fbpx
Wikipedia

Abductive reasoning

Abductive reasoning (also called abduction,[1] abductive inference,[1] or retroduction[2]) is a form of logical inference that seeks the simplest and most likely conclusion from a set of observations. It was formulated and advanced by American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce beginning in the latter half of the 19th century.

A Mastermind player uses abduction to infer the secret colors (top) from summaries (bottom left) of discrepancies in their guesses (bottom right).

Abductive reasoning, unlike deductive reasoning, yields a plausible conclusion but does not definitively verify it. Abductive conclusions do not eliminate uncertainty or doubt, which is expressed in retreat terms such as "best available" or "most likely". While inductive reasoning draws general conclusions that apply to many situations, abductive conclusions are confined to the particular observations in question.

In the 1990s, as computing power grew, the fields of law,[3] computer science, and artificial intelligence research[4] spurred renewed interest in the subject of abduction.[5] Diagnostic expert systems frequently employ abduction.[6]

Deduction, induction, and abduction edit

Deduction edit

Deductive reasoning allows deriving   from   only where   is a formal logical consequence of  . In other words, deduction derives the consequences of the assumed. Given the truth of the assumptions, a valid deduction guarantees the truth of the conclusion. For example, given that "Wikis can be edited by anyone" ( ) and "Wikipedia is a wiki" ( ), it follows that "Wikipedia can be edited by anyone" ( ).

Induction edit

Inductive reasoning is the process of inferring some general principle   from a body of knowledge  , where   does not necessarily follow from  .   might give us very good reason to accept  , but does not ensure  . For example, if all swans that we have observed so far are white, we may induce that the possibility that all swans are white is reasonable. We have good reason to believe the conclusion from the premise, but the truth of the conclusion is not guaranteed. (Indeed, it turns out that some swans are black.)

Abduction edit

Abductive reasoning allows inferring   as an explanation of  . As a result of this inference, abduction allows the precondition   to be abducted from the consequence  . Deductive reasoning and abductive reasoning thus differ in which end, left or right, of the proposition "  entails  " serves as conclusion. For example, in a billiard game, after glancing and seeing the eight ball moving towards us, we may abduce that the cue ball struck the eight ball. The strike of the cue ball would account for the movement of the eight ball. It serves as a hypothesis that explains our observation. Given the many possible explanations for the movement of the eight ball, our abduction does not leave us certain that the cue ball in fact struck the eight ball, but our abduction, still useful, can serve to orient us in our surroundings. Despite many possible explanations for any physical process that we observe, we tend to abduce a single explanation (or a few explanations) for this process in the expectation that we can better orient ourselves in our surroundings and disregard some possibilities. Properly used, abductive reasoning can be a useful source of priors in Bayesian statistics.

One can understand abductive reasoning as inference to the best explanation,[7] although not all usages of the terms abduction and inference to the best explanation are equivalent.[8][9]

Formalizations of abduction edit

Logic-based abduction edit

In logic, explanation is accomplished through the use of a logical theory   representing a domain and a set of observations  . Abduction is the process of deriving a set of explanations of   according to   and picking out one of those explanations. For   to be an explanation of   according to  , it should satisfy two conditions:

  •   follows from   and  ;
  •   is consistent with  .

In formal logic,   and   are assumed to be sets of literals. The two conditions for   being an explanation of   according to theory   are formalized as:

 
  is consistent.

Among the possible explanations   satisfying these two conditions, some other condition of minimality is usually imposed to avoid irrelevant facts (not contributing to the entailment of  ) being included in the explanations. Abduction is then the process that picks out some member of  . Criteria for picking out a member representing "the best" explanation include the simplicity, the prior probability, or the explanatory power of the explanation.

A proof-theoretical abduction method for first-order classical logic based on the sequent calculus and a dual one, based on semantic tableaux (analytic tableaux) have been proposed.[10] The methods are sound and complete and work for full first-order logic, without requiring any preliminary reduction of formulae into normal forms. These methods have also been extended to modal logic.[11]

Abductive logic programming is a computational framework that extends normal logic programming with abduction. It separates the theory   into two components, one of which is a normal logic program, used to generate   by means of backward reasoning, the other of which is a set of integrity constraints, used to filter the set of candidate explanations.

Set-cover abduction edit

A different formalization of abduction is based on inverting the function that calculates the visible effects of the hypotheses. Formally, we are given a set of hypotheses   and a set of manifestations  ; they are related by the domain knowledge, represented by a function   that takes as an argument a set of hypotheses and gives as a result the corresponding set of manifestations. In other words, for every subset of the hypotheses  , their effects are known to be  .

Abduction is performed by finding a set   such that  . In other words, abduction is performed by finding a set of hypotheses   such that their effects   include all observations  .

A common assumption is that the effects of the hypotheses are independent, that is, for every  , it holds that  . If this condition is met, abduction can be seen as a form of set covering.

Abductive validation edit

Abductive validation is the process of validating a given hypothesis through abductive reasoning. This can also be called reasoning through successive approximation.[citation needed] Under this principle, an explanation is valid if it is the best possible explanation of a set of known data. The best possible explanation is often defined in terms of simplicity and elegance (see Occam's razor). Abductive validation is common practice in hypothesis formation in science; moreover, Peirce claims that it is a ubiquitous aspect of thought:

Looking out my window this lovely spring morning, I see an azalea in full bloom. No, no! I don't see that; though that is the only way I can describe what I see. That is a proposition, a sentence, a fact; but what I perceive is not proposition, sentence, fact, but only an image, which I make intelligible in part by means of a statement of fact. This statement is abstract; but what I see is concrete. I perform an abduction when I so much as express in a sentence anything I see. The truth is that the whole fabric of our knowledge is one matted felt of pure hypothesis confirmed and refined by induction. Not the smallest advance can be made in knowledge beyond the stage of vacant staring, without making an abduction at every step.[12]

It was Peirce's own maxim that "Facts cannot be explained by a hypothesis more extraordinary than these facts themselves; and of various hypotheses the least extraordinary must be adopted."[13] After obtaining possible hypotheses that may explain the facts, abductive validation is a method for identifying the most likely hypothesis that should be adopted.

Subjective logic abduction edit

Subjective logic generalises probabilistic logic by including degrees of epistemic uncertainty in the input arguments, i.e. instead of probabilities, the analyst can express arguments as subjective opinions. Abduction in subjective logic is thus a generalization of probabilistic abduction described above.[14] The input arguments in subjective logic are subjective opinions which can be binomial when the opinion applies to a binary variable or multinomial when it applies to an n-ary variable. A subjective opinion thus applies to a state variable   which takes its values from a domain   (i.e. a state space of exhaustive and mutually disjoint state values  ), and is denoted by the tuple  , where   is the belief mass distribution over  ,   is the epistemic uncertainty mass, and   is the base rate distribution over  . These parameters satisfy   and   as well as  .

Assume the domains   and   with respective variables   and  , the set of conditional opinions   (i.e. one conditional opinion for each value  ), and the base rate distribution  . Based on these parameters, the subjective Bayes' theorem denoted with the operator   produces the set of inverted conditionals   (i.e. one inverted conditional for each value  ) expressed by:

 .

Using these inverted conditionals together with the opinion   subjective deduction denoted by the operator   can be used to abduce the marginal opinion  . The equality between the different expressions for subjective abduction is given below:

 

The symbolic notation for subjective abduction is " ", and the operator itself is denoted as " ". The operator for the subjective Bayes' theorem is denoted " ", and subjective deduction is denoted " ".[14]

The advantage of using subjective logic abduction compared to probabilistic abduction is that both aleatoric and epistemic uncertainty about the input argument probabilities can be explicitly expressed and taken into account during the analysis. It is thus possible to perform abductive analysis in the presence of uncertain arguments, which naturally results in degrees of uncertainty in the output conclusions.

History edit

The idea that the simplest, most easily verifiable solution should be preferred over its more complicated counterparts is a very old one. To this point, George Pólya, in his treatise on problem-solving, makes reference to the following Latin truism: simplex sigillum veri (simplicity is the seal of truth).[15]

Introduction and development by Peirce edit

Overview edit

The American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce introduced abduction into modern logic. Over the years he called such inference hypothesis, abduction, presumption, and retroduction. He considered it a topic in logic as a normative field in philosophy, not in purely formal or mathematical logic, and eventually as a topic also in economics of research.

As two stages of the development, extension, etc., of a hypothesis in scientific inquiry, abduction and also induction are often collapsed into one overarching concept—the hypothesis. That is why, in the scientific method known from Galileo and Bacon, the abductive stage of hypothesis formation is conceptualized simply as induction. Thus, in the twentieth century this collapse was reinforced by Karl Popper's explication of the hypothetico-deductive model, where the hypothesis is considered to be just "a guess"[16] (in the spirit of Peirce). However, when the formation of a hypothesis is considered the result of a process it becomes clear that this "guess" has already been tried and made more robust in thought as a necessary stage of its acquiring the status of hypothesis. Indeed, many abductions are rejected or heavily modified by subsequent abductions before they ever reach this stage.

Before 1900, Peirce treated abduction as the use of a known rule to explain an observation. For instance: it is a known rule that, if it rains, grass gets wet; so, to explain the fact that the grass on this lawn is wet, one abduces that it has rained. Abduction can lead to false conclusions if other rules that might explain the observation are not taken into account—e.g. the grass could be wet from dew. This remains the common use of the term "abduction" in the social sciences and in artificial intelligence.

Peirce consistently characterized it as the kind of inference that originates a hypothesis by concluding in an explanation, though an unassured one, for some very curious or surprising (anomalous) observation stated in a premise. As early as 1865 he wrote that all conceptions of cause and force are reached through hypothetical inference; in the 1900s he wrote that all explanatory content of theories is reached through abduction. In other respects Peirce revised his view of abduction over the years.[17]

In later years his view came to be:

  • Abduction is guessing.[18] It is "very little hampered" by rules of logic.[19] Even a well-prepared mind's individual guesses are more frequently wrong than right.[20] But the success of our guesses far exceeds that of random luck and seems born of attunement to nature by instinct[21] (some speak of intuition in such contexts[22]).
  • Abduction guesses a new or outside idea so as to account in a plausible, instinctive, economical way for a surprising or very complicated phenomenon. That is its proximate aim.[21]
  • Its longer aim is to economize inquiry itself. Its rationale is inductive: it works often enough, is the only source of new ideas, and has no substitute in expediting the discovery of new truths.[23] Its rationale especially involves its role in coordination with other modes of inference in inquiry. It is inference to explanatory hypotheses for selection of those best worth trying.
  • Pragmatism is the logic of abduction. Upon the generation of an explanation (which he came to regard as instinctively guided), the pragmatic maxim gives the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction in general. The hypothesis, being insecure, needs to have conceivable[24] implications for informed practice, so as to be testable[25][26] and, through its trials, to expedite and economize inquiry. The economy of research is what calls for abduction and governs its art.[27]

Writing in 1910, Peirce admits that "in almost everything I printed before the beginning of this century I more or less mixed up hypothesis and induction" and he traces the confusion of these two types of reasoning to logicians' too "narrow and formalistic a conception of inference, as necessarily having formulated judgments from its premises."[28]

He started out in the 1860s treating hypothetical inference in a number of ways which he eventually peeled away as inessential or, in some cases, mistaken:

  • as inferring the occurrence of a character (a characteristic) from the observed combined occurrence of multiple characters which its occurrence would necessarily involve;[29] for example, if any occurrence of A is known to necessitate occurrence of B, C, D, E, then the observation of B, C, D, E suggests by way of explanation the occurrence of A. (But by 1878 he no longer regarded such multiplicity as common to all hypothetical inference.[30]Wikisource)
  • as aiming for a more or less probable hypothesis (in 1867 and 1883 but not in 1878; anyway by 1900 the justification is not probability but the lack of alternatives to guessing and the fact that guessing is fruitful;[31] by 1903 he speaks of the "likely" in the sense of nearing the truth in an "indefinite sense";[32] by 1908 he discusses plausibility as instinctive appeal.[21]) In a paper dated by editors as circa 1901, he discusses "instinct" and "naturalness", along with the kind of considerations (low cost of testing, logical caution, breadth, and incomplexity) that he later calls methodeutical.[33]
  • as induction from characters (but as early as 1900 he characterized abduction as guessing[31])
  • as citing a known rule in a premise rather than hypothesizing a rule in the conclusion (but by 1903 he allowed either approach[19][34])
  • as basically a transformation of a deductive categorical syllogism[30] (but in 1903 he offered a variation on modus ponens instead,[19] and by 1911 he was unconvinced that any one form covers all hypothetical inference[35]).

