fbpx
Wikipedia

Cantor's diagonal argument

In set theory, Cantor's diagonal argument, also called the diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof, was published in 1891 by Georg Cantor as a mathematical proof that there are infinite sets which cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the infinite set of natural numbers.[1][2]: 20– [3] Such sets are now known as uncountable sets, and the size of infinite sets is now treated by the theory of cardinal numbers which Cantor began.

An illustration of Cantor's diagonal argument (in base 2) for the existence of uncountable sets. The sequence at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the enumeration of sequences above.
An infinite set may have the same cardinality as a proper subset of itself, as the depicted bijection f(x)=2x from the natural to the even numbers demonstrates. Nevertheless, infinite sets of different cardinalities exist, as Cantor's diagonal argument shows.

The diagonal argument was not Cantor's first proof of the uncountability of the real numbers, which appeared in 1874.[4][5] However, it demonstrates a general technique that has since been used in a wide range of proofs,[6] including the first of Gödel's incompleteness theorems[2] and Turing's answer to the Entscheidungsproblem. Diagonalization arguments are often also the source of contradictions like Russell's paradox[7][8] and Richard's paradox.[2]: 27 

Uncountable set

Cantor considered the set T of all infinite sequences of binary digits (i.e. each digit is zero or one).[note 1] He begins with a constructive proof of the following lemma:

If s1, s2, ... , sn, ... is any enumeration of elements from T,[note 2] then an element s of T can be constructed that doesn't correspond to any sn in the enumeration.

The proof starts with an enumeration of elements from T, for example

s1 = (0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, ...)
s2 = (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...)
s3 = (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, ...)
s4 = (1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, ...)
s5 = (1, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...)
s6 = (0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...)
s7 = (1, 0, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, ...)
...

Next, a sequence s is constructed by choosing the 1st digit as complementary to the 1st digit of s1 (swapping 0s for 1s and vice versa), the 2nd digit as complementary to the 2nd digit of s2, the 3rd digit as complementary to the 3rd digit of s3, and generally for every n, the nth digit as complementary to the nth digit of sn. For the example above, this yields

s1 = (0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, 0, ...)
s2 = (1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, 1, ...)
s3 = (0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, ...)
s4 = (1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, ...)
s5 = (1, 1, 0, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...)
s6 = (0, 0, 1, 1, 0, 1, 1, ...)
s7 = (1, 0, 0, 0, 1, 0, 0, ...)
...
s = (1, 0, 1, 1, 1, 0, 1, ...)

By construction, s is a member of T that differs from each sn, since their nth digits differ (highlighted in the example). Hence, s cannot occur in the enumeration.

Based on this lemma, Cantor then uses a proof by contradiction to show that:

The set T is uncountable.

The proof starts by assuming that T is countable. Then all its elements can be written in an enumeration s1, s2, ... , sn, ... . Applying the previous lemma to this enumeration produces a sequence s that is a member of T, but is not in the enumeration. However, if T is enumerated, then every member of T, including this s, is in the enumeration. This contradiction implies that the original assumption is false. Therefore, T is uncountable.[1]

Real numbers

The uncountability of the real numbers was already established by Cantor's first uncountability proof, but it also follows from the above result. To prove this, an injection will be constructed from the set T of infinite binary strings to the set R of real numbers. Since T is uncountable, the image of this function, which is a subset of R, is uncountable. Therefore, R is uncountable. Also, by using a method of construction devised by Cantor, a bijection will be constructed between T and R. Therefore, T and R have the same cardinality, which is called the "cardinality of the continuum" and is usually denoted by   or  .

An injection from T to R is given by mapping binary strings in T to decimal fractions, such as mapping t = 0111... to the decimal 0.0111.... This function, defined by f(t) = 0.t, is an injection because it maps different strings to different numbers.[note 3]

Constructing a bijection between T and R is slightly more complicated. Instead of mapping 0111... to the decimal 0.0111..., it can be mapped to the base b number: 0.0111...b. This leads to the family of functions: fb(t) = 0.tb. The functions fb(t) are injections, except for f2(t). This function will be modified to produce a bijection between T and R.

General sets

 
Illustration of the generalized diagonal argument: The set T = {n : nf(n)} at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the range of f: P( ). The example mapping f happens to correspond to the example enumeration s in the above picture.

