fbpx
Wikipedia

Enactivism

Enactivism is a position in cognitive science that argues that cognition arises through a dynamic interaction between an acting organism and its environment.[1] It claims that the environment of an organism is brought about, or enacted, by the active exercise of that organism's sensorimotor processes. "The key point, then, is that the species brings forth and specifies its own domain of problems ...this domain does not exist "out there" in an environment that acts as a landing pad for organisms that somehow drop or parachute into the world. Instead, living beings and their environments stand in relation to each other through mutual specification or codetermination" (p. 198).[2] "Organisms do not passively receive information from their environments, which they then translate into internal representations. Natural cognitive systems...participate in the generation of meaning ...engaging in transformational and not merely informational interactions: they enact a world."[3] These authors suggest that the increasing emphasis upon enactive terminology presages a new era in thinking about cognitive science.[3] How the actions involved in enactivism relate to age-old questions about free will remains a topic of active debate.[4]

The term 'enactivism' is close in meaning to 'enaction', defined as "the manner in which a subject of perception creatively matches its actions to the requirements of its situation".[5] The introduction of the term enaction in this context is attributed to Francisco Varela, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch in The Embodied Mind (1991),[5][6] who proposed the name to "emphasize the growing conviction that cognition is not the representation of a pre-given world by a pre-given mind but is rather the enactment of a world and a mind on the basis of a history of the variety of actions that a being in the world performs".[2] This was further developed by Thompson and others,[1] to place emphasis upon the idea that experience of the world is a result of mutual interaction between the sensorimotor capacities of the organism and its environment.[6] However, some writers maintain that there remains a need for some degree of the mediating function of representation in this new approach to the science of the mind.[7]

The initial emphasis of enactivism upon sensorimotor skills has been criticized as "cognitively marginal",[8] but it has been extended to apply to higher level cognitive activities, such as social interactions.[3] "In the enactive view,... knowledge is constructed: it is constructed by an agent through its sensorimotor interactions with its environment, co-constructed between and within living species through their meaningful interaction with each other. In its most abstract form, knowledge is co-constructed between human individuals in socio-linguistic interactions...Science is a particular form of social knowledge construction...[that] allows us to perceive and predict events beyond our immediate cognitive grasp...and also to construct further, even more powerful scientific knowledge."[9]

Enactivism is closely related to situated cognition and embodied cognition, and is presented as an alternative to cognitivism, computationalism, and Cartesian dualism.

Philosophical aspects edit

Enactivism is one of a cluster of related theories sometimes known as the 4Es.[10] As described by Mark Rowlands, mental processes are:

  • Embodied involving more than the brain, including a more general involvement of bodily structures and processes.
  • Embedded functioning only in a related external environment.
  • Enacted involving not only neural processes, but also things an organism does.
  • Extended into the organism's environment.

Enactivism proposes an alternative to dualism as a philosophy of mind, in that it emphasises the interactions between mind, body and the environment, seeing them all as inseparably intertwined in mental processes.[11] The self arises as part of the process of an embodied entity interacting with the environment in precise ways determined by its physiology. In this sense, individuals can be seen to "grow into" or arise from their interactive role with the world.[12]

"Enaction is the idea that organisms create their own experience through their actions. Organisms are not passive receivers of input from the environment, but are actors in the environment such that what they experience is shaped by how they act."[13]

