for Athenians fallen in war, and a brief quotation from an Encomium on the Eleans. Apart from the speeches, there are paraphrases of the treatise "On Nature or the Non-Existent." These works are each part of the Diels-Kranz collection, and although academics consider this source reliable, many of the works included are fragmentary and corrupt. Questions have also been raised as to the authenticity and accuracy of the texts attributed to Gorgias (Consigny 4).

Gorgias' writings are intended to be both rhetorical (persuasive) and performative. He goes to great lengths to exhibit his ability of making an absurd, argumentative position appear stronger. Consequently, each of his works defend positions that are unpopular, paradoxical and even absurd. The performative nature of Gorgias' writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody, artificial figuration and theatricality (Consigny 149). Gorgias' style of argumentation can be described as poetics-minus-the-meter (poiêsis-minus-meter). Gorgias argues that persuasive words have power (dunamis) that is equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force. In the Encomium, Gorgias likens the effect of speech on the soul to the effect of drugs on the body: "Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body – some putting a stop to disease, others to life – so too with words: some cause pain, others joy, some strike fear, some stir the audience to boldness, some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion" (Gorgias 32). The Encomium "argues for the totalizing power of language."[34]

Gorgias also believed that his "magical incantations" would bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions. He paid particular attention to the sounds of words, which, like poetry, could captivate audiences. His florid, rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences (Herrick 42).

Unlike other Sophists, such as Protagoras, Gorgias did not profess to teach arete (excellence, or, virtue). He believed that there was no absolute form of arete, but that it was relative to each situation. For example, virtue in a slave was not the same as virtue in a statesman. He believed that rhetoric, the art of persuasion, was the king of all sciences, since he saw it as a techné with which one could persuade an audience toward any course of action. While rhetoric existed in the curriculum of every Sophist, Gorgias placed more prominence upon it than any of the others.

Much debate over both the nature and value of rhetoric begins with Gorgias. Plato's dialogue Gorgias presents a counter-argument to Gorgias' embrace of rhetoric, its elegant form, and performative nature (Wardy 2). The dialogue tells the story of a debate about rhetoric, politics and justice that occurred at a dinner gathering between Socrates and a small group of Sophists. Plato attempts to show that rhetoric does not meet the requirements to actually be considered a technê but rather is a somewhat dangerous "knack" to possess, both for the orator and for his audience, because it gives the ignorant the power to seem more knowledgeable than an expert to a group.

On Non-Existence edit

Gorgias is the author of a lost work: On Nature or the Non-Existent (also On Non-Existence).[8] Rather than being one of his rhetorical works, it presented a theory of being that at the same time refuted and parodied the Eleatic thesis. The original text was lost and today there remain just two paraphrases of it. The first is preserved by the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus in Against the Logicians and the other by Pseudo-Aristotle, the author of On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias. Each work, however, excludes material that is discussed in the other, which suggests that each version may represent intermediary sources (Consigny 4). It is clear, however, that the work developed a skeptical argument, which has been extracted from the sources and translated as below:

  1. Nothing exists;
  2. Even if something exists, nothing can be known about it; and
  3. Even if something can be known about it, knowledge about it can't be communicated to others.
  4. Even if it can be communicated, it cannot be understood.

The argument has largely been seen as an ironic refutation of Parmenides' thesis on Being. Gorgias set out to prove that it is as easy to demonstrate that being is one, unchanging and timeless as it is to prove that being has no existence at all. Regardless of how it "has largely been seen" it seems clear that Gorgias was focused instead on the notion that true objectivity is impossible since the human mind can never be separated from its possessor.

"How can anyone communicate the idea of color by means of words since the ear does not hear colors but only sounds?" This quote was used to show his theory that 'there is nothing', 'if there were anything no one would know it', 'and if anyone did know it, no one could communicate it'. This theory, thought of in the late 5th century BC, is still being contemplated by many philosophers throughout the world. This argument has led some to label Gorgias a nihilist (one who believes nothing exists, or that the world is incomprehensible, and that the concept of truth is fictitious).

For the first main argument where Gorgias says, "there is no-thing", he tries to persuade the reader that thought and existence are not the same. By claiming that if thought and existence truly were the same, then everything that anyone thought would suddenly exist. He also attempted to prove that words and sensations could not be measured by the same standards, for even though words and sensations are both derived from the mind, they are essentially different. This is where his second idea comes into place.

Rhetorical works edit

Encomium of Helen edit

 
Helen of Troy by Evelyn De Morgan (1898, London)

The Encomium of Helen is considered to be a good example of epideictic oratory and was supposed to have been Gorgias' "show piece or demonstration piece," which was used to attract students (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). In their writings, Gorgias and other sophists speculated "about the structure and function of language" as a framework for expressing the implications of action and the ways decisions about such actions were made" (Jarratt 103). And this is exactly the purpose of Gorgias' Encomium of Helen. Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by Aristotle in his Rhetoric (forensic, deliberative, and epideictic), the Encomium can be classified as an epideictic speech, expressing praise for Helen of Troy and ridding her of the blame she faced for leaving Sparta with Paris (Wardy 26).

Helen – the proverbial "Helen of Troy" – exemplified both sexual passion and tremendous beauty for the Greeks. She was the daughter of Zeus and Leda, the Queen of Sparta, and her beauty was seen by the Trojans as the direct cause of the decade long Trojan War between Greece and Troy. The war began after the goddesses Hera, Athena, and Aphrodite asked Paris (a Trojan prince) to select who was the most beautiful of the three. Each goddess tried to influence Paris' decision, but he ultimately chose Aphrodite who then promised Paris the most beautiful woman. Paris then traveled to Greece where he was greeted by Helen and her husband Menelaus. Under the influence of Aphrodite, Helen allowed Paris to persuade her to elope with him. Together they traveled to Troy, not only sparking the war, but also a popular and literary tradition of blaming Helen for her wrongdoing. It is this tradition which Gorgias confronts in the Encomium.

