fbpx
Wikipedia

Interpretations of quantum mechanics

An interpretation of quantum mechanics is an attempt to explain how the mathematical theory of quantum mechanics might correspond to experienced reality. Although quantum mechanics has held up to rigorous and extremely precise tests in an extraordinarily broad range of experiments, there exist a number of contending schools of thought over their interpretation. These views on interpretation differ on such fundamental questions as whether quantum mechanics is deterministic or stochastic, local or non-local, which elements of quantum mechanics can be considered real, and what the nature of measurement is, among other matters.

While some variation of the Copenhagen interpretation is commonly presented in textbooks, many thought provoking interpretations have been developed. Despite nearly a century of debate and experiment, no consensus has been reached among physicists and philosophers of physics concerning which interpretation best "represents" reality.[1][2]

History edit

Influential figures in the interpretation of quantum mechanics

The definition of quantum theorists' terms, such as wave function and matrix mechanics, progressed through many stages. For instance, Erwin Schrödinger originally viewed the electron's wave function as its charge density smeared across space, but Max Born reinterpreted the absolute square value of the wave function as the electron's probability density distributed across space;[3]: 24–33  the Born rule, as it is now called, matched experiment, whereas Schrödinger's charge density view did not.

The views of several early pioneers of quantum mechanics, such as Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg, are often grouped together as the "Copenhagen interpretation", though physicists and historians of physics have argued that this terminology obscures differences between the views so designated.[3][4] Copenhagen-type ideas were never universally embraced, and challenges to a perceived Copenhagen orthodoxy gained increasing attention in the 1950s with the pilot-wave interpretation of David Bohm and the many-worlds interpretation of Hugh Everett III.[3][5][6]

The physicist N. David Mermin once quipped, "New interpretations appear every year. None ever disappear."[7] As a rough guide to development of the mainstream view during the 1990s and 2000s, a "snapshot" of opinions was collected in a poll by Schlosshauer et al. at the "Quantum Physics and the Nature of Reality" conference of July 2011.[8] The authors reference a similarly informal poll carried out by Max Tegmark at the "Fundamental Problems in Quantum Theory" conference in August 1997. The main conclusion of the authors is that "the Copenhagen interpretation still reigns supreme", receiving the most votes in their poll (42%), besides the rise to mainstream notability of the many-worlds interpretations: "The Copenhagen interpretation still reigns supreme here, especially if we lump it together with intellectual offsprings such as information-based interpretations and the quantum Bayesian interpretation. In Tegmark's poll, the Everett interpretation received 17% of the vote, which is similar to the number of votes (18%) in our poll."

Some concepts originating from studies of interpretations have found more practical application in quantum information science.[9][10]

Nature edit

More or less, all interpretations of quantum mechanics share two qualities:

  1. They interpret a formalism—a set of equations and principles to generate predictions via input of initial conditions
  2. They interpret a phenomenology—a set of observations, including those obtained by empirical research and those obtained informally, such as humans' experience of an unequivocal world

Two qualities vary among interpretations:

  1. Epistemology—claims about the possibility, scope, and means toward relevant knowledge of the world
  2. Ontology—claims about what things, such as categories and entities, exist in the world

In philosophy of science, the distinction of knowledge versus reality is termed epistemic versus ontic. A general law is a regularity of outcomes (epistemic), whereas a causal mechanism may regulate the outcomes (ontic). A phenomenon can receive interpretation either ontic or epistemic. For instance, indeterminism may be attributed to limitations of human observation and perception (epistemic), or may be explained as intrinsic physical randomness (ontic). Confusing the epistemic with the ontic—if for example one were to presume that a general law actually "governs" outcomes, and that the statement of a regularity has the role of a causal mechanism—is a category mistake.

In a broad sense, scientific theory can be viewed as offering scientific realism—approximately true description or explanation of the natural world—or might be perceived with antirealism. A realist stance seeks the epistemic and the ontic, whereas an antirealist stance seeks epistemic but not the ontic. In the 20th century's first half, antirealism was mainly logical positivism, which sought to exclude unobservable aspects of reality from scientific theory.

Since the 1950s, antirealism is more modest, usually instrumentalism, permitting talk of unobservable aspects, but ultimately discarding the very question of realism and posing scientific theory as a tool to help humans make predictions, not to attain metaphysical understanding of the world. The instrumentalist view is carried by the famous quote of David Mermin, "Shut up and calculate", often misattributed to Richard Feynman.[11]

Other approaches to resolve conceptual problems introduce new mathematical formalism, and so propose alternative theories with their interpretations. An example is Bohmian mechanics, whose empirical equivalence with the three standard formalisms—Schrödinger's wave mechanics, Heisenberg's matrix mechanics, and Feynman's path integral formalism—has been demonstrated.

Interpretive challenges edit

  1. Abstract, mathematical nature of quantum field theories: the mathematical structure of quantum mechanics is abstract without clear interpretation of its quantities.
  2. Existence of apparently indeterministic and irreversible processes: in classical field theory, a physical property at a given location in the field is readily derived. In most mathematical formulations of quantum mechanics, measurement is given a special role in the theory, as it is the sole process that can cause a nonunitary, irreversible evolution of the state.
  3. Role of the observer in determining outcomes: the Copenhagen-type interpretations imply that the wavefunction is a calculational tool, and represents reality only immediately after a measurement, perhaps performed by an observer; Everettian interpretations grant that all the possibilities can be real, and that the process of measurement-type interactions causes an effective branching process.[12]
  4. Classically unexpected correlations between remote objects: entangled quantum systems, as illustrated in the EPR paradox, obey statistics that seem to violate principles of local causality.[13]
  5. Complementarity of proffered descriptions: complementarity holds that no set of classical physical concepts can simultaneously refer to all properties of a quantum system. For instance, wave description A and particulate description B can each describe quantum system S, but not simultaneously. This implies the composition of physical properties of S does not obey the rules of classical propositional logic when using propositional connectives (see "Quantum logic"). Like contextuality, the "origin of complementarity lies in the non-commutativity of operators" that describe quantum objects (Omnès 1999).
  6. Rapidly rising intricacy, far exceeding humans' present calculational capacity, as a system's size increases: since the state space of a quantum system is exponential in the number of subsystems, it is difficult to derive classical approximations.
  7. Contextual behaviour of systems locally: Quantum contextuality demonstrates that classical intuitions, in which properties of a system hold definite values independent of the manner of their measurement, fail even for local systems. Also, physical principles such as Leibniz's Principle of the identity of indiscernibles no longer apply in the quantum domain, signaling that most classical intuitions may be incorrect about the quantum world.

Influential interpretations edit

Copenhagen interpretation edit

The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. It is one of the oldest attitudes towards quantum mechanics, as features of it date to the development of quantum mechanics during 1925–1927, and it remains one of the most commonly taught.[14][15] There is no definitive historical statement of what is the Copenhagen interpretation, and there were in particular fundamental disagreements between the views of Bohr and Heisenberg.[16][17] For example, Heisenberg emphasized a sharp "cut" between the observer (or the instrument) and the system being observed,[18]: 133  while Bohr offered an interpretation that is independent of a subjective observer or measurement or collapse, which relies on an "irreversible" or effectively irreversible process which imparts the classical behavior of "observation" or "measurement".[19][20][21][22]

Features common to Copenhagen-type interpretations include the idea that quantum mechanics is intrinsically indeterministic, with probabilities calculated using the Born rule, and the principle of complementarity, which states certain pairs of complementary properties cannot all be observed or measured simultaneously. Moreover, properties only result from the act of "observing" or "measuring"; the theory avoids assuming definite values from unperformed experiments. Copenhagen-type interpretations hold that quantum descriptions are objective, in that they are independent of physicists' mental arbitrariness.[23]: 85–90  The statistical interpretation of wavefunctions due to Max Born differs sharply from Schrödinger's original intent, which was to have a theory with continuous time evolution and in which wavefunctions directly described physical reality.[3]: 24–33 [24]

Many worlds edit

The many-worlds interpretation is an interpretation of quantum mechanics in which a universal wavefunction obeys the same deterministic, reversible laws at all times; in particular there is no (indeterministic and irreversible) wavefunction collapse associated with measurement. The phenomena associated with measurement are claimed to be explained by decoherence, which occurs when states interact with the environment. More precisely, the parts of the wavefunction describing observers become increasingly entangled with the parts of the wavefunction describing their experiments. Although all possible outcomes of experiments continue to lie in the wavefunction's support, the times at which they become correlated with observers effectively "split" the universe into mutually unobservable alternate histories.

Quantum information theories edit

Quantum informational approaches[25][26] have attracted growing support.[27][8] They subdivide into two kinds.[28]

  • Information ontologies, such as J. A. Wheeler's "it from bit". These approaches have been described as a revival of immaterialism.[28]
  • Interpretations where quantum mechanics is said to describe an observer's knowledge of the world, rather than the world itself. This approach has some similarity with Bohr's thinking.[29] Collapse (also known as reduction) is often interpreted as an observer acquiring information from a measurement, rather than as an objective event. These approaches have been appraised as similar to instrumentalism. James Hartle writes,

The state is not an objective property of an individual system but is that information, obtained from a knowledge of how a system was prepared, which can be used for making predictions about future measurements. ...A quantum mechanical state being a summary of the observer's information about an individual physical system changes both by dynamical laws, and whenever the observer acquires new information about the system through the process of measurement. The existence of two laws for the evolution of the state vector...becomes problematical only if it is believed that the state vector is an objective property of the system...The "reduction of the wavepacket" does take place in the consciousness of the observer, not because of any unique physical process which takes place there, but only because the state is a construct of the observer and not an objective property of the physical system.[30]

Relational quantum mechanics edit

The essential idea behind relational quantum mechanics, following the precedent of special relativity, is that different observers may give different accounts of the same series of events: for example, to one observer at a given point in time, a system may be in a single, "collapsed" eigenstate, while to another observer at the same time, it may be in a superposition of two or more states. Consequently, if quantum mechanics is to be a complete theory, relational quantum mechanics argues that the notion of "state" describes not the observed system itself, but the relationship, or correlation, between the system and its observer(s). The state vector of conventional quantum mechanics becomes a description of the correlation of some degrees of freedom in the observer, with respect to the observed system. However, it is held by relational quantum mechanics that this applies to all physical objects, whether or not they are conscious or macroscopic. Any "measurement event" is seen simply as an ordinary physical interaction, an establishment of the sort of correlation discussed above. Thus the physical content of the theory has to do not with objects themselves, but the relations between them.[31][32]

QBism edit

QBism, which originally stood for "quantum Bayesianism", is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that takes an agent's actions and experiences as the central concerns of the theory. This interpretation is distinguished by its use of a subjective Bayesian account of probabilities to understand the quantum mechanical Born rule as a normative addition to good decision-making. QBism draws from the fields of quantum information and Bayesian probability and aims to eliminate the interpretational conundrums that have beset quantum theory.

QBism deals with common questions in the interpretation of quantum theory about the nature of wavefunction superposition, quantum measurement, and entanglement.[33][34] According to QBism, many, but not all, aspects of the quantum formalism are subjective in nature. For example, in this interpretation, a quantum state is not an element of reality—instead it represents the degrees of belief an agent has about the possible outcomes of measurements. For this reason, some philosophers of science have deemed QBism a form of anti-realism.[35][36] The originators of the interpretation disagree with this characterization, proposing instead that the theory more properly aligns with a kind of realism they call "participatory realism", wherein reality consists of more than can be captured by any putative third-person account of it.[37][38]

Consistent histories edit

The consistent histories interpretation generalizes the conventional Copenhagen interpretation and attempts to provide a natural interpretation of quantum cosmology. The theory is based on a consistency criterion that allows the history of a system to be described so that the probabilities for each history obey the additive rules of classical probability. It is claimed to be consistent with the Schrödinger equation.

