fbpx
Wikipedia

Precautionary principle

The precautionary principle (or precautionary approach) is a broad epistemological, philosophical and legal approach to innovations with potential for causing harm when extensive scientific knowledge on the matter is lacking. It emphasizes caution, pausing and review before leaping into new innovations that may prove disastrous.[1] Critics argue that it is vague, self-cancelling, unscientific and an obstacle to progress.[2]

In an engineering context, the precautionary principle manifests itself as the factor of safety, discussed in detail in the monograph of Elishakoff.[3] It was apparently suggested, in civil engineering, by Belindor[4] in 1729. Interrelation between safety factor and reliability[5][4][6] is extensively studied by engineers and philosophers.

The principle is often used by policy makers in situations where there is the possibility of harm from making a certain decision (e.g. taking a particular course of action) and conclusive evidence is not yet available. For example, a government may decide to limit or restrict the widespread release of a medicine or new technology until it has been thoroughly tested. The principle acknowledges that while the progress of science and technology has often brought great benefit to humanity, it has also contributed to the creation of new threats and risks. It implies that there is a social responsibility to protect the public from exposure to such harm, when scientific investigation has found a plausible risk. These protections should be relaxed only if further scientific findings emerge that provide sound evidence that no harm will result.

The principle has become an underlying rationale for a large and increasing number of international treaties and declarations in the fields of sustainable development, environmental protection, health, trade, and food safety,[7] although at times it has attracted debate over how to accurately define it and apply it to complex scenarios with multiple risks. In some legal systems, as in law of the European Union, the application of the precautionary principle has been made a statutory requirement in some areas of law.[8]

Origins and theory Edit

The concept "precautionary principle" is generally considered to have arisen in English from a translation of the German term Vorsorgeprinzip in the 1970s in response to forest degradation and sea pollution, where German lawmakers adopted clean air act banning use of certain substances suspected in causing the environmental damage even though evidence of their impact was inconclusive at that time.[9] The concept was introduced into environmental legislation along with other innovative (at that time) mechanisms such as "polluter pays", principle of pollution prevention and responsibility for survival of future ecosystems.[1]

The precautionary principle was promulgated in philosophy by Hans Jonas in his 1979 text, The Imperative of Responsibility, wherein Jonas argued that technology had altered the range of the impact of human action and, as such, ethics must be modified so that the far distant effects of one's actions should now be considered. His maxim is designed to embody the precautionary principle in its prescription that one should "Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life" or, stated conversely, "Do not compromise the conditions for an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth."[10] To achieve this Jonas argued for the cultivation of a cautious, even fearful attitude, toward actions that may endanger the future of humanity or the biosphere that supported it.

In 1988, Konrad von Moltke described the German concept for a British audience, which he translated into English as the precautionary principle.[11]: 31 

In economics, the Precautionary Principle has been analyzed in terms of "the effect on rational decision-making", of "the interaction of irreversibility" and "uncertainty". Authors such as Epstein (1980)[12] and Arrow and Fischer (1974)[13] show that "irreversibility of possible future consequences" creates a "quasi-option effect" which should induce a "risk-neutral" society to favour current decisions that allow for more flexibility in the future. Gollier et al. conclude that "more scientific uncertainty as to the distribution of a future risk – that is, a larger variability of beliefs – should induce society to take stronger prevention measures today."[14]

The principle was also derived from religious beliefs that particular areas of science and technology should be restricted as they "belong to the realm of God", as postulated by Prince Charles and Pope Benedict XVI.[9]

Formulations Edit

Many definitions of the precautionary principle exist: Precaution may be defined as "caution in advance", "caution practiced in the context of uncertainty", or informed prudence. Two ideas lie at the core of the principle:[15]: 34 

  • An expression of a need by decision-makers to anticipate harm before it occurs. Within this element lies an implicit reversal of the onus of proof: under the precautionary principle it is the responsibility of an activity-proponent to establish that the proposed activity will not (or is very unlikely to) result in significant harm.
  • The concept of proportionality of the risk and the cost and feasibility of a proposed action.

One of the primary foundations of the precautionary principle, and globally accepted definitions, results from the work of the Rio Conference, or "Earth Summit" in 1992. Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration notes:[16][1]

In order to protect the environment, the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation.

— Rio Declaration, 1992

In 1998 Wingspread Statement on the Precautionary Principle was convened by the Science and Environmental Health Network and concluded with the following formulation,[17] described by Stewart Brand as "the clearest and most frequently cited":[9]

When an activity raises threats of harm to human health or the environment, precautionary measures should be taken even if some cause and effect relationships are not fully established scientifically. In this context the proponent of an activity, rather than the public, should bear the burden of proof.

In February 2000, the Commission of the European Communities noted in a Communication from the Commission on the Precautionary Principle that, "The precautionary principle is not defined in the Treaties of the European Union, which prescribes it [the Precautionary Principle] only once – to protect the environment. But in practice, its scope is much wider, and specifically where preliminary-objective-scientific-evaluation indicates that there are reasonable grounds for concern that potentially dangerous effects on the environment, human, animal or [and] plant health may be inconsistent with the high level of protection [for what] chosen for the Community."[18]: 10 

The January 2000 Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety says, in regard to controversies over GMOs: "Lack of scientific certainty due to insufficient relevant scientific information ... shall not prevent the Party of [I]mport, in order to avoid or minimize such potential adverse effects, from taking a decision, as appropriate, with regard to the import of the living modified organism in question."[19]: 6 

Application Edit

Various interests being represented by various groups proposing the principle resulted in great variability of its formulation: one study identified 14 different formulations of the principle in treaties and non-treaty declarations.[20] R.B. Stewart (2002)[21] reduced the precautionary principle to four basic versions:

  • Scientific uncertainty should not automatically preclude regulation of activities that pose a potential risk of significant harm (non-preclusion).
  • Regulatory controls should incorporate a margin of safety; activities should be limited below the level at which no adverse effect has been observed or predicted (margin of safety).
  • Activities that present an uncertain potential for significant harm should be subject to best technology available requirements to minimize the risk of harm unless the proponent of the activity shows that they present no appreciable risk of harm (BAT).
  • Activities that present an uncertain potential for significant harm should be prohibited unless the proponent of the activity shows that it presents no appreciable risk of harm (prohibitory).

Carolyn Raffensperger of the Wingspread convention placed the principle in opposition to approaches based on risk management and cost-benefit analysis.[9] Dave Brower (Friends of the Earth) concluded that "all technology should be assumed guilty until proven innocent".[9] Freeman Dyson described the application of precautionary principle as "deliberately one-sided", for example when used as justification to destroy genetic engineering research plantations and threaten researchers in spite of scientific evidence demonstrating lack of harm:[9]

The Precautionary Principle says that if some course of action carries even a remote chance of irreparable damage to the ecology, then you shouldn't do it, no matter how great the possible advantages of the action may be. You are not allowed to balance costs against benefits when deciding what to do.

— Freeman Dyson, Report from 2001 World Economic Forum

As noted by Rupert and O'Riordan, the challenge in application of the principle is "in making it clear that absence of certainty, or there being insufficient evidence-based analysis, were not impediments to innovation, so long as there was no reasonable likelihood of serious harm".[1] Lack of this nuanced application makes the principle "self-cancelling" according to Stewart Brand, because "nothing is fully established" in science, starting from the precautionary principle itself and including "gravity or Darwinian evolution". A balanced application should ensure that "precautionary measures should be" only taken "during early stages" and as "relevant scientific evidence becomes established", regulatory measures should only respond to that evidence.[9]

Strong vs. weak Edit

Strong precaution holds that regulation is required whenever there is a possible risk to health, safety, or the environment, even if the supporting evidence is speculative and even if the economic costs of regulation are high.[22]: 1295–96  In 1982, the United Nations World Charter for Nature gave the first international recognition to the strong version of the principle, suggesting that when "potential adverse effects are not fully understood, the activities should not proceed". The widely publicised Wingspread Declaration, from a meeting of environmentalists in 1998, is another example of the strong version.[23] Strong precaution can also be termed as a "no-regrets" principle, where costs are not considered in preventative action.[24]

Weak precaution holds that lack of scientific evidence does not preclude action if damage would otherwise be serious and irreversible.[25]: 1039  Humans practice weak precaution every day, and often incur costs, to avoid hazards that are far from certain: we do not walk in moderately dangerous areas at night, we exercise, we buy smoke detectors, we buckle our seatbelts.[23]

According to a publication by the New Zealand Treasury Department:

The weak version [of the Precautionary Principle] is the least restrictive and allows preventive measures to be taken in the face of uncertainty, but does not require them (e.g., Rio Declaration 1992; United Nations Framework Convention of Climate Change 1992). To satisfy the threshold of harm, there must be some evidence relating to both the likelihood of occurrence and the severity of consequences. Some, but not all, require consideration of the costs of precautionary measures. Weak formulations do not preclude weighing benefits against the costs. Factors other than scientific uncertainty, including economic considerations, may provide legitimate grounds for postponing action. Under weak formulations, the requirement to justify the need for action (the burden of proof) generally falls on those advocating precautionary action. No mention is made of assignment of liability for environmental harm. Strong versions justify or require precautionary measures and some also establish liability for environmental harm, which is effectively a strong form of "polluter pays". For example, the Earth Charter states: "When knowledge is limited apply a precautionary approach ... Place the burden of proof on those who argue that a proposed activity will not cause significant harm, and make the responsible parties liable for environmental harm." Reversal of proof requires those proposing an activity to prove that the product, process or technology is sufficiently "safe" before approval is granted. Requiring proof of "no environmental harm" before any action proceeds implies the public is not prepared to accept any environmental risk, no matter what economic or social benefits may arise (Peterson, 2006). At the extreme, such a requirement could involve bans and prohibitions on entire classes of potentially threatening activities or substances (Cooney, 2005). Over time, there has been a gradual transformation of the precautionary principle from what appears in the Rio Declaration to a stronger form that arguably [by whom] acts as restraint on development in the absence of firm evidence that it will do no harm.[26]

International agreements and declarations Edit

"Principle" vs. "approach" Edit

No introduction to the precautionary principle would be complete without brief reference to the difference between the precautionary principle and the precautionary approach. Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration 1992 states that: "in order to protect the environment, the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall be not used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent environmental degradation." As Garcia (1995) pointed out, "the wording, largely similar to that of the principle, is subtly different in that: it recognizes that there may be differences in local capabilities to apply the approach, and it calls for cost-effectiveness in applying the approach, e.g., taking economic and social costs into account." The "approach" is generally considered a softening of the "principle":