The Encomium opens with Gorgias explaining that "a man, woman, speech, deed, city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim, but the unworthy should be branded with blame" (Gorgias 30). In the speech Gorgias discusses the possible reasons for Helen's journey to Troy. He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways: by the gods, by physical force, by love, or by speech (logos). If it were indeed the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy, Gorgias argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves, "for a human's anticipation cannot restrain a god's inclination" (Gorgias 31). Gorgias explains that, by nature, the weak are ruled by the strong, and, since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects, Helen should be freed from her undesirable reputation. If, however, Helen was abducted by force, it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime. Thus, it should be he, not Helen, who should be blamed. And if Helen was persuaded by love, she should also be rid of ill repute because "if love is a god, with the divine power of the gods, how could a weaker person refuse and reject him? But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness, it must not be blamed as mistake, but claimed as misfortune" (Gorgias 32). Finally, if speech persuaded Helen, Gorgias claims he can easily clear her of blame. Gorgias explains: "Speech is a powerful master and achieves the most divine feats with the smallest and least evident body. It can stop fear, relieve pain, create joy, and increase pity" (Gorgias 31). It is here that Gorgias compares the effect of speech on the mind with the effect of drugs on the body. He states that Helen has the power to "lead" many bodies in competition by using her body as a weapon (Gumpert, 74). This image of "bodies led and misled, brought together and led apart, is of paramount importance in Gorgias' speech," (Gumpert, 74).

While Gorgias primarily used metaphors and paradox, he famously used "figures of speech, or schemata" (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa). This included balanced clauses (isocolon), the joining of contrasting ideas (antithesis), the structure of successive clauses (parison), and the repetition of word endings (homoeoteleuton) (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). The Encomium shows Gorgias' interest in argumentation, as he makes his point by "systematically refuting a series of possible alternatives," (Matsen, Rollinson and Sousa, 33). It is an encomium of the "rhetorical craft itself, and a demonstration of its power over us," (Gumpert, 73). According to Van Hook, The Encomium of Helen abounds in "amplification and brevity, a rhythm making prose akin to poetry, bold metaphors and poetic or unusual epithets" (122).[35]

Defense of Palamedes edit

In the Defense of Palamedes Gorgias describes logos as a positive instrument for creating ethical arguments (McComiskey 38). The Defense, an oration that deals with issues of morality and political commitment (Consigny 38), defends Palamedes who, in Greek mythology, is credited with the invention of the alphabet, written laws, numbers, armor, and measures and weights (McComiskey 47).

In the speech Palamedes defends himself against the charge of treason. In Greek mythology, Odysseus – in order to avoid going to Troy with Agamemnon and Menelaus to bring Helen back to Sparta – pretended to have gone mad and began sowing the fields with salt. When Palamedes threw Odysseus' son, Telemachus, in front of the plow, Odysseus avoided him, demonstrating that he was sane. Odysseus, who never forgave Palamedes for making him reveal himself, later accused Palamedes of betraying the Greeks to the Trojans. Soon after, Palamedes was condemned and killed (Jarratt 58).

In this epideictic speech, like the Encomium, Gorgias is concerned with experimenting with how plausible arguments can cause conventional truths to be doubted (Jarratt 59). Throughout the text, Gorgias presents a method for composing logical (logos), ethical (ethos) and emotional (pathos) arguments from possibility, which are similar to those described by Aristotle in Rhetoric. These types of arguments about motive and capability presented in the Defense are later described by Aristotle as forensic topoi. Gorgias demonstrates that in order to prove that treason had been committed, a set of possible occurrences also need to be established. In the Defense these occurrences are as follows: communication between Palamedes and the enemy, exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money, and not being detected by guards or citizens. In his defense, Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money, if indeed such a transaction had been made, would require the aid of many confederates in order for it to be transported. Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching, nor in the day because everyone would be able to see. Palamedes continues, explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were, in fact, arranged then action would need to follow. Such action needed to take place either with or without confederates; however, if these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired, but if they were slaves there was a risk of their voluntarily accusing to earn freedom, or accusing by force when tortured. Slaves, Palamedes says, are untrustworthy. Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives, all of which he proves false.

Through the Defense Gorgias demonstrates that a motive requires an advantage such as status, wealth, honour, and security, and insists that Palamedes lacked a motive (McComiskey 47–49).

Epitaphios (or the Athenian funeral oration) edit

This text is considered to be an important contribution to the genre of epitaphios. During the 5th and 4th centuries BC, such funeral orations were delivered by well-known orators during public burial ceremonies in Athens, whereby those who died in wars were honoured. Gorgias' text provides a clever critique of 5th century propagandist rhetoric in imperial Athens and is the basis for Plato's parody, Menexenus (Consigny 2).

Reception and legacy edit

In antiquity edit

Plato was one of Gorgias' greatest critics and a student of Socrates. Plato's dislike for sophistic doctrines is well known, and it is in his eponymous dialogue that both Gorgias himself as well as his rhetorical beliefs are ridiculed (McComiskey 17).

In his dialogue Gorgias, Plato distinguishes between philosophy and rhetoric, characterizing Gorgias as a shallow, opportunistic orator who entertains his audience with his eloquent words and who believes that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion.[36] In the dialogue, Gorgias responds to one of Socrates' statements as follows: "Rhetoric is the only area of expertise you need to learn. You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals!" (Plato 24).

Gorgias, whose On Non-Existence is taken to be critical of the Eleatic tradition and its founder Parmenides, describes philosophy as a type of seduction, but he does not deny philosophy entirely, giving some respect to philosophers.[37]

Plato answers Gorgias by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed, insisting that philosophy is a dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric (Wardy 52).

