fbpx
Wikipedia

Social anarchism

Social anarchism, also known as left-wing anarchism or socialist anarchism, is the branch of anarchism that sees liberty and social equality as interrelated.

It advocates for a social revolution to remove oppressive forms of hierarchy, such as capitalism and the state. In their place, social anarchists encourage social collaboration through mutual aid and envision non-hierarchical forms of social organization, such as voluntary associations.

Identified with the socialist tradition of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, Mikhail Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin, social anarchism is often contrasted with individualist anarchism, due to the latter's criticism of socialism.

Political principles edit

Social anarchism is opposed to all forms of social and political power, hierarchy and oppression, including (but not limited to) the State and capitalism.[1] Social anarchism sees liberty as interconnected with social equality,[2] and considers the maximization of one to be necessary for the maximization of the other.[3] Social anarchism therefore employs a utilitarian ethics, concerning itself with the well-being of all, as it considers each person's happiness to be equal to those of others.[4] As such, social anarchism seeks to guarantee equal rights to freedom and material security for all persons.[5]

Social anarchism envisions the overthrow of capitalism and the state in a social revolution,[6] which would establish a federal society of voluntary associations and local communities,[7] based on a network of mutual aid.[8]

The key principles that form the core of social anarchism include anti-capitalism, anti-statism and prefigurative politics.[9]

Anti-capitalism edit

As an anti-capitalist ideology, social anarchism is opposed to the dominant expressions of capitalism, including the expansion of transnational corporations through globalization.[10] It comprises one of the main forms of socialism, alongside utopian socialism, democratic socialism and authoritarian socialism.[11] Social anarchism rejects private property, particularly private ownership of the means of production, as the principal source of social inequality.[12] As such, social anarchists typically oppose propertarianism, as they consider it to exacerbate social and economic inequality, suppress individual agency and require the maintenance of hierarchical institutions.[13]

Social anarchists argue that the abolition of private property would lead to the development of new social mores, encouraging mutual respect for individual freedom and the satisfaction of individual needs.[14] Social anarchism therefore advocates the breaking up of monopolies and the institution of common ownership over the means of production.[15] Instead of capitalist markets, with their profit motives and wage systems, social anarchism desires to organise production through a collective system of worker cooperatives, agricultural communes and labour syndicates.[16]

While social anarchism has rejected the statism of Orthodox Marxism, it has also drawn from Marxist critiques of capitalism, particularly Marx's theory of alienation.[17] Social anarchists have also been reluctant to adopt the Marxist centring of the proletariat as revolutionary agents, instead identifying the revolutionary potential of the socially excluded segments of society.[18]

Anti-statism edit

As an anti-statist ideology, social anarchism opposes the concentration of power in the form of a State.[19] To social anarchists, the state is a type of coercive hierarchy designed to enforce private property and to limit individual self-development.[20] Social anarchists reject both centralised and limited forms of government, instead upholding social collaboration as a means to achieve a spontaneous order, without any social contract supplanting social relations.[21] Social anarchists believe that the abolition of the state will lead to greater "freedom, flourishing and fairness".[22]

In the place of a state structure, social anarchists desire anarchy, which can be defined as a society without government.[23] Social anarchists oppose the use of a state structure to achieve their goals of a stateless and classless society,[24] as they consider statism to be an inherently corrupting influence.[25] They thus have criticised the Marxist conception of the "dictatorship of the proletariat", which they consider to be elitist,[26] and have rejected the possibility of a "withering away of the state".[27]

However, some social anarchists such as Noam Chomsky sometimes hold state hierarchy to be preferable to economic hierarchy, and thus lend their support to welfare state programs like universal health care that can improve people's material conditions.[20]

Prefigurative politics edit

Alongside its opposition to political and economic hierarchies, social anarchism upholds prefigurative politics, considering it necessary for the means to achieve anarchy be consistent with that end goal.[28] Social anarchism prefigures itself through participatory and consensus decision-making, which are capable of generating the diversification of political values, tactics and identities.[29]

Social anarchism therefore promotes self-organization and the cultivation of a participatory culture, encouraging individuals to "do things for themselves".[1] Social anarchism upholds direct action as a means for people to themselves resist oppression,[30] without subordinating their own agency to democratic representatives or revolutionary vanguards.[31] Social anarchists thus reject the political party model of organization,[17] instead preferring forms of flat organization without any fixed leadership.[32]

Schools of thought edit

Characterised by its loose definition and ideological diversity,[33] social anarchism has lent itself to syncretism, both drawing from and influencing other ideological critiques of oppression,[34] and giving way to a number of different anarchist schools of thought.[35]

While early forms of anarchism were largely individualistic, the influence of Left Hegelianism infused anarchism with socialistic tendencies, leading to the constitution of social anarchism.[36] Over time, the question of the economic makeup of a future anarchist society drove the development of social anarchist thought.[37] The first school of social anarchism was formulated by Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, whose theory of mutualism retained a form of private property,[38] advocating for enterprises to be self-managed by worker cooperatives, which would compensate its workers in labour vouchers issued by "people's banks".[39] This was later supplanted by Mikhail Bakunin's collectivist anarchism, which advocated for the collective ownership of all property, but retained a form of individual compensation.[40] This finally led to the development of anarcho-communism by Peter Kropotkin, who considered that resources should be freely distributed "from each according to their ability, to each according to their needs", without money or wages.[41] Social anarchists also adopted the strategy of syndicalism, which saw trade unions as the basis for a new socialist economy,[42] with anarcho-syndicalism growing to its greatest influence during the Spanish Revolution of 1936.[43]