As Recuerda has noted, the distinction between the precautionary principle and a precautionary approach is diffuse and, in some contexts, controversial. In the negotiations of international declarations, the United States has opposed the use of the term principle because this term has special connotations in legal language, due to the fact that a principle of law is a source of law. This means that it is compulsory, so a court can quash or confirm a decision through the application of the precautionary principle. In this sense, the precautionary principle is not a simple idea or a desideratum but a source of law. This is the legal status of the precautionary principle in the European Union. On the other hand, an 'approach' usually does not have the same meaning, although in some particular cases an approach could be binding. A precautionary approach is a particular "lens" used to identify risk that every prudent person possesses (Recuerda, 2008)[27]

European Union Edit

On 2 February 2000, the European Commission issued a Communication on the precautionary principle,[18] in which it adopted a procedure for the application of this concept, but without giving a detailed definition of it. Paragraph 2 of article 191 of the Lisbon Treaty states that:

Union policy on the environment shall aim at a high level of protection taking into account the diversity of situations in the various regions of the Union. It shall be based on the precautionary principle and on the principles that preventive action should be taken, that environmental damage should as a priority be rectified at source and that the polluter should pay.[28]

After the adoption of the European Commission's communication on the precautionary principle, the principle has come to inform much EU policy, including areas beyond environmental policy. As of 2006 it had been integrated into EU laws "in matters such as general product safety, the use of additives for use in animal nutrition, the incineration of waste, and the regulation of genetically modified organisms".[29]: 282–83  Through its application in case law, it has become a "general principle of EU law".[29]: 283 

In Case T-74/00 Artegodan,[30] the General Court (then Court of First Instance) appeared willing to extrapolate from the limited provision for the precautionary principle in environmental policy in article 191(2) TFEU[31] to a general principle of EU law.[32]

France Edit

In France, the Charter for the Environment contains a formulation of the precautionary principle (article 5):

When the occurrence of any damage, albeit unpredictable in the current state of scientific knowledge, may seriously and irreversibly harm the environment, public authorities shall, with due respect for the principle of precaution and the areas within their jurisdiction, ensure the implementation of procedures for risk assessment and the adoption of temporary measures commensurate with the risk involved in order to preclude the occurrence of such damage.[33]

United States Edit

On 18 July 2005, the City of San Francisco passed a precautionary principle purchasing ordinance,[34] which requires the city to weigh the environmental and health costs of its $600 million in annual purchases – for everything from cleaning supplies to computers. Members of the Bay Area Working Group on the Precautionary Principle contributed to drafting the Ordinance.

Australia Edit

The most important Australian court case so far, due to its exceptionally detailed consideration of the precautionary principle, is Telstra Corporation Limited v Hornsby Shire Council.[35]

The principle was summarised by reference to the NSW Protection of the Environment Administration Act 1991, which itself provides a good definition of the principle:[36]

"If there are threats of serious or irreversible environmental damage, lack of full scientific certainty should not be used as a reasoning for postponing measures to prevent environmental degradation. In the application of the principle... decisions should be guided by: (i) careful evaluation to avoid, wherever practicable, serious or irreversible damage to the environment; and (ii) an assessment of risk-weighted consequence of various options".

The most significant points of Justice Preston's decision are the following findings:[37]

  • The principle and accompanying need to take precautionary measures is "triggered" when two prior conditions exist: a threat of serious or irreversible damage, and scientific uncertainty as to the extent of possible damage.
  • Once both are satisfied, "a proportionate precautionary measure may be taken to avert the anticipated threat of environmental damage, but it should be proportionate."
  • The threat of serious or irreversible damage should invoke consideration of five factors: the scale of threat (local, regional etc.); the perceived value of the threatened environment; whether the possible impacts are manageable; the level of public concern, and whether there is a rational or scientific basis for the concern.
  • The consideration of the level of scientific uncertainty should involve factors which may include: what would constitute sufficient evidence; the level and kind of uncertainty; and the potential to reduce uncertainty.
  • The principle shifts the burden of proof. If the principle applies, the burden shifts: "a decision maker must assume the threat of serious or irreversible environmental damage is... a reality [and] the burden of showing this threat... is negligible reverts to the proponent..."
  • The precautionary principle invokes preventative action: "the principle permits the taking of preventative measures without having to wait until the reality and seriousness of the threat become fully known".
  • "The precautionary principle should not be used to try to avoid all risks."
  • The precautionary measures appropriate will depend on the combined effect of "the degree of seriousness and irreversibility of the threat and the degree of uncertainty... the more significant and uncertain the threat, the greater...the precaution required". "...measures should be adopted... proportionate to the potential threats".

Philippines Edit

A petition filed 17 May 2013 by environmental group Greenpeace Southeast Asia and farmer-scientist coalition Masipag (Magsasaka at Siyentipiko sa Pagpapaunlad ng Agrikultura) asked the appellate court to stop the planting of Bt eggplant in test fields, saying the impacts of such an undertaking to the environment, native crops and human health are still unknown. The Court of Appeals granted the petition, citing the precautionary principle stating "when human activities may lead to threats of serious and irreversible damage to the environment that is scientifically plausible but uncertain, actions shall be taken to avoid or diminish the threat."[38] Respondents filed a motion for reconsideration in June 2013 and on 20 September 2013 the Court of Appeals chose to uphold their May decision saying the bt talong field trials violate the people's constitutional right to a "balanced and healthful ecology."[39][40] The Supreme Court on 8 December 2015 permanently stopped the field testing for Bt (Bacillus thuringiensis) talong (eggplant), upholding the decision of the Court of Appeals which stopped the field trials for the genetically modified eggplant.[41] The court is the first in the world to adopt the precautionary principle regarding GMO products in its decision. The Supreme Court decision was later reversed following an appeal by researchers at the University of the Philippines Los Baños.[42]

Corporate Edit

Body Shop International, a UK-based cosmetics company, included the precautionary principle in their 2006 chemicals strategy.[43]

Environment and health Edit

Fields typically concerned by the precautionary principle are the possibility of:

The precautionary principle is often applied to biological fields because changes cannot be easily contained and have the potential of being global. The principle has less relevance to contained fields such as aeronautics, where the few people undergoing risk have given informed consent (e.g., a test pilot). In the case of technological innovation, containment of impact tends to be more difficult if that technology can self-replicate. Bill Joy emphasised the dangers of replicating genetic technology, nanotechnology, and robotic technology in his article in Wired, "Why the future doesn't need us", though he does not specifically cite the precautionary principle. The application of the principle can be seen in the public policy of requiring pharmaceutical companies to carry out clinical trials to show that new medications are safe.

Oxford based philosopher Nick Bostrom discusses the idea of a future powerful superintelligence, and the risks should it attempt to gain atomic level control of matter.[44]

Application of the principle modifies the status of innovation and risk assessment: it is not the risk that must be avoided or amended, but a potential risk that must be prevented. Thus, in the case of regulation of scientific research, there is a third party beyond the scientist and the regulator: the consumer.

In an analysis concerning application of the precautionary principle to nanotechnology, Chris Phoenix and Mike Treder posit that there are two forms of the principle, which they call the "strict form" and the "active form".[45] The former "requires inaction when action might pose a risk", while the latter means "choosing less risky alternatives when they are available, and [...] taking responsibility for potential risks." Thomas Alured Faunce has argued for stronger application of the precautionary principle by chemical and health technology regulators particularly in relation to Ti02 and ZnO nanoparticles in sunscreens, biocidal nanosilver in waterways and products whose manufacture, handling or recycling exposes humans to the risk of inhaling multi-walled carbon nanotubes.[46]

Resource management Edit

 
The traffic light colour convention, showing the concept of harvest control rules (HCR), specifying when a rebuilding plan is mandatory in terms of precautionary and limit reference points for spawning biomass and fishing mortality rate

Several natural resources like fish stocks are now managed by precautionary approach, through harvest control rules (HCRs) based upon the precautionary principle. The figure indicates how the principle is implemented in the cod fisheries management proposed by the International Council for the Exploration of the Sea.[citation needed]

In classifying endangered species, the precautionary principle means that if there is doubt about an animal's or plant's exact conservation status, the one that would cause the strongest protective measures to be realised should be chosen. Thus, a species like the silvery pigeon that might exist in considerable numbers and simply be under-recorded or might just as probably be long extinct is not classified as "data deficient" or "extinct" (which both do not require any protective action to be taken), but as "critically endangered" (the conservation status that confers the need for the strongest protection), whereas the increasingly rare, but probably not yet endangered emerald starling is classified as "data deficient", because there is urgent need for research to clarify its status rather than for conservation action to save it from extinction.[citation needed]

If, for example, a large ground-water body that people use for drinking water is contaminated by bacteria (e.g. Escherichia coli O157:H7, Campylobacter or Leptospira) and the source of contamination is strongly suspected to be dairy cows but the exact science is not yet able to provide absolute proof, the cows should be removed from the environment until they are proved, by the dairy industry, not to be the source or until that industry ensures that such contamination will not recur.[citation needed]

Animal sentience precautionary principle Edit

Appeals to the precautionary principle have often characterized the debates concerning animal sentience – that is, the question of whether animals are able to feel "subjective experiences with an attractive or aversive quality",[47] such as pain, pleasure, happiness, or joy – in relation to the question of whether we should legally protect sentient animals. A version of the precautionary principle suitable for the problem of animal sentience has been proposed by LSE philosopher Jonathan Birch: "The idea is that when the evidence of sentience is inconclusive, we should 'give the animal the benefit of doubt' or 'err on the side of caution' in formulating animal protection legislation."[47] Since we cannot reach absolute certainty with regards to the fact that some animals are sentient, the precautionary principle has been invoked in order to grant potentially sentient animals "basic legal protections".[47] Birch's formulation of the animal sentience precautionary principle runs as follows:

Where there are threats of serious, negative animal welfare outcomes, lack of full scientific certainty as to the sentience of the animals in question shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective measures to prevent those outcomes.[47]

This version of the precautionary principle consists of an epistemic and a decision rule. The former concerns the "evidential bar" that should be required for animal sentience. In other words, how much evidence of sentience is necessary before one decides to apply precautionary measures? According to Birch, only some evidence would be sufficient, which means that the evidential bar should be set at low levels. Birch proposes to consider the evidence that certain animals are sentient sufficient whenever "statistically significant evidence ... of the presence of at least one credible indicator of sentience in at least one species of that order" has been obtained.[47] For practical reasons, Birch says, the evidence of sentience should concern the order, so that if one species meets the conditions of sentience, then all the species of the same order should be considered sentient and should be thus legally protected. This is due to the fact that, on the one hand, "to investigate sentience separately in different orders" is feasible,[47] whereas on the other hand, since some orders include thousands of species, it would be unfeasible to study their sentience separately.