The Natural Classification of Arguments (1867) edit

In 1867, Peirce's "On the Natural Classification of Arguments",[29] hypothetical inference always deals with a cluster of characters (call them P′, P′′, P′′′, etc.) known to occur at least whenever a certain character (M) occurs. Note that categorical syllogisms have elements traditionally called middles, predicates, and subjects. For example: All men [middle] are mortal [predicate]; Socrates [subject] is a man [middle]; ergo Socrates [subject] is mortal [predicate]". Below, 'M' stands for a middle; 'P' for a predicate; 'S' for a subject. Peirce held that all deduction can be put into the form of the categorical syllogism Barbara (AAA-1).

[Deduction].

[Any] M is P
[Any] S is M
  [Any] S is P.

Induction.

S′, S′′, S′′′, &c. are taken at random as M's;
S′, S′′, S′′′, &c. are P:
  Any M is probably P.

Hypothesis.

Any M is, for instance, P′, P′′, P′′′, &c.;
S is P′, P′′, P′′′, &c.:
  S is probably M.

Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis (1878) edit

In 1878, in "Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis",[30] there is no longer a need for multiple characters or predicates in order for an inference to be hypothetical, although it is still helpful. Moreover, Peirce no longer poses hypothetical inference as concluding in a probable hypothesis. In the forms themselves, it is understood but not explicit that induction involves random selection and that hypothetical inference involves response to a "very curious circumstance". The forms instead emphasize the modes of inference as rearrangements of one another's propositions (without the bracketed hints shown below).

Deduction.

Rule: All the beans from this bag are white.
Case: These beans are from this bag.
  Result: These beans are white.

Induction.

Case: These beans are [randomly selected] from this bag.
Result: These beans are white.
  Rule: All the beans from this bag are white.

Hypothesis.

Rule: All the beans from this bag are white.
Result: These beans [oddly] are white.
  Case: These beans are from this bag.

A Theory of Probable Inference (1883) edit

Peirce long treated abduction in terms of induction from characters or traits (weighed, not counted like objects), explicitly so in his influential 1883 "A theory of probable inference", in which he returns to involving probability in the hypothetical conclusion.[36] Like "Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis" in 1878, it was widely read (see the historical books on statistics by Stephen Stigler), unlike his later amendments of his conception of abduction. Today abduction remains most commonly understood as induction from characters and extension of a known rule to cover unexplained circumstances.

Sherlock Holmes used this method of reasoning in the stories of Arthur Conan Doyle, although Holmes refers to it as "deductive reasoning".[37][38][39]

Minute Logic (1902) and after edit

In 1902 Peirce wrote that he now regarded the syllogistical forms and the doctrine of extension and comprehension (i.e., objects and characters as referenced by terms), as being less fundamental than he had earlier thought.[40] In 1903 he offered the following form for abduction:[19]

The surprising fact, C, is observed;

But if A were true, C would be a matter of course,
Hence, there is reason to suspect that A is true.

The hypothesis is framed, but not asserted, in a premise, then asserted as rationally suspectable in the conclusion. Thus, as in the earlier categorical syllogistic form, the conclusion is formulated from some premise(s). But all the same the hypothesis consists more clearly than ever in a new or outside idea beyond what is known or observed. Induction in a sense goes beyond observations already reported in the premises, but it merely amplifies ideas already known to represent occurrences, or tests an idea supplied by hypothesis; either way it requires previous abductions in order to get such ideas in the first place. Induction seeks facts to test a hypothesis; abduction seeks a hypothesis to account for facts.

Note that the hypothesis ("A") could be of a rule. It need not even be a rule strictly necessitating the surprising observation ("C"), which needs to follow only as a "matter of course"; or the "course" itself could amount to some known rule, merely alluded to, and also not necessarily a rule of strict necessity. In the same year, Peirce wrote that reaching a hypothesis may involve placing a surprising observation under either a newly hypothesized rule or a hypothesized combination of a known rule with a peculiar state of facts, so that the phenomenon would be not surprising but instead either necessarily implied or at least likely.[34]

Peirce did not remain quite convinced about any such form as the categorical syllogistic form or the 1903 form. In 1911, he wrote, "I do not, at present, feel quite convinced that any logical form can be assigned that will cover all 'Retroductions'. For what I mean by a Retroduction is simply a conjecture which arises in the mind."[35]

Pragmatism edit

In 1901 Peirce wrote, "There would be no logic in imposing rules, and saying that they ought to be followed, until it is made out that the purpose of hypothesis requires them."[41] In 1903 Peirce called pragmatism "the logic of abduction" and said that the pragmatic maxim gives the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction in general.[26] The pragmatic maxim is:

Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, we conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object.

It is a method for fruitful clarification of conceptions by equating the meaning of a conception with the conceivable practical implications of its object's conceived effects. Peirce held that that is precisely tailored to abduction's purpose in inquiry, the forming of an idea that could conceivably shape informed conduct. In various writings in the 1900s[27][42] he said that the conduct of abduction (or retroduction) is governed by considerations of economy, belonging in particular to the economics of research. He regarded economics as a normative science whose analytic portion might be part of logical methodeutic (that is, theory of inquiry).[43]

Three levels of logic about abduction edit

Peirce came over the years to divide (philosophical) logic into three departments:

  1. Stechiology, or speculative grammar, on the conditions for meaningfulness. Classification of signs (semblances, symptoms, symbols, etc.) and their combinations (as well as their objects and interpretants).
  2. Logical critic, or logic proper, on validity or justifiability of inference, the conditions for true representation. Critique of arguments in their various modes (deduction, induction, abduction).
  3. Methodeutic, or speculative rhetoric, on the conditions for determination of interpretations. Methodology of inquiry in its interplay of modes.

Peirce had, from the start, seen the modes of inference as being coordinated together in scientific inquiry and, by the 1900s, held that hypothetical inference in particular is inadequately treated at the level of critique of arguments.[25][26] To increase the assurance of a hypothetical conclusion, one needs to deduce implications about evidence to be found, predictions which induction can test through observation so as to evaluate the hypothesis. That is Peirce's outline of the scientific method of inquiry, as covered in his inquiry methodology, which includes pragmatism or, as he later called it, pragmaticism, the clarification of ideas in terms of their conceivable implications regarding informed practice.

Classification of signs edit

As early as 1866,[44] Peirce held that:

1. Hypothesis (abductive inference) is inference through an icon (also called a likeness).
2. Induction is inference through an index (a sign by factual connection); a sample is an index of the totality from which it is drawn.
3. Deduction is inference through a symbol (a sign by interpretive habit irrespective of resemblance or connection to its object).

In 1902, Peirce wrote that, in abduction: "It is recognized that the phenomena are like, i.e. constitute an Icon of, a replica of a general conception, or Symbol."[45]

Critique of arguments edit

At the critical level Peirce examined the forms of abductive arguments (as discussed above), and came to hold that the hypothesis should economize explanation for plausibility in terms of the feasible and natural. In 1908 Peirce described this plausibility in some detail.[21] It involves not likeliness based on observations (which is instead the inductive evaluation of a hypothesis), but instead optimal simplicity in the sense of the "facile and natural", as by Galileo's natural light of reason and as distinct from "logical simplicity" (Peirce does not dismiss logical simplicity entirely but sees it in a subordinate role; taken to its logical extreme it would favor adding no explanation to the observation at all). Even a well-prepared mind guesses oftener wrong than right, but our guesses succeed better than random luck at reaching the truth or at least advancing the inquiry, and that indicates to Peirce that they are based in instinctive attunement to nature, an affinity between the mind's processes and the processes of the real, which would account for why appealingly "natural" guesses are the ones that oftenest (or least seldom) succeed; to which Peirce added the argument that such guesses are to be preferred since, without "a natural bent like nature's", people would have no hope of understanding nature. In 1910 Peirce made a three-way distinction between probability, verisimilitude, and plausibility, and defined plausibility with a normative "ought": "By plausibility, I mean the degree to which a theory ought to recommend itself to our belief independently of any kind of evidence other than our instinct urging us to regard it favorably."[46] For Peirce, plausibility does not depend on observed frequencies or probabilities, or on verisimilitude, or even on testability, which is not a question of the critique of the hypothetical inference as an inference, but rather a question of the hypothesis's relation to the inquiry process.

The phrase "inference to the best explanation" (not used by Peirce but often applied to hypothetical inference) is not always understood as referring to the most simple and natural hypotheses (such as those with the fewest assumptions). However, in other senses of "best", such as "standing up best to tests", it is hard to know which is the best explanation to form, since one has not tested it yet. Still, for Peirce, any justification of an abductive inference as "good" is not completed upon its formation as an argument (unlike with induction and deduction) and instead depends also on its methodological role and promise (such as its testability) in advancing inquiry.[25][26][47]

Methodology of inquiry edit

At the methodeutical level Peirce held that a hypothesis is judged and selected[25] for testing because it offers, via its trial, to expedite and economize the inquiry process itself toward new truths, first of all by being testable and also by further economies,[27] in terms of cost, value, and relationships among guesses (hypotheses). Here, considerations such as probability, absent from the treatment of abduction at the critical level, come into play. For examples:

  • Cost: A simple but low-odds guess, if low in cost to test for falsity, may belong first in line for testing, to get it out of the way. If surprisingly it stands up to tests, that is worth knowing early in the inquiry, which otherwise might have stayed long on a wrong though seemingly likelier track.
  • Value: A guess is intrinsically worth testing if it has instinctual plausibility or reasoned objective probability, while subjective likelihood, though reasoned, can be treacherous.
  • Interrelationships: Guesses can be chosen for trial strategically for their
    • caution, for which Peirce gave as an example the game of Twenty Questions,
    • breadth of applicability to explain various phenomena, and
    • incomplexity, that of a hypothesis that seems too simple but whose trial "may give a good 'leave', as the billiard-players say", and be instructive for the pursuit of various and conflicting hypotheses that are less simple.[48]

Uberty edit

Peirce[49] indicated that abductive reasoning is driven by the need for "economy in research"—the expected fact-based productivity of hypotheses, prior to deductive and inductive processes of verification. A key concept proposed by him in this regard is "uberty"[50]—the expected fertility and pragmatic value of reasoning. This concept seems to be gaining support via association to the Free Energy Principle.[51]

Gilbert Harman (1965) edit

Gilbert Harman is a professor of philosophy at Princeton University. Harman's 1965 account of the role of "inference to the best explanation" – inferring the existence of that which we need for the best explanation of observable phenomena – has been very influential.

Stephen Jay Gould (1995) edit

Stephen Jay Gould, in answering the Omphalos hypothesis, claimed that only hypotheses that can be proved incorrect lie within the domain of science and only these hypotheses are good explanations of facts worth inferring to.[52]

"[W]hat is so desperately wrong with Omphalos? Only this really (and perhaps paradoxically): that we can devise no way to find out whether it is wrong—or for that matter, right. Omphalos is the classic example of an utterly untestable notion, for the world will look exactly the same in all its intricate detail whether fossils and strata are prochronic [signs of a fictitious past] or products of an extended history. . . . Science is a procedure for testing and rejecting hypotheses, not a compendium of certain knowledge. Claims that can be proved incorrect lie within its domain. . . . But theories that cannot be tested in principle are not part of science. . . . [W]e reject Omphalos as useless, not wrong."

Applications edit

Artificial intelligence edit

Applications in artificial intelligence include fault diagnosis, belief revision, and automated planning. The most direct application of abduction is that of automatically detecting faults in systems: given a theory relating faults with their effects and a set of observed effects, abduction can be used to derive sets of faults that are likely to be the cause of the problem.[4]

Medicine edit

In medicine, abduction can be seen as a component of clinical evaluation and judgment.[53][54]

Automated planning edit

Abduction can also be used to model automated planning.[55] Given a logical theory relating action occurrences with their effects (for example, a formula of the event calculus), the problem of finding a plan for reaching a state can be modeled as the problem of abducting a set of literals implying that the final state is the goal state.

Intelligence analysis edit

In intelligence analysis, analysis of competing hypotheses and Bayesian networks, probabilistic abductive reasoning is used extensively. Similarly in medical diagnosis and legal reasoning, the same methods are being used, although there have been many examples of errors, especially caused by the base rate fallacy and the prosecutor's fallacy.

Belief revision edit

Belief revision, the process of adapting beliefs in view of new information, is another field in which abduction has been applied. The main problem of belief revision is that the new information may be inconsistent with the prior web of beliefs, while the result of the incorporation cannot be inconsistent. The process of updating the web of beliefs can be done by the use of abduction: once an explanation for the observation has been found, integrating it does not generate inconsistency.

Gärdenfors’ paper[56] contains a brief survey of the area of belief revision and its relation to updating of logical databases, and explores the relationship between belief revision and nonmonotonic logic.

This use of abduction is not straightforward, as adding propositional formulae to other propositional formulae can only make inconsistencies worse. Instead, abduction is done at the level of the ordering of preference of the possible worlds. Preference models use fuzzy logic or utility models.