Aristotle also criticizes Gorgias, labeling him a mere Sophist whose primary goal is to make money by appearing wise and clever, thus deceiving the public by means of misleading or sophistic arguments.[36]

Despite these negative portrayals, Gorgias's style of rhetoric was highly influential.[38] Gorgias's Defense of Helen influenced Euripides's Helen[39] and his Defense of Palamedes influenced the development of western dicanic argument, including possibly even Plato's version of the Apology of Socrates.[39]

Modern reception edit

For almost all of western history, Gorgias has been a marginalized and obscure figure in both philosophical thought and culture at large.[40] In the nineteenth century, however, writers such as the German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) and the English classicist George Grote (1794–1871) began to work to "rehabilitate" Gorgias and the other Sophists from their longstanding reputation as unscrupulous charlatans who taught people how to persuade others using rhetoric for unjust causes.[40] As early as 1872, the English philosopher Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900) was already calling this the "old view".[40] Modern sources continue to affirm that the old stereotype of the Sophists is not accurate.[40]

Since the late twentieth century, scholarly interest in Gorgias has increased dramatically[40] and the amount of research conducted on him is even beginning to rival the research on his more traditionally popular contemporary Parmenides.[40] Gorgias's distinctive writing style, filled with antithesis and figurative language, has been seen as foreshadowing the later development of Menippean satire, as well as, in more recent times, the mannerist, grotesque, and carnivalesque genres.[39] Several scholars have even argued that Gorgias's thoughts on the nature of knowledge, language, and truth foreshadow the views of modern philosophers such as Martin Heidegger, Jacques Derrida, Ludwig Wittgenstein, A. J. Ayer, Amélie Rorty, and Stanley Fish.[38] Nonetheless, many academic philosophers still ridicule any efforts to portray Gorgias as a serious thinker.[40]

See also edit

Notes edit

References edit

  1. ^ "Gorgias" entry in Collins English Dictionary.
  2. ^ Higgins, C. Francis. "Gorgias". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved February 6, 2019.
  3. ^ W. K. C. Guthrie, The Sophists (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1971), p. 270.
  4. ^ a b J. Radford Thomson (1887). A dictionary of philosophy in the words of philosophers. Reeves and Turner. p. 225. Gorgias the Nihilist.
  5. ^ a b Rosenkrantz, G. (2002). The Possibility of Metaphysics: Substance, Identity, and Time*. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 64(3), 728-736.
  6. ^ a b Gronbeck, B. E. (1972). Gorgias on rhetoric and poetic: A rehabilitation. Southern Journal of Communication, 38(1), 27–38.
  7. ^ Caston, V. (2002). Gorgias on Thought and its Objects. Presocratic philosophy: Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos.
  8. ^ a b c Chisholm 1911.
  9. ^ a b c d e Consigny 2001, p. 6.
  10. ^ Consigny 2001, pp. 6–7.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l Consigny 2001, p. 7.
  12. ^ Aristotle, fr. 130 Rose = Quintilian 3.1.13.
  13. ^ Suda, Gorgias
  14. ^ Diogenes Laërtius, vi. 2
  15. ^ Lives of the Sophists 1.9, trans. George Kennedy in The Older Sophists, ed. R.K. Sprague (Columbia, S.C., 1972), p. 31.
  16. ^ Sprague, Rosamond Kent, The Older Sophists, Hackett Publishing Company (ISBN 0-87220-556-8), p. 31
  17. ^ a b c Consigny 2001, pp. 2–3.
  18. ^ Kenny 2004, pp. 28–32.
  19. ^ a b c d Consigny 2001, p. 3.
  20. ^ Consigny 2001, p. 4.
  21. ^ Consigny 2001, pp. 4–5.
  22. ^ Consigny 2001, pp. 2–3, 5–6.
  23. ^ Consigny 2001, pp. 5–6.
  24. ^ A History of Philosophy from Thales to the Present Time by Friedrich Ueberweg: History of the ancient and mediaeval philosophy, Volume 1, Friedrich Ueberweg, Hodder and Stoughton, 1872 p. 72
  25. ^ The Crime of Credulity, Herbert Newton Casson,P. Eckler, 1901 p. 15
  26. ^ Higgins, C. Francis. "Gorgias". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2013.
  27. ^ Pratt, Alan. "Nihilism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2013.
  28. ^ McComiskey, Bruce (1997). "Gorgias, "On Non-Existence": Sextus Empiricus, "Against the Logicians" 1.65–87, Translated from the Greek Text in Hermann Diels's "Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker". Philosophy and Rhetoric. 30 (1): 45–49. JSTOR 40237935.
  29. ^ Striker, Gisela. "Methods of sophistry." Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics (1996): p. 13
  30. ^ Caston, Victor. "Gorgias on Thought and its Objects." Presocratic philosophy: Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos (2002): p. 205
  31. ^ Wardy, Robert. The birth of rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and their successors. Routledge, 2005.
  32. ^ Gigon, Olof. "Gorgias' Über das Nichtsein'." Hermes (1936): p. 213
  33. ^ Newiger, Hans-Joachim. Untersuchungen zu Gorgias' Schrift über das Nichtseiende. Walter de Gruyter, 1973.
  34. ^ Bizzell; Herzberg (1990). The Rhetorical Tradition. ISBN 9780312003487.
  35. ^ Van Hook, LaRue (February 15, 1913). "The Encomium of Helen by Gorgias". The Classical Weekly. 6 (16): 122–123. doi:10.2307/4386697. JSTOR 4386697.
  36. ^ a b Consigny 2001, pp. 1, 36.
  37. ^ Consigny 2001, p. 37.
  38. ^ a b Consigny 2001, pp. 1–2.
  39. ^ a b c Consigny 2001, p. 2.
  40. ^ a b c d e f g Consigny 2001, p. 1.

Bibliography edit

Primary sources edit

  • Gorgias. "Encomium of Helen." The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. Eds. Vincent B. Leitch, et al. New York: W.W. Norton & Company, 2001. 30–33.
  • Plato. Gorgias. Trans. Robin Waterfield. Oxford University Press, 1994.

