fbpx
Wikipedia

Participatory economics

Participatory economics, often abbreviated Parecon, is an economic system based on participatory decision making as the primary economic mechanism for allocation in society. In the system, the say in decision-making is proportional to the impact on a person or group of people. Participatory economics is a form of a socialist decentralized planned economy involving the collective ownership of the means of production. It is a proposed alternative to contemporary capitalism and centralized planning. This economic model is primarily associated with political theorist Michael Albert and economist Robin Hahnel, who describes participatory economics as an anarchist economic vision.[1]

The underlying values that parecon seeks to implement are: equity, solidarity, diversity, workers' self-management, efficiency (defined as accomplishing goals without wasting valued assets), and sustainability. The institutions of parecon include workers' and consumers' councils utilising self-managerial methods for decision-making, balanced job complexes, remuneration based on individual effort, and wide decentralized planning.

Albert and Hahnel claim that participatory economics has been practiced to varying degrees during the Russian Revolution of 1917, Spanish Revolution of 1936, and occasionally in South America.[2]

Decision-making principle edit

A primary proposition of parecon is that everyone should have a say in decisions proportionate to the degree to which they are affected by them. In their councils, workers would deliberate over plans regarding the productive enterprise and employ whichever voting scheme best instantiates this principle. Generally, a workers' council is not constrained to adopt a single threshold (such as a simple majority) to pass their resolutions, but can tailor their voting procedures to reflect the variation in impact of the enterprise's decisions.

In parecon, self-management constitutes a replacement for the mainstream conception of economic freedom, which Albert and Hahnel argue by its very vagueness has allowed it to be abused by capitalist ideologues.[3]

Work and distribution edit

Balanced job complexes edit

A balanced job complex is a collection of tasks within a given workplace that is balanced for its equity and empowerment implications against all other job complexes in that workplace.[4]

Compensation for effort and sacrifice (principle for distribution) edit

Albert and Hahnel argue that it is inequitable and ineffective to compensate people on the basis of luck (e.g. skills or talents that owe to their birth or heredity), or by virtue of workers' productivity (as measured by the value of the goods they produce). Therefore, the primary principle of participatory economics is to reward workers for their effort and sacrifice.[5] For example, mining work—which is dangerous and uncomfortable—would be more highly paid than office work for the same amount of time, thus allowing the miner to work fewer hours for the same pay, and the burden of highly dangerous and strenuous jobs to be shared among the populace.

Additionally, participatory economics would provide exemptions from the compensation for effort principle.[5] People with disabilities who are unable to work, children, the elderly, the infirm and workers who are legitimately in transitional circumstances, would be remunerated according to need, while all other able-bodied adults would be obliged to perform some socially useful work as a requirement for compensation. However, all individuals would enjoy a baseline of entitlements to free health care, education, skills training, and the freedom to choose between various democratically structured workplaces with balanced jobs balanced for desirability and empowerment.

The starting point for the income of all workers in a participatory economy is an equal share of the social product. From this point, incomes for personal expenditures and consumption rights for public goods can be expected to diverge by small degrees, reflecting the choices that individuals make in between work and leisure time, and the level of danger and difficulty of a job as judged by their immediate workplace peers.[5]

Allocation of resource edit

Participatory planning is the allocation mechanism in a participatory economy, and is meant to provide a workable alternative to market competition and centralized planning. The planning procedure is conceived as an iterative process in which, (1) production proposals made by workers' councils and (2) consumption proposals made by individuals and their neighborhood councils, are submitted and revised through multiple rounds of pricing updates until the process converges on a feasible plan for the upcoming year.

The process begins when the facilitation board (see below) announces a list of indicative prices for each final consumer good, as well as for each capital good, natural resource, and category of labor that is available to society. These indicative prices are calculated to reflect the estimated opportunity costs for producing various goods and services, and incorporate both social costs and pollution impacts. In response to this list of prices, individuals draft an annual consumption plan for goods/services they wish to consume in the coming year, and also meet in their neighborhood councils to deliberate and democratically arrive at a plan for the consumption of public goods (e.g. obtaining resources to build a public playground). As workers, individuals also meet in their workplaces to determine what outputs they will produce and what inputs they will consume in the production process, as well as how much they would each like to work. Thus, workers and consumers (as well as any federations of workers or consumers) submit their initial requests to the facilitation board, which aggregates this information.

Because the conclusion of the first round of this process will almost certainly not be a workable plan, the facilitation board proceeds to update the list of indicative prices for each good up or down, in proportion to the excess demand and supply for each, so that the updated prices reflect a more accurate estimate of the social opportunity costs of each item. The announcement of updated indicative prices then initiates the second round of the planning process, in which consumers and workers revise and resubmit their proposals in light of the new information. In particular, consumption proposals in which the individual's proposed effort rating does not warrant the proposed level of consumption will need to be adjusted, so that the individual will either have to reduce his/her consumption requests, shift them to less costly products, or increase his/her projected work-hours for the coming year. Other consumers may discover that their initial proposals were too modest, and can revise their consumption upwards, if they choose, or they can revise their projected effort rating downwards by proposing to work fewer hours and increasing leisure time.