The main division within social anarchism is over the means for achieving anarchy, with philosophical anarchists advocating for peaceful persuasion,[44] while insurrectionary anarchists advocated for "propaganda of the deed".[45] The former have upheld an anarchist form of education, free from coercion and dogmatism, in order to establish a self-governing society.[46] The latter have participated in rebellions in which they expropriated and collectivised property, and replaced the state with a network of autonomous and federally-linked communes.[47] The aim was to build a socialist society, without using the state, from the bottom-up.[47]

Principles of social anarchism, such as decentralisation, anti-authoritarianism and mutual aid, later held a key influence on the new social movements of the late-20th century.[48] It was particularly influential within the New Left and green politics,[49] with the green anarchist tendency of social ecology drawing directly from social anarchism.[50] Social anarchist strategies of direct action and spontaneity also formed the foundation of the black bloc tactic, which has become a staple of contemporary anarchism.[51] The social anarchist principle of prefiguration has also been shared by sections anti-state Marxism, particularly that of autonomism.[52]

In the contemporary era, anarcho-communism and anarcho-syndicalism are the dominant tendencies of social anarchism.[53]

Distinction from individualism edit

 
The social anarchist Murray Bookchin, who contrasted the tendency against individualist anarchism and claimed there to be an "unbridgeable chasm" that separated the two.

Social anarchism is commonly distinguished from individualist anarchism,[54] the latter of which favours individual sovereignty and property,[55] and can even oppose all forms of social organization altogether.[56] While individualists worry that social anarchism could lead to tyranny of the majority and forced collaboration, social anarchists criticise individualism for encouraging competition and atomizing individuals from each other.[57] Individualism was heavily criticised by classical social anarchists,[58] such as Bakunin and Kropotkin, who held that the liberty of a few individuals was potentially harmful to the equality of all mankind.[59]

However, this distinction is also contested,[60] as anarchism itself is often seen as a synthesis of liberal individualism and social egalitarianism.[61] Some social anarchists, such as Emma Goldman and Herbert Read, were even directly inspired by the individualist philosophy of Max Stirner.[62] Social anarchism generally attempts to reconcile individual freedoms with the freedom of others, in order to maximise the freedom of everyone and allow for individuality to flourish.[14] Individualists and social anarchists have even been able to cooperate by upholding "communal individuality", emphasising both individual freedom and community strength.[57] Some social anarchists have argued that the divisions between them and the individualists can be overcome, by emphasising their shared commitment to anti-capitalism and anti-authoritarianism.[63] But others draw the line at forms of individualism that uphold hierarchical power relations.[64]

In his 1995 book, Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism, Murray Bookchin defined social anarchism in contrast to what he called "lifestyle anarchism".[65] According to Bookchin, it was impossible for the two tendencies to coexist, claiming there to be an "unbridgeable chasm" that separated them from each other.[66] Bookchin held social anarchism to be the only genuine form of anarchism, considering individualism to be inherently oppressive.[67] But his separation of the two tendencies has been criticised and even rejected entirely by other anarchists.[68] His analysis has been criticised as "reductive" and "undialectical", due to his failure to recognise the many connections and interrelations between the two tendencies.[69]

Although sometimes considered a form of individualist anarchism,[70] anarcho-capitalism is typically rejected as a legitimate anarchist school of thought by social anarchists, who uphold anti-capitalism as a central principle.[71] The two have engaged in a contested debate over the term "libertarian", which was initially a synonym for the "left-libertarian" social anarchism but was later also claimed by "right-libertarian" anarcho-capitalists, with each rejecting the "libertarian" credentials of the other.[72] In contrast, social anarchists accept American individualist anarchists like Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner as genuine, due in part to their opposition to capitalism.[73] In turn, modern anti-capitalist individualists like Kevin Carson have drawn inspiration from social anarchism, while retaining their pro-market views.[74] Libertarian scholar Roderick T. Long has thus suggested that left-wing market anarchists could use their position to mediate between social anarchists and anarcho-capitalists, arguing for an ecumenical view of anarchism and libertarianism.[75]

Criticism edit

The social anarchist model for building socialism from the bottom-up was opposed by Marxists, who instead advocated for a "dictatorship of the proletariat".[76] Marxists considered social anarchism to be an ideology of the petite bourgeoisie and the lumpenproletariat, criticising it particularly for its anti-statism, which it considered to be a politically sectarian impulse.[77] Individualist anarchists such as David Morland have also criticised social anarchism as "incoherent", due to the disconnect between its "realistic" approach to human nature and its "optimistic" view of future anarchist societies.[78]