Secondary sources edit

  • Chisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Gorgias" . Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 12 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 257.
  • Consigny, Scott (2001), Gorgias: Sophist and Artist, Columbia, South Carolina: University of South Carolina Press, ISBN 978-1-57003-424-4
  • Gumpert, Matthew. Grafting Helen: the Abduction of the Classical Past. Wisconsin: University of Wisconsin Press, 2001.
  • Jarratt, Susan C. Rereading the Sophists: Classical Rhetoric Refigured. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 1991.
  • Kenny, Anthony (2004), Ancient Philosophy, A New History of Western Philosophy, vol. 1, Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, ISBN 978-0-19-875273-8
  • Leitch, Vincent B. et al., eds. The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 2001.
  • McComiskey, Bruce. Gorgias and the Art of Rhetoric: Toward a Holistic Reading of the Extant Gorgianic Fragments. Taylor & Francis, Ltd., 1997.
  • McComiskey, Bruce. Gorgias and the New Sophistic Rhetoric. Carbondale and Edwardsville: Southern Illinois University Press, 2001.
  • Matsen, Patricia P. Philip Rollinson and Marion Sousa. Readings from Classical Rhetoric, Illinois: Southern Illinois University Press, 1990.
  • Poulakos, John. "Sophistical Rhetoric in Classical Greece", University of South Carolina Press, 1995.
  • Sprague, Rosamond Kent. The Older Sophists, Hackett Publishing Company(ISBN 0-87220-556-8).
  • Walker, Jeffrey. Rhetoric and Poetics in Antiquity, New York: Oxford University Press, 2000.
  • Wardy, Robert. The Birth of Rhetoric: Gorgias, Plato and Their Successors, New York: Routledge, 1996.

External links edit

  •   Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article: Γοργίας
  • Gorgias' Encomium of Helen and Defense of Palamedes (in Ancient Greek), included in Friedrich Blass's edition of Antiphon's speeches
  • Encomium on Helen: and
  • Gorgias, selected texts (from Plato's Gorgias) in Greek (with German translation and vocabulary notes)
  • Gorgias, entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • On the Nonexistent in Sextus Empiricus, Adv. Ac. VII, 65–87
  • Encomium on Helen:
  • Mappa concettuale del ragionamento di Gorgia (Italian)
  • A theory referring to the theory of Gorgias
  • Works by or about Gorgias at Internet Archive
  • Works by Gorgias at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  