Production proposals are also summarized and evaluated on a quantitative basis, in this case by the ratio of social benefits to social costs. (The social benefit part of the ratio is calculated by multiplying the proposed quantity of outputs from a workplace by their indicative prices, adding negative prices for any proposed pollution emissions and summing. The social costs are calculated by multiplying the quantity of requested inputs by their indicative prices and summing.) Proposals with a benefits-to-cost ratio below one will need to make adjustments in order to gain approval in the next round, either by switching to a less polluting technology, producing a more socially desirable set of outputs, or using less costly inputs.

After receiving the revised proposals, the facilitation board once again updates the list of indicative prices. After several rounds of this revision and resubmission process, the result is convergence to a feasible plan in which workers and consumers are able to accomplish the activities that they detailed in their final submissions. Even after a feasible plan is achieved, flexible mid-year revisions of consumer/worker proposals can also be incorporated into the planning process.

Albert and Hahnel argue that participatory planning can achieve Pareto optimum, and does so under less restrictive assumptions than free market models (see: the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics). Their model incorporates both public goods and externalities, whereas markets do not achieve Pareto optimality when including these conditions.[6][7]

A feature of participatory planning which differs from other modes of democratic planning is that all deliberation on proposals occurs within councils, but does not take place between councils. That is, under parecon, a feasible economic plan is constructed due to an iterative adjustment of prices based on the information from councils' self-activity proposals, rather than owing to a procedure of deliberation among delegates from various workplaces/industries. This is potentially desirable by cutting down on the meeting time and bureaucratic burdens needed to converge on an annual plan.

Facilitation boards edit

In a proposed participatory economy, key information relevant to converging on an economic plan would be made available by Iteration Facilitation Boards (IFBs), which, based on proposals from worker/consumer councils and economic data, present indicative prices and economic projections at each round of the planning process.[8]

The IFB has no decision-making authority. In theory, the IFB's activity can consist mainly of computers performing the (agreed upon) algorithms for adjusting prices and forecasts, with little human involvement.[9]

Motivations (opposition to central planning and capitalism) edit

Robin Hahnel has argued that "participatory planning is not central planning", stating "The procedures are completely different and the incentives are completely different. And one of the important ways in which it is different from central planning is that it is incentive compatible, that is, actors have an incentive to report truthfully rather than an incentive to misrepresent their capabilities or preferences."[10] Unlike historical examples of central planning, the parecon proposal advocates the use and adjustment of price information reflecting marginal social opportunity costs and benefits as integral elements of the planning process. Hahnel has argued emphatically against Milton Friedman's a priori tendency to deny the possibility of alternatives:

Friedman assumes away the best solution for coordinating economic activities. He simply asserts "there are only two ways of coordinating the economic activities of millions—central direction involving the use of coercion—and voluntary cooperation, the technique of the marketplace." [...] a participatory economy can permit all to partake in economic decision making in proportion to the degree they are affected by outcomes. Since a participatory system uses a system of participatory planning instead of markets to coordinate economic activities, Friedman would have us believe that participatory planning must fall into the category of "central direction involving the use of coercion."[11]

Albert and Hahnel have voiced detailed critiques of centrally-planned economies in theory and practice, but are also highly-critical of capitalism. Hahnel claims "the truth is capitalism aggravates prejudice, is the most inequitable economy ever devised, is grossly inefficient—even if highly energetic—and is incompatible with both economic and political democracy. In the present era of free-market triumphalism it is useful to organize a sober evaluation of capitalism responding to Friedman's claims one by one."[12]

Critique of markets edit

Mainstream economists largely acknowledge the problem of externalities but believe they can be addressed either through Coasian bargaining or the use of Pigovian taxes—corrective taxes on goods that produce negative externalities.[13] According to mainstream theory, if Pigovian taxes are set so that the after-tax cost of a good is equal to its social cost (i.e. the sum of the good's private costs to producers and consumers and the good's external costs to society) then the quantity produced of that good will tend toward a socially optimal level.

While Hahnel (and Albert) favour the use of Pigovian taxes as solutions to environmental problems within market economies (over alternatives such as the issuance of marketable permits), he is critical about the regressive incidence of such taxes. Firms in a market economy will seek to shift the costs of taxation onto their consumers. While this might be considered a positive development in terms of incentives—since it penalizes consumers for "dirty" consumption—it fails to achieve the polluter pays principle and would instead aggravate "economic injustice."[14] Hahnel, therefore, recommends that pollution taxes be linked to cuts in regressive taxes such as social security taxes.