What is more, the evidential bar should be so low that only one indicator of sentience in the species of a specific order will be sufficient in order for the precautionary principle to be applied. Such indicator should be "an observable phenomenon that experiments can be designed to detect, and it must be credible that the presence of this indicator is explained by sentience".[48] Lists of such criteria already exist for detecting animal pain. The aim is to create analogous lists for other criteria of sentience, such as happiness, fear, or joy. The presence of one of these criteria should be demonstrated by means of experiments which must meet "the normal scientific standards".[47]

Regarding the second part of the animal sentience precautionary principle, the decision rule concerns the requirement that we have to act once there is sufficient evidence of a seriously bad outcome. According to Birch, "we should aim to include within the scope of animal protection legislation all animals for which the evidence of sentience is sufficient, according to the standard of sufficiency outlined [above]".[48] In other words, the decision rule states that once the aforementioned low evidential bar is met, then we should act in a precautionary way.[47] Birch's proposal also "deliberately leaves open the question of how, and to what extent, the treatment of these animals should be regulated", thus also leaving open the content of the regulations, as this will largely depend on the animal in question.[47]

Criticisms Edit

Critics of the principle use arguments similar to those against other formulations of technological conservatism.

Internal inconsistency: applying strong PP risks causing harm Edit

Strong formulations of the precautionary principle, without regard to its most basic provisions (i.e., that it is to be applied only where risks are potentially catastrophic and not easily calculable), when applied to the principle itself as a policy decision, beats its own purpose of reducing risk.[25]: 26ff  The reason suggested is that preventing innovation from coming to market means that only current technology may be used, and current technology itself may cause harm or leave needs unmet; there is a risk of causing harm by blocking innovation.[49][50] As Michael Crichton wrote in his novel State of Fear: "The 'precautionary principle', properly applied, forbids the precautionary principle."[51]

For example, forbidding nuclear power plants based on concerns about low-probability high-impact risks means continuing to rely on power plants that burn fossil fuels, which continue to release greenhouse gases and thousands of certain deaths from air pollution.[25]: 27 

In 2021 in response to early reports about rare blood clots seen in 25 patients out of 20 million vaccinated by Astra-Zeneca COVID-19 vaccine[52] a number of European Union member states suspended the use of the vaccine, quoting the "precautionary principle". This was criticized by other EU states who refused to suspend the vaccination program, declaring that the "precautionary" decisions are focusing on the wrong risk, as delay in a vaccination program results in a larger number of certain deaths than any yet unconfirmed complications.[53]

In another example, the Hazardous Air Pollutant provisions in the 1990 amendments to the US Clean Air Act are an example of the Precautionary Principle where the onus is now on showing a listed compound is harmless. Under this rule no distinction is made between those air pollutants that provide a higher or lower risk, so operators tend to choose less-examined agents that are not on the existing list.[54]

The very basis of the Precautionary Principle is to imagine the worst without supporting evidence... those with the darkest imaginations become the most influential.

Blocking innovation and progress generally Edit

Because applications of strong formulations of the precautionary principle can be used to block innovation, a technology which brings advantages may be banned by precautionary principle because of its potential for negative impacts, leaving the positive benefits unrealised.[55][56]: 201 [57]

The precautionary principle has been ethically questioned on the basis that its application could block progress in developing countries.[58][59]

The precautionary principle presents a serious hazard to our health which extends way beyond the generation of unnecessary neuroses. The biggest correlate of our health and well being is our standard of living, as measured in conventional economic and physical terms. People in technologically advanced societies suffer fewer diseases and live longer than those in less developed nations. The biggest killer in the world is not genetically modified soya, pesticide residues or even tobacco. It is something which is given the code Z59.5 in the International Classification of Disease Handbook and accounts for more deaths world-wide than any other single factor. It is defined as 'Extreme Poverty'.

— Social Issues Research Centre

Vagueness and plausibility Edit

The precautionary principle calls for action in the face of scientific uncertainty, but some formulations do not specify the minimal threshold of plausibility of risk that acts as a "triggering" condition, so that any indication that a proposed product or activity might harm health or the environment is sufficient to invoke the principle.[60][61] In Sancho vs. DOE, Helen Gillmor, Senior District Judge, wrote in a dismissal of Wagner's lawsuit which included a popular[62] worry that the LHC could cause "destruction of the earth" by a black hole:

Injury in fact requires some "credible threat of harm." Cent. Delta Water Agency v. United States, 306 F.3d 938, 950 (9th Cir. 2002). At most, Wagner has alleged that experiments at the Large Hadron Collider (the "Collider") have "potential adverse consequences." Speculative fear of future harm does not constitute an injury in fact sufficient to confer standing. Mayfield, 599 F.3d at 970.[63]

The precautionary dilemma Edit

The most commonly pressed objection to the precautionary principle ties together two of the above objections into the form of a dilemma.[64][55][65] This maintains that, of the two available interpretations of the principle, neither are plausible: weak formulations (which hold that precaution in the face of uncertain harms is permissible) are trivial, while strong formulations (which hold that precaution in the face of uncertain harms is required) are incoherent.[64][65][55] On the first horn of the dilemma Cass Sunstein states:

The weak versions of the Precautionary Principle state a truism—uncontroversial in principle and necessary in practice only to combat public confusion or the self-interested claims of private groups demanding unambiguous evidence of harm, which no rational society requires.[66]: 24 

If all that the (weak) principle states is that it is permissible to act in a precautionary manner where there is a possible risk of harm, then it constitutes a trivial truism and thus fails to be useful.

If we formulate the principle in the stronger sense however, it looks like it rules out all courses of action, including the precautionary measures it is intended to advocate. This is because, if we stipulate that precaution is required in the face of uncertain harms, and precautionary measures also carry a risk of harm, the precautionary principle can both demand and prohibit action at the same time. The risk of a policy resulting in catastrophic harm is always possible. For example: prohibiting genetically modified crops risks significantly reduced food production; placing a moratorium on nuclear power risks an over-reliance on coal that could lead to more air pollution; implementing extreme measures to slow global warming risks impoverishment and bad health outcomes for some people.[64][66][65] The strong version of the precautionary principle, in that "[i]t bans the very steps that it requires",[66]: 26  thus fails to be coherent. As Sunstein states, it is not protective, it is "paralyzing".[66]: 34 