gorgias, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, unclear, citation, style, references, used, made, clearer, with, different, consistent, style, citation, footnoting, february, 2023, learn, when, remove, this, template, message, ɔːr, greek, Γοργίας, ancient. For other uses see Gorgias disambiguation This article has an unclear citation style The references used may be made clearer with a different or consistent style of citation and footnoting February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Gorgias ˈ ɡ ɔːr dʒ i e s 1 Greek Gorgias 483 375 BC 2 was an ancient Greek sophist pre Socratic philosopher and rhetorician who was a native of Leontinoi in Sicily Along with Protagoras he forms the first generation of Sophists Several doxographers report that he was a pupil of Empedocles although he would only have been a few years younger W K C Guthrie writes that Like other Sophists he was an itinerant that practiced in various cities and giving public exhibitions of his skill at the great pan Hellenic centers of Olympia and Delphi and charged fees for his instruction and performances A special feature of his displays was to ask miscellaneous questions from the audience and give impromptu replies 3 He has been called Gorgias the Nihilist although the degree to which this epithet adequately describes his philosophy is controversial 4 5 6 7 GorgiasBorn483 BCLeontinoi Sicily today Lentini Italy Died375 BCEraPre Socratic philosophyRegionWestern philosophySchoolSophistsMain interestsOntology epistemology rhetoric moral relativism Prominent among his claims to recognition is that he transplanted rhetoric from his native Sicily to Attica and contributed to the diffusion of the Attic dialect as the language of literary prose 8 Contents 1 Life 2 Philosophy 3 Rhetorical innovation 4 On Non Existence 5 Rhetorical works 5 1 Encomium of Helen 5 2 Defense of Palamedes 5 3 Epitaphios or the Athenian funeral oration 6 Reception and legacy 6 1 In antiquity 6 2 Modern reception 7 See also 8 Notes 9 References 9 1 Bibliography 9 2 Primary sources 9 3 Secondary sources 10 External linksLife edit nbsp nbsp Leontinoi nbsp Acragas nbsp Athens nbsp Larissa nbsp Olympiaclass notpageimage Map of the Mediterranean showing locations associated with Gorgias Gorgias was born c 483 BC in Leontinoi a Chalcidian colony in eastern Sicily that was allied with Athens 9 His father s name was Charmantides 9 He had a brother named Herodicus who was a physician and sometimes accompanied him during his travels 10 He also had a sister whose name is not known but whose grandson dedicated a golden statue to his great uncle at Delphi 11 It is not known whether Gorgias married or had children 11 Gorgias is said to have studied under the Sicilian philosopher Empedocles of Acragas c 490 c 430 BC but it is not known when where for how long or in what capacity 11 He may have also studied under the rhetoricians Corax of Syracuse and Tisias 11 but very little is known about either of these men nor is anything known about their relationship with Gorgias 11 It is not known what kind of role Gorgias may have played in the politics in his native Leontinoi 11 but it is known that in 427 BC when he was around sixty years old he was sent to Athens by his fellow citizens as the head of an embassy to ask for Athenian protection against the aggression of the Syracusans 11 After 427 BC Gorgias appears to have settled in mainland Greece living at various points in a number of city states including Athens and Larisa 11 He was well known for delivering orations at Panhellenic Festivals and is described as having been conspicuous at Olympia 11 There is no surviving record of any role he might have played in organizing the festivals themselves 11 Gorgias s primary occupation was as a teacher of rhetoric 11 According to Aristotle his students included Isocrates 12 Other students are named in later traditions the Suda adds Pericles Polus and Alcidamas 13 Diogenes Laertius mentions Antisthenes 14 and according to Philostratus I understand that he attracted the attention of the most admired men Critias and Alcibiades who were young and Thucydides and Pericles who were already old Agathon too the tragic poet whom Comedy regards as wise and eloquent often Gorgianizes in his iambic verse 15 Additionally although they are not described as his students Gorgias is widely thought to have influenced the styles of the historian Thucydides the tragic playwright Agathon the doctor Hippocrates the rhetorician Alcidamas and the poet and commentator Lycophron 11 Gorgias is reputed to have lived to be one hundred and eight years old Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 He won admiration for his ability to speak on any subject Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 He accumulated considerable wealth enough to commission a gold statue of himself for a public temple 16 After his Pythian Oration the Greeks installed a solid gold statue of him in the temple of Apollo at Delphi Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 He died at Larissa in Thessaly Philosophy editThe philosophies of the pre Socratic Greek Sophists are controversial among scholars in general due to their highly subtle and ambiguous writings and also to the fact that they are best known as characters in Plato s dialogues 17 18 Gorgias however is particularly frustrating for modern scholars to attempt to understand 17 While scholars debate the precise subtleties of the teachings of Protagoras Hippias and Prodicus they generally agree on the basic frameworks of what these thinkers believed 19 With Gorgias however scholars widely disagree on even the most basic framework of his ideas including over whether or not that framework even existed at all 19 The greatest hindrance to scholarly understanding of Gorgias s philosophy is that the vast majority of his writings have been lost 20 and those that have survived have suffered considerable alteration by later copyists 21 These difficulties are further compounded by the fact that Gorgias s rhetoric is frequently elusive and confusing 22 he makes many of his most important points using elaborate but highly ambiguous metaphors similes and puns 23 Many of Gorgias s propositions are also thought to be sarcastic playful or satirical 9 In his treatise On Rhetoric Aristotle characterizes Gorgias s style of oratory as pervasively ironic and states that Gorgias recommended responding to seriousness with jests and to jests with seriousness 9 Gorgias frequently blurs the lines between serious philosophical discourse and satire 9 which makes it extremely difficult for scholars to tell when he is being serious and when he is merely joking 17 Gorgias frequently contradicts his own statements and adopts inconsistent perspectives on different issues 19 As a result of all these factors Scott Porter Consigny calls him perhaps the most elusive of the polytropic quarry hunted in Plato s Sophist 19 Gorgias has been labelled The Nihilist 4 5 6 24 25 because some scholars have interpreted his thesis on the non existent to be an argument against the existence of anything that is straightforwardly endorsed by Gorgias himself 26 According to Alan Pratt nihilism is the belief that all values are baseless and that nothing can be known or communicated It is associated with pessimism and a radical skepticism that condemns existence 27 Gorgias presented his nihilist arguments in On Non Existence however the original text is no longer extant We only know his arguments through commentary by Sextus Empiricus and Pseudo Aristotle s De Melisso Xenophane Gorgia 28 Ostensibly Gorgias developed three sequential arguments first that nothing exists second that even if existence exists it is inapprehensible to humans and third that even if existence is apprehensible it certainly cannot be communicated or interpreted to one s neighbors That being said there is consensus in late 20th century and early 21st century scholarship that the label nihilist is misleading in part because if his argument were genuinely meant to support nihilism it would be self undermining The argument of course is itself something and has pretensions to communicate knowledge