Hahnel is also critical of the mainstream assumption that externalities are anomalous and, on the whole, insignificant to market efficiency; he asserts instead that externalities are prevalent—the rule rather than the exception—and substantial.[15]

Ultimately, Hahnel argues that Pigovian taxes, along with associated corrective measures advanced by market economists, fall far short of adequately or fairly addressing externalities. He argues such methods are incapable of attaining accurate assessments of social costs:

Markets corrected by pollution taxes only lead to the efficient amount of pollution and satisfy the polluter pays principle if the taxes are set equal to the magnitude of the damage victims suffer. But because markets are not incentive compatible for polluters and pollution victims, markets provide no reliable way to estimate the magnitudes of efficient taxes for pollutants. Ambiguity over who has the property right, polluters or pollution victims, free rider problems among multiple victims, and the transaction costs of forming and maintaining an effective coalition of pollution victims, each of whom is affected to a small but unequal degree, all combine to render market systems incapable of eliciting accurate information from pollution victims about the damages they suffer, or acting upon that information even if it were known.[16]

Class and hierarchy edit

Advocates of parecon say the intention is that the four main ingredients of parecon be implemented with a minimum of hierarchy and a maximum of transparency in all discussions and decision-making. This model is designed to eliminate secrecy in economic decision-making, and instead encourage friendly cooperation and mutual support. This avoidance of power hierarchies puts parecon in the libertarian socialist political tradition. Stephen Shalom has produced a political system meant to complement parecon, called parpolity.

Although parecon falls under left-wing political tradition, it is designed to avoid the creation of powerful intellectual elites or the rule of a bureaucracy, which is perceived as the major problem of the economies of the communist states of the 20th century.[17] In their book Looking Forward Albert and Hanhel termed this situation 'coordinatorism'.[18]: 4–8  Parecon advocates recognize that monopolization of empowering labor, in addition to private ownership, can be a source of class division. Thus, a three-class view of the economy (capitalists, coordinators, and workers) is stressed, in contrast to the traditional two-class view of Marxism. The coordinator class, emphasized in parecon, refers to those who have a monopoly on empowering skills and knowledge, and corresponds to the doctors, lawyers, managers, engineers, and other professionals in present economies. Parecon advocates argue that, historically, Marxism ignored the ability of coordinators to become a new ruling class in a post-capitalist society.[17]

Innovation edit

Hahnel has also written a detailed discussion of parecon's desirability compared to capitalism with respect to incentives to innovate.[19] In capitalism, patent laws, intellectual property rights and barriers to market entry are institutional features that reward individual innovators while limiting the use of new technologies. Hahnel notes that, in contrast, "in a participatory economy all innovations will immediately be made available to all enterprises, so there will never be any loss of static efficiency.".[20]

Limitations edit

Participatory economics is not in itself intended to provide a general political system. Its practical implementation would depend on an accompanying political system.

According to Albert and Hahnel, parecon addresses only an alternative economic theory and must be accompanied by equally important alternatives in the fields of politics, culture and kinship. The authors have also discussed elements of anarchism in the field of politics, polyculturalism in the field of culture, and feminism in the field of family and gender relations as being possible foundations for future alternative visions in these other spheres of society; the totality of such changes is often referred to as 'participatory society'. Stephen R. Shalom has begun work on a participatory political vision he calls "parpolity".

Criticism edit

The market socialist David Schweickart suggests participatory economics would be undesirable even if it was possible:

It is a system obsessed with comparison (Is your job complex more empowering than mine?), with monitoring (You are not working at average intensity, mate—get with the program), with the details of consumption (How many rolls of toilet paper will I need next year? Why are some of my neighbors still using the kind not made of recycled paper?)[21]

Other criticism raised by Schweickart include:[22]

  • Difficulty with creating balanced job complexes and ensuring they do not suffer from inefficiency.
  • A system based on peer evaluation may not work as workers could slack off and there would be little incentive for colleagues to damage their relationships by giving them bad reviews. Alternatively it may cause workers to become suspicious of one another, undermining solidarity.
  • A compensation system based on effort would be difficult to measure and would need to be based on an average rating system of effort.
  • Parecon's compensation system would be overly egalitarian and likely cause resentment among workers who work harder while also discouraging them from putting in extra effort since they will gain no greater compensation.
  • Parecon would likely produce an onerous and tiresome requirement to list off all things people want produced, which would likely suffer from uncertainty given people do not always know what they desire, as well as issues with how much information they should be required to supply and complexities with the negotiations required between worker and consumer councils.

Planning edit

Participatory economics would create a large amount of administrative work for individual workers, who would have to plan their consumption in advance, and a new bureaucratic class. Proponents of parecon argue that capitalist economies are hardly free of bureaucracy or meetings, and a parecon would eliminate banks, advertising, stock market, tax returns and long-term financial planning. Albert and Hahnel claim that it is probable that a similar number of workers will be involved in a parecon bureaucracy as in a capitalist bureaucracy,[23] with much of the voting achieved by computer rather than meeting, and those who are not interested in the collective consumption proposals not required to attend.[24]