According to this interpretation, the purpose of a quantum-mechanical theory is to predict the relative probabilities of various alternative histories (for example, of a particle).

Ensemble interpretation edit

The ensemble interpretation, also called the statistical interpretation, can be viewed as a minimalist interpretation. That is, it claims to make the fewest assumptions associated with the standard mathematics. It takes the statistical interpretation of Born to the fullest extent. The interpretation states that the wave function does not apply to an individual system – for example, a single particle – but is an abstract statistical quantity that only applies to an ensemble (a vast multitude) of similarly prepared systems or particles. In the words of Einstein:

The attempt to conceive the quantum-theoretical description as the complete description of the individual systems leads to unnatural theoretical interpretations, which become immediately unnecessary if one accepts the interpretation that the description refers to ensembles of systems and not to individual systems.

— Einstein in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, ed. P.A. Schilpp (Harper & Row, New York)

The most prominent current advocate of the ensemble interpretation is Leslie E. Ballentine, professor at Simon Fraser University, author of the text book Quantum Mechanics, A Modern Development.

De Broglie–Bohm theory edit

The de Broglie–Bohm theory of quantum mechanics (also known as the pilot wave theory) is a theory by Louis de Broglie and extended later by David Bohm to include measurements. Particles, which always have positions, are guided by the wavefunction. The wavefunction evolves according to the Schrödinger wave equation, and the wavefunction never collapses. The theory takes place in a single spacetime, is non-local, and is deterministic. The simultaneous determination of a particle's position and velocity is subject to the usual uncertainty principle constraint. The theory is considered to be a hidden-variable theory, and by embracing non-locality it satisfies Bell's inequality. The measurement problem is resolved, since the particles have definite positions at all times.[39] Collapse is explained as phenomenological.[40]

Transactional interpretation edit

The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics (TIQM) by John G. Cramer is an interpretation of quantum mechanics inspired by the Wheeler–Feynman absorber theory.[41] It describes the collapse of the wave function as resulting from a time-symmetric transaction between a possibility wave from the source to the receiver (the wave function) and a possibility wave from the receiver to source (the complex conjugate of the wave function). This interpretation of quantum mechanics is unique in that it not only views the wave function as a real entity, but the complex conjugate of the wave function, which appears in the Born rule for calculating the expected value for an observable, as also real.

Von Neumann–Wigner interpretation edit

In his treatise The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, John von Neumann deeply analyzed the so-called measurement problem. He concluded that the entire physical universe could be made subject to the Schrödinger equation (the universal wave function). He also described how measurement could cause a collapse of the wave function.[42] This point of view was prominently expanded on by Eugene Wigner, who argued that human experimenter consciousness (or maybe even dog consciousness) was critical for the collapse, but he later abandoned this interpretation.[43][44]

Quantum logic edit

Quantum logic can be regarded as a kind of propositional logic suitable for understanding the apparent anomalies regarding quantum measurement, most notably those concerning composition of measurement operations of complementary variables. This research area and its name originated in the 1936 paper by Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann, who attempted to reconcile some of the apparent inconsistencies of classical Boolean logic with the facts related to measurement and observation in quantum mechanics.

Modal interpretations of quantum theory edit

Modal interpretations of quantum mechanics were first conceived of in 1972 by Bas van Fraassen, in his paper "A formal approach to the philosophy of science". Van Fraassen introduced a distinction between a dynamical state, which describes what might be true about a system and which always evolves according to the Schrödinger equation, and a value state, which indicates what is actually true about a system at a given time. The term "modal interpretation" now is used to describe a larger set of models that grew out of this approach. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy describes several versions, including proposals by Kochen, Dieks, Clifton, Dickson, and Bub.[45] According to Michel Bitbol, Schrödinger's views on how to interpret quantum mechanics progressed through as many as four stages, ending with a non-collapse view that in respects resembles the interpretations of Everett and van Fraassen. Because Schrödinger subscribed to a kind of post-Machian neutral monism, in which "matter" and "mind" are only different aspects or arrangements of the same common elements, treating the wavefunction as ontic and treating it as epistemic became interchangeable.[46]

Time-symmetric theories edit

Time-symmetric interpretations of quantum mechanics were first suggested by Walter Schottky in 1921.[47][48] Several theories have been proposed which modify the equations of quantum mechanics to be symmetric with respect to time reversal.[49][50][51][52][53][54] (See Wheeler–Feynman time-symmetric theory.) This creates retrocausality: events in the future can affect ones in the past, exactly as events in the past can affect ones in the future. In these theories, a single measurement cannot fully determine the state of a system (making them a type of hidden-variables theory), but given two measurements performed at different times, it is possible to calculate the exact state of the system at all intermediate times. The collapse of the wavefunction is therefore not a physical change to the system, just a change in our knowledge of it due to the second measurement. Similarly, they explain entanglement as not being a true physical state but just an illusion created by ignoring retrocausality. The point where two particles appear to "become entangled" is simply a point where each particle is being influenced by events that occur to the other particle in the future.

Not all advocates of time-symmetric causality favour modifying the unitary dynamics of standard quantum mechanics. Thus a leading exponent of the two-state vector formalism, Lev Vaidman, states that the two-state vector formalism dovetails well with Hugh Everett's many-worlds interpretation.[55]

Other interpretations edit

As well as the mainstream interpretations discussed above, a number of other interpretations have been proposed which have not made a significant scientific impact for whatever reason. These range from proposals by mainstream physicists to the more occult ideas of quantum mysticism.

Related concepts edit

Some ideas are discussed in the context of interpreting quantum mechanics but are not necessarily regarded as interpretations themselves.

Quantum Darwinism edit

Quantum Darwinism is a theory meant to explain the emergence of the classical world from the quantum world as due to a process of Darwinian natural selection induced by the environment interacting with the quantum system; where the many possible quantum states are selected against in favor of a stable pointer state. It was proposed in 2003 by Wojciech Zurek and a group of collaborators including Ollivier, Poulin, Paz and Blume-Kohout. The development of the theory is due to the integration of a number of Zurek's research topics pursued over the course of twenty-five years including pointer states, einselection and decoherence.

Objective-collapse theories edit

Objective-collapse theories differ from the Copenhagen interpretation by regarding both the wave function and the process of collapse as ontologically objective (meaning these exist and occur independent of the observer). In objective theories, collapse occurs either randomly ("spontaneous localization") or when some physical threshold is reached, with observers having no special role. Thus, objective-collapse theories are realistic, indeterministic, no-hidden-variables theories. Standard quantum mechanics does not specify any mechanism of collapse; quantum mechanics would need to be extended if objective collapse is correct. The requirement for an extension means that objective-collapse theories are alternatives to quantum mechanics rather than interpretations of it. Examples include

Comparisons edit

The most common interpretations are summarized in the table below. The values shown in the cells of the table are not without controversy, for the precise meanings of some of the concepts involved are unclear and, in fact, are themselves at the center of the controversy surrounding the given interpretation. For another table comparing interpretations of quantum theory, see reference.[57]

No experimental evidence exists that distinguishes among these interpretations. To that extent, the physical theory stands, and is consistent with itself and with reality; difficulties arise only when one attempts to "interpret" the theory. Nevertheless, designing experiments which would test the various interpretations is the subject of active research.

Most of these interpretations have variants. For example, it is difficult to get a precise definition of the Copenhagen interpretation as it was developed and argued by many people.

Interpre­tation Year pub­lished Author(s) Determ­inistic? Ontic wave­function? Unique
history?
Hidden
variables
?
Collapsing
wave­functions
?
Observer
role?
Local
dyna­mics
?
Counter­factually
definite
?
Extant
universal
wave­function
?
Ensemble interpretation 1926 Max Born Agnostic No Yes Agnostic No No No No No
Copenhagen interpretation 1927 Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg No Some[58] Yes No Some[59] No[60][61] Yes No No
De Broglie–Bohm theory 1927–
1952
Louis de Broglie, David Bohm Yes Yes[a] Yes[b] Yes Phenomen­ological No No Yes Yes
Quantum logic 1936 Garrett Birkhoff Agnostic Agnostic Yes[c] No No Interpre­tational[d] Agnostic No No
Time-
symmetric theories
1955 Satosi Watanabe Yes No Yes Yes No No No[62] No Yes
Many-worlds interpretation 1957 Hugh Everett Yes Yes No No No No Yes Ill-posed Yes
Consciousness causes collapse 1961–
1993
John von Neumann, Eugene Wigner, Henry Stapp No Yes Yes No Yes Causal No No Yes
Many-minds interpretation 1970 H. Dieter Zeh Yes Yes No No No Interpre­tational[e] Yes Ill-posed Yes
Consistent histories 1984 Robert B. Griffiths No No No No No[f] No[g] Yes No Yes
Transactional interpretation 1986 John G. Cramer No Yes Yes No Yes[h] No No[i] Yes No
Objective-collapse theories 1986–
1989
Giancarlo Ghirardi, Alberto Rimini, Tullio Weber, Roger Penrose No Yes Yes No Yes No No No No
Relational interpretation 1994 Carlo Rovelli No[63] No Agnostic[j] No Yes[k] Intrinsic[l] Possibly[m] No No
QBism 2010 Christopher Fuchs, Rüdiger Schack No No[n] Agnostic[o] No Yes[p] Intrinsic[q] Yes No No
  1. ^ Both particle AND guiding wavefunction are real.
  2. ^ Unique particle history, but multiple wave histories.
  3. ^ But quantum logic is more limited in applicability than Coherent Histories.
  4. ^ Quantum mechanics is regarded as a way of predicting observations, or a theory of measurement.
  5. ^ Observers separate the universal wavefunction into orthogonal sets of experiences.
  6. ^ In the consistent histories interpretation the collapse is a legitimate calculational procedure when describing the preparation of a quantum system, but it amounts to nothing more than a convenient way of calculating conditional probabilities.
  7. ^ In the consistent histories interpretation, observers are necessary to select a specific family of consistent histories (i.e., a framework), thus enabling the calculation of probabilities of physical events. Observers, however, play a purely passive role, similar to a photographer chosing a particular framing when taking a picture.
  8. ^ In the TI the collapse of the state vector is interpreted as the completion of the transaction between emitter and absorber.
  9. ^ The transactional interpretation is explicitly non-local.
  10. ^ Comparing histories between systems in this interpretation has no well-defined meaning.
  11. ^ Any physical interaction is treated as a collapse event relative to the systems involved, not just macroscopic or conscious observers.
  12. ^ The state of the system is observer-dependent, i.e., the state is specific to the reference frame of the observer.
  13. ^ The interpretation was originally presented as local,[64] but whether locality is well-posed in RQM has been disputed.[65]
  14. ^ A wavefunction merely encodes an agent’s expectations for future experiences. It is no more real than a probability distribution is in subjective Bayesianism.
  15. ^ Quantum theory is a tool any agent may use to help manage their expectations. The past comes into play only insofar as an agent’s individual experiences and temperament influence their priors.
  16. ^ Although QBism would eschew this terminology. A change in the wavefunction that an agent ascribes to a system as a result of having an experience represents a change in his or her beliefs about further experiences they may have. See Doxastic logic.
  17. ^ Observers, or more properly, participants, are as essential to the formalism as the systems they interact with.