in conflict with its explicit pronouncement that there is nothing and that it can t be known or communicated Gisela Striker argues I find it hard to believe that anyone should ever have thought that Gorgias seriously advocated the view that nothing is and that he was therefore a nihilist 29 Similarly Caston states Gorgias would have to be not merely disconsolate but quite dull witted to have missed the conflict between his presentation and its content 30 Finally Wardy says This sadly mistaken reading overlooks the most obvious consequence of Gorgias paradoxologia parado3ologia his message refutes itself and in consequence so far from constituting a theory of logos it confronts us with a picture of what language cannot be with what it cannot be assumed to aspire to be 31 Gigon and Newiger make similar points 32 33 Rhetorical innovation editGorgias ushered in rhetorical innovations involving structure and ornamentation and he introduced paradoxologia the idea of paradoxical thought and paradoxical expression For these advancements Gorgias has been labeled the father of sophistry Wardy 6 Gorgias is also known for contributing to the diffusion of the Attic Greek dialect as the language of literary prose 8 Gorgias was the first orator known to develop and teach a distinctive style of speaking Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 Gorgias extant rhetorical works Encomium of Helen Ἑlenhs ἐgkwmion Defense of Palamedes Ὑper Palamhdoys ἀpologia On Non Existence Perὶ toῦ mὴ ὄntos ἢ Perὶ fysews and Epitaphios Epitafios come to us via a work entitled Technai Texnai a manual of rhetorical instruction which may have consisted of models to be memorized and demonstrate various principles of rhetorical practice Leitch et al 29 Although some scholars claim that each work presents opposing statements the four texts can be read as interrelated contributions to the up and coming theory and art techne of rhetoric McComiskey 32 Of Gorgias surviving works only the Encomium and the Defense are believed to exist in their entirety Meanwhile there are his own speeches rhetorical political or other A number of these are referred to and quoted by Aristotle including a speech on Hellenic unity a funeral oration for Athenians fallen in war and a brief quotation from an Encomium on the Eleans Apart from the speeches there are paraphrases of the treatise On Nature or the Non Existent These works are each part of the Diels Kranz collection and although academics consider this source reliable many of the works included are fragmentary and corrupt Questions have also been raised as to the authenticity and accuracy of the texts attributed to Gorgias Consigny 4 Gorgias writings are intended to be both rhetorical persuasive and performative He goes to great lengths to exhibit his ability of making an absurd argumentative position appear stronger Consequently each of his works defend positions that are unpopular paradoxical and even absurd The performative nature of Gorgias writings is exemplified by the way that he playfully approaches each argument with stylistic devices such as parody artificial figuration and theatricality Consigny 149 Gorgias style of argumentation can be described as poetics minus the meter poiesis minus meter Gorgias argues that persuasive words have power dunamis that is equivalent to that of the gods and as strong as physical force In the Encomium Gorgias likens the effect of speech on the soul to the effect of drugs on the body Just as different drugs draw forth different humors from the body some putting a stop to disease others to life so too with words some cause pain others joy some strike fear some stir the audience to boldness some benumb and bewitch the soul with evil persuasion Gorgias 32 The Encomium argues for the totalizing power of language 34 Gorgias also believed that his magical incantations would bring healing to the human psyche by controlling powerful emotions He paid particular attention to the sounds of words which like poetry could captivate audiences His florid rhyming style seemed to hypnotize his audiences Herrick 42 Unlike other Sophists such as Protagoras Gorgias did not profess to teach arete excellence or virtue He believed that there was no absolute form of arete but that it was relative to each situation For example virtue in a slave was not the same as virtue in a statesman He believed that rhetoric the art of persuasion was the king of all sciences since he saw it as a techne with which one could persuade an audience toward any course of action While rhetoric existed in the curriculum of every Sophist Gorgias placed more prominence upon it than any of the others Much debate over both the nature and value of rhetoric begins with Gorgias Plato s dialogue Gorgias presents a counter argument to Gorgias embrace of rhetoric its elegant form and performative nature Wardy 2 The dialogue tells the story of a debate about rhetoric politics and justice that occurred at a dinner gathering between Socrates and a small group of Sophists Plato attempts to show that rhetoric does not meet the requirements to actually be considered a techne but rather is a somewhat dangerous knack to possess both for the orator and for his audience because it gives the ignorant the power to seem more knowledgeable than an expert to a group On Non Existence editGorgias is the author of a lost work On Nature or the Non Existent also On Non Existence 8 Rather than being one of his rhetorical works it presented a theory of being that at the same time refuted and parodied the Eleatic thesis The original text was lost and today there remain just two paraphrases of it The first is preserved by the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus in Against the Logicians and the other by Pseudo Aristotle the author of On Melissus Xenophanes and Gorgias Each work however excludes material that is discussed in the other which suggests that each version may represent intermediary sources Consigny 4 It is clear however that the work developed a skeptical argument which has been extracted from the sources and translated as below Nothing exists Even if something exists nothing can be known about it and Even if something can be known about it knowledge about it can t be communicated to others Even if it can be communicated it cannot be understood The argument has largely been seen as an ironic refutation of Parmenides thesis on Being Gorgias set out to prove that it is as easy to demonstrate that being is one unchanging and timeless as it is to prove that being has no existence at all Regardless of how it has largely been seen it seems clear that Gorgias was focused instead on the notion that true objectivity is impossible since the human mind can never be separated from its possessor How can anyone communicate the idea of color by means of words since the ear does not hear colors but only sounds This quote was used to show his theory that there is nothing if there were anything no one would know it and if anyone did know it no one could communicate it This theory thought of in the late 5th century BC is still being contemplated by many philosophers throughout the world This argument has led some to label Gorgias a nihilist one who believes nothing exists or that the world is incomprehensible and that the concept of truth is fictitious For the first main argument where Gorgias says there is no thing he tries to persuade the reader that thought and existence are not the same By claiming that if thought and existence truly were the same then everything that anyone thought would suddenly exist He also attempted to prove that words and sensations could not be measured by the same standards for even though words and sensations are both derived from the mind they are essentially different This is where his second idea comes into place Rhetorical works editEncomium of Helen edit nbsp Helen of Troy by Evelyn De Morgan 1898 London The Encomium of Helen is considered to be a good example of epideictic oratory and was supposed to have been Gorgias show piece or demonstration piece which was used to attract students Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 In their writings Gorgias and other