In The Tree of Knowledge Maturana & Varela proposed the term enactive[14] "to evoke the view of knowledge that what is known is brought forth, in contraposition to the more classical views of either cognitivism[Note 1] or connectionism.[Note 2] They see enactivism as providing a middle ground between the two extremes of representationalism and solipsism. They seek to "confront the problem of understanding how our existence-the praxis of our living- is coupled to a surrounding world which appears filled with regularities that are at every instant the result of our biological and social histories.... to find a via media: to understand the regularity of the world we are experiencing at every moment, but without any point of reference independent of ourselves that would give certainty to our descriptions and cognitive assertions. Indeed the whole mechanism of generating ourselves, as describers and observers tells us that our world, as the world which we bring forth in our coexistence with others, will always have precisely that mixture of regularity and mutability, that combination of solidity and shifting sand, so typical of human experience when we look at it up close."[Tree of Knowledge, p. 241] Another important notion relating to enactivism is autopoiesis. The word refers to a system that is able to reproduce and maintain itself. Maturana & Varela describe that "This was a word without a history, a word that could directly mean what takes place in the dynamics of the autonomy proper to living systems"[15] Using the term autopoiesis, they argue that any closed system that has autonomy, self-reference and self-construction (or, that has autopoietic activities) has cognitive capacities. Therefore, cognition is present in all living systems.[15] This view is also called autopoietic enactivism.

Radical enactivism is another form of enactivist view of cognition. Radical enactivists often adopt a thoroughly non-representational, enactive account of basic cognition. Basic cognitive capacities mentioned by Hutto and Myin include perceiving, imagining and remembering.[16][17] They argue that those forms of basic cognition can be explained without positing mental representations. With regard to complex forms of cognition such as language, they think mental representations are needed, because there needs explanations of content. In human being's public practices, they claim that "such intersubjective practices and sensitivity to the relevant norms comes with the mastery of the use of public symbol systems" (2017, p. 120), and so "as it happens, this appears only to have occurred in full form with construction of sociocultural cognitive niches in the human lineage" (2017, p. 134).[16] They conclude that basic cognition as well as cognition in simple organisms such as bacteria are best characterized as non-representational.[18][16][17]

Enactivism also addresses the hard problem of consciousness, referred to by Thompson as part of the explanatory gap in explaining how consciousness and subjective experience are related to brain and body.[19] "The problem with the dualistic concepts of consciousness and life in standard formulations of the hard problem is that they exclude each other by construction".[20] Instead, according to Thompson's view of enactivism, the study of consciousness or phenomenology as exemplified by Husserl and Merleau-Ponty is to complement science and its objectification of the world. "The whole universe of science is built upon the world as directly experienced, and if we want to subject science itself to rigorous scrutiny and arrive at a precise assessment of its meaning and scope, we must begin by reawakening the basic experience of the world of which science is the second-order expression" (Merleau-Ponty, The phenomenology of perception as quoted by Thompson, p. 165). In this interpretation, enactivism asserts that science is formed or enacted as part of humankind's interactivity with its world, and by embracing phenomenology "science itself is properly situated in relation to the rest of human life and is thereby secured on a sounder footing."[21][22]

Enaction has been seen as a move to conjoin representationalism with phenomenalism, that is, as adopting a constructivist epistemology, an epistemology centered upon the active participation of the subject in constructing reality.[23][24] However, 'constructivism' focuses upon more than a simple 'interactivity' that could be described as a minor adjustment to 'assimilate' reality or 'accommodate' to it.[25] Constructivism looks upon interactivity as a radical, creative, revisionist process in which the knower constructs a personal 'knowledge system' based upon their experience and tested by its viability in practical encounters with their environment. Learning is a result of perceived anomalies that produce dissatisfaction with existing conceptions.[26]

Shaun Gallagher also points out that pragmatism is a forerunner of enactive and extended approaches to cognition.[27] According to him, enactive conceptions of cognition can be found in many pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce and John Dewey. For example, Dewey says that "The brain is essentially an organ for effecting the reciprocal adjustment to each other of the stimuli received from the environment and responses directed upon it" (1916, pp. 336–337).[28] This view is fully consistent with enactivist arguments that cognition is not just a matter of brain processes and brain is one part of the body consisting of the dynamical regulation.[27][29] Robert Brandom, a neo-pragmatist, comments that "A founding idea of pragmatism is that the most fundamental kind of intentionality (in the sense of directedness towards objects) is the practical involvement with objects exhibited by a sentient creature dealing skillfully with its world" (2008, p. 178).[30]