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ a b c d Rupert Read and Tim O'Riordan (2017). "The Precautionary Principle Under Fire" (PDF). Environment: Science and Policy for Sustainable Development. Environment. 59 (September–October 2017): 4–15. doi:10.1080/00139157.2017.1350005. S2CID 158589782.
  2. ^ "The precautionary principle: Definitions, applications and governance – Think Tank". www.europarl.europa.eu. Retrieved 19 March 2020.
  3. ^ Elishakoff, I. Safety factors and reliability: friends or foes?, Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2004
  4. ^ a b de Bélidor, Bernard Forest, La science des ingénieurs, dans la conduite des travaux de fortification et d'architecture civile, Paris: Chez Claude Jombert 1729
  5. ^ Elishakoff, I., Interrelation between safety factors and reliability, NASA/CR-2001-211309, 2001
  6. ^ Doorn, N. and Hansson, S.O., Should probabilistic design replace safety factors?, Philosophy & Technology, 24(2), pp.151-16, 2011
  7. ^ "The Precautionary Principle". United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO). World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology (COMEST). p. 8. Retrieved 2 January 2020.
  8. ^ Art. 191 (2) TFEU, Explanations Relating to the Charter of Fundamental Rights (2007/C 303/02, OJ EU C303/35 14.12.2007 explanation on article 52 (5) of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights, T-13/99 Pfizer vs Council p.114-125
  9. ^ a b c d e f g Brand, Stewart (2010). Whole Earth Discipline. Penguin Books. ISBN 9780143118282.
  10. ^ Jonas, H. (1984). The imperative of responsibility: In search of an ethics for the technological age. University of Chicago press.
  11. ^ Christiansen, Sonja Boehmer (1994). "Chapter 2: The Precautionary Principle in Germany: Enabling Government". In O'Riordan, Tim; Cameron, James (eds.). Interpreting the Precautionary Principle. Earthscan Publications Ltd. ISBN 1134165781 – via Google Books.
  12. ^ Epstein, L.G. (1980). "Decision-making and the temporal resolution of uncertainty". International Economic Review. 21 (2): 269–283. doi:10.2307/2526180. JSTOR 2526180.
  13. ^ Arrow, K.J.; Fischer, A.C. (1974). "Environmental preservation, uncertainty and irreversibility". Quarterly Journal of Economics. 88 (2): 312–9. doi:10.2307/1883074. JSTOR 1883074.
  14. ^ Gollier, Christian; Jullien, Bruno; Treich, Nicolas (2000). "Scientific Progress and Irreversibility: An Economic Interpretation of the 'Precautionary Principle'". Journal of Public Economics. 75 (2): 229–253. doi:10.1016/S0047-2727(99)00052-3.
  15. ^ Andrew Jordan & Timothy O'Riordan. Chapter 3, The precautionary principle: a legal and policy history, in The precautionary principle: protecting public health, the environment and the future of our children. Edited by: Marco Martuzzi and Joel A. Tickner. World Health Organization 2004
  16. ^ UNEP. . Archived from the original on 4 September 2009. Retrieved 29 October 2014.
  17. ^ Staff, Science and Environmental Health Network. 26 January 1998 Wingspread Conference on the Precautionary Principle 2 November 2005 at the Wayback Machine
  18. ^ a b Commission of the European Communities. 2 February 2000 Communication From The Commission on the Precautionary Principle
  19. ^ "Official text of the Cartagena Protocol" (PDF). United Nations. 29 January 2000. Retrieved 12 March 2016.
  20. ^ Foster, Kenneth R.; Vecchia, Paolo; Repacholi, Michael H. (12 May 2000). "Science and the Precautionary Principle". Science. 288 (5468): 979–981. doi:10.1126/science.288.5468.979. ISSN 0036-8075. PMID 10841718. S2CID 153469283.
  21. ^ Stewart, R.B. (2002). "Environmental Regulatory Decision Making Under Uncertainty". Research in Law and Economics. 20: 76.
  22. ^ Sachs, Noah M. (2011). (PDF). University of Illinois Law Review. 2011 (4): 1285–1338. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 October 2011. Retrieved 13 October 2011.
  23. ^ a b Sunstein, Cass R. (2002). "Does the Precautionary Principle point us in any helpful direction ? The Paralyzing Principle" (PDF). Regulation. 25 (9): 32–37. S2CID 18622893.
  24. ^ The No Regrets Principle by Shawn Brodof. Retrieved 6 August 2019.
  25. ^ a b c Mandel, Gregory N.; Gathii, James Thuo (2006). (PDF). University of Illinois Law Review. 2006 (5): 1037–1079. Archived from the original (PDF) on 12 March 2012. Retrieved 13 October 2011.
  26. ^ "Precautionary Principle: Origins, definitions, and interpretations." Treasury Publication, Government of New Zealand. 2006. http://www.treasury.govt.nz/publications/research-policy/ppp/2006/06-06/05.htm
  27. ^ Recuerda, M. A. (2008). "Dangerous interpretations of the precautionary principle and the foundational values of the European Union Food Law: Risk versus Risk". Journal of Food Law & Policy. 4 (1).
  28. ^ Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union article 191, paragraph 2
  29. ^ a b Recuerda, Miguel A. (2006). "Risk and Reason in the European Union Law". European Food and Feed Law Review. 5.
  30. ^ "EUR-Lex - 62000TJ0074 - EN - EUR-Lex". eur-lex.europa.eu.
  31. ^ "EUR-Lex - 12008E191 - EN - EUR-Lex". eur-lex.europa.eu.
  32. ^ Craig, Paul; de Búrca, Gráinne (2015). EU law: text, cases, and materials (sixth ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 112–113. ISBN 978-0-19-871492-7.
  33. ^ Charter for the Environment, Constitutional Council (page visited on 28 August 2016).
  34. ^ Municode 5 December 2008 at the Wayback Machine
  35. ^ [2006] NSWLEC 133 (24 March 2006) [1].
  36. ^ "PROTECTION OF THE ENVIRONMENT ADMINISTRATION ACT 1991 - SECT 6 Objectives of the Authority". austlii.edu.au. Retrieved 3 April 2017.
  37. ^ Hon. Justice Brian J Preston, (2006), 'Telstra Corporation Limited v Hornsby Shire Council [2006] NSWLEC 133', Land and Environment Court of New South Wales. Paragraphs 125-183. https://www.caselaw.nsw.gov.au/decision/549f8a6b3004262463ad5606
  38. ^ (PDF). Manila: Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals. 17 May 2013. Archived from the original (PDF) on 18 January 2016. Retrieved 12 March 2016.
  39. ^ (PDF). Manila: Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals. 17 May 2013. Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 March 2016. Retrieved 12 March 2016 – via ELAW.
  40. ^ (PDF). Manila: Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals. 20 September 2013. Archived from the original (PDF) on 4 March 2016. Retrieved 12 March 2016 – via ELAW.
  41. ^ (Press release). Greenpeace International. 11 December 2015. Archived from the original on 22 December 2015.
  42. ^ "Boost for Bt 'talong'". inquirer.net. July 2016. Retrieved 19 July 2020.
  43. ^ "Chemicals Strategy" (PDF). The Body Shop. August 2006. Retrieved 12 March 2016.
  44. ^ Nick Bostrom 2003 Ethical Issues in Advanced Artificial Intelligence – section 2
  45. ^ "Nanotechnology: Precautionary Principle Analyzed". Center for Responsible Nanotechnology. January 2004. Retrieved 12 March 2016.
  46. ^ Faunce TA, et al. (2008). (PDF). Nanoethics. 2 (3): 231–240. doi:10.1007/s11569-008-0041-z. S2CID 55719697. Archived from the original (PDF) on 28 February 2011.
  47. ^ a b c d e f g h i Birch, Jonathan (2017). "Animal sentience and the precautionary principle" (PDF). Animal Sentience. 16 (1).
  48. ^ a b Birch, Jonathan. "Animal sentience and the precautionary principle". Animal Sentience: 1–16.
  49. ^ Brown, Tracey (9 July 2013)The precautionary principle is a blunt instrument The Guardian, Retrieved 9 August 2013
  50. ^ Sherry Seethaler. Lies, Damned Lies, and Science: How to Sort through the Noise around Global Warming, the Latest Health Claims, and Other Scientific Controversies FT Press, 2009
  51. ^ Merchant, G et al. Impact of the Precautionary Principle on Feeding Current and Future Generations 14 November 2013 at the Wayback Machine CAST Issue Paper 52, June 2013
  52. ^ Miller, Adam (20 March 2021). "Canada monitoring guidance on AstraZeneca-Oxford vaccine amid potential link to blood clots". CBC.
  53. ^ Waterfield, Bruno. "The EU's risk aversion cost thousands of lives". The Times. ISSN 0140-0460. Retrieved 25 March 2021.
  54. ^ Goldstein BD, Carruth RS (2004). "Implications of the Precautionary Principle: is it a threat to science?". International Journal of Occupational Medicine and Environmental Health. 17 (1): 153–61. PMID 15212219.
  55. ^ a b c Sunstein, Cass R. The Paralyzing Principle: Does the Precautionary Principle Point us in any Helpful Direction? 15 February 2007 at the Wayback Machine Regulation, Winter 2002–2003, The Cato Institute.
  56. ^ David Deutsch, The Beginning of Infinity Penguin Books (UK), Viking Press (US), 2011. ISBN 978-0-7139-9274-8
  57. ^ Morris SH, Spillane C (2008). "GM directive deficiencies in the European Union". EMBO Reports. 9 (6): 500–504. doi:10.1038/embor.2008.94. PMC 2427373. PMID 18516083.
  58. ^ Jimenez-Arias, Luis G. (2008). Biothics and the Environment. Libros en Red. p. 73. ISBN 9781597543804.
  59. ^ "Beware the Precautionary Principle". www.sirc.org. Retrieved 16 March 2021.
  60. ^ van den Belt H (July 2003). "Debating the Precautionary Principle: "Guilty until Proven Innocent" or "Innocent until Proven Guilty"?". Plant Physiol. 132 (3): 1122–6. doi:10.1104/pp.103.023531. PMC 526264. PMID 12857792.
  61. ^ Bailey, Ronald. Precautionary Tale 13 March 2008 at the Wayback Machine. Reason. April 1999
  62. ^ Highfield, Roger (5 September 2008). . Telegraph.co.uk. Archived from the original on 1 August 2009. Retrieved 29 October 2014.
  63. ^ . symmetry magazine. Archived from the original on 30 August 2010. Retrieved 29 October 2014.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  64. ^ a b c Steel, Daniel (2013). "The Precautionary Principle and the Dilemma Objection". Ethics, Policy and Environment: A Journal of Philosophy and Geography. 16 (3): 321–340. doi:10.1080/21550085.2013.844570. S2CID 56089605.
  65. ^ a b c Sunstein, Cass (2005). "The Precautionary Principle as a Basis for Decision Making" (PDF). The Economists' Voice. 2 (2): 8. doi:10.2202/1553-3832.1079. S2CID 52241337.
  66. ^ a b c d Sunstein, Cass (2005). Laws of fear. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Further reading Edit

  • Kai Purnhagen, "The Behavioural Law and Economics of the Precautionary Principle in the EU and its Impact on Internal Market Regulation", Wageningen Working Papers in Law and Governance 2013–04, [2]
  • Arrow, K.J.; et al. (1996). "Is There a Role for Cost-Benefit Analysis in Environmental, Health, and Safety Regulation?". Science. 272 (5259): 221–2. doi:10.1126/science.272.5259.221. PMID 8602504. S2CID 167753400.
  • Andorno, Roberto (2004). "The Precautionary Principle: A New Legal Standard for a Technological Age". Journal of International Biotechnology Law. 1: 11–19. doi:10.1515/jibl.2004.1.1.11.
  • Communication from the European Commission on the precautionary principle Brusells (2000)
  • European Union (2002), European Union consolidated versions of the treaty on European Union and of the treaty establishing the European community, Official Journal of the European Union, C325, 24 December 2002, Title XIX, article 174, paragraph 2 and 3.
  • Greenpeace, "Safe trade in the 21st Century, Greenpeace comprehensive proposals and recommendations for the 4th Ministerial Conference of the World Trade Organisation" pp. 8–9
  • Harremoës, Poul; David Gee; Malcolm MacGarvin; Andy Stirling; Jane Keys; Brian Wynne; Sofia Guedes Vaz (October 2002). "The Precautionary Principle in the 20th Century: Late Lessons from Early Warnings — Earthscan, 2002. Review". Nature. 419 (6906): 433. doi:10.1038/419433a. S2CID 4354366.
  • O'Riordan, T. and Cameron, J. (1995), Interpreting the Precautionary Principle, London: Earthscan Publications
  • Raffensperger, C., and Tickner, J. (eds.) (1999) Protecting Public Health and the Environment: Implementing the Precautionary Principle. Island Press, Washington, DC.
  • Rees, Martin. Our Final Hour (2003).
  • Recuerda Girela, M.A., (2006), Seguridad Alimentaria y Nuevos Alimentos, Régimen jurídico-administrativo. Thomson-Aranzadi, Cizur Menor.
  • Recuerda Girela, M.A., (2006), "Risk and Reason in the European Union Law", European Food and Feed Law Review, 5.
  • Ricci PF, Rice D, Ziagos J, Cox LA (April 2003). "Precaution, uncertainty and causation in environmental decisions". Environ Int. 29 (1): 1–19. doi:10.1016/S0160-4120(02)00191-5. PMID 12605931.
  • Sandin, P. "Better Safe than Sorry: Applying Philosophical Methods to the Debate on Risk and the Precautionary Principle," (2004).
  • Stewart, R.B. "Environmental Regulatory Decision making under Uncertainty". In An Introduction to the Law and Economics of Environmental Policy: Issues in Institutional Design, Volume 20: 71–126 (2002).
  • Sunstein, Cass R. (2005), Laws of Fear: Beyond the Precautionary Principle. New York: Cambridge University Press