sophists speculated about the structure and function of language as a framework for expressing the implications of action and the ways decisions about such actions were made Jarratt 103 And this is exactly the purpose of Gorgias Encomium of Helen Of the three divisions of rhetoric discussed by Aristotle in his Rhetoric forensic deliberative and epideictic the Encomium can be classified as an epideictic speech expressing praise for Helen of Troy and ridding her of the blame she faced for leaving Sparta with Paris Wardy 26 Helen the proverbial Helen of Troy exemplified both sexual passion and tremendous beauty for the Greeks She was the daughter of Zeus and Leda the Queen of Sparta and her beauty was seen by the Trojans as the direct cause of the decade long Trojan War between Greece and Troy The war began after the goddesses Hera Athena and Aphrodite asked Paris a Trojan prince to select who was the most beautiful of the three Each goddess tried to influence Paris decision but he ultimately chose Aphrodite who then promised Paris the most beautiful woman Paris then traveled to Greece where he was greeted by Helen and her husband Menelaus Under the influence of Aphrodite Helen allowed Paris to persuade her to elope with him Together they traveled to Troy not only sparking the war but also a popular and literary tradition of blaming Helen for her wrongdoing It is this tradition which Gorgias confronts in the Encomium The Encomium opens with Gorgias explaining that a man woman speech deed city or action that is worthy of praise should be honored with acclaim but the unworthy should be branded with blame Gorgias 30 In the speech Gorgias discusses the possible reasons for Helen s journey to Troy He explains that Helen could have been persuaded in one of four ways by the gods by physical force by love or by speech logos If it were indeed the plan of the gods that caused Helen to depart for Troy Gorgias argues that those who blame her should face blame themselves for a human s anticipation cannot restrain a god s inclination Gorgias 31 Gorgias explains that by nature the weak are ruled by the strong and since the gods are stronger than humans in all respects Helen should be freed from her undesirable reputation If however Helen was abducted by force it is clear that the aggressor committed a crime Thus it should be he not Helen who should be blamed And if Helen was persuaded by love she should also be rid of ill repute because if love is a god with the divine power of the gods how could a weaker person refuse and reject him But if love is a human sickness and a mental weakness it must not be blamed as mistake but claimed as misfortune Gorgias 32 Finally if speech persuaded Helen Gorgias claims he can easily clear her of blame Gorgias explains Speech is a powerful master and achieves the most divine feats with the smallest and least evident body It can stop fear relieve pain create joy and increase pity Gorgias 31 It is here that Gorgias compares the effect of speech on the mind with the effect of drugs on the body He states that Helen has the power to lead many bodies in competition by using her body as a weapon Gumpert 74 This image of bodies led and misled brought together and led apart is of paramount importance in Gorgias speech Gumpert 74 While Gorgias primarily used metaphors and paradox he famously used figures of speech or schemata Matsen Rollinson and Sousa This included balanced clauses isocolon the joining of contrasting ideas antithesis the structure of successive clauses parison and the repetition of word endings homoeoteleuton Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 The Encomium shows Gorgias interest in argumentation as he makes his point by systematically refuting a series of possible alternatives Matsen Rollinson and Sousa 33 It is an encomium of the rhetorical craft itself and a demonstration of its power over us Gumpert 73 According to Van Hook The Encomium of Helen abounds in amplification and brevity a rhythm making prose akin to poetry bold metaphors and poetic or unusual epithets 122 35 Defense of Palamedes edit In the Defense of Palamedes Gorgias describes logos as a positive instrument for creating ethical arguments McComiskey 38 The Defense an oration that deals with issues of morality and political commitment Consigny 38 defends Palamedes who in Greek mythology is credited with the invention of the alphabet written laws numbers armor and measures and weights McComiskey 47 In the speech Palamedes defends himself against the charge of treason In Greek mythology Odysseus in order to avoid going to Troy with Agamemnon and Menelaus to bring Helen back to Sparta pretended to have gone mad and began sowing the fields with salt When Palamedes threw Odysseus son Telemachus in front of the plow Odysseus avoided him demonstrating that he was sane Odysseus who never forgave Palamedes for making him reveal himself later accused Palamedes of betraying the Greeks to the Trojans Soon after Palamedes was condemned and killed Jarratt 58 In this epideictic speech like the Encomium Gorgias is concerned with experimenting with how plausible arguments can cause conventional truths to be doubted Jarratt 59 Throughout the text Gorgias presents a method for composing logical logos ethical ethos and emotional pathos arguments from possibility which are similar to those described by Aristotle in Rhetoric These types of arguments about motive and capability presented in the Defense are later described by Aristotle as forensic topoi Gorgias demonstrates that in order to prove that treason had been committed a set of possible occurrences also need to be established In the Defense these occurrences are as follows communication between Palamedes and the enemy exchange of a pledge in the form of hostages or money and not being detected by guards or citizens In his defense Palamedes claims that a small sum of money would not have warranted such a large undertaking and reasons that a large sum of money if indeed such a transaction had been made would require the aid of many confederates in order for it to be transported Palamedes reasons further that such an exchange could neither have occurred at night because the guards would be watching nor in the day because everyone would be able to see Palamedes continues explaining that if the aforementioned conditions were in fact arranged then action would need to follow Such action needed to take place either with or without confederates however if these confederates were free men then they were free to disclose any information they desired but if they were slaves there was a risk of their voluntarily accusing to earn freedom or accusing by force when tortured Slaves Palamedes says are untrustworthy Palamedes goes on to list a variety of possible motives all of which he proves false Through the Defense Gorgias demonstrates that a motive requires an advantage such as status wealth honour and security and insists that Palamedes lacked a motive McComiskey 47 49 Epitaphios or the Athenian funeral oration edit This text is considered to be an important contribution to the genre of epitaphios During the 5th and 4th centuries BC such funeral orations were delivered by well known orators during public burial ceremonies in Athens whereby those who died in wars were honoured Gorgias text provides a clever critique of 5th century propagandist rhetoric in imperial Athens and is the basis for Plato s parody Menexenus Consigny 2 Reception and legacy editIn antiquity edit Plato was one of Gorgias greatest critics and a student of Socrates Plato s dislike for sophistic doctrines is well known and it is in his eponymous dialogue that both Gorgias himself as well as his rhetorical beliefs are ridiculed McComiskey 17 In his dialogue Gorgias Plato distinguishes between philosophy and rhetoric characterizing Gorgias as a shallow opportunistic orator who entertains his audience with his eloquent words and who believes that it is unnecessary to learn the truth about actual matters when one has discovered the art of persuasion 36 In the dialogue Gorgias responds to one of Socrates statements as follows Rhetoric is the only area of expertise you need to learn