A generalized form of the diagonal argument was used by Cantor to prove Cantor's theorem: for every set S, the power set of S—that is, the set of all subsets of S (here written as P(S))—cannot be in bijection with S itself. This proof proceeds as follows:

Let f be any function from S to P(S). It suffices to prove f cannot be surjective. That means that some member T of P(S), i.e. some subset of S, is not in the image of f. As a candidate consider the set:

T = { sS: sf(s) }.

For every s in S, either s is in T or not. If s is in T, then by definition of T, s is not in f(s), so T is not equal to f(s). On the other hand, if s is not in T, then by definition of T, s is in f(s), so again T is not equal to f(s); cf. picture. For a more complete account of this proof, see Cantor's theorem.

Consequences

Ordering of cardinals

Cantor defines an order relation of cardinalities, e.g.   and  , in terms of the existence of injections between the underlying sets,   and  . The argument in the previous paragraph then proved that sets such as   are uncountable, which is to say  , and we can embed the naturals into the function space, so that we have that  . In the context of classical mathematics, this exhausts the possibilities and the diagonal argument can thus be used to establish that, for example, although both sets under consideration are infinite, there are actually more infinite sequences of ones and zeros than there are natural numbers. Cantor's result then also implies that the notion of the set of all sets is inconsistent: If S were the set of all sets, then P(S) would at the same time be bigger than S and a subset of S.

Assuming the law of excluded middle, every subcountable set (a property in terms of surjections) is also already countable.

In Constructive mathematics, it is harder or impossible to order ordinals and also cardinals. For example, the Schröder–Bernstein theorem requires the law of excluded middle.[10] Therefore, intuitionists do not accept the theorem about the cardinal ordering.[11] The ordering on the reals (the standard ordering extending that of the rational numbers) is also not necessarily decidable. Neither are most properties of interesting classes of functions decidable, by Rice's theorem, i.e. the right set of counting numbers for the subcountable sets may not be recursive. In a set theory, theories of mathematics are modeled. For example, in set theory, "the" set of real numbers is identified as a set that fulfills some axioms of real numbers. Various models have been studied, such as the Dedekind reals or the Cauchy reals. Weaker axioms mean less constraints and so allow for a richer class of models. Consequently, in an otherwise constructive context (law of excluded middle not taken as axiom), it is consistent to adopt non-classical axioms that contradict consequences of the law of excluded middle. For example, the uncountable space of functions   may be asserted to be subcountable, a notion of size orthogonal to the statement  .[12] In such a context, the subcountability of all sets is possible, or injections from the uncountable   into  .[13]

Open questions

Motivated by the insight that the set of real numbers is "bigger" than the set of natural numbers, one is led to ask if there is a set whose cardinality is "between" that of the integers and that of the reals. This question leads to the famous continuum hypothesis. Similarly, the question of whether there exists a set whose cardinality is between |S| and |P(S)| for some infinite S leads to the generalized continuum hypothesis.

Diagonalization in broader context

Russell's paradox has shown that naive set theory, based on an unrestricted comprehension scheme, is contradictory. Note that there is a similarity between the construction of T and the set in Russell's paradox. Therefore, depending on how we modify the axiom scheme of comprehension in order to avoid Russell's paradox, arguments such as the non-existence of a set of all sets may or may not remain valid.

Analogues of the diagonal argument are widely used in mathematics to prove the existence or nonexistence of certain objects. For example, the conventional proof of the unsolvability of the halting problem is essentially a diagonal argument. Also, diagonalization was originally used to show the existence of arbitrarily hard complexity classes and played a key role in early attempts to prove P does not equal NP.

Version for Quine's New Foundations

The above proof fails for W. V. Quine's "New Foundations" set theory (NF). In NF, the naive axiom scheme of comprehension is modified to avoid the paradoxes by introducing a kind of "local" type theory. In this axiom scheme,

{ sS: sf(s) }

is not a set — i.e., does not satisfy the axiom scheme. On the other hand, we might try to create a modified diagonal argument by noticing that

{ sS: sf({s}) }

is a set in NF. In which case, if P1(S) is the set of one-element subsets of S and f is a proposed bijection from P1(S) to P(S), one is able to use proof by contradiction to prove that |P1(S)| < |P(S)|.