The silent approach edit

Although interpretational opinions are openly and widely discussed today, that was not always the case. A notable exponent of a tendency of silence was Paul Dirac who once wrote: "The interpretation of quantum mechanics has been dealt with by many authors, and I do not want to discuss it here. I want to deal with more fundamental things."[66] This position is not uncommon among practitioners of quantum mechanics.[67] Similarly Richard Feynman wrote many popularizations of quantum mechanics without ever publishing about interpretation issues like quantum measurement.[68] Others, like Nico van Kampen and Willis Lamb, have openly criticized non-orthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics.[69][70]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Murray Gell-Mann – Quantum Mechanics Interpretations – Feynman Sum over Histories – EPR Bertlemann's https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=f-OFP5tNtMY Richard P Feynman: Quantum Mechanical View of Reality 1 (Part 1) https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=72us6pnbEvE
  2. ^ Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013-08-01). "A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. ISSN 1355-2198. S2CID 55537196.
  3. ^ a b c d Jammer, Max (1974). Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The interpretations of quantum mechanics in historical perspective. Wiley-Interscience. ISBN 9780471439585.
  4. ^ Camilleri, Kristian (2009-02-01). "Constructing the Myth of the Copenhagen Interpretation". Perspectives on Science. 17 (1): 26–57. doi:10.1162/posc.2009.17.1.26. ISSN 1530-9274. S2CID 57559199.
  5. ^ Vaidman, Lev (2021), "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2021 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2023-08-25
  6. ^ Frank J. Tipler (1994). The Physics of Immortality: Modern Cosmology, God, and the Resurrection of the Dead. Anchor Books. ISBN 978-0-385-46799-5.
  7. ^ Mermin, N. David (2012-07-01). "Commentary: Quantum mechanics: Fixing the shifty split". Physics Today. 65 (7): 8–10. Bibcode:2012PhT....65g...8M. doi:10.1063/PT.3.1618. ISSN 0031-9228.
  8. ^ a b Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013-01-06). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196.
  9. ^ Barnum, Howard; Wehner, Stephanie; Wilce, Alexander (August 2018). "Introduction: Quantum Information Theory and Quantum Foundations". Foundations of Physics. 48 (8): 853–856. Bibcode:2018FoPh...48..853B. doi:10.1007/s10701-018-0188-6. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 126293060.
  10. ^ DiVincenzo, David P.; Fuchs, Christopher A. (2019-02-01). "Quantum foundations". Physics Today. 72 (2): 50–51. Bibcode:2019PhT....72b..50D. doi:10.1063/PT.3.4141. ISSN 0031-9228. S2CID 241052502.
  11. ^ For a discussion of the provenance of the phrase "shut up and calculate", see Mermin, N. David (2004). "Could Feynman have said this?". Physics Today. 57 (5): 10–11. Bibcode:2004PhT....57e..10M. doi:10.1063/1.1768652.
  12. ^ Bacciagaluppi, Guido (2012), "The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2023-08-25
  13. ^ La nouvelle cuisine, by John S. Bell, last article of Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics, second edition.
  14. ^ Siddiqui, Shabnam; Singh, Chandralekha (2017). "How diverse are physics instructors' attitudes and approaches to teaching undergraduate level quantum mechanics?". European Journal of Physics. 38 (3): 035703. Bibcode:2017EJPh...38c5703S. doi:10.1088/1361-6404/aa6131.
  15. ^ Bell, John S. (1987), Speakable and Unspeakable in quantum Mechanics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press)
  16. ^ Faye, Jan (2019). "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  17. ^ Camilleri, K.; Schlosshauer, M. (2015). "Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment: Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr's Doctrine of Classical Concepts?". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 49: 73–83. arXiv:1502.06547. Bibcode:2015SHPMP..49...73C. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.01.005. S2CID 27697360.
  18. ^ Pauli, Wolfgang (1994) [1958]. "Albert Einstein and the development of physics". In Enz, C. P.; von Meyenn, K. (eds.). Writings on Physics and Philosophy. Berlin: Springer-Verlag. Bibcode:1994wpp..book.....P.
  19. ^ John Bell (1990), "Against 'measurement'", Physics World, 3 (8): 33–41, doi:10.1088/2058-7058/3/8/26
  20. ^ Niels Bohr (1985) [May 16, 1947], Jørgen Kalckar (ed.), Niels Bohr: Collected Works, vol. 6: Foundations of Quantum Physics I (1926–1932), pp. 451–454
  21. ^ Stenholm, Stig (1983), "To fathom space and time", in Meystre, Pierre (ed.), Quantum Optics, Experimental Gravitation, and Measurement Theory, Plenum Press, p. 121, The role of irreversibility in the theory of measurement has been emphasized by many. Only this way can a permanent record be obtained. The fact that separate pointer positions must be of the asymptotic nature usually associated with irreversibility has been utilized in the measurement theory of Daneri, Loinger and Prosperi (1962). It has been accepted as a formal representation of Bohr's ideas by Rosenfeld (1966).
  22. ^ Haake, Fritz (April 1, 1993), "Classical motion of meter variables in the quantum theory of measurement", Physical Review A, 47 (4): 2506–2517, Bibcode:1993PhRvA..47.2506H, doi:10.1103/PhysRevA.47.2506, PMID 9909217
  23. ^ Omnès, R. (1994). The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-03669-4. OCLC 439453957.
  24. ^ Beller, Mara (December 1983). "Matrix Theory before Schrödinger: Philosophy, Problems, Consequences". Isis. 74 (4): 469–491. doi:10.1086/353357. JSTOR 232208. S2CID 121780437.
  25. ^ "In the beginning was the bit". New Scientist. 2001-02-17. Retrieved 2022-01-18.
  26. ^ Janas, M.; Cuffaro, M. E.; Janssen, M. (2022). "Understanding Quantum Raffles". SpringerLink.
  27. ^ Kate Becker (2013-01-25). "Quantum physics has been rankling scientists for decades". Boulder Daily Camera. Retrieved 2013-01-25.
  28. ^ a b "Let us call the thought that information might be the basic category from which all else flows informational immaterialism." Information, Immaterialism, Instrumentalism: Old and New in Quantum Information. Christopher G. Timpson
  29. ^ "Physics concerns what we can say about nature". (Niels Bohr, quoted in Petersen, A. (1963). The philosophy of Niels Bohr. Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists, 19(7):8–14.)
  30. ^ Hartle, J. B. (1968). "Quantum mechanics of individual systems". Am. J. Phys. 36 (8): 704–712. arXiv:1907.02953. Bibcode:1968AmJPh..36..704H. doi:10.1119/1.1975096. S2CID 123454773.
  31. ^ "Relational Quantum Mechanics (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". Plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  32. ^ For more information, see Carlo Rovelli (1996). "Relational Quantum Mechanics". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 35 (8): 1637–1678. arXiv:quant-ph/9609002. Bibcode:1996IJTP...35.1637R. doi:10.1007/BF02302261. S2CID 16325959.
  33. ^ Timpson, Christopher Gordon (2008). "Quantum Bayesianism: A study" (postscript). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 39 (3): 579–609. arXiv:0804.2047. Bibcode:2008SHPMP..39..579T. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.03.006. S2CID 16775153.
  34. ^ Mermin, N. David (2012-07-01). "Commentary: Quantum mechanics: Fixing the shifty split". Physics Today. 65 (7): 8–10. Bibcode:2012PhT....65g...8M. doi:10.1063/PT.3.1618. ISSN 0031-9228.
  35. ^ Bub, Jeffrey (2016). Bananaworld: Quantum Mechanics for Primates. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 232. ISBN 978-0198718536.
  36. ^ Ladyman, James; Ross, Don; Spurrett, David; Collier, John (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 184. ISBN 9780199573097.
  37. ^ For "participatory realism," see, e.g.,
    Fuchs, Christopher A. (2017). "On Participatory Realism". In Durham, Ian T.; Rickles, Dean (eds.). Information and Interaction: Eddington, Wheeler, and the Limits of Knowledge. arXiv:1601.04360. Bibcode:2016arXiv160104360F. ISBN 9783319437606. OCLC 967844832.
    Fuchs, Christopher A.; Timpson, Christopher G. "Does Participatory Realism Make Sense? The Role of Observership in Quantum Theory". FQXi: Foundational Questions Institute. Retrieved 2017-04-18.
  38. ^ Cabello, Adán (2017). "Interpretations of quantum theory: A map of madness". In Lombardi, Olimpia; Fortin, Sebastian; Holik, Federico; López, Cristian (eds.). What is Quantum Information?. Cambridge University Press. pp. 138–143. arXiv:1509.04711. Bibcode:2015arXiv150904711C. doi:10.1017/9781316494233.009. ISBN 9781107142114. S2CID 118419619.
  39. ^ Maudlin, T. (1995). "Why Bohm's Theory Solves the Measurement Problem". Philosophy of Science. 62 (3): 479–483. doi:10.1086/289879. S2CID 122114295.
  40. ^ Durr, D.; Zanghi, N.; Goldstein, S. (Nov 14, 1995). "Bohmian Mechanics as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics". arXiv:quant-ph/9511016. Also published in Cushing, J. T.; Fine, Arthur; Goldstein, S. (17 April 2013). Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An Appraisal. Springer Science & Business Media. pp. 21–43. ISBN 978-94-015-8715-0.
  41. ^ . Npl.washington.edu. Archived from the original on 2010-12-29. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  42. ^ von Neumann, John. (1932/1955). Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Translated by Robert T. Beyer.
  43. ^ Esfeld, Michael (1999). "Essay Review: Wigner's View of Physical Reality". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 30B: 145–154.
  44. ^ Schreiber, Zvi (1995). "The Nine Lives of Schrödinger's Cat". arXiv:quant-ph/9501014.
  45. ^ Lombardi, Olimpia; Dieks, Dennis (2002-11-12). "Modal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Science.uva.nl. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  46. ^ Bitbol, Michel (1996). Schrödinger's Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. ISBN 978-94-009-1772-9. OCLC 851376153.
  47. ^ Schottky, Walter (1921). "Das Kausalproblem der Quantentheorie als eine Grundfrage der modernen Naturforschung überhaupt". Naturwissenschaften. 9 (25): 492–496. Bibcode:1921NW......9..492S. doi:10.1007/BF01494985. S2CID 22228793.
  48. ^ Schottky, Walter (1921). "Das Kausalproblem der Quantentheorie als eine Grundfrage der modernen Naturforschung überhaupt". Naturwissenschaften. 9 (26): 506–511. Bibcode:1921NW......9..506S. doi:10.1007/BF01496025. S2CID 26246226.
  49. ^ Watanabe, Satosi (1955). "Symmetry of physical laws. Part III. Prediction and retrodiction". Reviews of Modern Physics. 27 (2): 179–186. Bibcode:1955RvMP...27..179W. doi:10.1103/revmodphys.27.179. hdl:10945/47584. S2CID 122168419.
  50. ^ Aharonov, Y.; et al. (1964). "Time Symmetry in the Quantum Process of Measurement". Physical Review. 134 (6B): B1410–1416. Bibcode:1964PhRv..134.1410A. doi:10.1103/physrev.134.b1410.
  51. ^ Aharonov, Y. and Vaidman, L. "On the Two-State Vector Reformulation of Quantum Mechanics". Physica Scripta, Volume T76, pp. 85–92 (1998).
  52. ^ Wharton, K. B. (2007). "Time-Symmetric Quantum Mechanics". Foundations of Physics. 37 (1): 159–168. Bibcode:2007FoPh...37..159W. doi:10.1007/s10701-006-9089-1. S2CID 123086913.
  53. ^ Wharton, K. B. (2010). "A Novel Interpretation of the Klein–Gordon Equation". Foundations of Physics. 40 (3): 313–332. arXiv:0706.4075. Bibcode:2010FoPh...40..313W. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9398-2. S2CID 121170138.
  54. ^ Heaney, M. B. (2013). "A Symmetrical Interpretation of the Klein–Gordon Equation". Foundations of Physics. 43 (6): 733–746. arXiv:1211.4645. Bibcode:2013FoPh...43..733H. doi:10.1007/s10701-013-9713-9. S2CID 118770571.
  55. ^ Yakir Aharonov, Lev Vaidman: The Two-State Vector Formalism of Quantum Mechanics: an Updated Review. In: Juan Gonzalo Muga, Rafael Sala Mayato, Íñigo Egusquiza (eds.): Time in Quantum Mechanics, Volume 1, Lecture Notes in Physics 734, pp. 399–447, 2nd ed., Springer, 2008, ISBN 978-3-540-73472-7, doi:10.1007/978-3-540-73473-4_13, arXiv:quant-ph/0105101, p. 443
  56. ^ Frigg, Roman. (PDF). In Greenberger, Daniel; Hentschel, Klaus; Weinert, Friedel (eds.). Compendium of Quantum Physics. Springer. pp. 266–270. doi:10.1007/978-3-540-70626-7_81. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-06-24. Retrieved 2011-01-24.
  57. ^ Olimpia, Lombardi; Fortin, Sebastian; Federico, Holik; Cristian, López (2017). "Interpretations of Quantum Theory: A Map of Madness". What is quantum information?. pp. 138–144. arXiv:1509.04711. doi:10.1017/9781316494233.009. ISBN 9781107142114. OCLC 965759965. S2CID 118419619.
  58. ^ John L. Heilbron (1988), "The Earliest Missionaries of the Copenhagen Spirit", in E. Ullmann-Margalit (ed.), Science in Reflection, pp. 201–233, This resolution of EPR, which Rosen later characterized as a stipulation that "[physical] reality is whatever quantum mechanics is capable of describing," was applauded for its clarity by Bohr's close associates. Heisenberg, Klein, and Kramers particularly liked the reduction of the EPR thought experiment to the familiar problem of the diaphragm with holes. Perhaps the most interesting responses came from Bohr's old friend, the physicist C. W. Oseen, and from his new ally, the physicist-philosopher Philipp Frank. Oseen had understood at last what he now recognized that Bohr had been saying all along: before a measurement an atom's state with respect to the quantity measured is undefined. Frank saw that Bohr had indeed transfixed EPR on an essential ambiguity. What Frank liked most was the implication that physicists should avoid the term and concept of "physical reality". He understood Bohr to mean that complementarity characterized measuring procedures, not the things measured. Bohr acknowledged that that was indeed what he had had in mind.
  59. ^ Henrik Zinkernagel (2016), "Niels Bohr on the wave function and the classical/quantum divide", Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 53: 9–19, arXiv:1603.00353, Bibcode:2016SHPMP..53....9Z, doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2015.11.001, S2CID 18890207, For a start, discussions of the Copenhagen interpretation in the literature are ambiguous between two different views of the wave function, both of which of course accept the Born interpretation. Sometimes the Copenhagen (and Bohr's) interpretation is associated with the epistemic view of the quantum state, according to which the quantum state is but a representation of our knowledge of the physical system, and thus not a real existing entity in itself. On this view the 'collapse' of the wave function is not a physical process, and it just reflects an update of our information about the system; see e.g. Zeilinger (1999). By contrast, the Copenhagen interpretation has also been associated with an ontological view of the quantum state, in which the wave function somehow describes a real wave, and the collapse is a real physical process – presumably induced by the observer. This ontological view is usually attributed to von Neumann in his 1932 textbook exposition of quantum mechanics; see e.g. Henderson (2010). [...] Thus, for Bohr, the wave function is a representation of a quantum system in a particular, classically described, experimental context. Three important points need to be made regarding this contextuality: 1) When a measurement is performed (that is, when an irreversible recording has been made; see below), then the context changes, and hence the wave function changes. This can formally be seen as a "collapse" of the wave function, with the square quotes indicating that we are not talking about a physical process in which a real wave collapses.
  60. ^ W. Heisenberg (1955), "The Development of the Interpretation of the Quantum Theory", in W. Pauli (ed.), Essays dedicated to Niels Bohr on the occasion of his seventieth birthday, Pergamon Press, Of course it is entirely justified to imagine this transition, from the possible to the actual, moved to an earlier point of time, for the observer himself does not produce the transition; but it cannot be moved back to a time when the compound system was still separate from the external world, because such an assumption would not be compatible with the validity of quantum mechanics for the closed system. We see from this that a system cut off from the external world is potential but not actual in character, or, as BOHR has often expressed it, that the system cannot be described in terms of the classical concepts. We may say that the state of the closed system represented by a Hilbert vector is indeed objective, but not real, and that the classical idea of "objectively real things" must here, to this extent, be abandoned.
  61. ^ Niels Bohr (1958), "Quantum Physics and Philosophy—Causality and Complementarity", Essays 1958–1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge, p. 3, The description of atomic phenomena has in these respects a perfectly objective character, in the sense that no explicit reference is made to any individual observer and that therefore, with proper regard to relativistic exigencies, no ambiguity is involved in the communication of information.
  62. ^ Elitzur, Avshalom C.; Cohen, Eliahu; Okamoto, Ryo; Takeuchi, Shigeki (2018). "Nonlocal Position Changes of a Photon Revealed by Quantum Routers". Scientific Reports. 8 (1): 7730. arXiv:1707.09483. Bibcode:2018NatSR...8.7730E. doi:10.1038/s41598-018-26018-y. PMC 5955892. PMID 29769645.
  63. ^ Martin-Dussaud, P.; Rovelli, C.; Zalamea, F. (2019). "The Notion of Locality in Relational Quantum Mechanics". Foundations of Physics. 49 (2): 96–106. arXiv:1806.08150. Bibcode:2019FoPh...49...96M. doi:10.1007/s10701-019-00234-6. S2CID 50796079.
  64. ^ Smerlak, Matteo; Rovelli, Carlo (2007-03-01). "Relational EPR". Foundations of Physics. 37 (3): 427–445. arXiv:quant-ph/0604064. Bibcode:2007FoPh...37..427S. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9105-0. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 11816650.
  65. ^ Pienaar, Jacques (2019). "Comment on "The Notion of Locality in Relational Quantum Mechanics"". Foundations of Physics. 49 (12): 1404–1414. arXiv:1807.06457. Bibcode:2019FoPh...49.1404P. doi:10.1007/s10701-019-00303-w. S2CID 119473777.
  66. ^ P. A. M. Dirac, The inadequacies of quantum field theory, in Paul Adrien Maurice Dirac, B. N. Kursunoglu and E. P. Wigner, Eds. (Cambridge University, Cambridge, 1987) p. 194
  67. ^ Duarte, F. J. (2014). Quantum Optics for Engineers. New York: CRC. ISBN 978-1439888537.
  68. ^ Zeh, H. D. (July 2011). "Feynman's interpretation of quantum theory". The European Physical Journal H. 36 (1): 63–74. arXiv:0804.3348. doi:10.1140/epjh/e2011-10035-2. ISSN 2102-6459.
  69. ^ van Kampen, N. G. (2008). "The scandal of quantum mechanics". American Journal of Physics 76: 989.
  70. ^ Lamb, W. E. (2001). "Super classical quantum mechanics: the best interpretation of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics". American Journal of Physics. 69: 413–421.