You can ignore all the rest and still get the better of the professionals Plato 24 Gorgias whose On Non Existence is taken to be critical of the Eleatic tradition and its founder Parmenides describes philosophy as a type of seduction but he does not deny philosophy entirely giving some respect to philosophers 37 Plato answers Gorgias by reaffirming the Parmenidean ideal that being is the basic substance and reality of which all things are composed insisting that philosophy is a dialectic distinct from and superior to rhetoric Wardy 52 Aristotle also criticizes Gorgias labeling him a mere Sophist whose primary goal is to make money by appearing wise and clever thus deceiving the public by means of misleading or sophistic arguments 36 Despite these negative portrayals Gorgias s style of rhetoric was highly influential 38 Gorgias s Defense of Helen influenced Euripides s Helen 39 and his Defense of Palamedes influenced the development of western dicanic argument including possibly even Plato s version of the Apology of Socrates 39 Modern reception edit For almost all of western history Gorgias has been a marginalized and obscure figure in both philosophical thought and culture at large 40 In the nineteenth century however writers such as the German philosopher Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel 1770 1831 and the English classicist George Grote 1794 1871 began to work to rehabilitate Gorgias and the other Sophists from their longstanding reputation as unscrupulous charlatans who taught people how to persuade others using rhetoric for unjust causes 40 As early as 1872 the English philosopher Henry Sidgwick 1838 1900 was already calling this the old view 40 Modern sources continue to affirm that the old stereotype of the Sophists is not accurate 40 Since the late twentieth century scholarly interest in Gorgias has increased dramatically 40 and the amount of research conducted on him is even beginning to rival the research on his more traditionally popular contemporary Parmenides 40 Gorgias s distinctive writing style filled with antithesis and figurative language has been seen as foreshadowing the later development of Menippean satire as well as in more recent times the mannerist grotesque and carnivalesque genres 39 Several scholars have even argued that Gorgias s thoughts on the nature of knowledge language and truth foreshadow the views of modern philosophers such as Martin Heidegger Jacques Derrida Ludwig Wittgenstein A J Ayer Amelie Rorty and Stanley Fish 38 Nonetheless many academic philosophers still ridicule any efforts to portray Gorgias as a serious thinker 40 See also editHellenistic philosophy On Melissus Xenophanes and GorgiasNotes editReferences edit Gorgias entry in Collins English Dictionary Higgins C Francis Gorgias Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved February 6 2019 W K C Guthrie The Sophists New York Cambridge University Press 1971 p 270 a b J Radford Thomson 1887 A dictionary of philosophy in the words of philosophers Reeves and Turner p 225 Gorgias the Nihilist a b Rosenkrantz G 2002 The Possibility of Metaphysics Substance Identity and Time Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 3 728 736 a b Gronbeck B E 1972 Gorgias on rhetoric and poetic A rehabilitation Southern Journal of Communication 38 1 27 38 Caston V 2002 Gorgias on Thought and its Objects Presocratic philosophy Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos a b c Chisholm 1911 a b c d e Consigny 2001 p 6 Consigny 2001 pp 6 7 a b c d e f g h i j k l Consigny 2001 p 7 Aristotle fr 130 Rose Quintilian 3 1 13 Suda Gorgias Diogenes Laertius vi 2 Lives of the Sophists 1 9 trans George Kennedy in The Older Sophists ed R K Sprague Columbia S C 1972 p 31 Sprague Rosamond Kent The Older Sophists Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 0 87220 556 8 p 31 a b c Consigny 2001 pp 2 3 Kenny 2004 pp 28 32 a b c d Consigny 2001 p 3 Consigny 2001 p 4 Consigny 2001 pp 4 5 Consigny 2001 pp 2 3 5 6 Consigny 2001 pp 5 6 A History of Philosophy from Thales to the Present Time by Friedrich Ueberweg History of the ancient and mediaeval philosophy Volume 1 Friedrich Ueberweg Hodder and Stoughton 1872 p 72 The Crime of Credulity Herbert Newton Casson P Eckler 1901 p 15 Higgins C Francis Gorgias Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 17 October 2013 Pratt Alan Nihilism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 17 October 2013 McComiskey Bruce 1997 Gorgias On Non Existence Sextus Empiricus Against the Logicians 1 65 87 Translated from the Greek Text in Hermann Diels s Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker Philosophy and Rhetoric 30 1 45 49 JSTOR 40237935 Striker Gisela Methods of sophistry Essays on Hellenistic Epistemology and Ethics 1996 p 13 Caston Victor Gorgias on Thought and its Objects Presocratic philosophy Essays in honor of Alexander Mourelatos 2002 p 205 Wardy Robert The birth of rhetoric Gorgias Plato and their successors Routledge 2005 Gigon Olof Gorgias Uber das Nichtsein Hermes 1936 p 213 Newiger Hans Joachim Untersuchungen zu Gorgias Schrift uber das Nichtseiende Walter de Gruyter 1973 Bizzell Herzberg 1990 The Rhetorical Tradition ISBN 9780312003487 Van Hook LaRue February 15 1913 The Encomium of Helen by Gorgias The Classical Weekly 6 16 122 123 doi 10 2307 4386697 JSTOR 4386697 a b Consigny 2001 pp 1 36 Consigny 2001 p 37 a b Consigny 2001 pp 1 2 a b c Consigny 2001 p 2 a b c d e f g Consigny 2001 p 1 Bibliography edit Primary sources edit Gorgias Encomium of Helen The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism Eds Vincent B Leitch et al New York W W Norton amp Company 2001 30 33 Plato Gorgias Trans Robin Waterfield Oxford University Press 1994 Secondary sources edit Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Gorgias Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 12 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 257 Consigny Scott 2001 Gorgias Sophist and Artist Columbia South Carolina University of South Carolina Press ISBN 978 1 57003 424 4 Gumpert Matthew Grafting Helen the Abduction of the Classical Past Wisconsin University of Wisconsin Press 2001 Jarratt Susan C Rereading the Sophists Classical Rhetoric Refigured Carbondale and Edwardsville Southern Illinois University Press 1991 Kenny Anthony 2004 Ancient Philosophy A New History of Western Philosophy vol 1 Oxford England Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 875273 8 Leitch Vincent B et al eds The Norton Anthology of Theory and Criticism New York W W Norton amp Company 2001 McComiskey Bruce Gorgias and the Art of Rhetoric Toward a Holistic Reading of the Extant Gorgianic Fragments Taylor amp Francis Ltd 1997 McComiskey Bruce Gorgias and the New Sophistic Rhetoric Carbondale and Edwardsville Southern Illinois University Press 2001 Matsen Patricia P Philip Rollinson and Marion Sousa Readings from Classical Rhetoric Illinois Southern Illinois University Press 1990 Poulakos John Sophistical Rhetoric in Classical Greece University of South Carolina Press 1995 Sprague Rosamond Kent The Older Sophists Hackett Publishing Company ISBN 0 87220 556 8 Walker Jeffrey Rhetoric and Poetics in Antiquity New York Oxford University Press 2000 Wardy Robert The Birth of Rhetoric Gorgias Plato and Their Successors New York Routledge 1996 External links edit nbsp Greek Wikisource has original text related to this article Gorgias Gorgias Encomium of Helen and Defense of Palamedes in Ancient Greek included in Friedrich Blass s edition of Antiphon s speeches Encomium on Helen Greek text and English translation Gorgias selected texts from Plato s Gorgias in Greek with German translation and vocabulary notes Gorgias entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy On the Nonexistent in Sextus Empiricus Adv Ac VII 65 87 Encomium on Helen public domain audiobook Mappa concettuale del ragionamento di Gorgia Italian A theory referring to the theory of Gorgias Works by or about Gorgias at Internet Archive Works by Gorgias at LibriVox public domain audiobooks nbsp Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Gorgias amp oldid 1211850019 Encomium of Helen, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.