Philosophy of science edit

In the philosophy of science, abduction has been the key inference method to support scientific realism, and much of the debate about scientific realism is focused on whether abduction is an acceptable method of inference.[57]

Historical linguistics edit

In historical linguistics, abduction during language acquisition is often taken to be an essential part of processes of language change such as reanalysis and analogy.[58]

Applied linguistics edit

In applied linguistics research, abductive reasoning is starting to be used as an alternative explanation to inductive reasoning, in recognition of anticipated outcomes of qualitative inquiry playing a role in shaping the direction of analysis. It is defined as "The use of an unclear premise based on observations, pursuing theories to try to explain it" (Rose et al., 2020, p. 258)[59][60]

Anthropology edit

In anthropology, Alfred Gell in his influential book Art and Agency defined abduction (after Eco[61]) as "a case of synthetic inference 'where we find some very curious circumstances, which would be explained by the supposition that it was a case of some general rule, and thereupon adopt that supposition'".[62] Gell criticizes existing "anthropological" studies of art for being too preoccupied with aesthetic value and not preoccupied enough with the central anthropological concern of uncovering "social relationships", specifically the social contexts in which artworks are produced, circulated, and received.[63] Abduction is used as the mechanism for getting from art to agency. That is, abduction can explain how works of art inspire a sensus communis: the commonly held views shared by members that characterize a given society.[64]

The question Gell asks in the book is, "how does it initially 'speak' to people?" He answers by saying that "No reasonable person could suppose that art-like relations between people and things do not involve at least some form of semiosis."[62] However, he rejects any intimation that semiosis can be thought of as a language because then he would have to admit to some pre-established existence of the sensus communis that he wants to claim only emerges afterwards out of art. Abduction is the answer to this conundrum because the tentative nature of the abduction concept (Peirce likened it to guessing) means that not only can it operate outside of any pre-existing framework, but moreover, it can actually intimate the existence of a framework. As Gell reasons in his analysis, the physical existence of the artwork prompts the viewer to perform an abduction that imbues the artwork with intentionality. A statue of a goddess, for example, in some senses actually becomes the goddess in the mind of the beholder; and represents not only the form of the deity but also her intentions (which are adduced from the feeling of her very presence). Therefore, through abduction, Gell claims that art can have the kind of agency that plants the seeds that grow into cultural myths. The power of agency is the power to motivate actions and inspire ultimately the shared understanding that characterizes any given society.[64]

Computer programming edit

In formal methods, logic is used to specify and prove properties of computer programs. Abduction has been used in mechanized reasoning tools to increase the level of automation of the proof activity.

A technique known as bi-abduction, which mixes abduction and the frame problem, was used to scale reasoning techniques for memory properties to millions of lines of code;[65] logic-based abduction was used to infer pre-conditions for individual functions in a program, relieving the human of the need to do so. It led to a program-proof startup company, which was acquired by Facebook,[66] and the Infer program analysis tool, which led to thousands of bugs being prevented in industrial codebases.[67]

In addition to inference of function preconditions, abduction has been used to automate inference of invariants for program loops,[68] inference of specifications of unknown code,[69] and in synthesis of the programs themselves.[70]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b For example: Josephson, John R.; Josephson, Susan G., eds. (1994). Abductive Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511530128. ISBN 978-0521434614. OCLC 28149683.
  2. ^ . Commens – Digital Companion to C. S. Peirce. Mats Bergman, Sami Paavola & João Queiroz. Archived from the original on August 26, 2014. Retrieved August 24, 2014.
  3. ^ See, e.g. Analysis of Evidence, 2d ed. by Terence Anderson (Cambridge University Press, 2005)
  4. ^ a b For examples, see "", John R. Josephson, Laboratory for Artificial Intelligence Research, Ohio State University, and Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discovery and Explanation by Lorenzo Magnani (Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York, 2001).
  5. ^ Flach, P. A.; Kakas, A. C., eds. (2000). Abduction and Induction: Essays on their Relation and Integration. Springer. p. xiii. Retrieved October 31, 2016. This book grew out of a series of workshops on this topic. [Budapest 1996; Nagoya 1997; Brighton 1998]
  6. ^ Reggia, James A., et al. "Answer justification in diagnostic expert systems-Part I: Abductive inference and its justification." IEEE transactions on biomedical engineering 4 (1985): 263-267.
  7. ^ Sober, Elliott (2013). Core Questions in Philosophy: A Text with Readings (6th ed.). Boston: Pearson Education. p. 28. ISBN 9780205206698. OCLC 799024771. I now move to abduction—inference to the best explanation.
  8. ^ Campos, Daniel G. (June 2011). "On the distinction between Peirce's abduction and Lipton's inference to the best explanation". Synthese. 180 (3): 419–442. doi:10.1007/s11229-009-9709-3. S2CID 791688. I argue against the tendency in the philosophy of science literature to link abduction to the inference to the best explanation (IBE), and in particular, to claim that Peircean abduction is a conceptual predecessor to IBE. [...] In particular, I claim that Peircean abduction is an in-depth account of the process of generating explanatory hypotheses, while IBE, at least in Peter Lipton's thorough treatment, is a more encompassing account of the processes both of generating and of evaluating scientific hypotheses. There is then a two-fold problem with the claim that abduction is IBE. On the one hand, it conflates abduction and induction, which are two distinct forms of logical inference, with two distinct aims, as shown by Charles S. Peirce; on the other hand it lacks a clear sense of the full scope of IBE as an account of scientific inference.
  9. ^ Walton, Douglas (2001). "Abductive, presumptive and plausible arguments". Informal Logic. 21 (2): 141–169. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.127.1593. doi:10.22329/il.v21i2.2241. Abductive inference has often been equated with inference to the best explanation. [...] The account of abductive inference and inference to the best explanation presented above has emphasized the common elements found in the analyses given by Peirce, Harman and the Josephsons. It is necessary to add that this brief account may be misleading in some respects, and that a closer and more detailed explication of the finer points of the three analyses could reveal important underlying philosophical differences. Inferences to the best explanation, as expounded by Harman and the Josephsons, can involve deductive and inductive processes of a kind that would be apparently be excluded by Peirce's account of abduction.
  10. ^ Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora (1993) "First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi" Logic Jnl IGPL 1993 1: 99–117; doi:10.1093/jigpal/1.1.99. Oxford Journals
  11. ^ Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora (1993) "Propositional abduction in modal logic" Logic Jnl IGPL 1995 3(6) 907–919; doi:10.1093/jigpal/3.6.907. Oxford Journals
  12. ^ Peirce MS. 692, quoted in Sebeok, T. (1981) "You Know My Method" in Sebeok, T., The Play of Musement, Bloomington, IA: Indiana, page 24.
  13. ^ Peirce MS. 696, quoted in Sebeok, T. (1981) "You Know My Method" in Sebeok, T., The Play of Musement, Bloomington, IA: Indiana, page 31.
  14. ^ a b A. Jøsang. Subjective Logic: A Formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty, Springer 2016, ISBN 978-3-319-42337-1
  15. ^ Pólya, George (1945). How to solve it: a new aspect of mathematical method (Expanded Princeton Science Library (2004) ed.). Princeton [N.J.]: Princeton University Press. p. 45. ISBN 0-691-11966-X.
  16. ^ Popper, Karl (2002). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (2 ed.). London: Routledge. p. 536.
  17. ^ See Santaella, Lucia (1997) "The Development of Peirce's Three Types of Reasoning: Abduction, Deduction, and Induction", 6th Congress of the IASS. Eprint.
  18. ^ Peirce, C. S.
    • "On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient Documents especially from Testimonies" (1901), Collected Papers v. 7, paragraph 219.
    • "PAP" ["Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmatism"], MS 293 c. 1906, New Elements of Mathematics v. 4, pp. 319–320.
    • A Letter to F. A. Woods (1913), Collected Papers v. 8, paragraphs 385–388.
    (See under "Abduction" and "Retroduction" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.)
  19. ^ a b c d Peirce, C. S. (1903), Harvard lectures on pragmatism, Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 188–189.
  20. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", Hibbert Journal v. 7, pp. 90–112, see §4. In Collected Papers v. 6, see paragraph 476. In The Essential Peirce v. 2, see p. 444.
  21. ^ a b c d Peirce, C. S. (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", Hibbert Journal v. 7, pp. 90–112. See both part III and part IV. Reprinted, including originally unpublished portion, in Collected Papers v. 6, paragraphs 452–85, Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 434–50, and elsewhere.
  22. ^ Peirce used the term "intuition" not in the sense of an instinctive or anyway half-conscious inference as people often do currently. Instead he used "intuition" usually in the sense of a cognition devoid of logical determination by previous cognitions. He said, "We have no power of Intuition" in that sense. See his "Some Consequences of Four Incapacities" (1868), Eprint 2011-05-14 at the Wayback Machine.
  23. ^ For a relevant discussion of Peirce and the aims of abductive inference, see McKaughan, Daniel J. (2008), "From Ugly Duckling to Swan: C. S. Peirce, Abduction, and the Pursuit of Scientific Theories", Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, v. 44, no. 3 (summer), 446–468.
  24. ^ Peirce means "conceivable" very broadly. See Collected Papers v. 5, paragraph 196, or Essential Peirce v. 2, p. 235, "Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction" (Lecture VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism):

    It allows any flight of imagination, provided this imagination ultimately alights upon a possible practical effect; and thus many hypotheses may seem at first glance to be excluded by the pragmatical maxim that are not really so excluded.

  25. ^ a b c d Peirce, C. S., Carnegie Application (L75, 1902, New Elements of Mathematics v. 4, pp. 37–38. See under "Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms:

    Methodeutic has a special interest in Abduction, or the inference which starts a scientific hypothesis. For it is not sufficient that a hypothesis should be a justifiable one. Any hypothesis which explains the facts is justified critically. But among justifiable hypotheses we have to select that one which is suitable for being tested by experiment.

  26. ^ a b c d Peirce, "Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction" (Lecture VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism), see parts III and IV. Published in part in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 180–212 (see 196–200, Eprint and in full in Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 226–241 (see sections III and IV).

    .... What is good abduction? What should an explanatory hypothesis be to be worthy to rank as a hypothesis? Of course, it must explain the facts. But what other conditions ought it to fulfill to be good? .... Any hypothesis, therefore, may be admissible, in the absence of any special reasons to the contrary, provided it be capable of experimental verification, and only insofar as it is capable of such verification. This is approximately the doctrine of pragmatism.

  27. ^ a b c Peirce, C.S. (1902), application to the Carnegie Institution, see MS L75.329-330, from Draft D 2011-05-24 at the Wayback Machine of Memoir 27:

    Consequently, to discover is simply to expedite an event that would occur sooner or later, if we had not troubled ourselves to make the discovery. Consequently, the art of discovery is purely a question of economics. The economics of research is, so far as logic is concerned, the leading doctrine with reference to the art of discovery. Consequently, the conduct of abduction, which is chiefly a question of heuristic and is the first question of heuristic, is to be governed by economical considerations.

  28. ^ Peirce, A Letter to Paul Carus circa 1910, Collected Papers v. 8, paragraphs 227–228. See under "Hypothesis" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  29. ^ a b (1867), "On the Natural Classification of Arguments", Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences v. 7, pp. 261–287. Presented April 9, 1867. See especially starting at p. 284 in Part III §1. Reprinted in Collected Papers v. 2, paragraphs 461–516 and Writings v. 2, pp. 23–49.
  30. ^ a b c Peirce, C. S. (1878), "Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis", Popular Science Monthly, v. 13, pp. 470–82, see 472. Collected Papers 2.619–44, see 623.
  31. ^ a b A letter to Langley, 1900, published in Historical Perspectives on Peirce's Logic of Science. See excerpts under "Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  32. ^ "A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic'" (1903 manuscript), Essential Peirce v. 2, see p. 287. See under "Abduction" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  33. ^ Peirce, C. S., "On the Logic of Drawing History from Ancient Documents", dated as circa 1901 both by the editors of Collected Papers (see CP v. 7, bk 2, ch. 3, footnote 1) and by those of the Essential Peirce (EP) (Eprint 2012-09-05 at the Wayback Machine. The article's discussion of abduction is in CP v. 7, paragraphs 218–31 and in EP v. 2, pp. 107–14.
  34. ^ a b Peirce, C. S., "A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic" (1903), Essential Peirce v. 2, p. 287:

    The mind seeks to bring the facts, as modified by the new discovery, into order; that is, to form a general conception embracing them. In some cases, it does this by an act of generalization. In other cases, no new law is suggested, but only a peculiar state of facts that will "explain" the surprising phenomenon; and a law already known is recognized as applicable to the suggested hypothesis, so that the phenomenon, under that assumption, would not be surprising, but quite likely, or even would be a necessary result. This synthesis suggesting a new conception or hypothesis, is the Abduction.