External links Edit

  • Andorno Roberto (2004). "The Precautionary Principle: A New Legal Standard for a Technological Age". Journal of International Biotechnology Law. 1: 11–19. doi:10.1515/jibl.2004.1.1.11.
  • Report by the UK Interdepartmental Liaison Group on Risk Assessment, 2002. "The Precautionary Principle: Policy and Application" 23 March 2013 at the Wayback Machine
  • David Appell, Scientific American, January 2001: "The New Uncertainty Principle"[dead link]
  • The Times, 27 July 2007, Only a reckless mind could believe in safety first
  • The Times, 15 January 2005, "What is . . . the Precautionary Principle?"
  • Bill Durodié, Spiked, 16 March 2004:
  • European Environment Agency (2001),
  • Applying the Precautionary Principle to Nanotechnology, Center for Responsible Nanotechnology 2004
  • 1998 Wingspread Statement on the Precautionary Principle 2 November 2005 at the Wayback Machine
  • Science and Environmental Health Network, The Precautionary Principle in Action – a Handbook]
  • Gary E. Marchant, Kenneth L. Mossman: Arbitrary and Capricious: The Precautionary Principle in the European Union Courts. American Enterprise Institute Press 2004, ISBN 0-8447-4189-2;
  • Umberto Izzo, La precauzione nella responsabilità civile. Analisi di un concetto sul tema del danno da contagio per via trasfusionale (e-book reprint) [The Idea of Precaution in Tort Law. Analysis of a Concept against the Backdrop of the Tainted- Blood Litigation], UNITN e-prints, 2007, first edition Padua, Cedam 2004.free online PDF
  • Communication from the European Commission on the precautionary principle
  • UK Interdepartmental Liaison Group on Risk Assessment (ILGRA): The Precautionary Principle: Policy and Application
  • Report of UNESCO's group of experts on the Precautionary Principle (2005) [6]
  • Max More (2010), The Perils Of Precaution 6 November 2010 at the Wayback Machine