Post-structuralists have criticised social anarchism for its narrow analysis of power.[79] To the post-structuralist Todd May, power is irreducible and dispersed, arising from many different places.[80] Whereas social anarchists such as Mikhail Bakunin focus on the concentration of power within the hands of the ruling class or the bourgeoisie, which they hold to be the principal source of social issues.[81] Critical theorists have also criticised the social anarchist understanding of power for focusing too much on the state, without considering power dynamics inherent to racism, sexism and even some interpersonal relationships.[82]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Morland 2004, p. 26.
  2. ^ Adams 2001, p. 120; Franks 2018a, p. 557; Jun 2018, pp. 51–56; Marshall 2008, pp. 653–654; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13; Suissa 2001, pp. 629–630.
  3. ^ Jun 2018, pp. 51–56; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  4. ^ Franks 2018a, p. 554.
  5. ^ Marshall 2008, pp. 653–654.
  6. ^ Firth 2018, p. 495; Suissa 2001, pp. 637–638; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  7. ^ Adams 2001, p. 120; Firth 2018, p. 495; Suissa 2001, pp. 637–638; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  8. ^ Marshall 2008, pp. 655–656; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13; Suissa 2001, pp. 629–630; Thagard 2000, pp. 148–149.
  9. ^ Franks 2013, p. 390.
  10. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 24–25.
  11. ^ Busky 2000, p. 2.
  12. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 389–390; Jun 2018, p. 52; Long 2020, p. 28; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21.
  13. ^ Franks 2018a, pp. 557–558.
  14. ^ a b Marshall 2008, p. 651.
  15. ^ Jun 2018, p. 52.
  16. ^ Marshall 2008, p. 653.
  17. ^ a b Morland 2004, p. 25.
  18. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 25–26.
  19. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 23–24; Thagard 2000, pp. 148–149.
  20. ^ a b Franks 2013, p. 391.
  21. ^ Suissa 2001, p. 639.
  22. ^ Thagard 2000, pp. 150–152.
  23. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 23–24.
  24. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 23–24; Suissa 2001, pp. 630–631.
  25. ^ Morland 2004, p. 25; Suissa 2001, pp. 630–631.
  26. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 23–25; Suissa 2001, pp. 630–631.
  27. ^ Suissa 2001, pp. 630–631.
  28. ^ Franks 2018a, p. 551.
  29. ^ Franks 2018b, pp. 34–35.
  30. ^ Franks 2013, p. 390; Morland 2004, p. 26.
  31. ^ Franks 2013, p. 390; Morland 2004, pp. 25–26.
  32. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 390–391.
  33. ^ Morland 2004, p. 23.
  34. ^ Franks 2013, p. 400.
  35. ^ Franks 2013, p. 400; Morland 2004, p. 23.
  36. ^ McLaughlin 2007, p. 116.
  37. ^ Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, p. 6; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  38. ^ Adams 2001, pp. 120–121; Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, p. 7.
  39. ^ Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, p. 7.
  40. ^ Adams 2001, pp. 121–123; Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, pp. 7–8.
  41. ^ Adams 2001, pp. 123–124; Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, p. 8.
  42. ^ Adams 2001, pp. 125–126; Busky 2000, p. 5; Marshall 2008, pp. 8–9; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  43. ^ Adams 2001, p. 126; Marshall 2008, pp. 9–10; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  44. ^ Busky 2000, p. 6.
  45. ^ Adams 2001, pp. 124–125; Busky 2000, p. 6.
  46. ^ Suissa 2001, p. 638.
  47. ^ a b Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  48. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 30–31.
  49. ^ Busky 2000, pp. 5–6.
  50. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 397–398; Marshall 2008, pp. 692–693; Morland 2004, p. 23; Morris 2017, pp. 376–377.
  51. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 32–33.
  52. ^ Franks 2018b, p. 31.
  53. ^ Franks 2013, p. 394.
  54. ^ Busky 2000, p. 4; Franks 2013, pp. 386–388; Jun 2018, p. 51; Long 2020, p. 28; Marshall 2008, p. 6; McLaughlin 2007, pp. 17–21, 25–26, 116; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13; Suissa 2001, pp. 629–630.
  55. ^ Jun 2018, pp. 51–52; Long 2020, pp. 28–29; Marshall 2008, p. 10; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  56. ^ Busky 2000, p. 4.
  57. ^ a b Marshall 2008, p. 6.
  58. ^ Franks 2013, p. 388; Long 2020, p. 29; Suissa 2001, pp. 629–630.
  59. ^ Franks 2013, p. 388; Suissa 2001, pp. 629–630.
  60. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 386–388.
  61. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 386–388; Jun 2018, p. 52; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  62. ^ Marshall 2008, p. 221; McLaughlin 2007, pp. 162, 166–167.
  63. ^ Franks 2013, p. 393.
  64. ^ Franks 2013, pp. 393–394.
  65. ^ Davis 2018, pp. 51–52; Firth 2018, pp. 500–501; McLaughlin 2007, p. 165; Morland 2004, p. 24.
  66. ^ Davis 2018, p. 53; Marshall 2008, p. 694.
  67. ^ Franks 2013, p. 388.
  68. ^ Marshall 2008, pp. 692–693.
  69. ^ Davis 2018, pp. 53–54; Long 2020, p. 35.
  70. ^ Busky 2000, p. 4; Long 2020, pp. 30–31; Ostergaard 1991, p. 21; Ostergaard 2006, p. 13.
  71. ^ Davis 2018, p. 64; Franks 2013, p. 393; Franks 2018a, pp. 558–559; Long 2017, pp. 286–287; Long 2020, pp. 30–31; Marshall 2008, p. 650.
  72. ^ Long 2020, pp. 30–31.
  73. ^ Long 2017, pp. 287–290; Long 2020, pp. 31–33.
  74. ^ Long 2017, p. 292.
  75. ^ Long 2020, pp. 33–35.
  76. ^ Ostergaard 2006, pp. 13–14.
  77. ^ Ostergaard 1991, p. 22.
  78. ^ McLaughlin 2007, pp. 17–19.
  79. ^ Morland 2004, p. 27.
  80. ^ Morland 2004, pp. 27–28.
  81. ^ Morland 2004, p. 28.
  82. ^ Franks 2013, p. 397; Suissa 2001, pp. 640–641.