  35. ^ a b A Letter to J. H. Kehler (1911), New Elements of Mathematics v. 3, pp. 203–4, see under "Retroduction" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  36. ^ Peirce, Charles S. (1883). . In Peirce, Charles S. (ed.). Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins University. Boston, MA. Archived from the original on March 8, 2019. Retrieved March 7, 2019.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  37. ^ Sebeok, Thomas A.; Umiker-Sebeok, Jean (1979). "'You know my method': A juxtaposition of Charles S. Peirce and Sherlock Holmes". Semiotica. 26 (3–4): 203–250. doi:10.1515/semi.1979.26.3-4.203. S2CID 170683439. Marcello Truzzi, in a searching article on Holmes's method (1973:93–126), anticipated our present work by pointing to the similarities between the detective's so-called deductions, or inductions, and Peirce's abductions, or conjectures. According to Peirce's system of logic, furthermore, Holmes's observations are themselves a form of abduction, and abduction is as legitimate a type of logical inference as either induction or deduction (Peirce 8.228).
  38. ^ Niiniluoto, Ilkka (September 1999). "Defending abduction". Philosophy of Science. 66 (Supplement 1): S436–S451 (S440–S441). doi:10.1086/392744. S2CID 224841752. A historically interesting application of abduction as a heuristic method can be found in classical detective stories, as shown by the semiotical and logical essays collected in Eco and Sebeok 1983. C. Auguste Dupin, the hero of Edgar Allan Poe's novels in the 1840s, employed a method of 'ratiocination' or 'analysis' which has the structure of retroduction. Similarly, the logic of the 'deductions' of Sherlock Holmes is typically abductive.
  39. ^ Carson, David (June 2009). "The abduction of Sherlock Holmes" (PDF). International Journal of Police Science & Management. 11 (2): 193–202. doi:10.1350/ijps.2009.11.2.123. S2CID 145337828. Sherlock Holmes, although a fictional character, remains renowned as a great detective. However, his methodology, which was abduction rather than deduction, and which is innocently used by many real detectives, is rarely described, discussed, or researched. This paper compares and contrasts the three forms of inferential reasoning, and makes a case for articulating and developing the role of abduction in the work, and training, of police officers.
  40. ^ In Peirce, C. S., 'Minute Logic' circa 1902, Collected Papers v. 2, paragraph 102. See under "Abduction" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  41. ^ Peirce, "On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient Documents", 1901 manuscript, Collected Papers v. 7, paragraphs 164–231, see 202, reprinted in Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 75–114, see 95. See under "Abduction" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  42. ^ Peirce, "On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from Documents", Essential Peirce v. 2, see pp. 107–9.
  43. ^ Peirce, Carnegie application, L75 (1902), Memoir 28: "On the Economics of Research", scroll down to Draft E. Eprint 2011-05-24 at the Wayback Machine.
  44. ^ Peirce, C. S., the 1866 Lowell Lectures on the Logic of Science, Writings of Charles S. Peirce v. 1, p. 485. See under "Hypothesis" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  45. ^ Peirce, C. S., "A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic", written 1903. See The Essential Peirce v. 2, p. 287. Quote viewable under "Abduction" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  46. ^ Peirce, A Letter to Paul Carus 1910, Collected Papers v. 8, see paragraph 223.
  47. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1902), Application to the Carnegie Institution, Memoir 27, Eprint 2011-05-24 at the Wayback Machine: "Of the different classes of arguments, abductions are the only ones in which after they have been admitted to be just, it still remains to inquire whether they are advantageous."
  48. ^ Peirce, "On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from Documents", Essential Peirce v. 2, see pp. 107–9 and 113. On Twenty Questions, p. 109, Peirce has pointed out that if each question eliminates half the possibilities, twenty questions can choose from among 220 or 1,048,576 objects, and goes on to say:

    Thus, twenty skillful hypotheses will ascertain what 200,000 stupid ones might fail to do. The secret of the business lies in the caution which breaks a hypothesis up into its smallest logical components, and only risks one of them at a time.

  49. ^ . www.commens.org. Archived from the original on August 26, 2014. Retrieved February 5, 2022.
  50. ^ "Peirce's last philosophic will and testament: Uberty in the logic of". paperzz.com. Retrieved February 5, 2022.
  51. ^ Beni, Majid D.; Pietarinen, Ahti-Veikko (September 10, 2021). "Aligning the free-energy principle with Peirce's logic of science and economy of research". European Journal for Philosophy of Science. 11 (3): 94. doi:10.1007/s13194-021-00408-y. ISSN 1879-4920. S2CID 237475038.
  52. ^ Stephen Jay Gould, "Adam's Navel", in idem, Adam's Navel and Other Essays (London: Penguin, 1995), p. 3.
  53. ^ Rapezzi, C; Ferrari, R; Branzi, A (December 24, 2005). "White coats and fingerprints: diagnostic reasoning in medicine and investigative methods of fictional detectives". BMJ (Clinical Research Ed.). 331 (7531): 1491–4. doi:10.1136/bmj.331.7531.1491. PMC 1322237. PMID 16373725.
  54. ^ Rejón Altable, C (October 2012). "Logic structure of clinical judgment and its relation to medical and psychiatric semiology". Psychopathology. 45 (6): 344–51. doi:10.1159/000337968. PMID 22854297. Retrieved January 17, 2014.
  55. ^ Kave Eshghi. Abductive planning with the event calculus. In Robert A. Kowalski, Kenneth A. Bowen editors: Logic Programming, Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference and Symposium, Seattle, Washington, August 15–19, 1988. MIT Press 1988, ISBN 0-262-61056-6
  56. ^ Gärdenfors, Peter. "Belief revision: A vade-mecum." Meta-Programming in Logic: Third International Workshop, META-92 Uppsala, Sweden, June 10–12, 1992 Proceedings 3. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 1992.
  57. ^ Lipton, Peter. (2001). Inference to the Best Explanation, London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-24202-9.
  58. ^ April M. S. McMahon (1994): Understanding language change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-44665-1
  59. ^ Rose, McKinley, & Briggs Baffoe-Djan (2020). Data Collection Research Methods in Applied Linguistics. Bloomsbury. ISBN 9781350025851.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  60. ^ McKinley, J (December 6, 2019). (PDF). In McKinley & Rose (ed.). The Routledge Handbook of Research Methods in Applied Linguistics. Abingdon: Routledge. pp. 1–13. ISBN 9780367824471. Archived from the original (PDF) on February 15, 2020. Retrieved February 15, 2020.
  61. ^ Eco, Umberto (1976). A Theory of Semiotics. Indiana University Press. p. 131. ISBN 9780253359551.
  62. ^ a b Gell, A. (1998). Art and Agency. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 14. ISBN 9780191037450.
  63. ^ Bowden, R. (2004) A critique of Alfred Gell on Art and Agency. Retrieved Sept 2007 from:
  64. ^ a b Whitney D. (2006) "Abduction the agency of art". Retrieved May 2009 from: University of California, Berkeley 2008-11-20 at the Wayback Machine
  65. ^ Calcagno, Cristiano; Distefano, Dino; O'Hearn, Peter W.; Yang, Hongseok (December 1, 2011). "Compositional Shape Analysis by Means of Bi-Abduction". Journal of the ACM. 58 (6): 1–66. doi:10.1145/2049697.2049700. S2CID 52808268.
  66. ^ "Facebook Acquires Assets Of UK Mobile Bug-Checking Software Developer Monoidics". TechCrunch. July 18, 2013. Retrieved February 22, 2020.[permanent dead link]
  67. ^ Distefano, Dino; Fähndrich, Manuel; Logozzo, Francesco; O'Hearn, Peter W. (July 24, 2019). "Scaling static analyses at Facebook". Communications of the ACM. 62 (8): 62–70. doi:10.1145/3338112.
  68. ^ Dillig, Isil; Dillig, Thomas; Li, Boyang; McMillan, Ken (October 29, 2013). "Inductive invariant generation via abductive inference". Proceedings of the 2013 ACM SIGPLAN international conference on Object oriented programming systems languages & applications. ACM SIGPLAN Notices. Vol. 48. pp. 443–456. doi:10.1145/2509136.2509511. ISBN 9781450323741. S2CID 16518775.
  69. ^ Giacobazzi, Roberto (August 1, 1998). "Abductive Analysis of Modular Logic Programs". Journal of Logic and Computation. 8 (4): 457–483. doi:10.1093/logcom/8.4.457. ISSN 0955-792X.
  70. ^ Polikarpova, Nadia; Sergey, Ilya (January 2, 2019). "Structuring the synthesis of heap-manipulating programs". Proceedings of the ACM on Programming Languages. 3: 1–30. arXiv:1807.07022. doi:10.1145/3290385.

References edit

  • Akaike, Hirotugu (1994), "Implications of informational point of view on the development of statistical science", in Bozdogan, H. (ed.), Proceedings of the First US/JAPAN Conference on The Frontiers of Statistical Modeling: An Informational Approach—Volume 3, Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 27–38.
  • Awbrey, Jon, and Awbrey, Susan (1995), "Interpretation as Action: The Risk of Inquiry", Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines, 15, 40–52.
  • Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora (1993) "First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi" Logic Jnl IGPL 1993 1: 99–117; doi:10.1093/jigpal/1.1.99.
  • Cialdea Mayer, Marta and Pirri, Fiora (1995) "Propositional Abduction in Modal Logic", Logic Jnl IGPL 1995 3: 907–919; doi:10.1093/jigpal/3.6.907
  • Edwards, Paul (1967, eds.), "The Encyclopedia of Philosophy," Macmillan Publishing Co, Inc. & The Free Press, New York. Collier Macmillan Publishers, London.
  • Eiter, T., and Gottlob, G. (1995), "The Complexity of Logic-Based Abduction, Journal of the ACM, 42.1, 3–42.
  • Hanson, N. R. (1958). Patterns of Discovery: An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-09261-6.
  • Harman, Gilbert (1965). "The Inference to the Best Explanation". The Philosophical Review. 74 (1): 88–95. doi:10.2307/2183532. JSTOR 2183532.
  • Josephson, John R., and Josephson, Susan G. (1995, eds.), Abductive Inference: Computation, Philosophy, Technology, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
  • Lipton, Peter. (2001). Inference to the Best Explanation, London: Routledge. ISBN 0-415-24202-9.
  • Magnani, Lorenzo (2014), "Understanding abduction", Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology: Theoretical and Cognitive Issues (editor—Magnani L.) Springer, p. 173-205.
  • McKaughan, Daniel J. (2008), "From Ugly Duckling to Swan: C. S. Peirce, Abduction, and the Pursuit of Scientific Theories", Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, v. 44, no. 3 (summer), 446–468.
  • Menzies, T (1996). "Applications of Abduction: Knowledge-Level Modeling" (PDF). International Journal of Human-Computer Studies. 45 (3): 305–335. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.352.8159. doi:10.1006/ijhc.1996.0054.
  • Queiroz, Joao & Merrell, Floyd (guest eds.). (2005). "Abduction - between subjectivity and objectivity". (special issue on abductive inference) Semiotica 153 (1/4). [1].
  • Santaella, Lucia (1997) "The Development of Peirce's Three Types of Reasoning: Abduction, Deduction, and Induction", 6th Congress of the IASS. Eprint.
  • Sebeok, T. (1981) "You Know My Method". In Sebeok, T. "The Play of Musement". Indiana. Bloomington, IA.
  • Yu, Chong Ho (1994), "Is There a Logic of Exploratory Data Analysis?", Annual Meeting of American Educational Research Association, New Orleans, LA, April, 1994. Website of Dr. Chong Ho (Alex) Yu

External links edit

  • Douven, Igor. "Abduction". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Abductive reasoning at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project
  • Abductive reasoning at PhilPapers
  • "" (once there, scroll down), John R. Josephson, Laboratory for Artificial Intelligence Research, Ohio State University. ( via the Wayback Machine.)
  • "Deduction, Induction, and Abduction", Chapter 3 in article "Charles Sanders Peirce" by Robert W. Burch, 2001 and 2006, in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • "", links to articles and websites on abductive inference, .
  • , Uwe Wirth and Alexander Roesler, eds. Uses frames. Click on link at bottom of its home page for English. Wirth moved to U. of Gießen, Germany, and set up Abduktionsforschung, home page not in English but see Artikel section there. Abduktionsforschung home page via Google translation.
  • "'You Know My Method': A Juxtaposition of Charles S. Peirce and Sherlock Holmes" (1981), by Thomas Sebeok with Jean Umiker-Sebeok, from The Play of Musement, Thomas Sebeok, Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, pp. 17–52.
  • Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, editors, Helsinki U. Peirce's own definitions, often many per term across the decades. There, see "Hypothesis [as a form of reasoning]", "Abduction", "Retroduction", and "Presumption [as a form of reasoning]".
  • "Touching Reality", a critique of abductive reasoning in the context of cosmology.