The proof follows by the fact that if f were indeed a map onto P(S), then we could find r in S, such that f({r}) coincides with the modified diagonal set, above. We would conclude that if r is not in f({r}), then r is in f({r}) and vice versa.

It is not possible to put P1(S) in a one-to-one relation with S, as the two have different types, and so any function so defined would violate the typing rules for the comprehension scheme.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Cantor used "m and "w" instead of "0" and "1", "M" instead of "T", and "Ei" instead of "si".
  2. ^ Cantor does not assume that every element of T is in this enumeration.
  3. ^ While 0.0111... and 0.1000... would be equal if interpreted as binary fractions (destroying injectivity), they are different when interpreted as decimal fractions, as is done by f. On the other hand, since t is a binary string, the equality 0.0999... = 0.1000... of decimal fractions is not relevant here.

References

  1. ^ a b Georg Cantor (1891). "Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 1: 75–78. English translation: Ewald, William B., ed. (1996). From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert: A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics, Volume 2. Oxford University Press. pp. 920–922. ISBN 0-19-850536-1.
  2. ^ a b c Keith Simmons (30 July 1993). Universality and the Liar: An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-43069-2.
  3. ^ Rudin, Walter (1976). Principles of Mathematical Analysis (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. p. 30. ISBN 0070856133.
  4. ^ Gray, Robert (1994), "Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers" (PDF), American Mathematical Monthly, 101 (9): 819–832, doi:10.2307/2975129, JSTOR 2975129
  5. ^ Bloch, Ethan D. (2011). The Real Numbers and Real Analysis. New York: Springer. p. 429. ISBN 978-0-387-72176-7.
  6. ^ Sheppard, Barnaby (2014). The Logic of Infinity (illustrated ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 73. ISBN 978-1-107-05831-6. Extract of page 73
  7. ^ Russell's paradox. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. 2021.
  8. ^ Bertrand Russell (1931). Principles of mathematics. Norton. pp. 363–366.
  9. ^ See page 254 of Georg Cantor (1878), "Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre", Journal für die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik, 84: 242–258. This proof is discussed in Joseph Dauben (1979), Georg Cantor: His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite, Harvard University Press, ISBN 0-674-34871-0, pp. 61–62, 65. On page 65, Dauben proves a result that is stronger than Cantor's. He lets "φν denote any sequence of rationals in [0, 1]." Cantor lets φν denote a sequence enumerating the rationals in [0, 1], which is the kind of sequence needed for his construction of a bijection between [0, 1] and the irrationals in (0, 1).
  10. ^ Pradic, Pierre; Brown, Chad E. (2019). "Cantor-Bernstein implies Excluded Middle". arXiv:1904.09193 [math.LO].
  11. ^ Ettore Carruccio (2006). Mathematics and Logic in History and in Contemporary Thought. Transaction Publishers. p. 354. ISBN 978-0-202-30850-0.
  12. ^ Rathjen, M. "Choice principles in constructive and classical set theories", Proceedings of the Logic Colloquium, 2002
  13. ^ Bauer, A. "An injection from N^N to N", 2011