Bibliography edit

  • Adams, Ian (2001) [1993]. "Anarchism". Political Ideology Today (2nd ed.). Manchester University Press. pp. 120–126. ISBN 0-7190-6020-6.
  • Busky, Donald F. (2000). "Defining Democratic Socialism". Democratic Socialism: A Global Survey. Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 1–14. ISBN 978-0275968861.
  • Davis, Laurence (2018). "Individual and Community". In Adams, Matthew S.; Levy, Carl (eds.). The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 47–90. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-75620-2_3. ISBN 978-3319756196. S2CID 150149495.
  • Firth, Rhiannon (2018). "Utopianism and Intentional Communities" (PDF). In Adams, Matthew S.; Levy, Carl (eds.). The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 491–510. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-75620-2_28. ISBN 978-3319756196. S2CID 149636440.
  • Franks, Benjamin (August 2013). "Anarchism". In Freeden, Michael; Stears, Marc (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies. Oxford University Press. pp. 385–404. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199585977.013.0001.
  • Franks, Benjamin (2018a). "Anarchism and Ethics". In Adams, Matthew S.; Levy, Carl (eds.). The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 549–570. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-75620-2_31. ISBN 978-3319756196. S2CID 149845918.
  • Franks, Benjamin (2018b). "Prefiguration". In Franks, Benjamin; Jun, Nathan; Williams, Leonard (eds.). Anarchism: A Conceptual Approach. Routledge. pp. 28–43. ISBN 978-1-138-92565-6. LCCN 2017044519.
  • Harrell, Willie J. Jr. (2012). ""I am an Anarchist": The Social Anarchism of Lucy E. Parsons". Journal of International Women's Studies. 13 (1): 1–18. ISSN 1539-8706. OCLC 8093224507. Retrieved 21 June 2023.
  • Jun, Nathan (2018). "Freedom". In Franks, Benjamin; Jun, Nathan; Williams, Leonard (eds.). Anarchism: A Conceptual Approach. Routledge. pp. 44–59. ISBN 978-1-138-92565-6. LCCN 2017044519.
  • Long, Roderick T. (2017). "Anarchism and Libertarianism". In Jun, Nathan J. (ed.). Brill's Companion to Anarchism and Philosophy. Brill. pp. 285–317. doi:10.1163/9789004356894_012. ISBN 978-90-04-35689-4.
  • Long, Roderick T. (2020). "The Anarchist Landscape". In Chartier, Gary; Van Schoelandt, Chad (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought. New York: Routledge. pp. 28–38. doi:10.4324/9781315185255-2. ISBN 9781315185255. S2CID 228898569.
  • Marshall, Peter H. (2008) [1992]. Demanding the Impossible: A History of Anarchism. London: Harper Perennial. ISBN 978-0-00-686245-1. OCLC 218212571.
  • McLaughlin, Paul (2007). Anarchism and Authority: A Philosophical Introduction to Classical Anarchism. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-6196-2. LCCN 2007007973.
  • Morland, David (1997). Demanding the Impossible? Human Nature and Politics in Nineteenth-Century Social Anarchism. Cassell. ISBN 0-304-33685-8. LCCN 97-1672.
  • Morland, David (2004). "Anti-capitalism and poststructuralist anarchism". In Bowen, James; Purkis, Jon (eds.). Changing Anarchism: Anarchist Theory and Practice in a Global Age. Manchester University Press. pp. 23–38. ISBN 0-7190-6694-8.
  • Morris, Brian (2017). "Anarchism and Environmental Philosophy". In Jun, Nathan J. (ed.). Brill's Companion to Anarchism and Philosophy. Brill. pp. 369–400. doi:10.1163/9789004356894_015. ISBN 978-90-04-35689-4.
  • Ostergaard, Geoffrey (1991) [1983]. "Anarchism". In Bottomore, Tom (ed.). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought (2nd ed.). Blackwell Publishing. pp. 21–23. ISBN 0-631-16481-2. LCCN 91-17658.
  • Ostergaard, Geoffrey (2006) [1993]. "Anarchism". In Outhwaite, William (ed.). The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought (2 ed.). Blackwell Publishing. pp. 12–14. doi:10.1002/9780470999028.ch1. ISBN 9780470999028.
  • Spafford, Jesse (2020). "Social Anarchism and the Rejection of Private Property". In Chartier, Gary; Van Schoelandt, Chad (eds.). The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought. New York: Routledge. pp. 327–341. doi:10.4324/9781315185255-23. ISBN 9781315185255. S2CID 228898569.
  • Spafford, Jesse (October 2023). Social Anarchism and the Rejection of Moral Tyranny. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-00-937544-3.
  • Suissa, Judith (2001). "Anarchism, Utopias and Philosophy of Education". Journal of Philosophy of Education. 35 (4): 627–646. doi:10.1111/1467-9752.00249.
  • Thagard, Paul (2000). "Ethics and Politics". Coherence in Thought and Action. MIT Press. pp. 149–154. ISBN 0-262-20131-3. LCCN 00-035503.