How does constructivism relate to enactivism? From the above remarks it can be seen that Glasersfeld expresses an interactivity between the knower and the known quite acceptable to an enactivist, but does not emphasize the structured probing of the environment by the knower that leads to the "perturbation relative to some expected result" that then leads to a new understanding.[26] It is this probing activity, especially where it is not accidental but deliberate, that characterizes enaction, and invokes affect,[31] that is, the motivation and planning that lead to doing and to fashioning the probing, both observing and modifying the environment, so that "perceptions and nature condition one another through generating one another."[32] The questioning nature of this probing activity is not an emphasis of Piaget and Glasersfeld.

Sharing enactivism's stress upon both action and embodiment in the incorporation of knowledge, but giving Glasersfeld's mechanism of viability an evolutionary emphasis,[33] is evolutionary epistemology. Inasmuch as an organism must reflect its environment well enough for the organism to be able to survive in it, and to be competitive enough to be able to reproduce at sustainable rate, the structure and reflexes of the organism itself embody knowledge of its environment. This biology-inspired theory of the growth of knowledge is closely tied to universal Darwinism, and is associated with evolutionary epistemologists such as Karl Popper, Donald T. Campbell, Peter Munz, and Gary Cziko.[34] According to Munz, "an organism is an embodied theory about its environment... Embodied theories are also no longer expressed in language, but in anatomical structures or reflex responses, etc."[34][35]

One objection to enactive approaches to cognition is the so-called "scale-up objection". According to this objection, enactive theories only have limited value because they cannot "scale up" to explain more complex cognitive capacities like human thoughts. Those phenomena are extremely difficult to explain without positing representation.[36] But recently, some philosophers are trying to respond to such objection. For example, Adrian Downey (2020) provides a non-representational account of Obsessive-compulsive disorder, and then argues that ecological-enactive approaches can respond to the "scaling up" objection.[37]

Psychological aspects edit

McGann & others[38] argue that enactivism attempts to mediate between the explanatory role of the coupling between cognitive agent and environment and the traditional emphasis on brain mechanisms found in neuroscience and psychology. In the interactive approach to social cognition developed by De Jaegher & others,[39][40][41] the dynamics of interactive processes are seen to play significant roles in coordinating interpersonal understanding, processes that in part include what they call participatory sense-making.[42][43] Recent developments of enactivism in the area of social neuroscience involve the proposal of The Interactive Brain Hypothesis[44] where social cognition brain mechanisms, even those used in non-interactive situations, are proposed to have interactive origins.

Enactive views of perception edit

In the enactive view, perception "is not conceived as the transmission of information but more as an exploration of the world by various means. Cognition is not tied into the workings of an 'inner mind', some cognitive core, but occurs in directed interaction between the body and the world it inhabits."[45]

Alva Noë in advocating an enactive view of perception[46] sought to resolve how we perceive three-dimensional objects, on the basis of two-dimensional input. He argues that we perceive this solidity (or 'volumetricity') by appealing to patterns of sensorimotor expectations. These arise from our agent-active 'movements and interaction' with objects, or 'object-active' changes in the object itself. The solidity is perceived through our expectations and skills in knowing how the object's appearance would change with changes in how we relate to it. He saw all perception as an active exploration of the world, rather than being a passive process, something which happens to us.

Noë's idea of the role of 'expectations' in three-dimensional perception has been opposed by several philosophers, notably by Andy Clark.[47] Clark points to difficulties of the enactive approach. He points to internal processing of visual signals, for example, in the ventral and dorsal pathways, the two-streams hypothesis. This results in an integrated perception of objects (their recognition and location, respectively) yet this processing cannot be described as an action or actions. In a more general criticism, Clark suggests that perception is not a matter of expectations about sensorimotor mechanisms guiding perception. Rather, although the limitations of sensorimotor mechanisms constrain perception, this sensorimotor activity is drastically filtered to fit current needs and purposes of the organism, and it is these imposed 'expectations' that govern perception, filtering for the 'relevant' details of sensorimotor input (called "sensorimotor summarizing").[47]