External links

cantor, diagonal, argument, this, article, about, concept, number, theory, confused, with, matrix, diagonalization, diagonalization, disambiguation, several, other, uses, term, mathematics, theory, also, called, diagonalisation, argument, diagonal, slash, argu. This article is about a concept in set and number theory Not to be confused with matrix diagonalization See diagonalization disambiguation for several other uses of the term in mathematics In set theory Cantor s diagonal argument also called the diagonalisation argument the diagonal slash argument the anti diagonal argument the diagonal method and Cantor s diagonalization proof was published in 1891 by Georg Cantor as a mathematical proof that there are infinite sets which cannot be put into one to one correspondence with the infinite set of natural numbers 1 2 20 3 Such sets are now known as uncountable sets and the size of infinite sets is now treated by the theory of cardinal numbers which Cantor began An illustration of Cantor s diagonal argument in base 2 for the existence of uncountable sets The sequence at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the enumeration of sequences above An infinite set may have the same cardinality as a proper subset of itself as the depicted bijection f x 2x from the natural to the even numbers demonstrates Nevertheless infinite sets of different cardinalities exist as Cantor s diagonal argument shows The diagonal argument was not Cantor s first proof of the uncountability of the real numbers which appeared in 1874 4 5 However it demonstrates a general technique that has since been used in a wide range of proofs 6 including the first of Godel s incompleteness theorems 2 and Turing s answer to the Entscheidungsproblem Diagonalization arguments are often also the source of contradictions like Russell s paradox 7 8 and Richard s paradox 2 27 Contents 1 Uncountable set 1 1 Real numbers 1 2 General sets 2 Consequences 2 1 Ordering of cardinals 2 2 Open questions 2 3 Diagonalization in broader context 3 Version for Quine s New Foundations 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksUncountable set EditCantor considered the set T of all infinite sequences of binary digits i e each digit is zero or one note 1 He begins with a constructive proof of the following lemma If s1 s2 sn is any enumeration of elements from T note 2 then an element s of T can be constructed that doesn t correspond to any sn in the enumeration The proof starts with an enumeration of elements from T for example s1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 s2 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 s3 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 s4 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 s5 1 1 0 1 0 1 1 s6 0 0 1 1 0 1 1 s7 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 Next a sequence s is constructed by choosing the 1st digit as complementary to the 1st digit of s1 swapping 0s for 1s and vice versa the 2nd digit as complementary to the 2nd digit of s2 the 3rd digit as complementary to the 3rd digit of s3 and generally for every n the nth digit as complementary to the nth digit of sn For the example above this yields s1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 s2 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 s3 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 s4 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 s5 1 1 0 1 0 1 1 s6 0 0 1 1 0 1 1 s7 1 0 0 0 1 0 0 s 1 0 1 1 1 0 1 By construction s is a member of T that differs from each sn since their nth digits differ highlighted in the example Hence s cannot occur in the enumeration Based on this lemma Cantor then uses a proof by contradiction to show that The set T is uncountable The proof starts by assuming that T is countable Then all its elements can be written in an enumeration s1 s2 sn Applying the previous lemma to this enumeration produces a sequence s that is a member of T but is not in the enumeration However if T is enumerated then every member of T including this s is in the enumeration This contradiction implies that the original assumption is false Therefore T is uncountable 1 Real numbers Edit The uncountability of the real numbers was already established by Cantor s first uncountability proof but it also follows from the above result To prove this an injection will be constructed from the set T of infinite binary strings to the set R of real numbers Since T is uncountable the image of this function which is a subset of R is uncountable Therefore R is uncountable Also by using a method of construction devised by Cantor a bijection will be constructed between T and R Therefore T and R have the same cardinality which is called the cardinality of the continuum and is usually denoted by c displaystyle mathfrak c or 2 ℵ 0 displaystyle 2 aleph 0 An injection from T to R is given by mapping binary strings in T to decimal fractions such as mapping t 0111 to the decimal 0 0111 This function defined by f t 0 t is an injection because it maps different strings to different numbers note 3 Constructing a bijection between T and R is slightly more complicated Instead of mapping 0111 to the decimal 0 0111 it can be mapped to the base b number 0 0111 b This leads to the family of functions fb t 0 tb The functions f b t are injections except for f 2 t This function will be modified to produce a bijection between T and R Construction