Further reading edit

External links edit

  •   Media related to Social anarchism at Wikimedia Commons

social, anarchism, this, article, about, branch, anarchism, emphasizing, social, equality, libertarian, political, philosophy, within, socialist, movement, libertarian, socialism, also, known, left, wing, anarchism, socialist, anarchism, branch, anarchism, tha. This article is about the branch of anarchism emphasizing social equality For the libertarian political philosophy within the socialist movement see Libertarian socialism Social anarchism also known as left wing anarchism or socialist anarchism is the branch of anarchism that sees liberty and social equality as interrelated It advocates for a social revolution to remove oppressive forms of hierarchy such as capitalism and the state In their place social anarchists encourage social collaboration through mutual aid and envision non hierarchical forms of social organization such as voluntary associations Identified with the socialist tradition of Pierre Joseph Proudhon Mikhail Bakunin and Peter Kropotkin social anarchism is often contrasted with individualist anarchism due to the latter s criticism of socialism Contents 1 Political principles 1 1 Anti capitalism 1 2 Anti statism 1 3 Prefigurative politics 2 Schools of thought 3 Distinction from individualism 4 Criticism 5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 Further reading 9 External linksPolitical principles editSocial anarchism is opposed to all forms of social and political power hierarchy and oppression including but not limited to the State and capitalism 1 Social anarchism sees liberty as interconnected with social equality 2 and considers the maximization of one to be necessary for the maximization of the other 3 Social anarchism therefore employs a utilitarian ethics concerning itself with the well being of all as it considers each person s happiness to be equal to those of others 4 As such social anarchism seeks to guarantee equal rights to freedom and material security for all persons 5 Social anarchism envisions the overthrow of capitalism and the state in a social revolution 6 which would establish a federal society of voluntary associations and local communities 7 based on a network of mutual aid 8 The key principles that form the core of social anarchism include anti capitalism anti statism and prefigurative politics 9 Anti capitalism edit As an anti capitalist ideology social anarchism is opposed to the dominant expressions of capitalism including the expansion of transnational corporations through globalization 10 It comprises one of the main forms of socialism alongside utopian socialism democratic socialism and authoritarian socialism 11 Social anarchism rejects private property particularly private ownership of the means of production as the principal source of social inequality 12 As such social anarchists typically oppose propertarianism as they consider it to exacerbate social and economic inequality suppress individual agency and require the maintenance of hierarchical institutions 13 Social anarchists argue that the abolition of private property would lead to the development of new social mores encouraging mutual respect for individual freedom and the satisfaction of individual needs 14 Social anarchism therefore advocates the breaking up of monopolies and the institution of common ownership over the means of production 15 Instead of capitalist markets with their profit motives and wage systems social anarchism desires to organise production through a collective system of worker cooperatives agricultural communes and labour syndicates 16 While social anarchism has rejected the statism of Orthodox Marxism it has also drawn from Marxist critiques of capitalism particularly Marx s theory of alienation 17 Social anarchists have also been reluctant to adopt the Marxist centring of the proletariat as revolutionary agents instead identifying the revolutionary potential of the socially excluded segments of society 18 Anti statism edit As an anti statist ideology social anarchism opposes the concentration of power in the form of a State 19 To social anarchists the state is a type of coercive hierarchy designed to enforce private property and to limit individual self development 20 Social anarchists reject both centralised and limited forms of government instead upholding social collaboration as a means to achieve a spontaneous order without any social contract supplanting social relations 21 Social anarchists believe that the abolition of the state will lead to greater freedom flourishing and fairness 22 In the place of a state structure social anarchists desire anarchy which can be defined as a society without government 23 Social anarchists oppose the use of a state structure to achieve their goals of a stateless and classless society 24 as they consider statism to be an inherently corrupting influence 25 They thus have criticised the Marxist conception of the dictatorship of the proletariat which they consider to be elitist 26 and have rejected the possibility of a withering away of the state 27 However some social anarchists such as Noam Chomsky sometimes hold state hierarchy to be preferable to economic hierarchy and thus lend their support to welfare state programs like universal health care that can improve people s material conditions 20 Prefigurative politics edit Alongside its opposition to political and economic hierarchies social anarchism upholds prefigurative politics considering it necessary for the means to achieve anarchy be consistent with that end goal 28 Social anarchism prefigures itself through participatory and consensus decision