precautionary, principle, precautionary, principle, precautionary, approach, broad, epistemological, philosophical, legal, approach, innovations, with, potential, causing, harm, when, extensive, scientific, knowledge, matter, lacking, emphasizes, caution, paus. The precautionary principle or precautionary approach is a broad epistemological philosophical and legal approach to innovations with potential for causing harm when extensive scientific knowledge on the matter is lacking It emphasizes caution pausing and review before leaping into new innovations that may prove disastrous 1 Critics argue that it is vague self cancelling unscientific and an obstacle to progress 2 In an engineering context the precautionary principle manifests itself as the factor of safety discussed in detail in the monograph of Elishakoff 3 It was apparently suggested in civil engineering by Belindor 4 in 1729 Interrelation between safety factor and reliability 5 4 6 is extensively studied by engineers and philosophers The principle is often used by policy makers in situations where there is the possibility of harm from making a certain decision e g taking a particular course of action and conclusive evidence is not yet available For example a government may decide to limit or restrict the widespread release of a medicine or new technology until it has been thoroughly tested The principle acknowledges that while the progress of science and technology has often brought great benefit to humanity it has also contributed to the creation of new threats and risks It implies that there is a social responsibility to protect the public from exposure to such harm when scientific investigation has found a plausible risk These protections should be relaxed only if further scientific findings emerge that provide sound evidence that no harm will result The principle has become an underlying rationale for a large and increasing number of international treaties and declarations in the fields of sustainable development environmental protection health trade and food safety 7 although at times it has attracted debate over how to accurately define it and apply it to complex scenarios with multiple risks In some legal systems as in law of the European Union the application of the precautionary principle has been made a statutory requirement in some areas of law 8 Contents 1 Origins and theory 2 Formulations 3 Application 3 1 Strong vs weak 3 2 International agreements and declarations 3 2 1 Principle vs approach 3 2 2 European Union 3 2 3 France 3 2 4 United States 3 2 5 Australia 3 2 6 Philippines 3 2 7 Corporate 3 3 Environment and health 3 4 Resource management 3 5 Animal sentience precautionary principle 4 Criticisms 4 1 Internal inconsistency applying strong PP risks causing harm 4 2 Blocking innovation and progress generally 4 3 Vagueness and plausibility 4 4 The precautionary dilemma 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksOrigins and theory EditThe concept precautionary principle is generally considered to have arisen in English from a translation of the German term Vorsorgeprinzip in the 1970s in response to forest degradation and sea pollution where German lawmakers adopted clean air act banning use of certain substances suspected in causing the environmental damage even though evidence of their impact was inconclusive at that time 9 The concept was introduced into environmental legislation along with other innovative at that time mechanisms such as polluter pays principle of pollution prevention and responsibility for survival of future ecosystems 1 The precautionary principle was promulgated in philosophy by Hans Jonas in his 1979 text The Imperative of Responsibility wherein Jonas argued that technology had altered the range of the impact of human action and as such ethics must be modified so that the far distant effects of one s actions should now be considered His maxim is designed to embody the precautionary principle in its prescription that one should Act so that the effects of your action are compatible with the permanence of genuine human life or stated conversely Do not compromise the conditions for an indefinite continuation of humanity on earth 10 To achieve this Jonas argued for the cultivation of a cautious even fearful attitude toward actions that may endanger the future of humanity or the biosphere that supported it In 1988 Konrad von Moltke described the German concept for a British audience which he translated into English as the precautionary principle 11 31 In economics the Precautionary Principle has been analyzed in terms of the effect on rational decision making of the interaction of irreversibility and uncertainty Authors such as Epstein 1980 12 and Arrow and Fischer 1974 13 show that irreversibility of possible future consequences creates a quasi option effect which should induce a risk neutral society to favour current decisions that allow for more flexibility in the future Gollier et al conclude that more scientific uncertainty as to the distribution of a future risk that is a larger variability of beliefs should induce society to take stronger prevention measures today 14 The principle was also derived from religious beliefs that particular areas of science and technology should be restricted as they belong to the realm of God as postulated by Prince Charles and Pope Benedict XVI 9 Formulations EditMany definitions of the precautionary principle exist Precaution may be defined as caution in advance caution practiced in the context of uncertainty or informed prudence Two ideas lie at the core of the principle 15 34 An expression of a need by decision makers to anticipate harm before it occurs Within this element lies an implicit reversal of the onus of proof under the precautionary principle it is the responsibility of an activity proponent to establish that the proposed activity will not or is very unlikely to result in significant harm The concept of proportionality of the risk and the cost and feasibility of a proposed action One of the primary foundations of the precautionary principle and globally accepted definitions results from the work of the Rio Conference or Earth Summit in 1992 Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration notes 16 1 In order to protect the environment the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost effective measures to prevent environmental degradation Rio Declaration 1992 In 1998 Wingspread Statement on the Precautionary Principle was convened by the Science and Environmental Health Network and concluded with the following formulation 17 described by Stewart Brand as the clearest and most frequently cited 9 When an activity raises threats of harm to human health or the environment precautionary measures should be taken even if some cause and effect relationships are not fully established scientifically In this context the proponent of an activity rather than the public should bear the burden of proof In February 2000 the Commission of the European Communities noted in a Communication from the Commission on the Precautionary Principle that The precautionary principle is not defined in the Treaties of the European Union which prescribes it the Precautionary Principle only once to protect the environment But in practice its scope is much wider and specifically where preliminary objective scientific evaluation indicates that there are reasonable grounds for concern that potentially dangerous effects on the environment human animal or and plant health may be inconsistent with the high level of protection for what chosen for the Community 18 10 The January 2000 Cartagena Protocol on Biosafety says in regard to controversies over GMOs Lack of scientific certainty due to insufficient relevant scientific information shall not prevent the Party of I mport in order to avoid or minimize such potential adverse effects from taking a decision as appropriate with regard to the import of the living modified organism in question 19 6 Application EditVarious interests being represented by various groups proposing the principle resulted in great variability of its formulation one study identified 14 different formulations of the principle in treaties and non treaty declarations 20 R B Stewart 2002 21 reduced the precautionary principle to four basic versions Scientific uncertainty should not automatically preclude regulation of activities that pose a potential risk of significant harm non preclusion Regulatory controls should incorporate a margin of safety activities should be limited below the level at which no adverse effect has been observed or predicted margin of safety Activities that present an uncertain potential for significant harm should be subject to best technology available requirements to minimize the risk of harm unless the proponent of the activity shows that they present no appreciable risk of harm BAT Activities that present an uncertain potential for significant harm should be prohibited unless the proponent of the activity shows that it presents no appreciable risk of harm prohibitory Carolyn Raffensperger of the Wingspread convention placed the principle in opposition to approaches based on risk management and cost benefit analysis 9 Dave Brower Friends of the Earth concluded that all technology should be assumed guilty until proven innocent 9 Freeman Dyson described the application of precautionary principle as deliberately one sided for example when used as justification to destroy genetic engineering research plantations and threaten researchers in spite of scientific evidence demonstrating lack of harm 9 The Precautionary Principle says that if some course of action carries even a remote chance of irreparable damage to the ecology then you shouldn t do it no matter how great the possible advantages of the action may be You are not allowed to balance costs against benefits when deciding what to do Freeman Dyson Report from 2001 World Economic Forum As noted by Rupert and O Riordan the challenge in application of the principle is in making it clear that absence of certainty or there being insufficient evidence based analysis were not impediments to innovation so long as there was no reasonable likelihood of serious harm 1 Lack of this nuanced application makes the principle self cancelling according to Stewart Brand because nothing is fully established in science starting from the precautionary principle itself and including gravity or Darwinian evolution A balanced application should ensure that precautionary measures should be only taken during early stages and as relevant scientific evidence becomes established regulatory measures should only respond to that evidence 9 Strong vs weak Edit Strong precaution holds that regulation is required whenever there is a possible risk to health safety or the environment even if the supporting evidence is speculative and even if the economic costs of regulation are high 22 1295 96 In 1982 the United Nations World Charter for Nature gave the first international recognition to the strong version of the principle suggesting that when potential adverse effects are not fully understood the activities should not proceed The widely publicised Wingspread Declaration from a meeting of environmentalists in 1998 is another example of the strong version 23 Strong precaution can also be termed as a no regrets principle where costs are not considered in preventative action 24 Weak precaution holds that lack of scientific evidence does not preclude action if damage would otherwise be serious and irreversible 25 1039 Humans practice weak precaution every day and often incur costs to avoid hazards that are far from certain we do not walk in moderately dangerous areas at night we exercise we buy smoke detectors we buckle our seatbelts 23 According to a publication by the New Zealand Treasury Department The weak version of the Precautionary Principle is the least restrictive and allows preventive measures to be taken in the face of uncertainty but does not require them e g Rio Declaration 1992 United Nations Framework Convention of Climate Change 1992 To satisfy the threshold of harm there must be some evidence relating to both the likelihood of occurrence and the severity of consequences Some but not all require consideration of the costs of precautionary measures Weak formulations do not preclude weighing benefits against the costs Factors other than scientific uncertainty including economic considerations may provide legitimate grounds for postponing action Under weak formulations the requirement to justify the need for action the burden of proof generally falls on those advocating precautionary action No mention is made of assignment of liability for environmental harm Strong versions justify or require precautionary measures and some also establish liability for environmental harm which is effectively a strong form of polluter pays For example the Earth Charter states When knowledge is limited apply a precautionary approach Place the burden of proof on those who argue that a proposed activity will not cause significant harm and make the responsible parties liable for environmental harm Reversal of proof requires those proposing an activity to prove that the product process or technology is sufficiently safe before approval is granted Requiring proof of no environmental harm before any action proceeds implies the public is not prepared to accept any environmental risk no matter what economic or social benefits may arise Peterson 2006 At the extreme such a requirement could involve bans and prohibitions on entire classes of potentially threatening activities or substances Cooney 2005 Over time there has been a gradual transformation of the precautionary principle from what appears in the Rio Declaration to a stronger form that arguably by whom acts as restraint on development in the absence of firm evidence that it will do no harm 26 International agreements and declarations Edit Principle vs approach Edit No introduction to the precautionary principle would be complete without brief reference to the difference between the precautionary principle and the precautionary approach Principle 15 of the Rio Declaration 1992 states that in order to protect the environment the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage lack of full scientific certainty shall be not used as a reason for postponing cost effective measures to prevent environmental degradation As Garcia 1995 pointed out the wording largely similar to that of the principle is subtly different in that it recognizes that there may be differences in local capabilities to apply the approach and it calls for cost effectiveness in applying the approach e g taking economic and social costs into account The approach is generally considered a softening of the principle As Recuerda has noted the distinction between the precautionary principle and a precautionary approach is diffuse and in some contexts controversial In the negotiations of international declarations the United States has opposed the use of the term principle because this term has special connotations in legal language due to the fact that a principle of law is a source of law This means that it is compulsory so a court can quash or confirm a decision through the application of the precautionary principle In this sense the precautionary principle is not a simple idea or a desideratum but a source of law This is the legal status of the precautionary principle in the European Union On the other hand an approach usually does not have the same meaning although in some particular cases an approach could be binding A precautionary approach is a particular lens used to identify risk that every prudent person possesses Recuerda 2008 27 European Union Edit On 2 February 2000 the European Commission issued a Communication on the precautionary principle 18 in which it adopted a procedure for the application of this concept but without giving a detailed definition of it Paragraph 2 of article 191 of the Lisbon Treaty states that Union policy on the environment shall aim at a high level of protection taking into account the diversity of situations in the various regions of the Union It shall be based on the precautionary principle and on the principles that preventive action should be taken that environmental damage should as a priority be rectified at source and that the polluter should pay 28 After the adoption of the European Commission s communication on the precautionary principle the principle has come to inform much EU policy including areas beyond environmental policy As of 2006 it had been integrated into EU laws in matters such as general product safety the use of additives for use in animal nutrition the incineration of waste and the regulation of genetically modified organisms 29 282 83 Through its application in case law it has become a general principle of EU law 29 283 In Case T 74 00 Artegodan 30 the General Court then Court of First Instance appeared willing to extrapolate from the limited provision for the precautionary principle in environmental policy in article 191 2 TFEU 31 to a general principle of EU law 32 France Edit In France the Charter for the Environment contains a formulation of the precautionary principle article 5 When the occurrence of any damage albeit unpredictable in the current state of scientific knowledge may seriously and irreversibly harm the environment public authorities shall with due respect for the principle of precaution and the areas within