of a bijection between T and R The function h 0 1 p 2 p 2 The function tan p 2 p 2 R This construction uses a method devised by Cantor that was published in 1878 He used it to construct a bijection between the closed interval 0 1 and the irrationals in the open interval 0 1 He first removed a countably infinite subset from each of these sets so that there is a bijection between the remaining uncountable sets Since there is a bijection between the countably infinite subsets that have been removed combining the two bijections produces a bijection between the original sets 9 Cantor s method can be used to modify the function f 2 t 0 t2 to produce a bijection from T to 0 1 Because some numbers have two binary expansions f 2 t is not even injective For example f 2 1000 0 1000 2 1 2 and f 2 0111 0 0111 2 1 4 1 8 1 16 1 2 so both 1000 and 0111 map to the same number 1 2 To modify f2 t observe that it is a bijection except for a countably infinite subset of 0 1 and a countably infinite subset of T It is not a bijection for the numbers in 0 1 that have two binary expansions These are called dyadic numbers and have the form m 2n where m is an odd integer and n is a natural number Put these numbers in the sequence r 1 2 1 4 3 4 1 8 3 8 5 8 7 8 Also f2 t is not a bijection to 0 1 for the strings in T appearing after the binary point in the binary expansions of 0 1 and the numbers in sequence r Put these eventually constant strings in the sequence s 000 111 1000 0111 01000 00111 11000 10111 Define the bijection g t from T to 0 1 If t is the nth string in sequence s let g t be the nth number in sequence r otherwise g t 0 t2 To construct a bijection from T to R start with the tangent function tan x which is a bijection from p 2 p 2 to R see the figure shown on the right Next observe that the linear function h x px p 2 is a bijection from 0 1 to p 2 p 2 see the figure shown on the left The composite function tan h x tan px p 2 is a bijection from 0 1 to R Composing this function with g t produces the function tan h g t tan pg t p 2 which is a bijection from T to R General sets Edit Illustration of the generalized diagonal argument The set T n N displaystyle mathbb N n f n at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the range of f N displaystyle mathbb N P N displaystyle mathbb N The example mapping f happens to correspond to the example enumeration s in the above picture A generalized form of the diagonal argument was used by Cantor to prove Cantor s theorem for every set S the power set of S that is the set of all subsets of S here written as P S cannot be in bijection with S itself This proof proceeds as follows Let f be any function from S to P S It suffices to prove f cannot be surjective That means that some member T of P S i e some subset of S is not in the image of f As a candidate consider the set T s S s f s For every s in S either s is in T or not If s is in T then by definition of T s is not in f s so T is not equal to f s On the other hand if s is not in T then by definition of T s is in f s so again T is not equal to f s cf picture For a more complete account of this proof see Cantor s theorem Consequences EditOrdering of cardinals Edit Cantor defines an order relation of cardinalities e g S displaystyle S and T displaystyle T in terms of the existence of injections between the underlying sets S displaystyle S and T displaystyle T The argument in the previous paragraph then proved that sets such as N 0 1 displaystyle mathbb N to 0 1 are uncountable which is to say N 0 1 N displaystyle neg mathbb N to 0 1 leq mathbb N and we can embed the naturals into the function space so that we have that N lt N 0 1 displaystyle mathbb N lt mathbb N to 0 1 In the context of classical mathematics this exhausts the possibilities and the diagonal argument can thus be used to establish that for example although both sets under consideration are infinite there are actually more infinite sequences of ones and zeros than there are natural numbers Cantor s result then also implies that the notion of the set of all sets is inconsistent If S were the set of all sets then P S would at the same time be bigger than S and a subset of S Assuming the law of excluded middle every subcountable set a property in terms of surjections is also already countable In Constructive mathematics it is harder or impossible to order ordinals and also cardinals For example the Schroder Bernstein theorem requires the law of excluded middle 10 Therefore intuitionists do not accept the theorem about the cardinal ordering 11 The ordering on the reals the standard ordering extending that of the rational numbers is also not necessarily decidable Neither are most properties of interesting classes of functions decidable by Rice s theorem i e the right set of counting numbers for the subcountable sets may not be recursive In a set theory theories of mathematics are modeled For example in set theory the set of real numbers is identified as a set that fulfills some axioms of real numbers Various models have been studied such as the Dedekind reals or the Cauchy reals Weaker axioms mean less constraints and so allow for a richer class of models Consequently in an otherwise constructive context law of excluded middle not taken as axiom it is consistent to adopt non classical axioms that contradict consequences of the law of excluded middle For example the uncountable space of functions N 0 1 displaystyle