abductive, reasoning, abductive, redirects, here, other, uses, abduction, disambiguation, also, called, abduction, abductive, inference, retroduction, form, logical, inference, that, seeks, simplest, most, likely, conclusion, from, observations, formulated, ad. Abductive redirects here For other uses see Abduction disambiguation Abductive reasoning also called abduction 1 abductive inference 1 or retroduction 2 is a form of logical inference that seeks the simplest and most likely conclusion from a set of observations It was formulated and advanced by American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce beginning in the latter half of the 19th century A Mastermind player uses abduction to infer the secret colors top from summaries bottom left of discrepancies in their guesses bottom right Abductive reasoning unlike deductive reasoning yields a plausible conclusion but does not definitively verify it Abductive conclusions do not eliminate uncertainty or doubt which is expressed in retreat terms such as best available or most likely While inductive reasoning draws general conclusions that apply to many situations abductive conclusions are confined to the particular observations in question In the 1990s as computing power grew the fields of law 3 computer science and artificial intelligence research 4 spurred renewed interest in the subject of abduction 5 Diagnostic expert systems frequently employ abduction 6 Contents 1 Deduction induction and abduction 1 1 Deduction 1 2 Induction 1 3 Abduction 2 Formalizations of abduction 2 1 Logic based abduction 2 2 Set cover abduction 2 3 Abductive validation 2 4 Subjective logic abduction 3 History 3 1 Introduction and development by Peirce 3 1 1 Overview 3 1 2 The Natural Classification of Arguments 1867 3 1 3 Deduction Induction and Hypothesis 1878 3 1 4 A Theory of Probable Inference 1883 3 1 5 Minute Logic 1902 and after 3 1 6 Pragmatism 3 1 7 Three levels of logic about abduction 3 1 7 1 Classification of signs 3 1 7 2 Critique of arguments 3 1 7 3 Methodology of inquiry 3 1 8 Uberty 3 2 Gilbert Harman 1965 3 3 Stephen Jay Gould 1995 4 Applications 4 1 Artificial intelligence 4 2 Medicine 4 3 Automated planning 4 4 Intelligence analysis 4 5 Belief revision 4 6 Philosophy of science 4 7 Historical linguistics 4 8 Applied linguistics 4 9 Anthropology 4 10 Computer programming 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 External linksDeduction induction and abduction editMain article Logical reasoning Deduction edit Main article Deductive reasoning Deductive reasoning allows deriving b displaystyle b nbsp from a displaystyle a nbsp only where b displaystyle b nbsp is a formal logical consequence of a displaystyle a nbsp In other words deduction derives the consequences of the assumed Given the truth of the assumptions a valid deduction guarantees the truth of the conclusion For example given that Wikis can be edited by anyone a1 displaystyle a 1 nbsp and Wikipedia is a wiki a2 displaystyle a 2 nbsp it follows that Wikipedia can be edited by anyone b displaystyle b nbsp Induction edit Main article Inductive reasoning Inductive reasoning is the process of inferring some general principle b displaystyle b nbsp from a body of knowledge a displaystyle a nbsp where b displaystyle b nbsp does not necessarily follow from a displaystyle a nbsp a displaystyle a nbsp might give us very good reason to accept b displaystyle b nbsp but does not ensure b displaystyle b nbsp For example if all swans that we have observed so far are white we may induce that the possibility that all swans are white is reasonable We have good reason to believe the conclusion from the premise but the truth of the conclusion is not guaranteed Indeed it turns out that some swans are black Abduction edit Abductive reasoning allows inferring a displaystyle a nbsp as an explanation of b displaystyle b nbsp As a result of this inference abduction allows the precondition a displaystyle a nbsp to be abducted from the consequence b displaystyle b nbsp Deductive reasoning and abductive reasoning thus differ in which end left or right of the proposition a displaystyle a nbsp entails b displaystyle b nbsp serves as conclusion For example in a billiard game after glancing and seeing the eight ball moving towards us we may abduce that the cue ball struck the eight ball The strike of the cue ball would account for the movement of the eight ball It serves as a hypothesis that explains our observation Given the many possible explanations for the movement of the eight ball our abduction does not leave us certain that the cue ball in fact struck the eight ball but our abduction still useful can serve to orient us in our surroundings Despite many possible explanations for any physical process that we observe we tend to abduce a single explanation or a few explanations for this process in the expectation that we can better orient ourselves in our surroundings and disregard some possibilities Properly used abductive reasoning can be a useful source of priors in Bayesian statistics One can understand abductive reasoning as inference to the best explanation 7 although not all usages of the terms abduction and inference to the best explanation are equivalent 8 9 Formalizations of abduction editLogic based abduction edit In logic explanation is accomplished through the use of a logical theory T displaystyle T nbsp representing a domain and a set of observations O displaystyle O nbsp Abduction is the process of deriving a set of explanations of O displaystyle O nbsp according to T displaystyle T nbsp and picking out one of those explanations For E displaystyle E nbsp to be an explanation of O displaystyle O nbsp according to T displaystyle T nbsp it should satisfy two conditions O displaystyle O nbsp follows from E displaystyle E nbsp and T displaystyle T nbsp E displaystyle E nbsp is consistent with T displaystyle T nbsp In formal logic O displaystyle O nbsp and E displaystyle E nbsp are assumed to be sets of literals The two conditions for E displaystyle E nbsp being an explanation of O displaystyle O nbsp according to theory T displaystyle T nbsp are formalized as T E O displaystyle T cup E models O nbsp T E displaystyle T cup E nbsp is consistent Among the possible explanations E displaystyle E nbsp satisfying these two conditions some other condition of minimality is usually imposed to avoid irrelevant facts not contributing to the entailment of O displaystyle O nbsp being included in the explanations Abduction is then the process that picks out some member of E displaystyle E nbsp Criteria for picking out a member representing the best explanation include the simplicity the prior probability or the explanatory power of the explanation A proof theoretical abduction method for first order classical logic based on the sequent calculus and a dual one based on semantic tableaux analytic tableaux have been proposed 10 The methods are sound and complete and work for full first order logic without requiring any preliminary reduction of formulae into normal forms These methods have also been extended to modal logic 11 Abductive logic programming is a computational framework that extends normal logic programming with abduction It separates the theory T displaystyle T nbsp into two components one of which is a normal logic program used to generate E displaystyle E nbsp by means of backward reasoning the other of which is a set of integrity constraints used to filter the set of candidate explanations Set cover abduction edit A different formalization of abduction is based on inverting the function that calculates the visible effects of the hypotheses Formally we are given a set of hypotheses H displaystyle H nbsp and a set of manifestations M displaystyle M nbsp they are related by the domain knowledge represented by a function e displaystyle e nbsp that takes as an argument a set of hypotheses and gives as a result the corresponding set of manifestations In other words for every subset of the hypotheses H H displaystyle H subseteq H nbsp their effects are known to be e H displaystyle e H nbsp Abduction is performed by finding a set H H displaystyle H subseteq H nbsp such that M e H displaystyle M subseteq e H nbsp In other words abduction is performed by finding a set of hypotheses H displaystyle H nbsp such that their effects e H displaystyle e H nbsp include all observations M displaystyle M nbsp A common assumption is that the effects of the hypotheses are independent that is for every H H displaystyle H subseteq H nbsp it holds that e H h H e h displaystyle e H bigcup h in H e h nbsp If this condition is met abduction can be seen as a form of set covering Abductive validation edit Abductive validation is the process of validating a given hypothesis through abductive reasoning This can also be called reasoning through successive approximation citation needed Under this principle an explanation is valid if it is the best possible explanation of a set of known data The best possible explanation is often defined in terms of simplicity and elegance see Occam s razor Abductive validation is common practice in hypothesis formation in science moreover Peirce claims that it is a ubiquitous aspect of thought Looking out my window this lovely spring morning I see an azalea in full bloom No no I don t see that though that is the only way I can describe what I see That is a proposition a sentence a fact but what I perceive is not proposition sentence fact but only an image which I make intelligible in part by means of a statement of fact This statement is abstract but what I see is concrete I perform an abduction when I so much as express in a sentence anything I see The truth is that the whole fabric of our knowledge is one matted felt of pure hypothesis confirmed and refined by induction Not the smallest advance can be made in knowledge beyond the stage of vacant staring without making an abduction at every step 12 It was Peirce s own maxim that Facts cannot be explained by a hypothesis more extraordinary than these facts themselves and of various hypotheses the least extraordinary must be adopted 13 After obtaining possible hypotheses that may explain the facts abductive validation is a method for identifying the most likely hypothesis that should be adopted Subjective logic abduction edit Subjective logic generalises probabilistic logic by including degrees of epistemic uncertainty in the input arguments i e instead of probabilities the analyst can express arguments as subjective opinions Abduction in subjective logic is thus a generalization of probabilistic abduction described above 14 The input arguments in subjective logic are subjective opinions which can be binomial when the opinion applies to a binary variable or multinomial when it applies to an n ary variable A subjective opinion thus applies to a state variable X displaystyle X nbsp which takes its values from a domain X displaystyle mathbf X nbsp i e a state space of exhaustive and mutually disjoint state values x displaystyle x nbsp and is denoted by the tuple wX bX uX aX displaystyle omega X b X u X a X nbsp where bX displaystyle b X nbsp is the belief mass distribution over X displaystyle mathbf X nbsp uX displaystyle u X nbsp is the epistemic uncertainty mass and aX displaystyle a X nbsp is the base rate distribution over X displaystyle mathbf X nbsp These parameters satisfy uX bX x 1 displaystyle u X sum b X x 1 nbsp and aX x 1 displaystyle sum a X x 1 nbsp as well as bX x uX aX x 0 1 displaystyle b X x u X a X x in 0 1 nbsp Assume the domains X displaystyle mathbf X nbsp and Y displaystyle mathbf Y nbsp with respective variables X displaystyle X nbsp and Y displaystyle Y nbsp the set of conditional opinions wX Y displaystyle omega X mid Y nbsp i e one conditional opinion for each value y displaystyle y nbsp and the base rate distribution aY displaystyle a Y nbsp Based on these parameters the subjective Bayes theorem denoted with the operator ϕ displaystyle widetilde phi nbsp produces the set of inverted conditionals wY X displaystyle omega Y tilde mid X nbsp i e one inverted conditional for each value x displaystyle x nbsp expressed by wY X wX Yϕ aY displaystyle omega Y tilde X omega X Y widetilde phi a Y nbsp Using these inverted conditionals together with the opinion wX displaystyle omega X nbsp subjective deduction denoted by the operator displaystyle circledcirc nbsp can be used to abduce the marginal opinion wY X displaystyle omega Y overline X nbsp The equality between the different expressions for subjective abduction is given below wY X wX Y wX wX Yϕ aY wX wY X wX displaystyle begin aligned omega Y widetilde X amp omega X mid Y widetilde circledcirc omega X amp omega X mid Y widetilde phi a Y circledcirc omega X amp omega Y widetilde X circledcirc omega X end aligned nbsp The symbolic notation for subjective abduction is displaystyle widetilde nbsp and the operator itself is denoted as displaystyle widetilde circledcirc nbsp The operator for the subjective Bayes theorem is denoted ϕ displaystyle widetilde phi nbsp and subjective deduction is denoted displaystyle circledcirc nbsp 14 The advantage of using subjective logic abduction compared to probabilistic abduction is that both aleatoric and epistemic uncertainty about the input argument probabilities can be explicitly expressed and taken into account during the analysis It is thus possible to perform abductive analysis in the presence of uncertain arguments which naturally results in degrees of uncertainty in the output conclusions History editThe idea that the simplest most easily verifiable solution should be preferred over its more complicated counterparts is a very old one To this point George Polya in his treatise on problem solving makes reference to the following Latin truism simplex sigillum veri simplicity is the seal of truth 15 This section needs expansion with This deals only with Peirce and no other contributors or critics other relevant histories should be added and material that overlaps with the article on Peirce should be removed You can help by adding to it June 2020 Introduction and development by Peirce edit Overview edit The American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce introduced abduction into modern logic Over the years he called such inference hypothesis abduction presumption and retroduction He considered it a topic in logic as a normative field in philosophy not in purely formal or mathematical logic and eventually as a topic also in economics of research As two stages of the development extension etc of a hypothesis in scientific inquiry abduction and also induction are often collapsed into one overarching concept the hypothesis That is why in the scientific method known from Galileo and Bacon the abductive stage of hypothesis formation is conceptualized simply as induction Thus in the twentieth century this collapse was reinforced by Karl Popper s explication of the hypothetico deductive model where the hypothesis is considered to be just a guess 16 in the spirit of Peirce However when the formation of a hypothesis is considered the result of a process it becomes clear that this guess has already been tried and made more robust in thought as a necessary stage of its acquiring the status of hypothesis Indeed many abductions are rejected or heavily modified by subsequent abductions before they ever reach this stage Before 1900 Peirce treated abduction as the use of a known rule to explain an observation For instance it is a known rule that if it rains grass gets wet so to explain the fact that the grass on this lawn is wet one abduces that it has rained Abduction can lead to false conclusions if other rules that might explain the observation are not taken into account e g the grass could be wet from dew This remains the common use of the term abduction in the social sciences and in artificial intelligence