These sensorimotor-centered and purpose-centered views appear to agree on the general scheme but disagree on the dominance issue – is the dominant component peripheral or central. Another view, the closed-loop perception one, assigns equal a-priori dominance to the peripheral and central components. In closed-loop perception, perception emerges through the process of inclusion of an item in a motor-sensory-motor loop, i.e., a loop (or loops) connecting the peripheral and central components that are relevant to that item.[48] The item can be a body part (in which case the loops are in steady-state) or an external object (in which case the loops are perturbed and gradually converge to a steady state). These enactive loops are always active, switching dominance by the need.

Another application of enaction to perception is analysis of the human hand. The many remarkably demanding uses of the hand are not learned by instruction, but through a history of engagements that lead to the acquisition of skills. According to one interpretation, it is suggested that "the hand [is]...an organ of cognition", not a faithful subordinate working under top-down instruction, but a partner in a "bi-directional interplay between manual and brain activity."[49] According to Daniel Hutto: "Enactivists are concerned to defend the view that our most elementary ways of engaging with the world and others - including our basic forms of perception and perceptual experience - are mindful in the sense of being phenomenally charged and intentionally directed, despite being non-representational and content-free."[50] Hutto calls this position 'REC' (Radical Enactive Cognition): "According to REC, there is no way to distinguish neural activity that is imagined to be genuinely content involving (and thus truly mental, truly cognitive) from other non-neural activity that merely plays a supporting or enabling role in making mind and cognition possible."[50]

Participatory sense-making edit

Hanne De Jaegher and Ezequiel Di Paolo (2007)[42] have extended the enactive concept of sense-making[20] into the social domain. The idea takes as its departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter.[51] De Jaegher and Di Paolo argue that the interaction process itself can take on a form of autonomy (operationally defined). This allows them to define social cognition as the generation of meaning and its transformation through interacting individuals.

The notion of participatory sense-making has led to the proposal that interaction processes can sometimes play constitutive roles in social cognition (De Jaegher, Di Paolo, Gallagher, 2010).[43] It has been applied to research in social neuroscience[44][52] and autism.[53]

In a similar vein, "an inter-enactive approach to agency holds that the behavior of agents in a social situation unfolds not only according to their individual abilities and goals, but also according to the conditions and constraints imposed by the autonomous dynamics of the interaction process itself".[54] According to Torrance, enactivism involves five interlocking themes related to the question "What is it to be a (cognizing, conscious) agent?" It is:[54]

1. to be a biologically autonomous (autopoietic) organism
2. to generate significance or meaning, rather than to act via...updated internal representations of the external world
3. to engage in sense-making via dynamic coupling with the environment
4. to 'enact' or 'bring forth' a world of significances by mutual co-determination of the organism with its enacted world
5. to arrive at an experiential awareness via lived embodiment in the world.

Torrance adds that "many kinds of agency, in particular the agency of human beings, cannot be understood separately from understanding the nature of the interaction that occurs between agents." That view introduces the social applications of enactivism. "Social cognition is regarded as the result of a special form of action, namely social interaction...the enactive approach looks at the circular dynamic within a dyad of embodied agents."[55]

In cultural psychology, enactivism is seen as a way to uncover cultural influences upon feeling, thinking and acting.[56] Baerveldt and Verheggen argue that "It appears that seemingly natural experience is thoroughly intertwined with sociocultural realities." They suggest that the social patterning of experience is to be understood through enactivism, "the idea that the reality we have in common, and in which we find ourselves, is neither a world that exists independently from us, nor a socially shared way of representing such a pregiven world, but a world itself brought forth by our ways of communicating and our joint action....The world we inhabit is manufactured of 'meaning' rather than 'information'.[57]