their jurisdiction ensure the implementation of procedures for risk assessment and the adoption of temporary measures commensurate with the risk involved in order to preclude the occurrence of such damage 33 United States Edit On 18 July 2005 the City of San Francisco passed a precautionary principle purchasing ordinance 34 which requires the city to weigh the environmental and health costs of its 600 million in annual purchases for everything from cleaning supplies to computers Members of the Bay Area Working Group on the Precautionary Principle contributed to drafting the Ordinance Australia Edit The most important Australian court case so far due to its exceptionally detailed consideration of the precautionary principle is Telstra Corporation Limited v Hornsby Shire Council 35 The principle was summarised by reference to the NSW Protection of the Environment Administration Act 1991 which itself provides a good definition of the principle 36 If there are threats of serious or irreversible environmental damage lack of full scientific certainty should not be used as a reasoning for postponing measures to prevent environmental degradation In the application of the principle decisions should be guided by i careful evaluation to avoid wherever practicable serious or irreversible damage to the environment and ii an assessment of risk weighted consequence of various options The most significant points of Justice Preston s decision are the following findings 37 The principle and accompanying need to take precautionary measures is triggered when two prior conditions exist a threat of serious or irreversible damage and scientific uncertainty as to the extent of possible damage Once both are satisfied a proportionate precautionary measure may be taken to avert the anticipated threat of environmental damage but it should be proportionate The threat of serious or irreversible damage should invoke consideration of five factors the scale of threat local regional etc the perceived value of the threatened environment whether the possible impacts are manageable the level of public concern and whether there is a rational or scientific basis for the concern The consideration of the level of scientific uncertainty should involve factors which may include what would constitute sufficient evidence the level and kind of uncertainty and the potential to reduce uncertainty The principle shifts the burden of proof If the principle applies the burden shifts a decision maker must assume the threat of serious or irreversible environmental damage is a reality and the burden of showing this threat is negligible reverts to the proponent The precautionary principle invokes preventative action the principle permits the taking of preventative measures without having to wait until the reality and seriousness of the threat become fully known The precautionary principle should not be used to try to avoid all risks The precautionary measures appropriate will depend on the combined effect of the degree of seriousness and irreversibility of the threat and the degree of uncertainty the more significant and uncertain the threat the greater the precaution required measures should be adopted proportionate to the potential threats Philippines Edit A petition filed 17 May 2013 by environmental group Greenpeace Southeast Asia and farmer scientist coalition Masipag Magsasaka at Siyentipiko sa Pagpapaunlad ng Agrikultura asked the appellate court to stop the planting of Bt eggplant in test fields saying the impacts of such an undertaking to the environment native crops and human health are still unknown The Court of Appeals granted the petition citing the precautionary principle stating when human activities may lead to threats of serious and irreversible damage to the environment that is scientifically plausible but uncertain actions shall be taken to avoid or diminish the threat 38 Respondents filed a motion for reconsideration in June 2013 and on 20 September 2013 the Court of Appeals chose to uphold their May decision saying the bt talong field trials violate the people s constitutional right to a balanced and healthful ecology 39 40 The Supreme Court on 8 December 2015 permanently stopped the field testing for Bt Bacillus thuringiensis talong eggplant upholding the decision of the Court of Appeals which stopped the field trials for the genetically modified eggplant 41 The court is the first in the world to adopt the precautionary principle regarding GMO products in its decision The Supreme Court decision was later reversed following an appeal by researchers at the University of the Philippines Los Banos 42 Corporate Edit Body Shop International a UK based cosmetics company included the precautionary principle in their 2006 chemicals strategy 43 Environment and health Edit Fields typically concerned by the precautionary principle are the possibility of Global warming or abrupt climate change in general Extinction of species Introduction of new products into the environment with potential impact on biodiversity e g genetically modified organisms Threats to public health due to new diseases and techniques e g HIV transmitted through blood transfusion Long term effects of new technologies e g health concerns regarding radiation from cell phones and other electronics communications devices Persistent or acute pollution e g asbestos endocrine disruptors Food safety e g Creutzfeldt Jakob disease Other new biosafety issues e g artificial life new molecules The precautionary principle is often applied to biological fields because changes cannot be easily contained and have the potential of being global The principle has less relevance to contained fields such as aeronautics where the few people undergoing risk have given informed consent e g a test pilot In the case of technological innovation containment of impact tends to be more difficult if that technology can self replicate Bill Joy emphasised the dangers of replicating genetic technology nanotechnology and robotic technology in his article in Wired Why the future doesn t need us though he does not specifically cite the precautionary principle The application of the principle can be seen in the public policy of requiring pharmaceutical companies to carry out clinical trials to show that new medications are safe Oxford based philosopher Nick Bostrom discusses the idea of a future powerful superintelligence and the risks should it attempt to gain atomic level control of matter 44 Application of the principle modifies the status of innovation and risk assessment it is not the risk that must be avoided or amended but a potential risk that must be prevented Thus in the case of regulation of scientific research there is a third party beyond the scientist and the regulator the consumer In an analysis concerning application of the precautionary principle to nanotechnology Chris Phoenix and Mike Treder posit that there are two forms of the principle which they call the strict form and the active form 45 The former requires inaction when action might pose a risk while the latter means choosing less risky alternatives when they are available and taking responsibility for potential risks Thomas Alured Faunce has argued for stronger application of the precautionary principle by chemical and health technology regulators particularly in relation to Ti02 and ZnO nanoparticles in sunscreens biocidal nanosilver in waterways and products whose manufacture handling or recycling exposes humans to the risk of inhaling multi walled carbon nanotubes 46 Resource management Edit nbsp The traffic light colour convention showing the concept of harvest control rules HCR specifying when a rebuilding plan is mandatory in terms of precautionary and limit reference points for spawning biomass and fishing mortality rateSeveral natural resources like fish stocks are now managed by precautionary approach through harvest control rules HCRs based upon the precautionary principle The figure indicates how the principle is implemented in the cod fisheries management proposed by the International Council for the Exploration of the Sea citation needed In classifying endangered species the precautionary principle means that if there is doubt about an animal s or plant s exact conservation status the one that would cause the strongest protective measures to be realised should be chosen Thus a species like the silvery pigeon that might exist in considerable numbers and simply be under recorded or might just as probably be long extinct is not classified as data deficient or extinct which both do not require any protective action to be taken but as critically endangered the conservation status that confers the need for the strongest protection whereas the increasingly rare but probably not yet endangered emerald starling is classified as data deficient because there is urgent need for research to clarify its status rather than for conservation action to save it from extinction citation needed If for example a large ground water body that people use for drinking water is contaminated by bacteria e g Escherichia coli O157 H7 Campylobacter or Leptospira and the source of contamination is strongly suspected to be dairy cows but the exact science is not yet able to provide absolute proof the cows should be removed from the environment until they are proved by the dairy industry not to be the source or until that industry ensures that such contamination will not recur citation needed Animal sentience precautionary principle Edit See also Ethics of uncertain sentienceAppeals to the precautionary principle have often characterized the debates concerning animal sentience that is the question of whether animals are able to feel subjective experiences with an attractive or aversive quality 47 such as pain pleasure happiness or joy in relation to the question of whether we should legally protect sentient animals A version of the precautionary principle suitable for the problem of animal sentience has been proposed by LSE philosopher Jonathan Birch The idea is that when the evidence of sentience is inconclusive we should give the animal the benefit of doubt or err on the side of caution in formulating animal protection legislation 47 Since we cannot reach absolute certainty with regards to the fact that some animals are sentient the precautionary principle has been invoked in order to grant potentially sentient animals basic legal protections 47 Birch s formulation of the animal sentience precautionary principle runs as follows Where there are threats of serious negative animal welfare outcomes lack of full scientific certainty as to the sentience of the animals in question shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost effective measures to prevent those outcomes 47 This version of the precautionary principle consists of an epistemic and a decision rule The former concerns the evidential bar that should be required for animal sentience In other words how much evidence of sentience is necessary before one decides to apply precautionary measures According to Birch only some evidence would be sufficient which means that the evidential bar should be set at low levels Birch proposes to consider the evidence that certain animals are sentient sufficient whenever statistically significant evidence of the presence of at least one credible indicator of sentience in at least one species of that order has been obtained 47 For practical reasons Birch says the evidence of sentience should concern the order so that if one species meets the conditions of sentience then all the species of the same order should be considered sentient and should be thus legally protected This is due to the fact that on the one hand to investigate sentience separately in different orders is feasible 47 whereas on the other hand since some orders include thousands of species it would be unfeasible to study their sentience separately What is more the evidential bar should be so low that only one indicator of sentience in the species of a specific order will be sufficient in order for the precautionary principle to be applied Such indicator should be an observable phenomenon that experiments can be designed to detect and it must be credible that the presence of this indicator is explained by sentience 48 Lists of such criteria already exist for detecting animal pain The aim is to create analogous lists for other criteria of sentience such as happiness fear or joy The presence of one of these criteria should be demonstrated by means of experiments which must meet the normal scientific standards 47 Regarding the second part of the animal sentience precautionary principle the decision rule concerns the requirement that we have to act once there is sufficient evidence of a seriously bad outcome According to Birch we should aim to include within the scope of animal protection legislation all animals for which the evidence of sentience is sufficient according to the standard of sufficiency outlined above 48 In other words the decision rule states that once the aforementioned low evidential bar is met then we should act in a precautionary way 47 Birch s proposal also deliberately leaves open the question of how and to what extent the treatment of these animals should be regulated thus also leaving open the content of the regulations as this will largely depend on the animal in question 47 Criticisms EditCritics of the principle use arguments similar to those against other formulations of technological conservatism Internal inconsistency applying strong PP risks causing harm Edit Strong formulations of the precautionary principle without regard to its most basic provisions i e that it is to be applied only where risks are potentially catastrophic and not easily calculable when applied to the principle itself as a policy decision beats its own purpose of reducing risk 25 26ff The reason suggested is that preventing innovation from coming to market means that only current technology may be used and current technology itself may cause harm or leave needs unmet there is a risk of causing harm by blocking innovation 49 50 As Michael Crichton wrote in his novel State of Fear The precautionary principle properly applied forbids the precautionary principle 51 For example forbidding nuclear power plants based on concerns about low probability high impact risks means continuing to rely on power plants that burn fossil fuels which continue to release greenhouse gases and thousands of certain deaths from air pollution 25 27 In 2021 in response to early reports about rare blood clots seen in 25 patients out of 20 million vaccinated by Astra Zeneca COVID 19 vaccine 52 a number of European Union member states suspended the use of the vaccine quoting the precautionary principle This was criticized by other EU states who refused to suspend the vaccination program declaring that the precautionary decisions are focusing on the wrong risk as delay in a vaccination program results in a larger number of certain deaths than any yet unconfirmed complications 53 Main article European Commission AstraZeneca COVID 19 vaccine dispute In another example the Hazardous Air Pollutant provisions in the 1990 amendments to the US Clean Air Act are an example of the Precautionary Principle where the onus is now on showing a listed compound is harmless Under this rule no distinction is made between those air pollutants that provide a higher or lower risk so operators tend to choose less examined agents that are not on the existing list 54 The very basis of the Precautionary Principle is to imagine the worst without supporting evidence those with the darkest imaginations become the most influential Adam Curtis The Power of Nightmares Blocking innovation and progress generally Edit See also Fear uncertainty and doubt Because applications of strong formulations of the precautionary principle can be used to block innovation a technology which brings advantages may be banned by precautionary principle because of its potential for negative impacts leaving the positive benefits unrealised 55 56 201 57 The precautionary principle has been ethically questioned on the basis that its application could block progress in developing countries 58 59 The precautionary principle presents a serious hazard to our health which extends way beyond the generation of unnecessary neuroses The biggest correlate of our health and well being is our standard of living as measured in conventional economic and physical terms People in technologically advanced societies suffer fewer diseases and live longer than those in less developed nations The biggest killer in the world is not genetically modified soya pesticide residues or even tobacco It is something which is given the code Z59 5 in the International Classification of Disease Handbook and accounts for more deaths world wide than any other single factor It is defined as Extreme Poverty Social Issues Research Centre Vagueness and plausibility Edit The precautionary principle calls for action in the face of scientific uncertainty but some formulations do not specify the minimal threshold of plausibility of risk that acts as a triggering condition so that any indication that a proposed product or activity might harm health or the environment is sufficient to invoke the principle 60 61 In Sancho vs DOE Helen Gillmor Senior District Judge wrote in a dismissal of Wagner s lawsuit which included a popular 62 worry that the LHC could cause destruction of the earth by a black hole Injury in fact