Peirce consistently characterized it as the kind of inference that originates a hypothesis by concluding in an explanation though an unassured one for some very curious or surprising anomalous observation stated in a premise As early as 1865 he wrote that all conceptions of cause and force are reached through hypothetical inference in the 1900s he wrote that all explanatory content of theories is reached through abduction In other respects Peirce revised his view of abduction over the years 17 In later years his view came to be Abduction is guessing 18 It is very little hampered by rules of logic 19 Even a well prepared mind s individual guesses are more frequently wrong than right 20 But the success of our guesses far exceeds that of random luck and seems born of attunement to nature by instinct 21 some speak of intuition in such contexts 22 Abduction guesses a new or outside idea so as to account in a plausible instinctive economical way for a surprising or very complicated phenomenon That is its proximate aim 21 Its longer aim is to economize inquiry itself Its rationale is inductive it works often enough is the only source of new ideas and has no substitute in expediting the discovery of new truths 23 Its rationale especially involves its role in coordination with other modes of inference in inquiry It is inference to explanatory hypotheses for selection of those best worth trying Pragmatism is the logic of abduction Upon the generation of an explanation which he came to regard as instinctively guided the pragmatic maxim gives the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction in general The hypothesis being insecure needs to have conceivable 24 implications for informed practice so as to be testable 25 26 and through its trials to expedite and economize inquiry The economy of research is what calls for abduction and governs its art 27 Writing in 1910 Peirce admits that in almost everything I printed before the beginning of this century I more or less mixed up hypothesis and induction and he traces the confusion of these two types of reasoning to logicians too narrow and formalistic a conception of inference as necessarily having formulated judgments from its premises 28 He started out in the 1860s treating hypothetical inference in a number of ways which he eventually peeled away as inessential or in some cases mistaken as inferring the occurrence of a character a characteristic from the observed combined occurrence of multiple characters which its occurrence would necessarily involve 29 for example if any occurrence of A is known to necessitate occurrence of B C D E then the observation of B C D E suggests by way of explanation the occurrence of A But by 1878 he no longer regarded such multiplicity as common to all hypothetical inference 30 Wikisource as aiming for a more or less probable hypothesis in 1867 and 1883 but not in 1878 anyway by 1900 the justification is not probability but the lack of alternatives to guessing and the fact that guessing is fruitful 31 by 1903 he speaks of the likely in the sense of nearing the truth in an indefinite sense 32 by 1908 he discusses plausibility as instinctive appeal 21 In a paper dated by editors as circa 1901 he discusses instinct and naturalness along with the kind of considerations low cost of testing logical caution breadth and incomplexity that he later calls methodeutical 33 as induction from characters but as early as 1900 he characterized abduction as guessing 31 as citing a known rule in a premise rather than hypothesizing a rule in the conclusion but by 1903 he allowed either approach 19 34 as basically a transformation of a deductive categorical syllogism 30 but in 1903 he offered a variation on modus ponens instead 19 and by 1911 he was unconvinced that any one form covers all hypothetical inference 35 The Natural Classification of Arguments 1867 edit In 1867 Peirce s On the Natural Classification of Arguments 29 hypothetical inference always deals with a cluster of characters call them P P P etc known to occur at least whenever a certain character M occurs Note that categorical syllogisms have elements traditionally called middles predicates and subjects For example All men middle are mortal predicate Socrates subject is a man middle ergo Socrates subject is mortal predicate Below M stands for a middle P for a predicate S for a subject Peirce held that all deduction can be put into the form of the categorical syllogism Barbara AAA 1 Deduction Any M is P Any S is M displaystyle therefore nbsp Any S is P Induction S S S amp c are taken at random as M s S S S amp c are P displaystyle therefore nbsp Any M is probably P Hypothesis Any M is for instance P P P amp c S is P P P amp c displaystyle therefore nbsp S is probably M Deduction Induction and Hypothesis 1878 edit In 1878 in Deduction Induction and Hypothesis 30 there is no longer a need for multiple characters or predicates in order for an inference to be hypothetical although it is still helpful Moreover Peirce no longer poses hypothetical inference as concluding in a probable hypothesis In the forms themselves it is understood but not explicit that induction involves random selection and that hypothetical inference involves response to a very curious circumstance The forms instead emphasize the modes of inference as rearrangements of one another s propositions without the bracketed hints shown below Deduction Rule All the beans from this bag are white Case These beans are from this bag displaystyle therefore nbsp Result These beans are white Induction Case These beans are randomly selected from this bag Result These beans are white displaystyle therefore nbsp Rule All the beans from this bag are white Hypothesis Rule All the beans from this bag are white Result These beans oddly are white displaystyle therefore nbsp Case These beans are from this bag A Theory of Probable Inference 1883 edit Peirce long treated abduction in terms of induction from characters or traits weighed not counted like objects explicitly so in his influential 1883 A theory of probable inference in which he returns to involving probability in the hypothetical conclusion 36 Like Deduction Induction and Hypothesis in 1878 it was widely read see the historical books on statistics by Stephen Stigler unlike his later amendments of his conception of abduction Today abduction remains most commonly understood as induction from characters and extension of a known rule to cover unexplained circumstances Sherlock Holmes used this method of reasoning in the stories of Arthur Conan Doyle although Holmes refers to it as deductive reasoning 37 38 39 Minute Logic 1902 and after edit In 1902 Peirce wrote that he now regarded the syllogistical forms and the doctrine of extension and comprehension i e objects and characters as referenced by terms as being less fundamental than he had earlier thought 40 In 1903 he offered the following form for abduction 19 The surprising fact C is observed But if A were true C would be a matter of course Hence there is reason to suspect that A is true The hypothesis is framed but not asserted in a premise then asserted as rationally suspectable in the conclusion Thus as in the earlier categorical syllogistic form the conclusion is formulated from some premise s But all the same the hypothesis consists more clearly than ever in a new or outside idea beyond what is known or observed Induction in a sense goes beyond observations already reported in the premises but it merely amplifies ideas already known to represent occurrences or tests an idea supplied by hypothesis either way it requires previous abductions in order to get such ideas in the first place Induction seeks facts to test a hypothesis abduction seeks a hypothesis to account for facts Note that the hypothesis A could be of a rule It need not even be a rule strictly necessitating the surprising observation C which needs to follow only as a matter of course or the course itself could amount to some known rule merely alluded to and also not necessarily a rule of strict necessity In the same year Peirce wrote that reaching a hypothesis may involve placing a surprising observation under either a newly hypothesized rule or a hypothesized combination of a known rule with a peculiar state of facts so that the phenomenon would be not surprising but instead either necessarily implied or at least likely 34 Peirce did not remain quite convinced about any such form as the categorical syllogistic form or the 1903 form In 1911 he wrote I do not at present feel quite convinced that any logical form can be assigned that will cover all Retroductions For what I mean by a Retroduction is simply a conjecture which arises in the mind 35 Pragmatism edit In 1901 Peirce wrote There would be no logic in imposing rules and saying that they ought to be followed until it is made out that the purpose of hypothesis requires them 41 In 1903 Peirce called pragmatism the logic of abduction and said that the pragmatic maxim gives the necessary and sufficient logical rule to abduction in general 26 The pragmatic maxim is Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearings we conceive the object of our conception to have Then our conception of these effects is the whole of our conception of the object It is a method for fruitful clarification of conceptions by equating the meaning of a conception with the conceivable practical implications of its object s conceived effects Peirce held that that is precisely tailored to abduction s purpose in inquiry the forming of an idea that could conceivably shape informed conduct In various writings in the 1900s 27 42 he said that the conduct of abduction or retroduction is governed by considerations of economy belonging in particular to the economics of research He regarded economics as a normative science whose analytic portion might be part of logical methodeutic that is theory of inquiry 43 Three levels of logic about abduction edit Peirce came over the years to divide philosophical logic into three departments Stechiology or speculative grammar on the conditions for meaningfulness Classification of signs semblances symptoms symbols etc and their combinations as well as their objects and interpretants Logical critic or logic proper on validity or justifiability of inference the conditions for true representation Critique of arguments in their various modes deduction induction abduction Methodeutic or speculative rhetoric on the conditions for determination of interpretations Methodology of inquiry in its interplay of modes Peirce had from the start seen the modes of inference as being coordinated together in scientific inquiry and by the 1900s held that hypothetical inference in particular is inadequately treated at the level of critique of arguments 25 26 To increase the assurance of a hypothetical conclusion one needs to deduce implications about evidence to be found predictions which induction can test through observation so as to evaluate the hypothesis That is Peirce s outline of the scientific method of inquiry as covered in his inquiry methodology which includes pragmatism or as he later called it pragmaticism the clarification of ideas in terms of their conceivable implications regarding informed practice Classification of signs edit As early as 1866 44 Peirce held that 1 Hypothesis abductive inference is inference through an icon also called a likeness 2 Induction is inference through an index a sign by factual connection a sample is an index of the totality from which it is drawn 3 Deduction is inference through a symbol a sign by interpretive habit irrespective of resemblance or connection to its object In 1902 Peirce wrote that in abduction It is recognized that the phenomena are like i e constitute an Icon of a replica of a general conception or Symbol 45 Critique of arguments edit At the critical level Peirce examined the forms of abductive arguments as discussed above and came to hold that the hypothesis should economize explanation for plausibility in terms of the feasible and natural In 1908 Peirce described this plausibility in some detail 21 It involves not likeliness based on observations which is instead the inductive evaluation of a hypothesis but instead optimal simplicity in the sense of the facile and natural as by Galileo s natural light of reason and as distinct from logical simplicity Peirce does not dismiss logical simplicity entirely but sees it in a subordinate role taken to its logical extreme it would favor adding no explanation to the observation at all Even a well prepared mind guesses oftener wrong than right but our guesses succeed better than random luck at reaching the truth or at least advancing the inquiry and that indicates to Peirce that they are based in instinctive attunement to nature an affinity between the mind s processes and the processes of the real which would account for why appealingly natural guesses are the ones that oftenest or least seldom succeed to which Peirce added the argument that such guesses are to be preferred since without a natural bent like nature s people would have no hope of understanding nature In 1910 Peirce made a three way distinction between probability verisimilitude and plausibility and defined plausibility with a normative ought By plausibility I mean the degree to which a theory ought to recommend itself to our belief independently of any kind of evidence other than our instinct urging us to regard it favorably 46 For Peirce plausibility does not depend on observed frequencies or probabilities or on verisimilitude or even on testability which is not a question of the critique of the hypothetical inference as an inference but rather a question of the hypothesis s relation to the inquiry process The phrase inference to the best explanation not used by Peirce but often applied to hypothetical inference is not always understood as referring to the most simple and natural hypotheses such as those with the fewest assumptions However in other senses of best such as standing up best to tests it is hard to know which is the best explanation to form since one has not tested it yet Still for Peirce any justification of an abductive inference as good is not completed upon its formation as an argument unlike with induction and deduction and instead depends also on its methodological role and promise such as its testability in advancing inquiry 25 26 47 Methodology of inquiry edit At the methodeutical level Peirce held that a hypothesis is judged and selected 25 for testing because it offers via its trial to expedite and economize the inquiry process itself toward new truths first of all by being testable and also by further economies 27 in terms of cost value and relationships among guesses hypotheses Here considerations such as probability absent from the treatment of abduction at the critical level come into play For examples Cost A simple but low odds guess if low in cost to test for falsity may belong first in line for testing to get it out of the way If surprisingly it stands up to tests that is worth knowing early in the inquiry which otherwise might have stayed long on a wrong though seemingly likelier track Value A guess is intrinsically worth testing if it has instinctual plausibility or reasoned objective probability while subjective likelihood though reasoned can be treacherous Interrelationships Guesses can be chosen for trial strategically for their caution for which Peirce gave as an example the game of Twenty Questions breadth of applicability to explain various phenomena and incomplexity that of a hypothesis that seems too simple but whose trial may give a good leave as the billiard players say and be instructive for the pursuit of various and conflicting hypotheses that are less simple 48 Uberty edit Peirce 49 indicated that abductive reasoning is driven by the need for economy in research the expected