Sources edit

  • Bub, J.; Clifton, R. (1996). "A uniqueness theorem for interpretations of quantum mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 27B: 181–219. doi:10.1016/1355-2198(95)00019-4.
  • Rudolf Carnap, 1939, "The interpretation of physics", in Foundations of Logic and Mathematics of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.
  • Dickson, M., 1994, "Wavefunction tails in the modal interpretation" in Hull, D., Forbes, M., and Burian, R., eds., Proceedings of the PSA 1" 366–376. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association.
  • --------, and Clifton, R., 1998, "Lorentz-invariance in modal interpretations" in Dieks, D. and Vermaas, P., eds., The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers: 9–48.
  • Fuchs, Christopher, 2002, "Quantum Mechanics as Quantum Information (and only a little more)". arXiv:quant-ph/0205039
  • --------, and A. Peres, 2000, "Quantum theory needs no 'interpretation'", Physics Today.
  • Herbert, N., 1985. Quantum Reality: Beyond the New Physics. New York: Doubleday. ISBN 0-385-23569-0.
  • Hey, Anthony, and Walters, P., 2003. The New Quantum Universe, 2nd ed. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-56457-3.
  • Jackiw, Roman; Kleppner, D. (2000). "One Hundred Years of Quantum Physics". Science. 289 (5481): 893–898. arXiv:quant-ph/0008092. Bibcode:2000quant.ph..8092K. doi:10.1126/science.289.5481.893. PMID 17839156. S2CID 6604344.
  • Max Jammer, 1966. The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. McGraw-Hill.
  • --------, 1974. The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Wiley & Sons.
  • Al-Khalili, 2003. Quantum: A Guide for the Perplexed. London: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
  • de Muynck, W. M., 2002. Foundations of quantum mechanics, an empiricist approach. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. ISBN 1-4020-0932-1.
  • Roland Omnès, 1999. Understanding Quantum Mechanics. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.
  • Karl Popper, 1963. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. The chapter "Three views Concerning Human Knowledge" addresses, among other things, instrumentalism in the physical sciences.
  • Hans Reichenbach, 1944. Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. University of California Press.
  • Tegmark, Max; Wheeler, J. A. (2001). "100 Years of Quantum Mysteries". Scientific American. 284 (2): 68–75. Bibcode:2001SciAm.284b..68T. doi:10.1038/scientificamerican0201-68. S2CID 119375538.
  • Bas van Fraassen, 1972, "A formal approach to the philosophy of science", in R. Colodny, ed., Paradigms and Paradoxes: The Philosophical Challenge of the Quantum Domain. Univ. of Pittsburgh Press: 303–366.
  • John A. Wheeler and Wojciech Hubert Zurek (eds), Quantum Theory and Measurement, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, ISBN 0-691-08316-9, LoC QC174.125.Q38 1983.

Further reading edit

Almost all authors below are professional physicists.