Luhmann attempted to apply Maturana and Varela's notion of autopoiesis to social systems.[58] "A core concept of social systems theory is derived from biological systems theory: the concept of autopoiesis. Chilean biologist Humberto Maturana come up with the concept to explain how biological systems such as cells are a product of their own production." "Systems exist by way of operational closure and this means that they each construct themselves and their own realities."[59]

Educational aspects edit

The first definition of enaction was introduced by psychologist Jerome Bruner,[60][61] who introduced enaction as 'learning by doing' in his discussion of how children learn, and how they can best be helped to learn.[62][63] He associated enaction with two other ways of knowledge organization: Iconic and Symbolic.[64]

"Any domain of knowledge (or any problem within that domain of knowledge) can be represented in three ways: by a set of actions appropriate for achieving a certain result (enactive representation); by a set of summary images or graphics that stand for a concept without defining it fully (iconic representation); and by a set of symbolic or logical propositions drawn from a symbolic system that is governed by rules or laws for forming and transforming propositions (symbolic representation)"

The term 'enactive framework' was elaborated upon by Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana.[65]

Sriramen argues that enactivism provides "a rich and powerful explanatory theory for learning and being."[66] and that it is closely related to both the ideas of cognitive development of Piaget, and also the social constructivism of Vygotsky.[66] Piaget focused on the child's immediate environment, and suggested cognitive structures like spatial perception emerge as a result of the child's interaction with the world.[67] According to Piaget, children construct knowledge, using what they know in new ways and testing it, and the environment provides feedback concerning the adequacy of their construction.[68] In a cultural context, Vygotsky suggested that the kind of cognition that can take place is not dictated by the engagement of the isolated child, but is also a function of social interaction and dialogue that is contingent upon a sociohistorical context.[69] Enactivism in educational theory "looks at each learning situation as a complex system consisting of teacher, learner, and context, all of which frame and co-create the learning situation."[70] Enactivism in education is very closely related to situated cognition,[71] which holds that "knowledge is situated, being in part a product of the activity, context, and culture in which it is developed and used."[72] This approach challenges the "separating of what is learned from how it is learned and used."[72]

Artificial intelligence aspects edit

The ideas of enactivism regarding how organisms engage with their environment have interested those involved in robotics and man-machine interfaces. The analogy is drawn that a robot can be designed to interact and learn from its environment in a manner similar to the way an organism does,[73] and a human can interact with a computer-aided design tool or data base using an interface that creates an enactive environment for the user, that is, all the user's tactile, auditory, and visual capabilities are enlisted in a mutually explorative engagement, capitalizing upon all the user's abilities, and not at all limited to cerebral engagement.[74] In these areas it is common to refer to affordances as a design concept, the idea that an environment or an interface affords opportunities for enaction, and good design involves optimizing the role of such affordances.[75][76][77][78][79]

The activity in the AI community has influenced enactivism as a whole. Referring extensively to modeling techniques for evolutionary robotics by Beer,[80] the modeling of learning behavior by Kelso,[81] and to modeling of sensorimotor activity by Saltzman,[82] McGann, De Jaegher, and Di Paolo discuss how this work makes the dynamics of coupling between an agent and its environment, the foundation of enactivism, "an operational, empirically observable phenomenon."[83] That is, the AI environment invents examples of enactivism using concrete examples that, although not as complex as living organisms, isolate and illuminate basic principles.

Mathematical formalisms edit

Enactive cognition has been formalised in order to address subjectivity in artificial general intelligence.

A mathematical formalism of AGI is an agent proven to maximise a measure of intelligence.[84] Prior to 2022, the only such formalism was AIXI, which maximised “the ability to satisfy goals in a wide range of environments”.[85] In 2015 Jan Lieke and Marcus Hutter showed that "Legg-Hutter intelligence is measured with respect to a fixed UTM. AIXI is the most intelligent policy if it uses the same UTM", a result which "undermines all existing optimality properties for AIXI", rendering them subjective.[86]