fact based productivity of hypotheses prior to deductive and inductive processes of verification A key concept proposed by him in this regard is uberty 50 the expected fertility and pragmatic value of reasoning This concept seems to be gaining support via association to the Free Energy Principle 51 Gilbert Harman 1965 edit Gilbert Harman is a professor of philosophy at Princeton University Harman s 1965 account of the role of inference to the best explanation inferring the existence of that which we need for the best explanation of observable phenomena has been very influential Stephen Jay Gould 1995 edit Stephen Jay Gould in answering the Omphalos hypothesis claimed that only hypotheses that can be proved incorrect lie within the domain of science and only these hypotheses are good explanations of facts worth inferring to 52 W hat is so desperately wrong with Omphalos Only this really and perhaps paradoxically that we can devise no way to find out whether it is wrong or for that matter right Omphalos is the classic example of an utterly untestable notion for the world will look exactly the same in all its intricate detail whether fossils and strata are prochronic signs of a fictitious past or products of an extended history Science is a procedure for testing and rejecting hypotheses not a compendium of certain knowledge Claims that can be proved incorrect lie within its domain But theories that cannot be tested in principle are not part of science W e reject Omphalos as useless not wrong Applications editArtificial intelligence edit Applications in artificial intelligence include fault diagnosis belief revision and automated planning The most direct application of abduction is that of automatically detecting faults in systems given a theory relating faults with their effects and a set of observed effects abduction can be used to derive sets of faults that are likely to be the cause of the problem 4 Medicine edit In medicine abduction can be seen as a component of clinical evaluation and judgment 53 54 Automated planning edit Abduction can also be used to model automated planning 55 Given a logical theory relating action occurrences with their effects for example a formula of the event calculus the problem of finding a plan for reaching a state can be modeled as the problem of abducting a set of literals implying that the final state is the goal state Intelligence analysis edit In intelligence analysis analysis of competing hypotheses and Bayesian networks probabilistic abductive reasoning is used extensively Similarly in medical diagnosis and legal reasoning the same methods are being used although there have been many examples of errors especially caused by the base rate fallacy and the prosecutor s fallacy Belief revision edit This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed January 2019 Learn how and when to remove this template message Belief revision the process of adapting beliefs in view of new information is another field in which abduction has been applied The main problem of belief revision is that the new information may be inconsistent with the prior web of beliefs while the result of the incorporation cannot be inconsistent The process of updating the web of beliefs can be done by the use of abduction once an explanation for the observation has been found integrating it does not generate inconsistency Gardenfors paper 56 contains a brief survey of the area of belief revision and its relation to updating of logical databases and explores the relationship between belief revision and nonmonotonic logic This use of abduction is not straightforward as adding propositional formulae to other propositional formulae can only make inconsistencies worse Instead abduction is done at the level of the ordering of preference of the possible worlds Preference models use fuzzy logic or utility models Philosophy of science edit In the philosophy of science abduction has been the key inference method to support scientific realism and much of the debate about scientific realism is focused on whether abduction is an acceptable method of inference 57 Historical linguistics edit In historical linguistics abduction during language acquisition is often taken to be an essential part of processes of language change such as reanalysis and analogy 58 Applied linguistics edit In applied linguistics research abductive reasoning is starting to be used as an alternative explanation to inductive reasoning in recognition of anticipated outcomes of qualitative inquiry playing a role in shaping the direction of analysis It is defined as The use of an unclear premise based on observations pursuing theories to try to explain it Rose et al 2020 p 258 59 60 Anthropology edit In anthropology Alfred Gell in his influential book Art and Agency defined abduction after Eco 61 as a case of synthetic inference where we find some very curious circumstances which would be explained by the supposition that it was a case of some general rule and thereupon adopt that supposition 62 Gell criticizes existing anthropological studies of art for being too preoccupied with aesthetic value and not preoccupied enough with the central anthropological concern of uncovering social relationships specifically the social contexts in which artworks are produced circulated and received 63 Abduction is used as the mechanism for getting from art to agency That is abduction can explain how works of art inspire a sensus communis the commonly held views shared by members that characterize a given society 64 The question Gell asks in the book is how does it initially speak to people He answers by saying that No reasonable person could suppose that art like relations between people and things do not involve at least some form of semiosis 62 However he rejects any intimation that semiosis can be thought of as a language because then he would have to admit to some pre established existence of the sensus communis that he wants to claim only emerges afterwards out of art Abduction is the answer to this conundrum because the tentative nature of the abduction concept Peirce likened it to guessing means that not only can it operate outside of any pre existing framework but moreover it can actually intimate the existence of a framework As Gell reasons in his analysis the physical existence of the artwork prompts the viewer to perform an abduction that imbues the artwork with intentionality A statue of a goddess for example in some senses actually becomes the goddess in the mind of the beholder and represents not only the form of the deity but also her intentions which are adduced from the feeling of her very presence Therefore through abduction Gell claims that art can have the kind of agency that plants the seeds that grow into cultural myths The power of agency is the power to motivate actions and inspire ultimately the shared understanding that characterizes any given society 64 Computer programming edit In formal methods logic is used to specify and prove properties of computer programs Abduction has been used in mechanized reasoning tools to increase the level of automation of the proof activity A technique known as bi abduction which mixes abduction and the frame problem was used to scale reasoning techniques for memory properties to millions of lines of code 65 logic based abduction was used to infer pre conditions for individual functions in a program relieving the human of the need to do so It led to a program proof startup company which was acquired by Facebook 66 and the Infer program analysis tool which led to thousands of bugs being prevented in industrial codebases 67 In addition to inference of function preconditions abduction has been used to automate inference of invariants for program loops 68 inference of specifications of unknown code 69 and in synthesis of the programs themselves 70 See also edit nbsp Philosophy portalArgument Attempt to persuade or to determine the truth of a conclusion Argumentation theory Academic field of logic and rhetoric Attribution psychology The process by which individuals explain the causes of behavior and events Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography Critical thinking Analysis of facts to form a judgment Conclusion making Defeasible reasoning Reasoning that is rationally compelling though not deductively valid Douglas N Walton Canadian academic and author 1942 2020 Duck test Classification based on observable evidence Falsifiability Property of a statement that can be logically contradicted Gregory Bateson British American psychological anthropologist 1904 1980 Heuristic Problem solving method Inductive probability Determining the probability of future events based on past events Logical reasoning Process of drawing correct inferences Maximum likelihood estimation Method of estimating the parameters of a statistical model given observations Occam s razor Philosophical problem solving principle Sensemaking Process by which people give meaning to their collective experiences Sign relation Concept in semiotics Statistical model Type of mathematical modelNotes edit a b For example Josephson John R Josephson Susan G eds 1994 Abductive Inference Computation Philosophy Technology Cambridge UK New York Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 CBO9780511530128 ISBN 978 0521434614 OCLC 28149683 Retroduction Commens Digital Companion to C S Peirce Mats Bergman Sami Paavola amp Joao Queiroz Archived from the original on August 26 2014 Retrieved August 24 2014 See e g Analysis of Evidence 2d ed by Terence Anderson Cambridge University Press 2005 a b For examples see Abductive Inference in Reasoning and Perception John R Josephson Laboratory for Artificial Intelligence Research Ohio State University and Abduction Reason and Science Processes of Discovery and Explanation by Lorenzo Magnani Kluwer Academic Plenum Publishers New York 2001 Flach P A Kakas A C eds 2000 Abduction and Induction Essays on their Relation and Integration Springer p xiii Retrieved October 31 2016 This book grew out of a series of workshops on this topic Budapest 1996 Nagoya 1997 Brighton 1998 Reggia James A et al Answer justification in diagnostic expert systems Part I Abductive inference and its justification IEEE transactions on biomedical engineering 4 1985 263 267 Sober Elliott 2013 Core Questions in Philosophy A Text with Readings 6th ed Boston Pearson Education p 28 ISBN 9780205206698 OCLC 799024771 I now move to abduction inference to the best explanation Campos Daniel G June 2011 On the distinction between Peirce s abduction and Lipton s inference to the best explanation Synthese 180 3 419 442 doi 10 1007 s11229 009 9709 3 S2CID 791688 I argue against the tendency in the philosophy of science literature to link abduction to the inference to the best explanation IBE and in particular to claim that Peircean abduction is a conceptual predecessor to IBE In particular I claim that Peircean abduction is an in depth account of the process of generating explanatory hypotheses while IBE at least in Peter Lipton s thorough treatment is a more encompassing account of the processes both of generating and of evaluating scientific hypotheses There is then a two fold problem with the claim that abduction is IBE On the one hand it conflates abduction and induction which are two distinct forms of logical inference with two distinct aims as shown by Charles S Peirce on the other hand it lacks a clear sense of the full scope of IBE as an account of scientific inference Walton Douglas 2001 Abductive presumptive and plausible arguments Informal Logic 21 2 141 169 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 127 1593 doi 10 22329 il v21i2 2241 Abductive inference has often been equated with inference to the best explanation The account of abductive inference and inference to the best explanation presented above has emphasized the common elements found in the analyses given by Peirce Harman and the Josephsons It is necessary to add that this brief account may be misleading in some respects and that a closer and more detailed explication of the finer points of the three analyses could reveal important underlying philosophical differences Inferences to the best explanation as expounded by Harman and the Josephsons can involve deductive and inductive processes of a kind that would be apparently be excluded by Peirce s account of abduction Cialdea Mayer Marta and Pirri Fiora 1993 First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi Logic Jnl IGPL 1993 1 99 117 doi 10 1093 jigpal 1 1 99 Oxford Journals Cialdea Mayer Marta and Pirri Fiora 1993 Propositional abduction in modal logic Logic Jnl IGPL 1995 3 6 907 919 doi 10 1093 jigpal 3 6 907 Oxford Journals Peirce MS 692 quoted in Sebeok T 1981 You Know My Method in Sebeok T The Play of Musement Bloomington IA Indiana page 24 Peirce MS 696 quoted in Sebeok T 1981 You Know My Method in Sebeok T The Play of Musement Bloomington IA Indiana page 31 a b A Josang Subjective Logic A Formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty Springer 2016 ISBN 978 3 319 42337 1 Polya George 1945 How to solve it a new aspect of mathematical method Expanded Princeton Science Library 2004 ed Princeton N J Princeton University Press p 45 ISBN 0 691 11966 X Popper Karl 2002 Conjectures and Refutations The Growth of Scientific Knowledge 2 ed London Routledge p 536 See Santaella Lucia 1997 The Development of Peirce s Three Types of Reasoning Abduction Deduction and Induction 6th Congress of the IASS Eprint Peirce C S On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient Documents especially from Testimonies 1901 Collected Papers v 7 paragraph 219 PAP Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmatism MS 293 c 1906 New Elements of Mathematics v 4 pp 319 320 A Letter to F A Woods 1913 Collected Papers v 8 paragraphs 385 388 See under Abduction and Retroduction at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms a b c d Peirce C S 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 188 189 Peirce C S 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God Hibbert Journal v 7 pp 90 112 see 4 In Collected Papers v 6 see paragraph 476 In The Essential Peirce v 2 see p 444 a b c d Peirce C S 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God Hibbert Journal v 7 pp 90 112 See both part III and part IV Reprinted including originally unpublished portion in Collected Papers v 6 paragraphs 452 85 Essential Peirce v 2 pp 434 50 and elsewhere Peirce used the term intuition not in the sense of an instinctive or anyway half conscious inference as people often do currently Instead he used intuition usually in the sense of a cognition devoid of logical determination by previous cognitions He said We have no power of Intuition in that sense See his Some Consequences of Four Incapacities 1868 Eprint Archived 2011 05 14 at the Wayback Machine For a relevant discussion of Peirce and the aims of abductive inference see McKaughan Daniel J 2008 From Ugly Duckling to Swan C S Peirce Abduction and the Pursuit of Scientific Theories Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society v 44 no 3 summer 446 468 Peirce means conceivable very broadly See Collected Papers v 5 paragraph 196 or Essential Peirce v 2 p 235 Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction Lecture VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism It allows any flight of imagination provided this imagination ultimately alights upon a possible practical effect and thus many hypotheses may seem at first glance to be excluded by the pragmatical maxim that are not really so excluded a b c d Peirce C S Carnegie Application L75 1902 New Elements of Mathematics v 4 pp 37 38 See under Abduction at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Methodeutic has a special interest in Abduction or the inference which starts a scientific hypothesis For it is