External links edit

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • "Bohmian mechanics" by Sheldon Goldstein.
    • "Collapse Theories." by Giancarlo Ghirardi.
    • "Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics" by Jan Faye.
    • "Everett's Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics" by Jeffrey Barrett.
    • "Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics" by Lev Vaidman.
    • "Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics" by Michael Dickson and Dennis Dieks.
    • "Philosophical Issues in Quantum Theory" by Wayne Myrvold.
    • "Quantum-Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory" by Richard Healey.
    • "Quantum Entanglement and Information" by Jeffrey Bub.
    • "Quantum mechanics" by Jenann Ismael.
    • "Quantum Logic and Probability Theory" by Alexander Wilce.
    • "Relational Quantum Mechanics" by Federico Laudisa and Carlo Rovelli.
    • "The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics" by Guido Bacciagaluppi.
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy:
    • "Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics" by Peter J. Lewis.
    • "Everettian Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics" by Christina Conroy.

interpretations, quantum, mechanics, interpretation, quantum, mechanics, attempt, explain, mathematical, theory, quantum, mechanics, might, correspond, experienced, reality, although, quantum, mechanics, held, rigorous, extremely, precise, tests, extraordinari. An interpretation of quantum mechanics is an attempt to explain how the mathematical theory of quantum mechanics might correspond to experienced reality Although quantum mechanics has held up to rigorous and extremely precise tests in an extraordinarily broad range of experiments there exist a number of contending schools of thought over their interpretation These views on interpretation differ on such fundamental questions as whether quantum mechanics is deterministic or stochastic local or non local which elements of quantum mechanics can be considered real and what the nature of measurement is among other matters While some variation of the Copenhagen interpretation is commonly presented in textbooks many thought provoking interpretations have been developed Despite nearly a century of debate and experiment no consensus has been reached among physicists and philosophers of physics concerning which interpretation best represents reality 1 2 Contents 1 History 2 Nature 3 Interpretive challenges 4 Influential interpretations 4 1 Copenhagen interpretation 4 2 Many worlds 4 3 Quantum information theories 4 4 Relational quantum mechanics 4 5 QBism 4 6 Consistent histories 4 7 Ensemble interpretation 4 8 De Broglie Bohm theory 4 9 Transactional interpretation 4 10 Von Neumann Wigner interpretation 4 11 Quantum logic 4 12 Modal interpretations of quantum theory 4 13 Time symmetric theories 4 14 Other interpretations 5 Related concepts 5 1 Quantum Darwinism 5 2 Objective collapse theories 6 Comparisons 7 The silent approach 8 See also 9 References 10 Sources 11 Further reading 12 External linksHistory editInfluential figures in the interpretation of quantum mechanics nbsp Schrodinger nbsp Born nbsp Bohr The definition of quantum theorists terms such as wave function and matrix mechanics progressed through many stages For instance Erwin Schrodinger originally viewed the electron s wave function as its charge density smeared across space but Max Born reinterpreted the absolute square value of the wave function as the electron s probability density distributed across space 3 24 33 the Born rule as it is now called matched experiment whereas Schrodinger s charge density view did not The views of several early pioneers of quantum mechanics such as Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg are often grouped together as the Copenhagen interpretation though physicists and historians of physics have argued that this terminology obscures differences between the views so designated 3 4 Copenhagen type ideas were never universally embraced and challenges to a perceived Copenhagen orthodoxy gained increasing attention in the 1950s with the pilot wave interpretation of David Bohm and the many worlds interpretation of Hugh Everett III 3 5 6 The physicist N David Mermin once quipped New interpretations appear every year None ever disappear 7 As a rough guide to development of the mainstream view during the 1990s and 2000s a snapshot of opinions was collected in a poll by Schlosshauer et al at the Quantum Physics and the Nature of Reality conference of July 2011 8 The authors reference a similarly informal poll carried out by Max Tegmark at the Fundamental Problems in Quantum Theory conference in August 1997 The main conclusion of the authors is that the Copenhagen interpretation still reigns supreme receiving the most votes in their poll 42 besides the rise to mainstream notability of the many worlds interpretations The Copenhagen interpretation still reigns supreme here especially if we lump it together with intellectual offsprings such as information based interpretations and the quantum Bayesian interpretation In Tegmark s poll the Everett interpretation received 17 of the vote which is similar to the number of votes 18 in our poll Some concepts originating from studies of interpretations have found more practical application in quantum information science 9 10 Nature editMore or less all interpretations of quantum mechanics share two qualities They interpret a formalism a set of equations and principles to generate predictions via input of initial conditions They interpret a phenomenology a set of observations including those obtained by empirical research and those obtained informally such as humans experience of an unequivocal worldTwo qualities vary among interpretations Epistemology claims about the possibility scope and means toward relevant knowledge of the world Ontology claims about what things such as categories and entities exist in the worldIn philosophy of science the distinction of knowledge versus reality is termed epistemic versus ontic A general law is a regularity of outcomes epistemic whereas a causal mechanism may regulate the outcomes ontic A phenomenon can receive interpretation either ontic or epistemic For instance indeterminism may be attributed to limitations of human observation and perception epistemic or may be explained as intrinsic physical randomness ontic Confusing the epistemic with the ontic if for example one were to presume that a general law actually governs outcomes and that the statement of a regularity has the role of a causal mechanism is a category mistake In a broad sense scientific theory can be viewed as offering scientific realism approximately true description or explanation of the natural world or might be perceived with antirealism A realist stance seeks the epistemic and the ontic whereas an antirealist stance seeks epistemic but not the ontic In the 20th century s first half antirealism was mainly logical positivism which sought to exclude unobservable aspects of reality from scientific theory Since the 1950s antirealism is more modest usually instrumentalism permitting talk of unobservable aspects but ultimately discarding the very question of realism and posing scientific theory as a tool to help humans make predictions not to attain metaphysical understanding of the world The instrumentalist view is carried by the famous quote of David Mermin Shut up and calculate often misattributed to Richard Feynman 11 Other approaches to resolve conceptual problems introduce new mathematical formalism and so propose alternative theories with their interpretations An example is Bohmian mechanics whose empirical equivalence with the three standard formalisms Schrodinger s wave mechanics Heisenberg s matrix mechanics and Feynman s path integral formalism has been demonstrated Interpretive challenges editAbstract mathematical nature of quantum field theories the mathematical structure of quantum mechanics is abstract without clear interpretation of its quantities Existence of apparently indeterministic and irreversible processes in classical field theory a physical property at a given location in the field is readily derived In most mathematical formulations of quantum mechanics measurement is given a special role in the theory as it is the sole process that can cause a nonunitary irreversible evolution of the state Role of the observer in determining outcomes the Copenhagen type interpretations imply that the wavefunction is a calculational tool and represents reality only immediately after a measurement perhaps performed by an observer Everettian interpretations grant that all the possibilities can be real and that the process of measurement type interactions causes an effective branching process 12 Classically unexpected correlations between remote objects entangled quantum systems as illustrated in the EPR paradox obey statistics that seem to violate principles of local causality 13 Complementarity of proffered descriptions complementarity holds that no set of classical physical concepts can simultaneously refer to all properties of a quantum system For instance wave description A and particulate description B can each describe quantum system S but not simultaneously This implies the composition of physical properties of S does not obey the rules of classical propositional logic when using propositional connectives see Quantum logic Like contextuality the origin of complementarity lies in the non commutativity of operators that describe quantum objects Omnes 1999 Rapidly rising intricacy far exceeding humans present calculational capacity as a system s size increases since the state space of a quantum system is exponential in the number of subsystems it is difficult to derive classical approximations Contextual behaviour of systems locally Quantum contextuality demonstrates that classical intuitions in which properties of a system hold definite values independent of the manner of their measurement fail even for local systems Also physical principles such as Leibniz s Principle of the identity of indiscernibles no longer apply in the quantum domain signaling that most classical intuitions may be incorrect about the quantum world Influential interpretations editCopenhagen interpretation edit Main article Copenhagen interpretation The Copenhagen interpretation is a collection of views about the meaning of quantum mechanics principally attributed to Niels Bohr and Werner Heisenberg It is one of the oldest attitudes towards quantum mechanics as features of it date to the development of quantum mechanics during 1925 1927 and it remains one of the most commonly taught 14 15 There is no definitive historical statement of what is the Copenhagen interpretation and there were in particular fundamental disagreements between the views of Bohr and Heisenberg 16 17 For example Heisenberg emphasized a sharp cut between the observer or the instrument and the system being observed 18 133 while Bohr offered an interpretation that is independent of a subjective observer or measurement or collapse which relies on an irreversible or effectively irreversible process which imparts the classical behavior of observation or measurement 19 20 21 22 Features common to Copenhagen type interpretations include the idea that quantum mechanics is intrinsically indeterministic with probabilities calculated using the Born rule and the principle of complementarity which states certain pairs of complementary properties cannot all be observed or measured simultaneously Moreover properties only result from the act of observing or measuring the theory avoids assuming definite values from unperformed experiments Copenhagen type interpretations hold that quantum descriptions are objective in that they are independent of physicists mental arbitrariness 23 85 90 The statistical interpretation of wavefunctions due to Max Born differs sharply from Schrodinger s original intent which was to have a theory with continuous time evolution and in which wavefunctions directly described physical reality 3 24 33 24 Many worlds edit Main article Many worlds interpretation The many worlds interpretation is an interpretation of quantum mechanics in which a universal wavefunction obeys the same deterministic reversible laws at all times in particular there is no indeterministic and irreversible wavefunction collapse associated with measurement The phenomena associated with measurement are claimed to be explained by decoherence which occurs when states interact with the environment More precisely the parts of the wavefunction describing observers become increasingly entangled with the parts of the wavefunction describing their experiments Although all possible outcomes of experiments continue to lie in the wavefunction s support the times at which they become correlated with observers effectively split the universe into mutually unobservable alternate histories Quantum information theories edit Quantum informational approaches 25 26 have attracted growing support 27 8 They subdivide into two kinds 28 Information ontologies such as J A Wheeler s it from bit These approaches have been described as a revival of immaterialism 28 Interpretations where quantum mechanics is said to describe an observer s knowledge of the world rather than the world itself This approach has some similarity with Bohr s thinking 29 Collapse also known as reduction is often interpreted as an observer acquiring information from a measurement rather than as an objective event These approaches have been appraised as similar to instrumentalism James Hartle writes The state is not an objective property of an individual system but is that information obtained from a knowledge of how a system was prepared which can be used for making predictions about future measurements A quantum mechanical state being a summary of the observer s information about an individual physical system changes both