requires some credible threat of harm Cent Delta Water Agency v United States 306 F 3d 938 950 9th Cir 2002 At most Wagner has alleged that experiments at the Large Hadron Collider the Collider have potential adverse consequences Speculative fear of future harm does not constitute an injury in fact sufficient to confer standing Mayfield 599 F 3d at 970 63 The precautionary dilemma EditThe most commonly pressed objection to the precautionary principle ties together two of the above objections into the form of a dilemma 64 55 65 This maintains that of the two available interpretations of the principle neither are plausible weak formulations which hold that precaution in the face of uncertain harms is permissible are trivial while strong formulations which hold that precaution in the face of uncertain harms is required are incoherent 64 65 55 On the first horn of the dilemma Cass Sunstein states The weak versions of the Precautionary Principle state a truism uncontroversial in principle and necessary in practice only to combat public confusion or the self interested claims of private groups demanding unambiguous evidence of harm which no rational society requires 66 24 If all that the weak principle states is that it is permissible to act in a precautionary manner where there is a possible risk of harm then it constitutes a trivial truism and thus fails to be useful If we formulate the principle in the stronger sense however it looks like it rules out all courses of action including the precautionary measures it is intended to advocate This is because if we stipulate that precaution is required in the face of uncertain harms and precautionary measures also carry a risk of harm the precautionary principle can both demand and prohibit action at the same time The risk of a policy resulting in catastrophic harm is always possible For example prohibiting genetically modified crops risks significantly reduced food production placing a moratorium on nuclear power risks an over reliance on coal that could lead to more air pollution implementing extreme measures to slow global warming risks impoverishment and bad health outcomes for some people 64 66 65 The strong version of the precautionary principle in that i t bans the very steps that it requires 66 26 thus fails to be coherent As Sunstein states it is not protective it is paralyzing 66 34 See also EditArgument from ignorance Benefit of the doubt similar concept Best available technology Biosecurity Centre for the Study of Existential Risk Chesterton s fence Complex systems Diffusion of innovations Ecologically sustainable development Environmental law Environmental Principles and Policies Health impact assessment Maximin principle Micromort Possible carcinogen Postcautionary principle Prevention of disasters principle Proactionary principle Risk aversion Safe trade Substitution principle sustainability Superconducting Super Collider Sustainability Tombstone mentality Vaccine controversiesReferences Edit a b c d Rupert Read and Tim O Riordan 2017 The Precautionary Principle Under Fire PDF Environment Science and Policy for Sustainable Development Environment 59 September October 2017 4 15 doi 10 1080 00139157 2017 1350005 S2CID 158589782 The precautionary principle Definitions applications and governance Think Tank www europarl europa eu Retrieved 19 March 2020 Elishakoff I Safety factors and reliability friends or foes Dordrecht Kluwer Academic Publishers 2004 a b de Belidor Bernard Forest La science des ingenieurs dans la conduite des travaux de fortification et d architecture civile Paris Chez Claude Jombert 1729 Elishakoff I Interrelation between safety factors and reliability NASA CR 2001 211309 2001 Doorn N and Hansson S O Should probabilistic design replace safety factors Philosophy amp Technology 24 2 pp 151 16 2011 The Precautionary Principle United Nations Educational Scientific and Cultural Organization UNESCO World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology COMEST p 8 Retrieved 2 January 2020 Art 191 2 TFEU Explanations Relating to the Charter of Fundamental Rights 2007 C 303 02 OJ EU C303 35 14 12 2007 explanation on article 52 5 of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights T 13 99 Pfizer vs Council p 114 125 a b c d e f g Brand Stewart 2010 Whole Earth Discipline Penguin Books ISBN 9780143118282 Jonas H 1984 The imperative of responsibility In search of an ethics for the technological age University of Chicago press Christiansen Sonja Boehmer 1994 Chapter 2 The Precautionary Principle in Germany Enabling Government In O Riordan Tim Cameron James eds Interpreting the Precautionary Principle Earthscan Publications Ltd ISBN 1134165781 via Google Books Epstein L G 1980 Decision making and the temporal resolution of uncertainty International Economic Review 21 2 269 283 doi 10 2307 2526180 JSTOR 2526180 Arrow K J Fischer A C 1974 Environmental preservation uncertainty and irreversibility Quarterly Journal of Economics 88 2 312 9 doi 10 2307 1883074 JSTOR 1883074 Gollier Christian Jullien Bruno Treich Nicolas 2000 Scientific Progress and Irreversibility An Economic Interpretation of the Precautionary Principle Journal of Public Economics 75 2 229 253 doi 10 1016 S0047 2727 99 00052 3 Andrew Jordan amp Timothy O Riordan Chapter 3 The precautionary principle a legal and policy history in The precautionary principle protecting public health the environment and the future of our children Edited by Marco Martuzzi and Joel A Tickner World Health Organization 2004 UNEP Rio Declaration on Environment and Development Archived from the original on 4 September 2009 Retrieved 29 October 2014 Staff Science and Environmental Health Network 26 January 1998 Wingspread Conference on the Precautionary Principle Archived 2 November 2005 at the Wayback Machine a b Commission of the European Communities 2 February 2000 Communication From The Commission on the Precautionary Principle Official text of the Cartagena Protocol PDF United Nations 29 January 2000 Retrieved 12 March 2016 Foster Kenneth R Vecchia Paolo Repacholi Michael H 12 May 2000 Science and the Precautionary Principle Science 288 5468 979 981 doi 10 1126 science 288 5468 979 ISSN 0036 8075 PMID 10841718 S2CID 153469283 Stewart R B 2002 Environmental Regulatory Decision Making Under Uncertainty Research in Law and Economics 20 76 Sachs Noah M 2011 Rescuing the Strong Precautionary Principle from its Critics PDF University of Illinois Law Review 2011 4 1285 1338 Archived from the original PDF on 28 October 2011 Retrieved 13 October 2011 a b Sunstein Cass R 2002 Does the Precautionary Principle point us in any helpful direction The Paralyzing Principle PDF Regulation 25 9 32 37 S2CID 18622893 The No Regrets Principle by Shawn Brodof Retrieved 6 August 2019 a b c Mandel Gregory N Gathii James Thuo 2006 Cost Benefit Analysis Versus the Precautionary Principle Beyond Cass Sunstein s Laws of Fear PDF University of Illinois Law Review 2006 5 1037 1079 Archived from the original PDF on 12 March 2012 Retrieved 13 October 2011 Precautionary Principle Origins definitions and interpretations Treasury Publication Government of New Zealand 2006 http www treasury govt nz publications research policy ppp 2006 06 06 05 htm Recuerda M A 2008 Dangerous interpretations of the precautionary principle and the foundational values of the European Union Food Law Risk versus Risk Journal of Food Law amp Policy 4 1 Consolidated Version of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union article 191 paragraph 2 a b Recuerda Miguel A 2006 Risk and Reason in the European Union Law European Food and Feed Law Review 5 EUR Lex 62000TJ0074 EN EUR Lex eur lex europa eu EUR Lex 12008E191 EN EUR Lex eur lex europa eu Craig Paul de Burca Grainne 2015 EU law text cases and materials sixth ed Oxford University Press pp 112 113 ISBN 978 0 19 871492 7 Charter for the Environment Constitutional Council page visited on 28 August 2016 Municode Archived 5 December 2008 at the Wayback Machine 2006 NSWLEC 133 24 March 2006 1 PROTECTION OF THE ENVIRONMENT ADMINISTRATION ACT 1991 SECT 6 Objectives of the Authority austlii edu au Retrieved 3 April 2017 Hon Justice Brian J Preston 2006 Telstra Corporation Limited v Hornsby Shire Council 2006 NSWLEC 133 Land and Environment Court of New South Wales Paragraphs 125 183 https www caselaw nsw gov au decision 549f8a6b3004262463ad5606 Greenpeace Southeast Asia Philippines et al vs Environmental Management Bureau of the Department of Environment and Natural Resources et al PDF Manila Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals 17 May 2013 Archived from the original PDF on 18 January 2016 Retrieved 12 March 2016 Greenpeace Southeast Asia Philippines et al vs Environment Management Bureau of the Department of Environment and Natural Resources et al PDF Manila Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals 17 May 2013 Archived from the original PDF on 4 March 2016 Retrieved 12 March 2016 via ELAW Greenpeace Southeast Asia Philippines et al vs Environment Management Bureau of the Department of Environment and Natural Resources et al PDF Manila Republic of the Philippines Court of Appeals 20 September 2013 Archived from the original PDF on 4 March 2016 Retrieved 12 March 2016 via ELAW Philippines Supreme Court bans development of genetically engineered products Press release Greenpeace International 11 December 2015 Archived from the original on 22 December 2015 Boost for Bt talong inquirer net July 2016 Retrieved 19 July 2020 Chemicals Strategy PDF The Body Shop August 2006 Retrieved 12 March 2016 Nick Bostrom 2003 Ethical Issues in Advanced Artificial Intelligence section 2 Nanotechnology Precautionary Principle Analyzed Center for Responsible Nanotechnology January 2004 Retrieved 12 March 2016 Faunce TA et al 2008 Sunscreen Safety The Precautionary Principle The Australian Therapeutic Goods Administration and Nanoparticles in Sunscreens PDF Nanoethics 2 3 231 240 doi 10 1007 s11569 008 0041 z S2CID 55719697 Archived from the original PDF on 28 February 2011 a b c d e f g h i Birch Jonathan 2017 Animal sentience and the precautionary principle PDF Animal Sentience 16 1 a b Birch Jonathan Animal sentience and the precautionary principle Animal Sentience 1 16 Brown Tracey 9 July 2013 The precautionary principle is a blunt instrument The Guardian Retrieved 9 August 2013 Sherry Seethaler Lies Damned Lies and Science How to Sort through the Noise around Global Warming the Latest Health Claims and Other Scientific Controversies FT Press 2009 Merchant G et al Impact of the Precautionary Principle on Feeding Current and Future Generations Archived 14 November 2013 at the Wayback Machine CAST Issue Paper 52 June 2013 Miller Adam 20 March 2021 Canada monitoring guidance on AstraZeneca Oxford vaccine amid potential link to blood clots CBC Waterfield Bruno The EU s risk aversion cost thousands of lives The Times ISSN 0140 0460 Retrieved 25 March 2021 Goldstein BD Carruth RS 2004 Implications of the Precautionary Principle is it a threat to science International Journal of Occupational Medicine and Environmental Health 17 1 153 61 PMID 15212219 a b c Sunstein Cass R The Paralyzing Principle Does the Precautionary Principle Point us in any Helpful Direction Archived 15 February 2007 at the Wayback Machine Regulation Winter 2002 2003 The Cato Institute David Deutsch The Beginning of Infinity Penguin Books UK Viking Press US 2011 ISBN 978 0 7139 9274 8 Morris SH Spillane C 2008 GM directive deficiencies in the European Union EMBO Reports 9 6 500 504 doi 10 1038 embor 2008 94 PMC 2427373 PMID 18516083 Jimenez Arias Luis G 2008 Biothics and the Environment Libros en Red p 73 ISBN 9781597543804 Beware the Precautionary Principle www sirc org Retrieved 16 March 2021 van den Belt H July 2003 Debating the Precautionary Principle Guilty until Proven Innocent or Innocent until Proven Guilty Plant Physiol 132 3 1122 6 doi 10 1104 pp 103 023531 PMC 526264 PMID 12857792 Bailey Ronald Precautionary Tale Archived 13 March 2008 at the Wayback Machine Reason April 1999 Highfield Roger 5 September 2008 Scientists get death threats over Large Hadron Collider Telegraph co uk Archived from the original on 1 August 2009 Retrieved 29 October 2014 LHC lawsuit dismissed by US court symmetry magazine Archived from the original on 30 August 2010 Retrieved 29 October 2014 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint unfit URL link a b c Steel Daniel 2013 The Precautionary Principle and the Dilemma Objection Ethics Policy and Environment A Journal of Philosophy and Geography 16 3 321 340 doi 10 1080 21550085 2013 844570 S2CID 56089605 a b c Sunstein Cass 2005 The Precautionary Principle as a Basis for Decision Making PDF The Economists Voice 2 2 8 doi 10 2202 1553 3832 1079 S2CID 52241337 a b c d Sunstein Cass 2005 Laws of fear Cambridge Cambridge University Press Further reading EditKai Purnhagen The Behavioural Law and Economics of the Precautionary Principle in the EU and its Impact on Internal Market Regulation Wageningen Working Papers in Law and Governance 2013 04 2 Arrow K J et al 1996 Is There a Role for Cost Benefit Analysis in Environmental Health and Safety Regulation Science 272 5259 221 2 doi 10 1126 science 272 5259 221 PMID 8602504 S2CID 167753400 Andorno Roberto 2004 The Precautionary Principle A New Legal Standard for a Technological Age Journal of International Biotechnology Law 1 11 19 doi 10 1515 jibl 2004 1 1 11 Communication from the European Commission on the precautionary principle Brusells 2000 European Union 2002 European Union consolidated versions of the treaty on European Union and of the treaty establishing the European community Official Journal of the European Union C325 24 December 2002 Title XIX article 174 paragraph 2 and 3 Greenpeace Safe trade in the 21st Century Greenpeace comprehensive proposals and recommendations for the 4th Ministerial Conference of the World Trade Organisation pp 8 9 3 Harremoes Poul David Gee Malcolm MacGarvin Andy Stirling Jane Keys Brian Wynne Sofia Guedes Vaz October 2002 The Precautionary Principle in the 20th Century Late Lessons from Early Warnings Earthscan 2002 Review Nature 419 6906 433 doi 10 1038 419433a S2CID 4354366 O Riordan T and Cameron J 1995 Interpreting the Precautionary Principle London Earthscan Publications Raffensperger C and Tickner J eds 1999 Protecting Public Health and the Environment Implementing the Precautionary Principle Island Press Washington DC Rees Martin Our Final Hour 2003 Recuerda Girela M A 2006 Seguridad Alimentaria y Nuevos Alimentos Regimen juridico administrativo Thomson Aranzadi Cizur Menor Recuerda Girela M A 2006 Risk and Reason in the European Union Law European Food and Feed Law Review 5 Ricci PF Rice D Ziagos J Cox LA April 2003 Precaution uncertainty and causation in environmental decisions Environ Int 29 1 1 19 doi 10 1016 S0160 4120 02 00191 5 PMID 12605931 Sandin P Better Safe than Sorry Applying Philosophical Methods to the Debate on Risk and the Precautionary Principle 2004 Stewart R B Environmental Regulatory Decision making under Uncertainty In An Introduction to the Law and Economics of Environmental Policy Issues in Institutional Design Volume 20 71 126 2002 Sunstein Cass R 2005 Laws of Fear Beyond the Precautionary Principle New York Cambridge University PressExternal links EditAndorno Roberto 2004 The Precautionary Principle A New Legal Standard for a Technological Age Journal of International Biotechnology Law 1 11 19 doi 10 1515 jibl 2004 1 1 11 Report by the UK Interdepartmental Liaison Group on Risk Assessment 2002 The Precautionary Principle Policy and Application Archived 23 March 2013 at the Wayback Machine David Appell Scientific American January 2001 The New Uncertainty Principle dead link The Times 27 July 2007 Only a reckless mind could believe in safety first The Times 15 January 2005 What is the Precautionary Principle Bill Durodie Spiked 16 March 2004 The precautionary principle assumes that prevention is better than cure European Environment Agency 2001 Late lessons from early warnings the precautionary principle 1896 2000 Applying the Precautionary Principle to Nanotechnology Center for Responsible Nanotechnology 2004 1998 Wingspread Statement on the Precautionary Principle Archived 2 November 2005 at the Wayback Machine Science and Environmental Health Network 4 The Precautionary Principle in Action a Handbook Gary E Marchant Kenneth L Mossman Arbitrary and Capricious The Precautionary Principle in the European Union Courts American Enterprise Institute Press 2004 ISBN 0 8447 4189 2 free online PDF Umberto Izzo La precauzione nella responsabilita civile Analisi di un concetto sul tema del danno da contagio per via trasfusionale e book reprint The Idea of Precaution in Tort Law Analysis of a Concept against the Backdrop of the Tainted Blood Litigation UNITN e prints 2007 first edition Padua Cedam 2004 free online PDF Better Safe than Sorry Applying Philosophical Methods to the Debate on Risk and the Precautionary Principle Communication from the European Commission on the precautionary principle UK Interdepartmental Liaison Group on Risk Assessment ILGRA The Precautionary Principle Policy and Application 5 Report of UNESCO s group of experts on the Precautionary Principle 2005 6 Max More 2010 The Perils Of Precaution Archived 6 November 2010 at the Wayback Machine Portals nbsp Environment nbsp Law Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Precautionary principle amp oldid 1179836417, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.