Critics suggest that proposals require consideration of an unfeasibly large set of policy choices,[21] and that lessons from planned societies show that peoples' daily needs cannot be established well in advance simply by asking people what they want.[25] Albert and Hahnel note that markets themselves hardly adjust prices instantaneously,[26] and suggest that in a participatory economy facilitation boards could modify prices on a regular basis. According to Hahnel these act according to democratically decided guidelines, can be composed of members from other regions and are impossible to bribe due to parecon's non-transferable currency.[27] However, Takis Fotopoulos argues that "no kind of economic organisation based on planning alone, however democratic and decentralized it is, can secure real self-management and freedom of choice."[25]

Loss of efficiency edit

Parecon might reduce efficiency in the workplace. For one, expert and exceptional workers (e.g. exceptional surgeons and scientists) would not be performing their tasks full-time—in other words, working with very high opportunity costs. Participatory economics would expect them to share in "disempowering work" and would not offer opportunities to seek additional compensation for their high ability or finding solutions to problems. In a lecture at Willamette University in Oregon in 2015, Hahnel responded to this criticism by explaining that these jobs could be filled by machines, which are underutilized in capitalist economic systems due to the lowered rates of profit, and also division of labor would not exist under a participatory economic system as much as it does under capitalism, so people would not always have the same jobs.[citation needed]

Theodore Burczak argues that it is impossible for workers to give the unbiased assessments of the "largely unobservable" characteristics of effort proposed as the basis for salary levels, and the absence of market exchange mechanisms likewise makes calculating social costs of production and consumption impossible.[28]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Albert, Michael Parecon: Life After Capitalism 2008-10-16 at the Wayback Machine Chapter 19 Individuals / Society
  2. ^ "Introduction | Participatory Economics". Retrieved 2024-01-29.
  3. ^ Albert, Michael; Hahnel, Robin; Kotz, David M.; O'Neill, John (2002). "In Defense of Participatory Economics". Science & Society. 66 (1): 7–28. doi:10.1521/siso.66.1.7.21015. ISSN 0036-8237. JSTOR 40403950.
  4. ^ "Balanced Jobs | Participatory Economics". Retrieved 2020-09-27.
  5. ^ a b c Albert, Michael Parecon: Life After Capitalism Part II, Chapter 7: Remuneration pp. 112–17.
  6. ^ Albert, Michael; Hahnel, Robin (1992). "Participatory Planning". Science & Society. 56 (1): 39–59. ISSN 0036-8237. JSTOR 40403236.
  7. ^ Albert, Michael (1991). The political economy of participatory economics. Robin Hahnel. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-04274-8. OCLC 22766907.
  8. ^ "Participatory Planning | Participatory Economics". Retrieved 2024-01-08.
  9. ^ "13 Allocating". Z Communications. Retrieved 8 July 2015.
  10. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation, p. 221, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.[ISBN missing]
  11. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation p. 81, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.
  12. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation ch. 4, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.
  13. ^ "Pigovian Tax". Investopedia. Retrieved 2021-12-07.
  14. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation, p. 274.
  15. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation, p. 85.
  16. ^ Robin Hahnel, (2004). "Protecting the Environment in a Participatory Economy". Retrieved February 13, 2006.
  17. ^ a b Michael Albert (April 20, 2008). . www.zcommunications.org. Archived from the original on 2012-02-26.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)
  18. ^ Albert, Michael; Hanhel, Robin (1990). Looking Forward: Participatory Economics for the Twenty First Century. South End Press. ISBN 978-0896084056.
  19. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation p. 241, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.
  20. ^ Economic Justice and Democracy: From Competition to Cooperation p. 240, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.
  21. ^ a b Schweickart, David (January 2006). . Archived from the original on 2015-07-11. Retrieved 2012-07-08.
  22. ^ Schweickart, David "Nonsense on Stilts: Michael Albert's Parecon", January 2006, Loyola University Chicago, accessed 11/12/2018
  23. ^ Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel, "Looking Forward" pp. 86–89.
  24. ^ "Participatory Economics by Michael Albert | ZNet Article". ZCommunications. 2008-11-19. Retrieved 2010-08-17.
  25. ^ a b Takis Fotopoulos (2003), "Inclusive Democracy and Participatory Economics", Democracy & Nature, Volume 9, Issue 3 November 2003, pp. 401–25.
  26. ^ Michael Albert, "Parecon: Life After Capitalism", p. 282.
  27. ^ Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel, "Looking Forward" pp. 92–93.
  28. ^ Burczak, Theodore A. Socialism after Hayek. pp. 143–44.