by dynamical laws and whenever the observer acquires new information about the system through the process of measurement The existence of two laws for the evolution of the state vector becomes problematical only if it is believed that the state vector is an objective property of the system The reduction of the wavepacket does take place in the consciousness of the observer not because of any unique physical process which takes place there but only because the state is a construct of the observer and not an objective property of the physical system 30 Relational quantum mechanics edit Main article Relational quantum mechanics The essential idea behind relational quantum mechanics following the precedent of special relativity is that different observers may give different accounts of the same series of events for example to one observer at a given point in time a system may be in a single collapsed eigenstate while to another observer at the same time it may be in a superposition of two or more states Consequently if quantum mechanics is to be a complete theory relational quantum mechanics argues that the notion of state describes not the observed system itself but the relationship or correlation between the system and its observer s The state vector of conventional quantum mechanics becomes a description of the correlation of some degrees of freedom in the observer with respect to the observed system However it is held by relational quantum mechanics that this applies to all physical objects whether or not they are conscious or macroscopic Any measurement event is seen simply as an ordinary physical interaction an establishment of the sort of correlation discussed above Thus the physical content of the theory has to do not with objects themselves but the relations between them 31 32 QBism edit Main article Quantum Bayesianism QBism which originally stood for quantum Bayesianism is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that takes an agent s actions and experiences as the central concerns of the theory This interpretation is distinguished by its use of a subjective Bayesian account of probabilities to understand the quantum mechanical Born rule as a normative addition to good decision making QBism draws from the fields of quantum information and Bayesian probability and aims to eliminate the interpretational conundrums that have beset quantum theory QBism deals with common questions in the interpretation of quantum theory about the nature of wavefunction superposition quantum measurement and entanglement 33 34 According to QBism many but not all aspects of the quantum formalism are subjective in nature For example in this interpretation a quantum state is not an element of reality instead it represents the degrees of belief an agent has about the possible outcomes of measurements For this reason some philosophers of science have deemed QBism a form of anti realism 35 36 The originators of the interpretation disagree with this characterization proposing instead that the theory more properly aligns with a kind of realism they call participatory realism wherein reality consists of more than can be captured by any putative third person account of it 37 38 Consistent histories edit Main article Consistent histories The consistent histories interpretation generalizes the conventional Copenhagen interpretation and attempts to provide a natural interpretation of quantum cosmology The theory is based on a consistency criterion that allows the history of a system to be described so that the probabilities for each history obey the additive rules of classical probability It is claimed to be consistent with the Schrodinger equation According to this interpretation the purpose of a quantum mechanical theory is to predict the relative probabilities of various alternative histories for example of a particle Ensemble interpretation edit Main article Ensemble interpretation The ensemble interpretation also called the statistical interpretation can be viewed as a minimalist interpretation That is it claims to make the fewest assumptions associated with the standard mathematics It takes the statistical interpretation of Born to the fullest extent The interpretation states that the wave function does not apply to an individual system for example a single particle but is an abstract statistical quantity that only applies to an ensemble a vast multitude of similarly prepared systems or particles In the words of Einstein The attempt to conceive the quantum theoretical description as the complete description of the individual systems leads to unnatural theoretical interpretations which become immediately unnecessary if one accepts the interpretation that the description refers to ensembles of systems and not to individual systems Einstein in Albert Einstein Philosopher Scientist ed P A Schilpp Harper amp Row New York The most prominent current advocate of the ensemble interpretation is Leslie E Ballentine professor at Simon Fraser University author of the text book Quantum Mechanics A Modern Development De Broglie Bohm theory edit Main article De Broglie Bohm theory The de Broglie Bohm theory of quantum mechanics also known as the pilot wave theory is a theory by Louis de Broglie and extended later by David Bohm to include measurements Particles which always have positions are guided by the wavefunction The wavefunction evolves according to the Schrodinger wave equation and the wavefunction never collapses The theory takes place in a single spacetime is non local and is deterministic The simultaneous determination of a particle s position and velocity is subject to the usual uncertainty principle constraint The theory is considered to be a hidden variable theory and by embracing non locality it satisfies Bell s inequality The measurement problem is resolved since the particles have definite positions at all times 39 Collapse is explained as phenomenological 40 Transactional interpretation edit Main article Transactional interpretation The transactional interpretation of quantum mechanics TIQM by John G Cramer is an interpretation of quantum mechanics inspired by the Wheeler Feynman absorber theory 41 It describes the collapse of the wave function as resulting from a time symmetric transaction between a possibility wave from the source to the receiver the wave function and a possibility wave from the receiver to source the complex conjugate of the wave function This interpretation of quantum mechanics is unique in that it not only views the wave function as a real entity but the complex conjugate of the wave function which appears in the Born rule for calculating the expected value for an observable as also real Von Neumann Wigner interpretation edit Main article Von Neumann Wigner interpretation In his treatise The Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics John von Neumann deeply analyzed the so called measurement problem He concluded that the entire physical universe could be made subject to the Schrodinger equation the universal wave function He also described how measurement could cause a collapse of the wave function 42 This point of view was prominently expanded on by Eugene Wigner who argued that human experimenter consciousness or maybe even dog consciousness was critical for the collapse but he later abandoned this interpretation 43 44 Quantum logic edit Main article Quantum logic Quantum logic can be regarded as a kind of propositional logic suitable for understanding the apparent anomalies regarding quantum measurement most notably those concerning composition of measurement operations of complementary variables This research area and its name originated in the 1936 paper by Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann who attempted to reconcile some of the apparent inconsistencies of classical Boolean logic with the facts related to measurement and observation in quantum mechanics Modal interpretations of quantum theory edit Modal interpretations of quantum mechanics were first conceived of in 1972 by Bas van Fraassen in his paper A formal approach to the philosophy of science Van Fraassen introduced a distinction between a dynamical state which describes what might be true about a system and which always evolves according to the Schrodinger equation and a value state which indicates what is actually true about a system at a given time The term modal interpretation now is used to describe a larger set of models that grew out of this approach The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy describes several versions including proposals by Kochen Dieks Clifton Dickson and Bub 45 According to Michel Bitbol Schrodinger s views on how to interpret quantum mechanics progressed through as many as four stages ending with a non collapse view that in respects resembles the interpretations of Everett and van Fraassen Because Schrodinger subscribed to a kind of post Machian neutral monism in which matter and mind are only different aspects or arrangements of the same common elements treating the wavefunction as ontic and treating it as epistemic became interchangeable 46 Time symmetric theories edit Time symmetric interpretations of quantum mechanics were first suggested by Walter Schottky in 1921 47 48 Several theories have been proposed which modify the equations of quantum mechanics to be symmetric with respect to time reversal 49 50 51 52 53 54 See Wheeler Feynman time symmetric theory This creates retrocausality events in the future can affect ones in the past exactly as events in the past can affect ones in the future In these theories a single measurement cannot fully determine the state of a system making them a type of hidden variables theory but given two measurements performed at different times it is possible to calculate the exact state of the system at all intermediate times The collapse of the wavefunction is therefore not a physical change to the system just a change in our knowledge of it due to the second measurement Similarly they explain entanglement as not being a true physical state but just an illusion created by ignoring retrocausality The point where two particles appear to become entangled is simply a point where each particle is being influenced by events that occur to the other particle in the future Not all advocates of time symmetric causality favour modifying the unitary dynamics of standard quantum mechanics Thus a leading exponent of the two state vector formalism Lev Vaidman states that the two state vector formalism dovetails well with Hugh Everett s many worlds interpretation 55 Other interpretations edit Main article Minority interpretations of quantum mechanics As well as the mainstream interpretations discussed above a number of other interpretations have been proposed which have not made a significant scientific impact for whatever reason These range from proposals by mainstream physicists to the more occult ideas of quantum mysticism Related concepts editSome ideas are discussed in the context of interpreting quantum mechanics but are not necessarily regarded as interpretations themselves Quantum Darwinism edit Main article Quantum Darwinism Quantum Darwinism is a theory meant to explain the emergence of the classical world from the quantum world as due to a process of Darwinian natural selection induced by the environment interacting with the quantum system where the many possible quantum states are selected against in favor of a stable pointer state It was proposed in 2003 by Wojciech Zurek and a group of collaborators including Ollivier Poulin Paz and Blume Kohout The development of the theory is due to the integration of a number of Zurek s research topics pursued over the course of twenty five years including pointer states einselection and decoherence Objective collapse theories edit Main article Objective collapse theory Objective collapse theories differ from the Copenhagen interpretation by regarding both the wave function and the process of collapse as ontologically objective meaning these exist and occur independent of the observer In objective theories collapse occurs either randomly spontaneous localization or when some physical threshold is reached with observers having no special role Thus objective collapse theories are realistic indeterministic no hidden variables theories Standard quantum mechanics does not specify any mechanism of collapse quantum mechanics would need to be extended if objective collapse is correct The requirement for an extension means that objective collapse theories are alternatives to quantum mechanics rather than interpretations of it Examples include the Ghirardi Rimini Weber theory 56 the continuous spontaneous localization model the Penrose interpretationComparisons editThe most common interpretations are summarized in the table below The values shown in the cells of the table are not without controversy for the precise meanings of some of the concepts involved are unclear and in fact are themselves at the center of the controversy surrounding the given interpretation For another table comparing interpretations of quantum theory see reference 57 No experimental evidence exists that distinguishes among these interpretations To that extent the physical theory stands and is consistent with itself and with reality difficulties arise only when one attempts to interpret the theory Nevertheless designing experiments which would test the various interpretations is the subject of active research Most of these interpretations have variants For example it is difficult to get a precise definition of the Copenhagen interpretation as it was developed and argued by many people Interpre tation Year pub lished Author s Determ inistic Ontic wave function Unique history Hidden variables Collapsing wave functions Observer role Local dyna mics Counter factually definite Extant universal wave function Ensemble interpretation 1926 Max Born Agnostic No Yes Agnostic No No No No NoCopenhagen interpretation 1927 Niels Bohr Werner Heisenberg