making which are capable of generating the diversification of political values tactics and identities 29 Social anarchism therefore promotes self organization and the cultivation of a participatory culture encouraging individuals to do things for themselves 1 Social anarchism upholds direct action as a means for people to themselves resist oppression 30 without subordinating their own agency to democratic representatives or revolutionary vanguards 31 Social anarchists thus reject the political party model of organization 17 instead preferring forms of flat organization without any fixed leadership 32 Schools of thought edit nbsp Mikhail Bakunin founding figure of collectivist anarchism nbsp Peter Kropotkin founding figure of communist anarchism Characterised by its loose definition and ideological diversity 33 social anarchism has lent itself to syncretism both drawing from and influencing other ideological critiques of oppression 34 and giving way to a number of different anarchist schools of thought 35 While early forms of anarchism were largely individualistic the influence of Left Hegelianism infused anarchism with socialistic tendencies leading to the constitution of social anarchism 36 Over time the question of the economic makeup of a future anarchist society drove the development of social anarchist thought 37 The first school of social anarchism was formulated by Pierre Joseph Proudhon whose theory of mutualism retained a form of private property 38 advocating for enterprises to be self managed by worker cooperatives which would compensate its workers in labour vouchers issued by people s banks 39 This was later supplanted by Mikhail Bakunin s collectivist anarchism which advocated for the collective ownership of all property but retained a form of individual compensation 40 This finally led to the development of anarcho communism by Peter Kropotkin who considered that resources should be freely distributed from each according to their ability to each according to their needs without money or wages 41 Social anarchists also adopted the strategy of syndicalism which saw trade unions as the basis for a new socialist economy 42 with anarcho syndicalism growing to its greatest influence during the Spanish Revolution of 1936 43 The main division within social anarchism is over the means for achieving anarchy with philosophical anarchists advocating for peaceful persuasion 44 while insurrectionary anarchists advocated for propaganda of the deed 45 The former have upheld an anarchist form of education free from coercion and dogmatism in order to establish a self governing society 46 The latter have participated in rebellions in which they expropriated and collectivised property and replaced the state with a network of autonomous and federally linked communes 47 The aim was to build a socialist society without using the state from the bottom up 47 Principles of social anarchism such as decentralisation anti authoritarianism and mutual aid later held a key influence on the new social movements of the late 20th century 48 It was particularly influential within the New Left and green politics 49 with the green anarchist tendency of social ecology drawing directly from social anarchism 50 Social anarchist strategies of direct action and spontaneity also formed the foundation of the black bloc tactic which has become a staple of contemporary anarchism 51 The social anarchist principle of prefiguration has also been shared by sections anti state Marxism particularly that of autonomism 52 In the contemporary era anarcho communism and anarcho syndicalism are the dominant tendencies of social anarchism 53 Distinction from individualism edit nbsp The social anarchist Murray Bookchin who contrasted the tendency against individualist anarchism and claimed there to be an unbridgeable chasm that separated the two Social anarchism is commonly distinguished from individualist anarchism 54 the latter of which favours individual sovereignty and property 55 and can even oppose all forms of social organization altogether 56 While individualists worry that social anarchism could lead to tyranny of the majority and forced collaboration social anarchists criticise individualism for encouraging competition and atomizing individuals from each other 57 Individualism was heavily criticised by classical social anarchists 58 such as Bakunin and Kropotkin who held that the liberty of a few individuals was potentially harmful to the equality of all mankind 59 However this distinction is also contested 60 as anarchism itself is often seen as a synthesis of liberal individualism and social egalitarianism 61 Some social anarchists such as Emma Goldman and Herbert Read were even directly inspired by the individualist philosophy of Max Stirner 62 Social anarchism generally attempts to reconcile individual freedoms with the freedom of others in order to maximise the freedom of everyone and allow for individuality to flourish 14 Individualists and social anarchists have even been able to cooperate by upholding communal individuality emphasising both individual freedom and community strength 57 Some social anarchists have argued that the divisions between them and the individualists can be overcome by emphasising their shared commitment to anti capitalism and anti authoritarianism 63 But others draw the line at forms of individualism that uphold hierarchical power relations 64 In his 1995 book Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism Murray Bookchin defined social anarchism in contrast to what he called lifestyle anarchism 65 According to Bookchin it was impossible for the two tendencies to coexist claiming there