Further reading edit

  • , Albert and Hahnel, Princeton University Press, 1990.
  • , Albert and Hahnel, South End Press, 1991.
  • , Albert and Hahnel, Princeton University Press, 1991.
  • , Albert, AK Press, 1997.
  • Parecon: Life After Capitalism, Albert, Verso Books, 2003.
  • Economic Justice And Democracy: From Competition To Cooperation, Hahnel, Routledge, 2005.
  • , Albert, Zed Press, 2006.
  • , Chris Spannos (Ed.), AK Press, 2008.
  • Takis Fotopoulos (2003), Inclusive Democracy and Participatory Economics, Democracy & Nature, Volume 9, Issue 3 November 2003, pp. 401–25 – a comparison with Inclusive Democracy
  • Rameez Rahman, Michel Meulpolder, David Hales, Johan Pouwelse, Henk Sips (2009), "", Delft University of Technology Report. – applying Participatory Economics principles to analysis of peer-to-peer computing systems

participatory, economics, often, abbreviated, parecon, economic, system, based, participatory, decision, making, primary, economic, mechanism, allocation, society, system, decision, making, proportional, impact, person, group, people, form, socialist, decentra. Participatory economics often abbreviated Parecon is an economic system based on participatory decision making as the primary economic mechanism for allocation in society In the system the say in decision making is proportional to the impact on a person or group of people Participatory economics is a form of a socialist decentralized planned economy involving the collective ownership of the means of production It is a proposed alternative to contemporary capitalism and centralized planning This economic model is primarily associated with political theorist Michael Albert and economist Robin Hahnel who describes participatory economics as an anarchist economic vision 1 The underlying values that parecon seeks to implement are equity solidarity diversity workers self management efficiency defined as accomplishing goals without wasting valued assets and sustainability The institutions of parecon include workers and consumers councils utilising self managerial methods for decision making balanced job complexes remuneration based on individual effort and wide decentralized planning Albert and Hahnel claim that participatory economics has been practiced to varying degrees during the Russian Revolution of 1917 Spanish Revolution of 1936 and occasionally in South America 2 Contents 1 Decision making principle 2 Work and distribution 2 1 Balanced job complexes 2 2 Compensation for effort and sacrifice principle for distribution 3 Allocation of resource 3 1 Facilitation boards 4 Motivations opposition to central planning and capitalism 4 1 Critique of markets 4 2 Class and hierarchy 4 3 Innovation 5 Limitations 6 Criticism 6 1 Planning 6 2 Loss of efficiency 7 See also 8 References 9 Further readingDecision making principle editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message A primary proposition of parecon is that everyone should have a say in decisions proportionate to the degree to which they are affected by them In their councils workers would deliberate over plans regarding the productive enterprise and employ whichever voting scheme best instantiates this principle Generally a workers council is not constrained to adopt a single threshold such as a simple majority to pass their resolutions but can tailor their voting procedures to reflect the variation in impact of the enterprise s decisions In parecon self management constitutes a replacement for the mainstream conception of economic freedom which Albert and Hahnel argue by its very vagueness has allowed it to be abused by capitalist ideologues 3 Work and distribution editBalanced job complexes edit A balanced job complex is a collection of tasks within a given workplace that is balanced for its equity and empowerment implications against all other job complexes in that workplace 4 Compensation for effort and sacrifice principle for distribution edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Albert and Hahnel argue that it is inequitable and ineffective to compensate people on the basis of luck e g skills or talents that owe to their birth or heredity or by virtue of workers productivity as measured by the value of the goods they produce Therefore the primary principle of participatory economics is to reward workers for their effort and sacrifice 5 For example mining work which is dangerous and uncomfortable would be more highly paid than office work for the same amount of time thus allowing the miner to work fewer hours for the same pay and the burden of highly dangerous and strenuous jobs to be shared among the populace Additionally participatory economics would provide exemptions from the compensation for effort principle 5 People with disabilities who are unable to work children the elderly the infirm and workers who are legitimately in transitional circumstances would be remunerated according to need while all other able bodied adults would be obliged to perform some socially useful work as a requirement for compensation However all individuals would enjoy a baseline of entitlements to free health care education skills training and the freedom to choose between various democratically structured workplaces with balanced jobs balanced for desirability and empowerment The starting point for the income of all workers in a participatory economy is an equal share of the social product From this point incomes for personal expenditures and consumption rights for public goods can be expected to diverge by small degrees reflecting the choices that individuals make in between work and leisure time and the level of danger and difficulty of a job as judged by their immediate workplace peers 5 Allocation of resource editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Participatory planning is the allocation mechanism in a participatory economy and is meant to provide a workable alternative to market competition and centralized planning The planning procedure is conceived as an iterative process in which 1 production proposals made by workers councils and 2 consumption proposals made by individuals and their neighborhood councils are submitted and revised through multiple rounds of pricing updates until the process converges on a feasible plan for the upcoming year The process begins when the facilitation board see below announces a list of indicative prices for each final consumer good as well as for each capital good natural resource and category of labor that is available to society These indicative prices are calculated to reflect the estimated opportunity costs for producing various goods and services and incorporate both social costs and pollution impacts In response to this list of prices individuals draft an annual consumption plan for goods services they wish to consume in the coming year