Criticism edit

One of the essential theses of this approach is that biological systems generate meanings, engaging in transformational and not merely informational interactions.[3] Since this thesis raised the problems of beginning cognition for organisms in the developmental stage of only simple reflexes (the binding problem and the problem of primary data entry[87][88]), enactivists proposed the concept of embodied information that serves to start cognition.[1] However, critics highlight that this idea requires introducing the nature of intentionality before engaging embodied information.[89] In a natural environment, the stimulus-reaction pair (causation) is unpredictable due to many irrelevant stimuli claiming to be randomly associated with the embodied information.[89] While embodied information is only beneficial when intentionality is already in place, enactivists introduced the notion of the generation of meanings by biological systems (engaging in transformational interactions) without introducing a neurophysiological basis of intentionality.[89]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b c Evan Thompson (2010). "Chapter 1: The enactive approach" (PDF). Mind in life:Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674057517. ToC, first 65 pages, and index found here.
  2. ^ a b Francisco J Varela; Evan Thompson; Eleanor Rosch (1992). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press. p. 9. ISBN 978-0262261234.
  3. ^ a b c d Ezequiel A Di Paolo; Marieke Rhohde; Hanne De Jaegher (2014). "Horizons for the enactive mind: Values, social interaction, and play". In John Stewart; Oliver Gapenne; Ezequiel A Di Paolo (eds.). Enaction: Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science. MIT Press. pp. 33 ff. ISBN 978-0262526012.
  4. ^ A collection of papers on this topic is introduced by Duccio Manetti; Silvano Zipoli Caiani (January 2011). (PDF). Humana Mente. 15: VXIII. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-04-09. Retrieved 2014-05-07.
  5. ^ a b John Protevi, ed. (2006). "Enaction". A Dictionary of Continental Philosophy. Yale University Press. pp. 169–170. ISBN 9780300116052.
  6. ^ a b Robert A Wilson; Lucia Foglia (25 July 2011). "Embodied Cognition: §2.2 Enactive cognition". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2017 Edition).
  7. ^ Mark Rowlands (2010). "Chapter 3: The mind embedded §5 The mind enacted". The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. MIT Press. pp. 70 ff. ISBN 978-0262014557. Rowlands attributes this idea to D M MacKay (1967). "Ways of looking at perception". In W Watthen-Dunn (ed.). Models for the perception of speech and visual form (Proceedings of a symposium). MIT Press. pp. 25 ff. ISBN 9780262230261.
  8. ^ Andy Clark; Josefa Toribio (1994). "Doing without representing" (PDF). Synthese. 101 (3): 401–434. doi:10.1007/bf01063896. hdl:1842/1301. S2CID 17136030.
  9. ^ Marieke Rohde (2010). "§3.1 The scientist as observing subject". Enaction, Embodiment, Evolutionary Robotics: Simulation Models for a Post-Cognitivist Science of Mind. Atlantis Press. pp. 30 ff. ISBN 978-9078677239.
  10. ^ Mark Rowlands (2010, p. 3) attributes the term 4Es to Shaun Gallagher.
  11. ^ Evan Thompson (2007). "The enactive approach". Mind in life (Paperback ed.). Harvard University Press. pp. 13 ff. ISBN 978-0674057517. ToC, first 65 pages, and index found here
  12. ^ Jeremy Trevelyan Burman (2006). (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 13 (12): 115–124. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2007-09-27. Retrieved 2006-12-30. From a review of Ralph D. Ellis; Natika Newton, eds. (2005). Consciousness & Emotion: Agency, conscious choice, and selective perception. John Benjamins Publishing. ISBN 9789027294616.