to be an unbridgeable chasm that separated them from each other 66 Bookchin held social anarchism to be the only genuine form of anarchism considering individualism to be inherently oppressive 67 But his separation of the two tendencies has been criticised and even rejected entirely by other anarchists 68 His analysis has been criticised as reductive and undialectical due to his failure to recognise the many connections and interrelations between the two tendencies 69 Although sometimes considered a form of individualist anarchism 70 anarcho capitalism is typically rejected as a legitimate anarchist school of thought by social anarchists who uphold anti capitalism as a central principle 71 The two have engaged in a contested debate over the term libertarian which was initially a synonym for the left libertarian social anarchism but was later also claimed by right libertarian anarcho capitalists with each rejecting the libertarian credentials of the other 72 In contrast social anarchists accept American individualist anarchists like Benjamin Tucker and Lysander Spooner as genuine due in part to their opposition to capitalism 73 In turn modern anti capitalist individualists like Kevin Carson have drawn inspiration from social anarchism while retaining their pro market views 74 Libertarian scholar Roderick T Long has thus suggested that left wing market anarchists could use their position to mediate between social anarchists and anarcho capitalists arguing for an ecumenical view of anarchism and libertarianism 75 Criticism editThe social anarchist model for building socialism from the bottom up was opposed by Marxists who instead advocated for a dictatorship of the proletariat 76 Marxists considered social anarchism to be an ideology of the petite bourgeoisie and the lumpenproletariat criticising it particularly for its anti statism which it considered to be a politically sectarian impulse 77 Individualist anarchists such as David Morland have also criticised social anarchism as incoherent due to the disconnect between its realistic approach to human nature and its optimistic view of future anarchist societies 78 Post structuralists have criticised social anarchism for its narrow analysis of power 79 To the post structuralist Todd May power is irreducible and dispersed arising from many different places 80 Whereas social anarchists such as Mikhail Bakunin focus on the concentration of power within the hands of the ruling class or the bourgeoisie which they hold to be the principal source of social issues 81 Critical theorists have also criticised the social anarchist understanding of power for focusing too much on the state without considering power dynamics inherent to racism sexism and even some interpersonal relationships 82 See also editSocial anarchists category References edit a b Morland 2004 p 26 Adams 2001 p 120 Franks 2018a p 557 Jun 2018 pp 51 56 Marshall 2008 pp 653 654 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Suissa 2001 pp 629 630 Jun 2018 pp 51 56 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Franks 2018a p 554 Marshall 2008 pp 653 654 Firth 2018 p 495 Suissa 2001 pp 637 638 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Adams 2001 p 120 Firth 2018 p 495 Suissa 2001 pp 637 638 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Marshall 2008 pp 655 656 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Suissa 2001 pp 629 630 Thagard 2000 pp 148 149 Franks 2013 p 390 Morland 2004 pp 24 25 Busky 2000 p 2 Franks 2013 pp 389 390 Jun 2018 p 52 Long 2020 p 28 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Franks 2018a pp 557 558 a b Marshall 2008 p 651 Jun 2018 p 52 Marshall 2008 p 653 a b Morland 2004 p 25 Morland 2004 pp 25 26 Morland 2004 pp 23 24 Thagard 2000 pp 148 149 a b Franks 2013 p 391 Suissa 2001 p 639 Thagard 2000 pp 150 152 Morland 2004 pp 23 24 Morland 2004 pp 23 24 Suissa 2001 pp 630 631 Morland 2004 p 25 Suissa 2001 pp 630 631 Morland 2004 pp 23 25 Suissa 2001 pp 630 631 Suissa 2001 pp 630 631 Franks 2018a p 551 Franks 2018b pp 34 35 Franks 2013 p 390 Morland 2004 p 26 Franks 2013 p 390 Morland 2004 pp 25 26 Franks 2013 pp 390 391 Morland 2004 p 23 Franks 2013 p 400 Franks 2013 p 400 Morland 2004 p 23 McLaughlin 2007 p 116 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 p 6 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Adams 2001 pp 120 121 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 p 7 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 p 7 Adams 2001 pp 121 123 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 pp 7 8 Adams 2001 pp 123 124 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 p 8 Adams 2001 pp 125 126 Busky 2000 p 5 Marshall 2008 pp 8 9 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Adams 2001 p 126 Marshall 2008 pp 9 10 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Busky 2000 p 6 Adams 2001 pp 124 125 Busky 2000 p 6 Suissa 2001 p 638 a b Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Morland 2004 pp 30 31 Busky 2000 pp 5 6 Franks 2013 pp 397 398 Marshall 2008 pp 692 693 Morland 2004 p 23 Morris 2017 pp 376 377 Morland 2004 pp 32 33 Franks 2018b p 31 Franks 2013 p 394 Busky 2000 p 4 Franks 2013 pp 386 388 Jun 2018 p 51 Long 2020 p 28 Marshall 2008 p 6 McLaughlin 2007 pp 17 21 25 26 116 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Suissa 2001 pp 629 630 Jun 2018 pp 51 52 Long 2020 pp 28 29 Marshall 2008 p 10 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Busky 2000 p 4 a b Marshall 2008 p 6 Franks 2013 p 388 Long 2020 p 29 Suissa 2001 pp 629 630 Franks 2013 p 388 Suissa 2001 pp 629 630 Franks 2013 pp 386 388 Franks 2013 pp 386 388 Jun 2018 p 52 