and also meet in their neighborhood councils to deliberate and democratically arrive at a plan for the consumption of public goods e g obtaining resources to build a public playground As workers individuals also meet in their workplaces to determine what outputs they will produce and what inputs they will consume in the production process as well as how much they would each like to work Thus workers and consumers as well as any federations of workers or consumers submit their initial requests to the facilitation board which aggregates this information Because the conclusion of the first round of this process will almost certainly not be a workable plan the facilitation board proceeds to update the list of indicative prices for each good up or down in proportion to the excess demand and supply for each so that the updated prices reflect a more accurate estimate of the social opportunity costs of each item The announcement of updated indicative prices then initiates the second round of the planning process in which consumers and workers revise and resubmit their proposals in light of the new information In particular consumption proposals in which the individual s proposed effort rating does not warrant the proposed level of consumption will need to be adjusted so that the individual will either have to reduce his her consumption requests shift them to less costly products or increase his her projected work hours for the coming year Other consumers may discover that their initial proposals were too modest and can revise their consumption upwards if they choose or they can revise their projected effort rating downwards by proposing to work fewer hours and increasing leisure time Production proposals are also summarized and evaluated on a quantitative basis in this case by the ratio of social benefits to social costs The social benefit part of the ratio is calculated by multiplying the proposed quantity of outputs from a workplace by their indicative prices adding negative prices for any proposed pollution emissions and summing The social costs are calculated by multiplying the quantity of requested inputs by their indicative prices and summing Proposals with a benefits to cost ratio below one will need to make adjustments in order to gain approval in the next round either by switching to a less polluting technology producing a more socially desirable set of outputs or using less costly inputs After receiving the revised proposals the facilitation board once again updates the list of indicative prices After several rounds of this revision and resubmission process the result is convergence to a feasible plan in which workers and consumers are able to accomplish the activities that they detailed in their final submissions Even after a feasible plan is achieved flexible mid year revisions of consumer worker proposals can also be incorporated into the planning process Albert and Hahnel argue that participatory planning can achieve Pareto optimum and does so under less restrictive assumptions than free market models see the first fundamental theorem of welfare economics Their model incorporates both public goods and externalities whereas markets do not achieve Pareto optimality when including these conditions 6 7 A feature of participatory planning which differs from other modes of democratic planning is that all deliberation on proposals occurs within councils but does not take place between councils That is under parecon a feasible economic plan is constructed due to an iterative adjustment of prices based on the information from councils self activity proposals rather than owing to a procedure of deliberation among delegates from various workplaces industries This is potentially desirable by cutting down on the meeting time and bureaucratic burdens needed to converge on an annual plan Facilitation boards edit Main article Facilitation board economics In a proposed participatory economy key information relevant to converging on an economic plan would be made available by Iteration Facilitation Boards IFBs which based on proposals from worker consumer councils and economic data present indicative prices and economic projections at each round of the planning process 8 The IFB has no decision making authority In theory the IFB s activity can consist mainly of computers performing the agreed upon algorithms for adjusting prices and forecasts with little human involvement 9 Motivations opposition to central planning and capitalism editSee also Libertarian socialism Robin Hahnel has argued that participatory planning is not central planning stating The procedures are completely different and the incentives are completely different And one of the important ways in which it is different from central planning is that it is incentive compatible that is actors have an incentive to report truthfully rather than an incentive to misrepresent their capabilities or preferences 10 Unlike historical examples of central planning the parecon proposal advocates the use and adjustment of price information reflecting marginal social opportunity costs and benefits as integral elements of the planning process Hahnel has argued emphatically against Milton Friedman s a priori tendency to deny the possibility of alternatives Friedman assumes away the best solution for coordinating economic activities He simply asserts there are only two ways of coordinating the economic activities of millions central direction involving the use of coercion and voluntary cooperation the technique of the marketplace a participatory economy can permit all to partake in economic decision making in proportion to the degree they are affected by outcomes Since a participatory system uses a system of participatory planning instead of markets to coordinate economic activities Friedman would have us believe that participatory planning must fall into the category of central direction involving the use of coercion 11 Albert and Hahnel have voiced detailed critiques of centrally planned economies in theory and practice but are also highly critical of capitalism Hahnel claims the truth is capitalism aggravates prejudice is the most inequitable economy ever devised is grossly inefficient even if highly energetic and is incompatible with both economic and political democracy In the present era of free market triumphalism it is useful to organize a sober evaluation of capitalism responding to Friedman s claims one by one 12 Critique of markets edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Mainstream economists largely acknowledge the problem of externalities but believe they can be addressed either through Coasian bargaining or the use of Pigovian taxes corrective taxes on goods that produce negative externalities 13 According to mainstream theory if Pigovian taxes are set so that the after tax cost of a good