  13. ^ Edwin Hutchins (1996). Cognition in the Wild. MIT Press. p. 428. ISBN 9780262581462. Quoted by Marcio Rocha (2011). (PDF). Transtechnology Research Reader. ISBN 978-0-9538332-2-1. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-05-24. Retrieved 2014-05-23.
  14. ^ Humberto R Maturana; Francisco J Varela (1992). "Afterword". The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding (Revised ed.). Shambhala Publications Inc. p. 255. ISBN 978-0877736424.
  15. ^ a b Maturana, Humberto R.; Varela, Francisco (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition : the realization of the living. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel Pub. Co. ISBN 90-277-1015-5. OCLC 5726379.
  16. ^ a b c Hutto, Daniel D.; Myin, Erik. Evolving enactivism: basic minds meet content. Cambridge, MA. ISBN 978-0-262-33977-3. OCLC 988028776.
  17. ^ a b Schlicht, Tobias; Starzak, Tobias (2019-09-07). "Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition". Synthese. 198: 89–113. doi:10.1007/s11229-019-02361-z. ISSN 0039-7857. S2CID 201868153.
  18. ^ Hutto, Daniel D.; Myin, Erik (2013). Radicalizing enactivism : basic minds without content. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. ISBN 978-0-262-31217-2. OCLC 822894365.
  19. ^ Evan Thompson (2007). "Autonomy and emergence". Mind in life (Paperback ed.). Harvard University Press. pp. 37 ff. ISBN 978-0674057517. See also the Introduction, p. x.
  20. ^ a b Evan Thompson (2007). "Chapter 8: Life beyond the gap". Mind in life (Paperback ed.). Harvard University Press. p. 225. ISBN 978-0674057517.
  21. ^ Evan Thompson (2007). "Life can be known only by life". Mind in life (Paperback ed.). Harvard University Press. p. 165. ISBN 978-0674057517.
  22. ^ Thomas Baldwin (2003). "Part One: Merleau-Ponty's prospectus of his work". Maurice Merleau-Ponty: Basic Writings. Routledge. p. 65. ISBN 978-0415315869. Science has not and never will have, by its nature, the same significance qua form of being as the world which we perceive, for the simple reason that it is a rationale or explanation of that world.
  23. ^ Edmond Mutelesi (November 15, 2006). "Radical constructivism seen with Edmund Husserl as starting point". Constructivist Foundations. 2 (1): 6–16.
  24. ^ Gabriele Chiari; M. Laura Nuzzo. "Constructivism". The Internet Encyclopaedia of Personal Construct Psychology.
  25. ^ Ernst von Glasersfeld (1974). "Report no. 14: Piaget and the Radical Constructivist Epistemology". In CD Smock; E von Glaserfeld (eds.). Epistemology and education. Follow Through Publications. pp. 1–24.
  26. ^ a b Ernst von Glasersfeld (1989). "Cognition, construction of knowledge and teaching" (PDF). Synthese. 80 (1): 121–140. doi:10.1007/bf00869951. S2CID 46967038.
  27. ^ a b Gallagher, Shaun (October 2014). "Pragmatic Interventions into Enactive and Extended Conceptions of Cognition: Pragmatic Interventions into Enactive and Extended Conceptions of Cognition". Philosophical Issues. 24 (1): 110–126. doi:10.1111/phis.12027.
  28. ^ Hoernle, R. F. Alfred; Dewey, John (July 1917). "Essays in Experimental Logic". The Philosophical Review. 26 (4): 421. doi:10.2307/2178488. hdl:2027/hvd.32044005126057. JSTOR 2178488.
  29. ^ Cosmelli, Diego; Thompson, Evan (2010-11-24). Stewart, John; Gapenne, Olivier; Di Paolo, Ezequiel A. (eds.). Embodiment or Envatment?: Reflections on the Bodily Basis of Consciousness. The MIT Press. pp. 360–385. doi:10.7551/mitpress/9780262014601.003.0014. ISBN 978-0-262-01460-1.
  30. ^ Brandom, Robert (2008). Between saying and doing: towards an analytic pragmatism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-156226-6. OCLC 258378350.
  31. ^ "The underpinnings of cognition are inextricable from those of affect, that the phenomenon of cognition itself is essentially bound up with affect.." See p. 104: Dave Ward; Mog Stapleton (2012). "Es are good. Cognition as enacted, embodied, embedded, affective and extended". In Fabio Paglieri (ed.). Consciousness in Interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness. John Benjamins Publishing. pp. 89 ff. ISBN 978-9027213525. On-line version here.