mathbb N to 0 1 may be asserted to be subcountable a notion of size orthogonal to the statement N lt N 0 1 displaystyle mathbb N lt mathbb N to 0 1 12 In such a context the subcountability of all sets is possible or injections from the uncountable N N displaystyle mathbb N mathbb N into N displaystyle mathbb N 13 Open questions Edit Motivated by the insight that the set of real numbers is bigger than the set of natural numbers one is led to ask if there is a set whose cardinality is between that of the integers and that of the reals This question leads to the famous continuum hypothesis Similarly the question of whether there exists a set whose cardinality is between S and P S for some infinite S leads to the generalized continuum hypothesis Diagonalization in broader context Edit Russell s paradox has shown that naive set theory based on an unrestricted comprehension scheme is contradictory Note that there is a similarity between the construction of T and the set in Russell s paradox Therefore depending on how we modify the axiom scheme of comprehension in order to avoid Russell s paradox arguments such as the non existence of a set of all sets may or may not remain valid Analogues of the diagonal argument are widely used in mathematics to prove the existence or nonexistence of certain objects For example the conventional proof of the unsolvability of the halting problem is essentially a diagonal argument Also diagonalization was originally used to show the existence of arbitrarily hard complexity classes and played a key role in early attempts to prove P does not equal NP Version for Quine s New Foundations EditThe above proof fails for W V Quine s New Foundations set theory NF In NF the naive axiom scheme of comprehension is modified to avoid the paradoxes by introducing a kind of local type theory In this axiom scheme s S s f s is not a set i e does not satisfy the axiom scheme On the other hand we might try to create a modified diagonal argument by noticing that s S s f s is a set in NF In which case if P1 S is the set of one element subsets of S and f is a proposed bijection from P1 S to P S one is able to use proof by contradiction to prove that P1 S lt P S The proof follows by the fact that if f were indeed a map onto P S then we could find r in S such that f r coincides with the modified diagonal set above We would conclude that if r is not in f r then r is in f r and vice versa It is not possible to put P1 S in a one to one relation with S as the two have different types and so any function so defined would violate the typing rules for the comprehension scheme See also EditCantor s first uncountability proof Controversy over Cantor s theory Diagonal lemmaNotes Edit Cantor used m and w instead of 0 and 1 M instead of T and Ei instead of si Cantor does not assume that every element of T is in this enumeration While 0 0111 and 0 1000 would be equal if interpreted as binary fractions destroying injectivity they are different when interpreted as decimal fractions as is done by f On the other hand since t is a binary string the equality 0 0999 0 1000 of decimal fractions is not relevant here References Edit a b Georg Cantor 1891 Ueber eine elementare Frage der Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung 1 75 78 English translation Ewald William B ed 1996 From Immanuel Kant to David Hilbert A Source Book in the Foundations of Mathematics Volume 2 Oxford University Press pp 920 922 ISBN 0 19 850536 1 a b c Keith Simmons 30 July 1993 Universality and the Liar An Essay on Truth and the Diagonal Argument Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 43069 2 Rudin Walter 1976 Principles of Mathematical Analysis 3rd ed New York McGraw Hill p 30 ISBN 0070856133 Gray Robert 1994 Georg Cantor and Transcendental Numbers PDF American Mathematical Monthly 101 9 819 832 doi 10 2307 2975129 JSTOR 2975129 Bloch Ethan D 2011 The Real Numbers and Real Analysis New York Springer p 429 ISBN 978 0 387 72176 7 Sheppard Barnaby 2014 The Logic of Infinity illustrated ed Cambridge University Press p 73 ISBN 978 1 107 05831 6 Extract of page 73 Russell s paradox Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy 2021 Bertrand Russell 1931 Principles of mathematics Norton pp 363 366 See page 254 of Georg Cantor 1878 Ein Beitrag zur Mannigfaltigkeitslehre Journal fur die Reine und Angewandte Mathematik 84 242 258 This proof is discussed in Joseph Dauben 1979 Georg Cantor His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 34871 0 pp 61 62 65 On page 65 Dauben proves a result that is stronger than Cantor s He lets fn denote any sequence of rationals in 0 1 Cantor lets fn denote a sequence enumerating the rationals in 0 1 which is the kind of sequence needed for his construction of a bijection between 0 1 and the irrationals in 0 1 Pradic Pierre Brown Chad E 2019 Cantor Bernstein implies Excluded Middle arXiv 1904 09193 math LO Ettore Carruccio 2006 Mathematics and Logic in History and in Contemporary Thought Transaction Publishers p 354 ISBN 978 0 202 30850 0 Rathjen M Choice principles in constructive and classical set theories Proceedings of the Logic Colloquium 2002 Bauer A An injection from N N to N 2011External links EditCantor s Diagonal Proof at MathPages Weisstein Eric W Cantor Diagonal Method MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Cantor 27s diagonal argument amp oldid 1126881957, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.