No Some 58 Yes No Some 59 No 60 61 Yes No NoDe Broglie Bohm theory 1927 1952 Louis de Broglie David Bohm Yes Yes a Yes b Yes Phenomen ological No No Yes YesQuantum logic 1936 Garrett Birkhoff Agnostic Agnostic Yes c No No Interpre tational d Agnostic No NoTime symmetric theories 1955 Satosi Watanabe Yes No Yes Yes No No No 62 No YesMany worlds interpretation 1957 Hugh Everett Yes Yes No No No No Yes Ill posed YesConsciousness causes collapse 1961 1993 John von Neumann Eugene Wigner Henry Stapp No Yes Yes No Yes Causal No No YesMany minds interpretation 1970 H Dieter Zeh Yes Yes No No No Interpre tational e Yes Ill posed YesConsistent histories 1984 Robert B Griffiths No No No No No f No g Yes No YesTransactional interpretation 1986 John G Cramer No Yes Yes No Yes h No No i Yes NoObjective collapse theories 1986 1989 Giancarlo Ghirardi Alberto Rimini Tullio Weber Roger Penrose No Yes Yes No Yes No No No NoRelational interpretation 1994 Carlo Rovelli No 63 No Agnostic j No Yes k Intrinsic l Possibly m No NoQBism 2010 Christopher Fuchs Rudiger Schack No No n Agnostic o No Yes p Intrinsic q Yes No No Both particle AND guiding wavefunction are real Unique particle history but multiple wave histories But quantum logic is more limited in applicability than Coherent Histories Quantum mechanics is regarded as a way of predicting observations or a theory of measurement Observers separate the universal wavefunction into orthogonal sets of experiences In the consistent histories interpretation the collapse is a legitimate calculational procedure when describing the preparation of a quantum system but it amounts to nothing more than a convenient way of calculating conditional probabilities In the consistent histories interpretation observers are necessary to select a specific family of consistent histories i e a framework thus enabling the calculation of probabilities of physical events Observers however play a purely passive role similar to a photographer chosing a particular framing when taking a picture In the TI the collapse of the state vector is interpreted as the completion of the transaction between emitter and absorber The transactional interpretation is explicitly non local Comparing histories between systems in this interpretation has no well defined meaning Any physical interaction is treated as a collapse event relative to the systems involved not just macroscopic or conscious observers The state of the system is observer dependent i e the state is specific to the reference frame of the observer The interpretation was originally presented as local 64 but whether locality is well posed in RQM has been disputed 65 A wavefunction merely encodes an agent s expectations for future experiences It is no more real than a probability distribution is in subjective Bayesianism Quantum theory is a tool any agent may use to help manage their expectations The past comes into play only insofar as an agent s individual experiences and temperament influence their priors Although QBism would eschew this terminology A change in the wavefunction that an agent ascribes to a system as a result of having an experience represents a change in his or her beliefs about further experiences they may have See Doxastic logic Observers or more properly participants are as essential to the formalism as the systems they interact with The silent approach editAlthough interpretational opinions are openly and widely discussed today that was not always the case A notable exponent of a tendency of silence was Paul Dirac who once wrote The interpretation of quantum mechanics has been dealt with by many authors and I do not want to discuss it here I want to deal with more fundamental things 66 This position is not uncommon among practitioners of quantum mechanics 67 Similarly Richard Feynman wrote many popularizations of quantum mechanics without ever publishing about interpretation issues like quantum measurement 68 Others like Nico van Kampen and Willis Lamb have openly criticized non orthodox interpretations of quantum mechanics 69 70 See also editBohr Einstein debates Einstein s thought experiments Glossary of quantum philosophy Local hidden variable theory Philosophical interpretation of classical physics Popper s experiment Superdeterminism Quantum foundationsReferences edit Murray Gell Mann Quantum Mechanics Interpretations Feynman Sum over Histories EPR Bertlemann s https www youtube com watch v f OFP5tNtMY Richard P Feynman Quantum Mechanical View of Reality 1 Part 1 https www youtube com watch v 72us6pnbEvE Schlosshauer Maximilian Kofler Johannes Zeilinger Anton 2013 08 01 A snapshot of foundational attitudes toward quantum mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 3 222 230 arXiv 1301 1069 Bibcode 2013SHPMP 44 222S doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2013 04 004 ISSN 1355 2198 S2CID 55537196 a b c d Jammer Max 1974 Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics The interpretations of quantum mechanics in historical perspective Wiley Interscience ISBN 9780471439585 Camilleri Kristian 2009 02 01 Constructing the Myth of the Copenhagen Interpretation Perspectives on Science 17 1 26 57 doi 10 1162 posc 2009 17 1 26 ISSN 1530 9274 S2CID 57559199 Vaidman Lev 2021 Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2021 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2023 08 25 Frank J Tipler 1994 The Physics of Immortality Modern Cosmology God and the Resurrection of the Dead Anchor Books ISBN 978 0 385 46799 5 Mermin N David 2012 07 01 Commentary Quantum mechanics Fixing the shifty split Physics Today 65 7 8 10 Bibcode 2012PhT 65g 8M doi 10 1063 PT 3 1618 ISSN 0031 9228 a b Schlosshauer Maximilian Kofler Johannes Zeilinger Anton 2013 01 06 A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 3 222 230 arXiv 1301 1069 Bibcode 2013SHPMP 44 222S doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2013 04 004 S2CID 55537196 Barnum Howard Wehner Stephanie Wilce Alexander August 2018 Introduction Quantum Information Theory and Quantum Foundations Foundations of Physics 48 8 853 856 Bibcode 2018FoPh 48 853B doi 10 1007 s10701 018 0188 6 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 126293060 DiVincenzo David P Fuchs Christopher A 2019 02 01 Quantum foundations Physics Today 72 2 50 51 Bibcode 2019PhT 72b 50D doi 10 1063 PT 3 4141 ISSN 0031 9228 S2CID 241052502 For a discussion of the provenance of the phrase shut up and calculate see Mermin N David 2004 Could Feynman have said this Physics Today 57 5 10 11 Bibcode 2004PhT 57e 10M doi 10 1063 1 1768652 Bacciagaluppi Guido 2012 The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2012 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2023 08 25 La nouvelle cuisine by John S Bell last article of Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics second edition Siddiqui Shabnam Singh Chandralekha 2017 How diverse are physics instructors attitudes and approaches to teaching undergraduate level quantum mechanics European Journal of Physics 38 3 035703 Bibcode 2017EJPh 38c5703S doi 10 1088 1361 6404 aa6131 Bell John S 1987 Speakable and Unspeakable in quantum Mechanics Cambridge Cambridge University Press Faye Jan 2019 Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Camilleri K Schlosshauer M 2015 Niels Bohr as Philosopher of Experiment Does Decoherence Theory Challenge Bohr s Doctrine of Classical Concepts Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 49 73 83 arXiv 1502 06547 Bibcode 2015SHPMP 49 73C doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 01 005 S2CID 27697360 Pauli Wolfgang 1994 1958 Albert Einstein and the development of physics In Enz C P von Meyenn K eds Writings on Physics and Philosophy Berlin Springer Verlag Bibcode 1994wpp book P John Bell 1990 Against measurement Physics World 3 8 33 41 doi 10 1088 2058 7058 3 8 26 Niels Bohr 1985 May 16 1947 Jorgen Kalckar ed Niels Bohr Collected Works vol 6 Foundations of Quantum Physics I 1926 1932 pp 451 454 Stenholm Stig 1983 To fathom space and time in Meystre Pierre ed Quantum Optics Experimental Gravitation and Measurement Theory Plenum Press p 121 The role of irreversibility in the theory of measurement has been emphasized by many Only this way can a permanent record be obtained The fact that separate pointer positions must be of the asymptotic nature usually associated with irreversibility has been utilized in the measurement theory of Daneri Loinger and Prosperi 1962 It has been accepted as a formal representation of Bohr s ideas by Rosenfeld 1966 Haake Fritz April 1 1993 Classical motion of meter variables in the quantum theory of measurement Physical Review A 47 4 2506 2517 Bibcode 1993PhRvA 47 2506H doi 10 1103 PhysRevA 47 2506 PMID 9909217 Omnes R 1994 The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 03669 4 OCLC 439453957 Beller Mara December 1983 Matrix Theory before Schrodinger Philosophy Problems Consequences Isis 74 4 469 491 doi 10 1086 353357 JSTOR 232208 S2CID 121780437 In the beginning was the bit New Scientist 2001 02 17 Retrieved 2022 01 18 Janas M Cuffaro M E Janssen M 2022 Understanding Quantum Raffles SpringerLink Kate Becker 2013 01 25 Quantum physics has been rankling scientists for decades Boulder Daily Camera Retrieved 2013 01 25 a b Let us call the thought that information might be the basic category from which all else flows informational immaterialism Information Immaterialism Instrumentalism Old and New in Quantum Information Christopher G Timpson Physics concerns what we can say about nature Niels Bohr quoted in Petersen A 1963 The philosophy of Niels Bohr Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists 19 7 8 14 Hartle J B 1968 Quantum mechanics of individual systems Am J Phys 36 8 704 712 arXiv 1907 02953 Bibcode 1968AmJPh 36 704H doi 10 1119 1 1975096 S2CID 123454773 Relational Quantum Mechanics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Plato stanford edu Retrieved 2011 01 24 For more information see Carlo Rovelli 1996 Relational Quantum Mechanics International Journal of Theoretical Physics 35 8 1637 1678 arXiv quant ph 9609002 Bibcode 1996IJTP 35 1637R doi 10 1007 BF02302261 S2CID 16325959 Timpson Christopher Gordon 2008 Quantum Bayesianism A study postscript Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 3 579 609 arXiv 0804 2047 Bibcode 2008SHPMP 39 579T doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2008 03 006 S2CID 16775153 Mermin N David 2012 07 01 Commentary Quantum mechanics Fixing the shifty split Physics Today 65 7 8 10 Bibcode 2012PhT 65g 8M doi 10 1063 PT 3 1618 ISSN 0031 9228 Bub Jeffrey 2016 Bananaworld Quantum Mechanics for Primates Oxford Oxford University Press p 232 ISBN 978 0198718536 Ladyman James Ross Don Spurrett David Collier John 2007 Every Thing Must Go Metaphysics Naturalized Oxford Oxford University Press pp 184 ISBN 9780199573097 For participatory realism see e g Fuchs Christopher A 2017 On Participatory Realism In Durham Ian T Rickles Dean eds Information and Interaction Eddington Wheeler and the Limits of Knowledge arXiv 1601 04360 Bibcode 2016arXiv160104360F ISBN 9783319437606 OCLC 967844832 Fuchs Christopher A Timpson Christopher G Does Participatory Realism Make Sense The Role of Observership in Quantum Theory FQXi Foundational Questions Institute Retrieved 2017 04 18 Cabello Adan 2017 Interpretations of quantum theory A map of madness In Lombardi Olimpia Fortin Sebastian Holik Federico Lopez Cristian eds What is Quantum Information Cambridge University Press pp 138 143 arXiv 1509 04711 Bibcode 2015arXiv150904711C doi 10 1017 9781316494233 009 ISBN 9781107142114 S2CID 118419619 Maudlin T 1995 Why Bohm s Theory Solves the Measurement Problem Philosophy of Science 62 3 479 483 doi 10 1086 289879 S2CID 122114295 Durr D Zanghi N Goldstein S Nov 14 1995 Bohmian Mechanics as the Foundation of Quantum Mechanics arXiv quant ph 9511016 Also published in Cushing J T Fine Arthur Goldstein S 17 April 2013 Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory An Appraisal Springer Science amp Business Media pp 21 43 ISBN 978 94 015 8715 0 Quantum Nocality Cramer Npl washington edu Archived from the original on 2010 12 29 Retrieved 2011 01 24 von Neumann John 1932 1955 Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press Translated by Robert T Beyer Esfeld Michael 1999 Essay Review Wigner s View of Physical Reality Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 30B 145 154 Schreiber Zvi 1995 The Nine Lives of Schrodinger s Cat arXiv quant ph 9501014 Lombardi Olimpia Dieks Dennis 2002 11 12 Modal Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Science uva nl Retrieved 2011 01 24 Bitbol Michel 1996 Schrodinger s Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics Dordrecht Springer Netherlands ISBN 978 94 009 1772 9 OCLC 851376153 Schottky Walter 1921 Das Kausalproblem der Quantentheorie als eine Grundfrage der modernen Naturforschung uberhaupt Naturwissenschaften 9 25 492 496 Bibcode 1921NW 9 492S doi 10 1007 BF01494985 S2CID 22228793 Schottky Walter 1921 Das Kausalproblem der Quantentheorie als eine Grundfrage der modernen Naturforschung uberhaupt Naturwissenschaften 9 26 506 511 Bibcode 1921NW 9 506S doi 10 1007 BF01496025 S2CID 26246226 Watanabe Satosi 1955 Symmetry of physical laws Part III Prediction and retrodiction Reviews of Modern Physics 27 2 179 186 Bibcode 1955RvMP 27 179W doi 10 1103 revmodphys 27 179 hdl 10945 47584 S2CID 122168419 Aharonov Y et al 1964 Time Symmetry in the Quantum Process of Measurement Physical Review 134 6B B1410 1416 Bibcode 1964PhRv 134 1410A doi 10 1103 physrev 134 b1410 Aharonov Y and Vaidman L On the Two State Vector Reformulation of Quantum Mechanics Physica Scripta Volume T76 pp 85 92 1998 Wharton K B 2007 Time Symmetric Quantum Mechanics Foundations of Physics 37 1 159 168 Bibcode 2007FoPh 37 159W doi 10 1007 s10701 006 9089 1 S2CID 123086913 Wharton K B 2010 A Novel Interpretation of the Klein Gordon Equation Foundations of Physics 40 3 313 332 arXiv 0706 4075 Bibcode 2010FoPh 40 313W doi 10 1007 s10701 009 