is equal to its social cost i e the sum of the good s private costs to producers and consumers and the good s external costs to society then the quantity produced of that good will tend toward a socially optimal level While Hahnel and Albert favour the use of Pigovian taxes as solutions to environmental problems within market economies over alternatives such as the issuance of marketable permits he is critical about the regressive incidence of such taxes Firms in a market economy will seek to shift the costs of taxation onto their consumers While this might be considered a positive development in terms of incentives since it penalizes consumers for dirty consumption it fails to achieve the polluter pays principle and would instead aggravate economic injustice 14 Hahnel therefore recommends that pollution taxes be linked to cuts in regressive taxes such as social security taxes Hahnel is also critical of the mainstream assumption that externalities are anomalous and on the whole insignificant to market efficiency he asserts instead that externalities are prevalent the rule rather than the exception and substantial 15 Ultimately Hahnel argues that Pigovian taxes along with associated corrective measures advanced by market economists fall far short of adequately or fairly addressing externalities He argues such methods are incapable of attaining accurate assessments of social costs Markets corrected by pollution taxes only lead to the efficient amount of pollution and satisfy the polluter pays principle if the taxes are set equal to the magnitude of the damage victims suffer But because markets are not incentive compatible for polluters and pollution victims markets provide no reliable way to estimate the magnitudes of efficient taxes for pollutants Ambiguity over who has the property right polluters or pollution victims free rider problems among multiple victims and the transaction costs of forming and maintaining an effective coalition of pollution victims each of whom is affected to a small but unequal degree all combine to render market systems incapable of eliciting accurate information from pollution victims about the damages they suffer or acting upon that information even if it were known 16 Class and hierarchy edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Advocates of parecon say the intention is that the four main ingredients of parecon be implemented with a minimum of hierarchy and a maximum of transparency in all discussions and decision making This model is designed to eliminate secrecy in economic decision making and instead encourage friendly cooperation and mutual support This avoidance of power hierarchies puts parecon in the libertarian socialist political tradition Stephen Shalom has produced a political system meant to complement parecon called parpolity Although parecon falls under left wing political tradition it is designed to avoid the creation of powerful intellectual elites or the rule of a bureaucracy which is perceived as the major problem of the economies of the communist states of the 20th century 17 In their book Looking Forward Albert and Hanhel termed this situation coordinatorism 18 4 8 Parecon advocates recognize that monopolization of empowering labor in addition to private ownership can be a source of class division Thus a three class view of the economy capitalists coordinators and workers is stressed in contrast to the traditional two class view of Marxism The coordinator class emphasized in parecon refers to those who have a monopoly on empowering skills and knowledge and corresponds to the doctors lawyers managers engineers and other professionals in present economies Parecon advocates argue that historically Marxism ignored the ability of coordinators to become a new ruling class in a post capitalist society 17 Innovation edit Hahnel has also written a detailed discussion of parecon s desirability compared to capitalism with respect to incentives to innovate 19 In capitalism patent laws intellectual property rights and barriers to market entry are institutional features that reward individual innovators while limiting the use of new technologies Hahnel notes that in contrast in a participatory economy all innovations will immediately be made available to all enterprises so there will never be any loss of static efficiency 20 Limitations editParticipatory economics is not in itself intended to provide a general political system Its practical implementation would depend on an accompanying political system According to Albert and Hahnel parecon addresses only an alternative economic theory and must be accompanied by equally important alternatives in the fields of politics culture and kinship The authors have also discussed elements of anarchism in the field of politics polyculturalism in the field of culture and feminism in the field of family and gender relations as being possible foundations for future alternative visions in these other spheres of society the totality of such changes is often referred to as participatory society Stephen R Shalom has begun work on a participatory political vision he calls parpolity Criticism editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message The market socialist David Schweickart suggests participatory economics would be undesirable even if it was possible It is a system obsessed with comparison Is your job complex more empowering than mine with monitoring You are not working at average intensity mate get with the program with the details of consumption How many rolls of toilet paper will I need next year Why are some of my neighbors still using the kind not made of recycled paper 21 Other criticism raised by Schweickart include 22 Difficulty with creating balanced job complexes and ensuring they do not suffer from inefficiency A system based on peer evaluation may not work as workers could slack off and there would be little incentive for colleagues to damage their relationships by giving them bad reviews Alternatively it may cause workers to become suspicious of one another undermining solidarity A compensation system based on effort would be difficult to measure and would need to be based on an average rating system of effort Parecon s compensation system would be overly egalitarian and likely cause resentment among workers who work harder while also discouraging them from putting in extra effort since they will gain no greater compensation Parecon would likely produce an onerous and tiresome requirement to list off all things people want produced which would likely suffer from uncertainty given people do not always know what they desire as well as issues with how much information they should be required to supply and complexities with the negotiations required between worker and consumer councils Planning edit Further information Economic calculation