not sufficient that a hypothesis should be a justifiable one Any hypothesis which explains the facts is justified critically But among justifiable hypotheses we have to select that one which is suitable for being tested by experiment a b c d Peirce Pragmatism as the Logic of Abduction Lecture VII of the 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism see parts III and IV Published in part in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 180 212 see 196 200 Eprint and in full in Essential Peirce v 2 pp 226 241 see sections III and IV What is good abduction What should an explanatory hypothesis be to be worthy to rank as a hypothesis Of course it must explain the facts But what other conditions ought it to fulfill to be good Any hypothesis therefore may be admissible in the absence of any special reasons to the contrary provided it be capable of experimental verification and only insofar as it is capable of such verification This is approximately the doctrine of pragmatism a b c Peirce C S 1902 application to the Carnegie Institution see MS L75 329 330 from Draft D Archived 2011 05 24 at the Wayback Machine of Memoir 27 Consequently to discover is simply to expedite an event that would occur sooner or later if we had not troubled ourselves to make the discovery Consequently the art of discovery is purely a question of economics The economics of research is so far as logic is concerned the leading doctrine with reference to the art of discovery Consequently the conduct of abduction which is chiefly a question of heuristic and is the first question of heuristic is to be governed by economical considerations Peirce A Letter to Paul Carus circa 1910 Collected Papers v 8 paragraphs 227 228 See under Hypothesis at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms a b 1867 On the Natural Classification of Arguments Proceedings of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences v 7 pp 261 287 Presented April 9 1867 See especially starting at p 284 in Part III 1 Reprinted in Collected Papers v 2 paragraphs 461 516 andWritingsv 2 pp 23 49 a b c Peirce C S 1878 Deduction Induction and Hypothesis Popular Science Monthly v 13 pp 470 82 see 472 Collected Papers 2 619 44 see 623 a b A letter to Langley 1900 published in Historical Perspectives on Peirce s Logic of Science See excerpts under Abduction at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic 1903 manuscript Essential Peirce v 2 see p 287 See under Abduction at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce C S On the Logic of Drawing History from Ancient Documents dated as circa 1901 both by the editors of Collected Papers see CP v 7 bk 2 ch 3 footnote 1 and by those of the Essential Peirce EP Eprint Archived 2012 09 05 at the Wayback Machine The article s discussion of abduction is in CP v 7 paragraphs 218 31 and in EP v 2 pp 107 14 a b Peirce C S A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic 1903 Essential Peirce v 2 p 287 The mind seeks to bring the facts as modified by the new discovery into order that is to form a general conception embracing them In some cases it does this by an act of generalization In other cases no new law is suggested but only a peculiar state of facts that will explain the surprising phenomenon and a law already known is recognized as applicable to the suggested hypothesis so that the phenomenon under that assumption would not be surprising but quite likely or even would be a necessary result This synthesis suggesting a new conception or hypothesis is the Abduction a b A Letter to J H Kehler 1911 New Elements of Mathematics v 3 pp 203 4 see under Retroduction at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce Charles S 1883 A theory of probable inference In Peirce Charles S ed Studies in Logic by Members of the Johns Hopkins University Boston MA Archived from the original on March 8 2019 Retrieved March 7 2019 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Sebeok Thomas A Umiker Sebeok Jean 1979 You know my method A juxtaposition of Charles S Peirce and Sherlock Holmes Semiotica 26 3 4 203 250 doi 10 1515 semi 1979 26 3 4 203 S2CID 170683439 Marcello Truzzi in a searching article on Holmes s method 1973 93 126 anticipated our present work by pointing to the similarities between the detective s so called deductions or inductions and Peirce s abductions or conjectures According to Peirce s system of logic furthermore Holmes s observations are themselves a form of abduction and abduction is as legitimate a type of logical inference as either induction or deduction Peirce 8 228 Niiniluoto Ilkka September 1999 Defending abduction Philosophy of Science 66 Supplement 1 S436 S451 S440 S441 doi 10 1086 392744 S2CID 224841752 A historically interesting application of abduction as a heuristic method can be found in classical detective stories as shown by the semiotical and logical essays collected in Eco and Sebeok 1983 C Auguste Dupin the hero of Edgar Allan Poe s novels in the 1840s employed a method of ratiocination or analysis which has the structure of retroduction Similarly the logic of the deductions of Sherlock Holmes is typically abductive Carson David June 2009 The abduction of Sherlock Holmes PDF International Journal of Police Science amp Management 11 2 193 202 doi 10 1350 ijps 2009 11 2 123 S2CID 145337828 Sherlock Holmes although a fictional character remains renowned as a great detective However his methodology which was abduction rather than deduction and which is innocently used by many real detectives is rarely described discussed or researched This paper compares and contrasts the three forms of inferential reasoning and makes a case for articulating and developing the role of abduction in the work and training of police officers In Peirce C S Minute Logic circa 1902 Collected Papers v 2 paragraph 102 See under Abduction at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce On the Logic of drawing History from Ancient Documents 1901 manuscript Collected Papers v 7 paragraphs 164 231 see 202 reprinted in Essential Peirce v 2 pp 75 114 see 95 See under Abduction at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from Documents Essential Peirce v 2 see pp 107 9 Peirce Carnegie application L75 1902 Memoir 28 On the Economics of Research scroll down to Draft E Eprint Archived 2011 05 24 at the Wayback Machine Peirce C S the 1866 Lowell Lectures on the Logic of Science Writings of Charles S Peirce v 1 p 485 See under Hypothesis at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce C S A Syllabus of Certain Topics of Logic written 1903 See The Essential Peirce v 2 p 287 Quote viewable under Abduction at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Peirce A Letter to Paul Carus 1910 Collected Papers v 8 see paragraph 223 Peirce C S 1902 Application to the Carnegie Institution Memoir 27 Eprint Archived 2011 05 24 at the Wayback Machine Of the different classes of arguments abductions are the only ones in which after they have been admitted to be just it still remains to inquire whether they are advantageous Peirce On the Logic of Drawing Ancient History from Documents Essential Peirce v 2 see pp 107 9 and 113 On Twenty Questions p 109 Peirce has pointed out that if each question eliminates half the possibilities twenty questions can choose from among 220 or 1 048 576 objects and goes on to say Thus twenty skillful hypotheses will ascertain what 200 000 stupid ones might fail to do The secret of the business lies in the caution which breaks a hypothesis up into its smallest logical components and only risks one of them at a time An Essay toward Improving Our Reasoning in Security and in Uberty www commens org Archived from the original on August 26 2014 Retrieved February 5 2022 Peirce s last philosophic will and testament Uberty in the logic of paperzz com Retrieved February 5 2022 Beni Majid D Pietarinen Ahti Veikko September 10 2021 Aligning the free energy principle with Peirce s logic of science and economy of research European Journal for Philosophy of Science 11 3 94 doi 10 1007 s13194 021 00408 y ISSN 1879 4920 S2CID 237475038 Stephen Jay Gould Adam s Navel in idem Adam s Navel and Other Essays London Penguin 1995 p 3 Rapezzi C Ferrari R Branzi A December 24 2005 White coats and fingerprints diagnostic reasoning in medicine and investigative methods of fictional detectives BMJ Clinical Research Ed 331 7531 1491 4 doi 10 1136 bmj 331 7531 1491 PMC 1322237 PMID 16373725 Rejon Altable C October 2012 Logic structure of clinical judgment and its relation to medical and psychiatric semiology Psychopathology 45 6 344 51 doi 10 1159 000337968 PMID 22854297 Retrieved January 17 2014 Kave Eshghi Abductive planning with the event calculus In Robert A Kowalski Kenneth A Bowen editors Logic Programming Proceedings of the Fifth International Conference and Symposium Seattle Washington August 15 19 1988 MIT Press 1988 ISBN 0 262 61056 6 Gardenfors Peter Belief revision A vade mecum Meta Programming in Logic Third International Workshop META 92 Uppsala Sweden June 10 12 1992 Proceedings 3 Springer Berlin Heidelberg 1992 Lipton Peter 2001 Inference to the Best Explanation London Routledge ISBN 0 415 24202 9 April M S McMahon 1994 Understanding language change Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 44665 1 Rose McKinley amp Briggs Baffoe Djan 2020 Data Collection Research Methods in Applied Linguistics Bloomsbury ISBN 9781350025851 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link McKinley J December 6 2019 Introduction Theorizing research methods in the golden age of applied linguistics research PDF In McKinley amp Rose ed The Routledge Handbook of Research Methods in Applied Linguistics Abingdon Routledge pp 1 13 ISBN 9780367824471 Archived from the original PDF on February 15 2020 Retrieved February 15 2020 Eco Umberto 1976 A Theory of Semiotics Indiana University Press p 131 ISBN 9780253359551 a b Gell A 1998 Art and Agency Oxford Clarendon Press p 14 ISBN 9780191037450 Bowden R 2004 A critique of Alfred Gell on Art and Agency Retrieved Sept 2007 from Find Articles at BNET a b Whitney D 2006 Abduction the agency of art Retrieved May 2009 from University of California Berkeley Archived 2008 11 20 at the Wayback Machine Calcagno Cristiano Distefano Dino O Hearn Peter W Yang Hongseok December 1 2011 Compositional Shape Analysis by Means of Bi Abduction Journal of the ACM 58 6 1 66 doi 10 1145 2049697 2049700 S2CID 52808268 Facebook Acquires Assets Of UK Mobile Bug Checking Software Developer Monoidics TechCrunch July 18 2013 Retrieved February 22 2020 permanent dead link Distefano Dino Fahndrich Manuel Logozzo Francesco O Hearn Peter W July 24 2019 Scaling static analyses at Facebook Communications of the ACM 62 8 62 70 doi 10 1145 3338112 Dillig Isil Dillig Thomas Li Boyang McMillan Ken October 29 2013 Inductive invariant generation via abductive inference Proceedings of the 2013 ACM SIGPLAN international conference on Object oriented programming systems languages amp applications ACM SIGPLAN Notices Vol 48 pp 443 456 doi 10 1145 2509136 2509511 ISBN 9781450323741 S2CID 16518775 Giacobazzi Roberto August 1 1998 Abductive Analysis of Modular Logic Programs Journal of Logic and Computation 8 4 457 483 doi 10 1093 logcom 8 4 457 ISSN 0955 792X Polikarpova Nadia Sergey Ilya January 2 2019 Structuring the synthesis of heap manipulating programs Proceedings of the ACM on Programming Languages 3 1 30 arXiv 1807 07022 doi 10 1145 3290385 References editAkaike Hirotugu 1994 Implications of informational point of view on the development of statistical science in Bozdogan H ed Proceedings of the First US JAPAN Conference on The Frontiers of Statistical Modeling An Informational Approach Volume 3 Kluwer Academic Publishers pp 27 38 Awbrey Jon and Awbrey Susan 1995 Interpretation as Action The Risk of Inquiry Inquiry Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 15 40 52 Eprint Cialdea Mayer Marta and Pirri Fiora 1993 First order abduction via tableau and sequent calculi Logic Jnl IGPL 1993 1 99 117 doi 10 1093 jigpal 1 1 99 Oxford Journals Cialdea Mayer Marta and Pirri Fiora 1995 Propositional Abduction in Modal Logic Logic Jnl IGPL 1995 3 907 919 doi 10 1093 jigpal 3 6 907 Oxford Journals Edwards Paul 1967 eds The Encyclopedia of Philosophy Macmillan Publishing Co Inc amp The Free Press New York Collier Macmillan Publishers London Eiter T and Gottlob G 1995 The Complexity of Logic Based Abduction Journal of the ACM 42 1 3 42 Hanson N R 1958 Patterns of Discovery An Inquiry into the Conceptual Foundations of Science Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 09261 6 Harman Gilbert 1965 The Inference to the Best Explanation The Philosophical Review 74 1 88 95 doi 10 2307 2183532 JSTOR 2183532 Josephson John R and Josephson Susan G 1995 eds Abductive Inference Computation Philosophy Technology Cambridge University Press Cambridge UK Lipton Peter 2001 Inference to the Best Explanation London Routledge ISBN 0 415 24202 9 Magnani Lorenzo 2014 Understanding abduction Model Based Reasoning in Science and Technology Theoretical and Cognitive Issues editor Magnani L Springer p 173 205 McKaughan Daniel J 2008 From Ugly Duckling to Swan C S Peirce Abduction and the Pursuit of Scientific Theories Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society v 44 no 3 summer 446 468 Menzies T 1996 Applications of Abduction Knowledge Level Modeling PDF International Journal of Human Computer Studies 45 3 305 335 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 352 8159 doi 10 1006 ijhc 1996 0054 Queiroz Joao amp Merrell Floyd guest eds 2005 Abduction between subjectivity and objectivity special issue on abductive inference Semiotica 153 1 4 1 Santaella Lucia 1997 The Development of Peirce s Three Types of Reasoning Abduction Deduction and Induction 6th Congress of the IASS Eprint Sebeok T 1981 You Know My Method In Sebeok T The Play of Musement Indiana Bloomington IA Yu Chong Ho 1994 Is There a Logic of Exploratory Data Analysis Annual Meeting of American Educational Research Association New Orleans LA April 1994 Website of Dr Chong Ho Alex YuExternal links edit nbsp Look up abductive reasoning in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Look up abductive or abductive reasoning in Wiktionary the free dictionary Douven Igor Abduction In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Abductive reasoning at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Abductive reasoning at PhilPapers Abductive Inference once there scroll down John R Josephson Laboratory for Artificial Intelligence Research Ohio State University Former webpage via the Wayback Machine Deduction Induction and Abduction Chapter 3 in article Charles Sanders Peirce by Robert W Burch 2001 and 2006 in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Abduction links to articles and websites on abductive inference Martin Ryder International Research Group on Abductive Inference Uwe Wirth and Alexander Roesler eds Uses frames Click on link at bottom of its home page for English Wirth moved to U of Giessen Germany and set up Abduktionsforschung home page not in English but see Artikel section there Abduktionsforschung home page via Google translation You Know My Method A Juxtaposition of Charles S Peirce and Sherlock Holmes 1981 by Thomas Sebeok with Jean Umiker Sebeok from The Play of Musement Thomas Sebeok Bloomington Indiana Indiana University Press pp 17 52 Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola editors Helsinki U Peirce s own definitions often many per term across the decades There see Hypothesis as a form of reasoning Abduction Retroduction and Presumption as a form of reasoning Touching Reality a critique of abductive reasoning in the context of cosmology Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Abductive reasoning amp oldid 1211883736, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.