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Marshall 2008 p 221 McLaughlin 2007 pp 162 166 167 Franks 2013 p 393 Franks 2013 pp 393 394 Davis 2018 pp 51 52 Firth 2018 pp 500 501 McLaughlin 2007 p 165 Morland 2004 p 24 Davis 2018 p 53 Marshall 2008 p 694 Franks 2013 p 388 Marshall 2008 pp 692 693 Davis 2018 pp 53 54 Long 2020 p 35 Busky 2000 p 4 Long 2020 pp 30 31 Ostergaard 1991 p 21 Ostergaard 2006 p 13 Davis 2018 p 64 Franks 2013 p 393 Franks 2018a pp 558 559 Long 2017 pp 286 287 Long 2020 pp 30 31 Marshall 2008 p 650 Long 2020 pp 30 31 Long 2017 pp 287 290 Long 2020 pp 31 33 Long 2017 p 292 Long 2020 pp 33 35 Ostergaard 2006 pp 13 14 Ostergaard 1991 p 22 McLaughlin 2007 pp 17 19 Morland 2004 p 27 Morland 2004 pp 27 28 Morland 2004 p 28 Franks 2013 p 397 Suissa 2001 pp 640 641 Bibliography editAdams Ian 2001 1993 Anarchism Political Ideology Today 2nd ed Manchester University Press pp 120 126 ISBN 0 7190 6020 6 Busky Donald F 2000 Defining Democratic Socialism Democratic Socialism A Global Survey Greenwood Publishing Group pp 1 14 ISBN 978 0275968861 Davis Laurence 2018 Individual and Community In Adams Matthew S Levy Carl eds The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism London Palgrave Macmillan pp 47 90 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 75620 2 3 ISBN 978 3319756196 S2CID 150149495 Firth Rhiannon 2018 Utopianism and Intentional Communities PDF In Adams Matthew S Levy Carl eds The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism London Palgrave Macmillan pp 491 510 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 75620 2 28 ISBN 978 3319756196 S2CID 149636440 Franks Benjamin August 2013 Anarchism In Freeden Michael Stears Marc eds The Oxford Handbook of Political Ideologies Oxford University Press pp 385 404 doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780199585977 013 0001 Franks Benjamin 2018a Anarchism and Ethics In Adams Matthew S Levy Carl eds The Palgrave Handbook of Anarchism London Palgrave Macmillan pp 549 570 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 75620 2 31 ISBN 978 3319756196 S2CID 149845918 Franks Benjamin 2018b Prefiguration In Franks Benjamin Jun Nathan Williams Leonard eds Anarchism A Conceptual Approach Routledge pp 28 43 ISBN 978 1 138 92565 6 LCCN 2017044519 Harrell Willie J Jr 2012 I am an Anarchist The Social Anarchism of Lucy E Parsons Journal of International Women s Studies 13 1 1 18 ISSN 1539 8706 OCLC 8093224507 Retrieved 21 June 2023 Jun Nathan 2018 Freedom In Franks Benjamin Jun Nathan Williams Leonard eds Anarchism A Conceptual Approach Routledge pp 44 59 ISBN 978 1 138 92565 6 LCCN 2017044519 Long Roderick T 2017 Anarchism and Libertarianism In Jun Nathan J ed Brill s Companion to Anarchism and Philosophy Brill pp 285 317 doi 10 1163 9789004356894 012 ISBN 978 90 04 35689 4 Long Roderick T 2020 The Anarchist Landscape In Chartier Gary Van Schoelandt Chad eds The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought New York Routledge pp 28 38 doi 10 4324 9781315185255 2 ISBN 9781315185255 S2CID 228898569 Marshall Peter H 2008 1992 Demanding the Impossible A History of Anarchism London Harper Perennial ISBN 978 0 00 686245 1 OCLC 218212571 McLaughlin Paul 2007 Anarchism and Authority A Philosophical Introduction to Classical Anarchism Aldershot Ashgate Publishing ISBN 978 0 7546 6196 2 LCCN 2007007973 Morland David 1997 Demanding the Impossible Human Nature and Politics in Nineteenth Century Social Anarchism Cassell ISBN 0 304 33685 8 LCCN 97 1672 Morland David 2004 Anti capitalism and poststructuralist anarchism In Bowen James Purkis Jon eds Changing Anarchism Anarchist Theory and Practice in a Global Age Manchester University Press pp 23 38 ISBN 0 7190 6694 8 Morris Brian 2017 Anarchism and Environmental Philosophy In Jun Nathan J ed Brill s Companion to Anarchism and Philosophy Brill pp 369 400 doi 10 1163 9789004356894 015 ISBN 978 90 04 35689 4 Ostergaard Geoffrey 1991 1983 Anarchism In Bottomore Tom ed A Dictionary of Marxist Thought 2nd ed Blackwell Publishing pp 21 23 ISBN 0 631 16481 2 LCCN 91 17658 Ostergaard Geoffrey 2006 1993 Anarchism In Outhwaite William ed The Blackwell Dictionary of Modern Social Thought 2 ed Blackwell Publishing pp 12 14 doi 10 1002 9780470999028 ch1 ISBN 9780470999028 Spafford Jesse 2020 Social Anarchism and the Rejection of Private Property In Chartier Gary Van Schoelandt Chad eds The Routledge Handbook of Anarchy and Anarchist Thought New York Routledge pp 327 341 doi 10 4324 9781315185255 23 ISBN 9781315185255 S2CID 228898569 Spafford Jesse October 2023 Social Anarchism and the Rejection of Moral Tyranny Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 00 937544 3 Suissa Judith 2001 Anarchism Utopias and Philosophy of Education Journal of Philosophy of Education 35 4 627 646 doi 10 1111 1467 9752 00249 Thagard Paul 2000 Ethics and Politics Coherence in Thought and Action MIT Press pp 149 154 ISBN 0 262 20131 3 LCCN 00 035503 Further reading editBaldelli Giovanni 2010 1971 Social Anarchism Transaction Publishers ISBN 978 0 202 36339 4 LCCN 2009030191 Retrieved 31 March 2019 Bookchin Murray 1995 Social Anarchism or Lifestyle Anarchism An Unbridgeable Chasm AK Press Shantz Jeff 2013 Introduction In Ehrlich Howard J ed The Best of Social Anarchism Tucson Arizona See Sharp Press ISBN 9781937276461 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Social anarchism nbsp Media related to Social anarchism at Wikimedia Commons Portals nbsp Anarchism nbsp Liberalism nbsp Libertarianism nbsp Politics nbsp Socialism Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Social anarchism amp oldid 1220851831, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.