problem Participatory economics would create a large amount of administrative work for individual workers who would have to plan their consumption in advance and a new bureaucratic class Proponents of parecon argue that capitalist economies are hardly free of bureaucracy or meetings and a parecon would eliminate banks advertising stock market tax returns and long term financial planning Albert and Hahnel claim that it is probable that a similar number of workers will be involved in a parecon bureaucracy as in a capitalist bureaucracy 23 with much of the voting achieved by computer rather than meeting and those who are not interested in the collective consumption proposals not required to attend 24 Critics suggest that proposals require consideration of an unfeasibly large set of policy choices 21 and that lessons from planned societies show that peoples daily needs cannot be established well in advance simply by asking people what they want 25 Albert and Hahnel note that markets themselves hardly adjust prices instantaneously 26 and suggest that in a participatory economy facilitation boards could modify prices on a regular basis According to Hahnel these act according to democratically decided guidelines can be composed of members from other regions and are impossible to bribe due to parecon s non transferable currency 27 However Takis Fotopoulos argues that no kind of economic organisation based on planning alone however democratic and decentralized it is can secure real self management and freedom of choice 25 Loss of efficiency edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Parecon might reduce efficiency in the workplace For one expert and exceptional workers e g exceptional surgeons and scientists would not be performing their tasks full time in other words working with very high opportunity costs Participatory economics would expect them to share in disempowering work and would not offer opportunities to seek additional compensation for their high ability or finding solutions to problems In a lecture at Willamette University in Oregon in 2015 Hahnel responded to this criticism by explaining that these jobs could be filled by machines which are underutilized in capitalist economic systems due to the lowered rates of profit and also division of labor would not exist under a participatory economic system as much as it does under capitalism so people would not always have the same jobs citation needed Theodore Burczak argues that it is impossible for workers to give the unbiased assessments of the largely unobservable characteristics of effort proposed as the basis for salary levels and the absence of market exchange mechanisms likewise makes calculating social costs of production and consumption impossible 28 See also editAnarchist economics Anarcho syndicalism Collaborative e democracy Co operative Economic democracy Inclusive Democracy Libertarian municipalism Participatory politics Social justiceReferences edit Albert Michael Parecon Life After Capitalism Archived 2008 10 16 at the Wayback Machine Chapter 19 Individuals Society Introduction Participatory Economics Retrieved 2024 01 29 Albert Michael Hahnel Robin Kotz David M O Neill John 2002 In Defense of Participatory Economics Science amp Society 66 1 7 28 doi 10 1521 siso 66 1 7 21015 ISSN 0036 8237 JSTOR 40403950 Balanced Jobs Participatory Economics Retrieved 2020 09 27 a b c Albert Michael Parecon Life After Capitalism Part II Chapter 7 Remuneration pp 112 17 Albert Michael Hahnel Robin 1992 Participatory Planning Science amp Society 56 1 39 59 ISSN 0036 8237 JSTOR 40403236 Albert Michael 1991 The political economy of participatory economics Robin Hahnel Princeton N J Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 04274 8 OCLC 22766907 Participatory Planning Participatory Economics Retrieved 2024 01 08 13 Allocating Z Communications Retrieved 8 July 2015 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 221 Hahnel Routledge 2005 ISBN missing Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 81 Hahnel Routledge 2005 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation ch 4 Hahnel Routledge 2005 Pigovian Tax Investopedia Retrieved 2021 12 07 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 274 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 85 Robin Hahnel 2004 Protecting the Environment in a Participatory Economy Retrieved February 13 2006 a b Michael Albert April 20 2008 Parecon and Marxism www zcommunications org Archived from the original on 2012 02 26 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint unfit URL link Albert Michael Hanhel Robin 1990 Looking Forward Participatory Economics for the Twenty First Century South End Press ISBN 978 0896084056 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 241 Hahnel Routledge 2005 Economic Justice and Democracy From Competition to Cooperation p 240 Hahnel Routledge 2005 a b Schweickart David January 2006 Michael Albert s Parecon A Critique Archived from the original on 2015 07 11 Retrieved 2012 07 08 Schweickart David Nonsense on Stilts Michael Albert s Parecon January 2006 Loyola University Chicago accessed 11 12 2018 Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel Looking Forward pp 86 89 Participatory Economics by Michael Albert ZNet Article ZCommunications 2008 11 19 Retrieved 2010 08 17 a b Takis Fotopoulos 2003 Inclusive Democracy and Participatory Economics Democracy amp Nature Volume 9 Issue 3 November 2003 pp 401 25 Michael Albert Parecon Life After Capitalism p 282 Michael Albert and Robin Hahnel Looking Forward pp 92 93 Burczak Theodore A Socialism after Hayek pp 143 44 Further reading editA Quiet Revolution In Welfare Economics Albert and Hahnel Princeton University Press 1990 Looking Forward Participatory Economics for the Twenty First Century Albert and Hahnel South End Press 1991 The Political Economy of Participatory Economics Albert and Hahnel Princeton University Press 1991 Moving Forward Program for a Participatory Economy Albert AK Press 1997 Parecon Life After Capitalism Albert Verso Books 2003 Economic Justice And Democracy From Competition To Cooperation Hahnel Routledge 2005 Realizing Hope Life Beyond Capitalism Albert Zed Press 2006 Real Utopia Participatory Society for the 21st Century Chris Spannos Ed AK Press 2008 Takis Fotopoulos 2003 Inclusive Democracy and Participatory Economics Democracy amp Nature Volume 9 Issue 3 November 2003 pp 401 25 a comparison with Inclusive Democracy Rameez Rahman Michel Meulpolder David Hales Johan Pouwelse Henk Sips 2009 Revisiting Social Welfare in P2P Delft University of Technology Report applying Participatory Economics principles to analysis of peer to peer computing systems Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Participatory economics amp oldid 1205939204, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.