9398 2 S2CID 121170138 Heaney M B 2013 A Symmetrical Interpretation of the Klein Gordon Equation Foundations of Physics 43 6 733 746 arXiv 1211 4645 Bibcode 2013FoPh 43 733H doi 10 1007 s10701 013 9713 9 S2CID 118770571 Yakir Aharonov Lev Vaidman The Two State Vector Formalism of Quantum Mechanics an Updated Review In Juan Gonzalo Muga Rafael Sala Mayato Inigo Egusquiza eds Time in Quantum Mechanics Volume 1 Lecture Notes in Physics 734 pp 399 447 2nd ed Springer 2008 ISBN 978 3 540 73472 7 doi 10 1007 978 3 540 73473 4 13 arXiv quant ph 0105101 p 443 Frigg Roman GRW Theory Ghirardi Rimini Weber Model of Quantum Mechanics PDF In Greenberger Daniel Hentschel Klaus Weinert Friedel eds Compendium of Quantum Physics Springer pp 266 270 doi 10 1007 978 3 540 70626 7 81 Archived from the original PDF on 2016 06 24 Retrieved 2011 01 24 Olimpia Lombardi Fortin Sebastian Federico Holik Cristian Lopez 2017 Interpretations of Quantum Theory A Map of Madness What is quantum information pp 138 144 arXiv 1509 04711 doi 10 1017 9781316494233 009 ISBN 9781107142114 OCLC 965759965 S2CID 118419619 John L Heilbron 1988 The Earliest Missionaries of the Copenhagen Spirit in E Ullmann Margalit ed Science in Reflection pp 201 233 This resolution of EPR which Rosen later characterized as a stipulation that physical reality is whatever quantum mechanics is capable of describing was applauded for its clarity by Bohr s close associates Heisenberg Klein and Kramers particularly liked the reduction of the EPR thought experiment to the familiar problem of the diaphragm with holes Perhaps the most interesting responses came from Bohr s old friend the physicist C W Oseen and from his new ally the physicist philosopher Philipp Frank Oseen had understood at last what he now recognized that Bohr had been saying all along before a measurement an atom s state with respect to the quantity measured is undefined Frank saw that Bohr had indeed transfixed EPR on an essential ambiguity What Frank liked most was the implication that physicists should avoid the term and concept of physical reality He understood Bohr to mean that complementarity characterized measuring procedures not the things measured Bohr acknowledged that that was indeed what he had had in mind Henrik Zinkernagel 2016 Niels Bohr on the wave function and the classical quantum divide Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 53 9 19 arXiv 1603 00353 Bibcode 2016SHPMP 53 9Z doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2015 11 001 S2CID 18890207 For a start discussions of the Copenhagen interpretation in the literature are ambiguous between two different views of the wave function both of which of course accept the Born interpretation Sometimes the Copenhagen and Bohr s interpretation is associated with the epistemic view of the quantum state according to which the quantum state is but a representation of our knowledge of the physical system and thus not a real existing entity in itself On this view the collapse of the wave function is not a physical process and it just reflects an update of our information about the system see e g Zeilinger 1999 By contrast the Copenhagen interpretation has also been associated with an ontological view of the quantum state in which the wave function somehow describes a real wave and the collapse is a real physical process presumably induced by the observer This ontological view is usually attributed to von Neumann in his 1932 textbook exposition of quantum mechanics see e g Henderson 2010 Thus for Bohr the wave function is a representation of a quantum system in a particular classically described experimental context Three important points need to be made regarding this contextuality 1 When a measurement is performed that is when an irreversible recording has been made see below then the context changes and hence the wave function changes This can formally be seen as a collapse of the wave function with the square quotes indicating that we are not talking about a physical process in which a real wave collapses W Heisenberg 1955 The Development of the Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in W Pauli ed Essays dedicated to Niels Bohr on the occasion of his seventieth birthday Pergamon Press Of course it is entirely justified to imagine this transition from the possible to the actual moved to an earlier point of time for the observer himself does not produce the transition but it cannot be moved back to a time when the compound system was still separate from the external world because such an assumption would not be compatible with the validity of quantum mechanics for the closed system We see from this that a system cut off from the external world is potential but not actual in character or as BOHR has often expressed it that the system cannot be described in terms of the classical concepts We may say that the state of the closed system represented by a Hilbert vector is indeed objective but not real and that the classical idea of objectively real things must here to this extent be abandoned Niels Bohr 1958 Quantum Physics and Philosophy Causality and Complementarity Essays 1958 1962 on Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge p 3 The description of atomic phenomena has in these respects a perfectly objective character in the sense that no explicit reference is made to any individual observer and that therefore with proper regard to relativistic exigencies no ambiguity is involved in the communication of information Elitzur Avshalom C Cohen Eliahu Okamoto Ryo Takeuchi Shigeki 2018 Nonlocal Position Changes of a Photon Revealed by Quantum Routers Scientific Reports 8 1 7730 arXiv 1707 09483 Bibcode 2018NatSR 8 7730E doi 10 1038 s41598 018 26018 y PMC 5955892 PMID 29769645 Martin Dussaud P Rovelli C Zalamea F 2019 The Notion of Locality in Relational Quantum Mechanics Foundations of Physics 49 2 96 106 arXiv 1806 08150 Bibcode 2019FoPh 49 96M doi 10 1007 s10701 019 00234 6 S2CID 50796079 Smerlak Matteo Rovelli Carlo 2007 03 01 Relational EPR Foundations of Physics 37 3 427 445 arXiv quant ph 0604064 Bibcode 2007FoPh 37 427S doi 10 1007 s10701 007 9105 0 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 11816650 Pienaar Jacques 2019 Comment on The Notion of Locality in Relational Quantum Mechanics Foundations of Physics 49 12 1404 1414 arXiv 1807 06457 Bibcode 2019FoPh 49 1404P doi 10 1007 s10701 019 00303 w S2CID 119473777 P A M Dirac The inadequacies of quantum field theory in Paul Adrien Maurice Dirac B N Kursunoglu and E P Wigner Eds Cambridge University Cambridge 1987 p 194 Duarte F J 2014 Quantum Optics for Engineers New York CRC ISBN 978 1439888537 Zeh H D July 2011 Feynman s interpretation of quantum theory The European Physical Journal H 36 1 63 74 arXiv 0804 3348 doi 10 1140 epjh e2011 10035 2 ISSN 2102 6459 van Kampen N G 2008 The scandal of quantum mechanics American Journal of Physics 76 989 Lamb W E 2001 Super classical quantum mechanics the best interpretation of nonrelativistic quantum mechanics American Journal of Physics 69 413 421 Sources editBub J Clifton R 1996 A uniqueness theorem for interpretations of quantum mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 27B 181 219 doi 10 1016 1355 2198 95 00019 4 Rudolf Carnap 1939 The interpretation of physics in Foundations of Logic and Mathematics of the International Encyclopedia of Unified Science Chicago Illinois University of Chicago Press Dickson M 1994 Wavefunction tails in the modal interpretation in Hull D Forbes M and Burian R eds Proceedings of the PSA 1 366 376 East Lansing Michigan Philosophy of Science Association and Clifton R 1998 Lorentz invariance in modal interpretations in Dieks D and Vermaas P eds The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Dordrecht Kluwer Academic Publishers 9 48 Fuchs Christopher 2002 Quantum Mechanics as Quantum Information and only a little more arXiv quant ph 0205039 and A Peres 2000 Quantum theory needs no interpretation Physics Today Herbert N 1985 Quantum Reality Beyond the New Physics New York Doubleday ISBN 0 385 23569 0 Hey Anthony and Walters P 2003 The New Quantum Universe 2nd ed Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 56457 3 Jackiw Roman Kleppner D 2000 One Hundred Years of Quantum Physics Science 289 5481 893 898 arXiv quant ph 0008092 Bibcode 2000quant ph 8092K doi 10 1126 science 289 5481 893 PMID 17839156 S2CID 6604344 Max Jammer 1966 The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics McGraw Hill 1974 The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics Wiley amp Sons Al Khalili 2003 Quantum A Guide for the Perplexed London Weidenfeld amp Nicolson de Muynck W M 2002 Foundations of quantum mechanics an empiricist approach Dordrecht Kluwer Academic Publishers ISBN 1 4020 0932 1 Roland Omnes 1999 Understanding Quantum Mechanics Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press Karl Popper 1963 Conjectures and Refutations London Routledge and Kegan Paul The chapter Three views Concerning Human Knowledge addresses among other things instrumentalism in the physical sciences Hans Reichenbach 1944 Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics University of California Press Tegmark Max Wheeler J A 2001 100 Years of Quantum Mysteries Scientific American 284 2 68 75 Bibcode 2001SciAm 284b 68T doi 10 1038 scientificamerican0201 68 S2CID 119375538 Bas van Fraassen 1972 A formal approach to the philosophy of science in R Colodny ed Paradigms and Paradoxes The Philosophical Challenge of the Quantum Domain Univ of Pittsburgh Press 303 366 John A Wheeler and Wojciech Hubert Zurek eds Quantum Theory and Measurement Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 08316 9 LoC QC174 125 Q38 1983 Further reading editAlmost all authors below are professional physicists David Z Albert 1992 Quantum Mechanics and Experience Cambridge Massachusetts Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 74112 9 John S Bell 1987 Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 36869 3 The 2004 edition ISBN 0 521 52338 9 includes two additional papers and an introduction by Alain Aspect Dmitrii Ivanovich Blokhintsev 1968 The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics D Reidel Publishing Company ISBN 90 277 0105 9 David Bohm 1980 Wholeness and the Implicate Order London Routledge ISBN 0 7100 0971 2 Adan Cabello 15 November 2004 Bibliographic guide to the foundations of quantum mechanics and quantum information arXiv quant ph 0012089 David Deutsch 1997 The Fabric of Reality London Allen Lane ISBN 0 14 027541 X ISBN 0 7139 9061 9 Argues forcefully against instrumentalism For general readers F J Duarte 2014 Quantum Optics for Engineers New York CRC ISBN 978 1439888537 Provides a pragmatic perspective on interpretations For general readers Bernard d Espagnat 1976 Conceptual Foundation of Quantum Mechanics 2nd ed Addison Wesley ISBN 0 8133 4087 X Bernard d Espagnat 1983 In Search of Reality Springer ISBN 0 387 11399 1 Bernard d Espagnat 2003 Veiled Reality An Analysis of Quantum Mechanical Concepts Westview Press Bernard d Espagnat 2006 On Physics and Philosophy Princetone New Jersey Princeton University Press Arthur Fine 1986 The Shaky Game Einstein Realism and the Quantum Theory Science and its Conceptual Foundations Chicago Illinois University of Chicago Press ISBN 0 226 24948 4 Ghirardi Giancarlo 2004 Sneaking a Look at God s Cards Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press Gregg Jaeger 2009 Entanglement Information and the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Springer ISBN 978 3 540 92127 1 N David Mermin 1990 Boojums all the way through Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 38880 5 Roland Omnes 1994 The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 03669 1 Roland Omnes 1999 Understanding Quantum Mechanics Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press Roland Omnes 1999 Quantum Philosophy Understanding and Interpreting Contemporary Science Princeton New Jersey Princeton University Press Roger Penrose 1989 The Emperor s New Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 851973 7 Especially chapter 6 Roger Penrose 1994 Shadows of the Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 853978 9 Roger Penrose 2004 The Road to Reality New York Alfred A Knopf Argues that quantum theory is incomplete Lee Phillips 2017 A brief history of quantum alternatives Ars Technica Styer Daniel F Balkin Miranda S Becker Kathryn M Burns Matthew R Dudley Christopher E Forth Scott T Gaumer Jeremy S Kramer Mark A et al March 2002 Nine formulations of quantum mechanics PDF American Journal of Physics 70 3 288 297 Bibcode 2002AmJPh 70 288S doi 10 1119 1 1445404 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Interpretations of quantum mechanics nbsp Wikiversity has learning resources about Making sense of quantum mechanics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Bohmian mechanics by Sheldon Goldstein Collapse Theories by Giancarlo Ghirardi Copenhagen Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics by Jan Faye Everett s Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics by Jeffrey Barrett Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics by Lev Vaidman Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics by Michael Dickson and Dennis Dieks Philosophical Issues in Quantum Theory by Wayne Myrvold Quantum Bayesian and Pragmatist Views of Quantum Theory by Richard Healey Quantum Entanglement and Information by Jeffrey Bub Quantum mechanics by Jenann Ismael Quantum Logic and Probability Theory by Alexander Wilce Relational Quantum Mechanics by Federico Laudisa and Carlo Rovelli The Role of Decoherence in Quantum Mechanics by Guido Bacciagaluppi Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics by Peter J Lewis Everettian Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics by Christina Conroy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Interpretations of quantum mechanics amp oldid 1216629093, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.