  32. ^ Olaf Diettrich (2006). "The biological boundary conditions for our classical physical world view". In Nathalie Gontier; Jean Paul van Bendegem; Diederik Aerts (eds.). Evolutionary Epistemology, Language and Culture. Springer. p. 88. ISBN 9781402033957.
  33. ^ "The notion of 'truth' is replaced with 'viability' within the subjects' experiential world." From Olaf Diettrich (2008). "Cognitive evolution; footnote 2". In Franz M. Wuketits; Christoph Antweiler (eds.). The handbook of evolution: The evolution of human societies and culture. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 61. ISBN 9783527620333. and in Evolutionary Epistemology, Language and Culture cited above, p. 90.
  34. ^ a b Nathalie Gontier (2006). "Evolutionary Epistemology". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  35. ^ Peter Munz (2002). Philosophical Darwinism: On the Origin of Knowledge by Means of Natural Selection. Routledge. p. 154. ISBN 9781134884841.
  36. ^ Clark, Andy; Toribio, Josefa (December 1994). "Doing without representing?". Synthese. 101 (3): 401–431. doi:10.1007/BF01063896. hdl:1842/1301. ISSN 0039-7857. S2CID 17136030.
  37. ^ Downey, Adrian (September 2020). "It Just Doesn't Feel Right: OCD and the 'Scaling Up' Problem". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 19 (4): 705–727. doi:10.1007/s11097-019-09644-3. ISSN 1568-7759. S2CID 214154577.
  38. ^ Marek McGann; Hanne De Jaegher; Ezequiel Di Paolo (2013). "Enaction and psychology". Review of General Psychology. 17 (2): 203–209. doi:10.1037/a0032935. S2CID 8986622.
  39. ^ Shaun Gallagher (2001). "The practice of mind" (PDF). Journal of Consciousness Studies. 8 (5–7): 83–107.
  40. ^ Shaun Gallagher (2006). How the Body Shapes the Mind (Paperback ed.). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0199204168.
  41. ^ Matthew Ratcliffe (2008). Rethinking Commonsense Psychology: A Critique of Folk Psychology, Theory of Mind and Simulation. Palgrave Macmillan. ISBN 978-0230221208.
  42. ^ a b Hanne De Jaegher; Ezequiel Di Paolo (2007). "Participatory Sense-Making: An enactive approach to social cognition" (PDF). Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 6 (4): 485–507. doi:10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9. S2CID 142842155.
  43. ^ a b Hanne De Jaegher; Ezequiel Di Paolo; Shaun Gallagher (2010). "Can social interaction constitute social cognition?" (PDF). Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 14 (10): 441–447. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009. PMID 20674467. S2CID 476406.
  44. ^ a b Ezequiel Di Paolo; Hanne De Jaegher (June 2012). "The Interactive Brain Hypothesis". Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. 7 (6): 163. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2012.00163. PMC 3369190. PMID 22701412.
  45. ^ Marek McGann; Steve Torrance (2005). "Doing It and Meaning It: And the relation between the two". In Ralph D. Ellis; Natika Newton (eds.). Consciousness & Emotion: Agency, conscious choice, and selective perception. John Benjamins Publishing. p. 184. ISBN 9789027294616.
  46. ^ Alva Noë (2004). "Chapter 1: The enactive approach to perception: An introduction". Action in Perception. MIT Press. pp. 1 ff. ISBN 9780262140881.
  47. ^ a b Andy Clark (March 2006). "Vision as Dance? Three Challenges for Sensorimotor Contingency Theory" (PDF). Psyche. 12 (1).
  48. ^ Ahissar, E. and E. Assa (2016) Perception as a closed-loop convergence process. eLife 5:e12830.DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.7554/eLife.12830
  49. ^ Daniel D Hutto, Erik Myin (2013). "A helping hand". Radicalizing Enactivism: Minds without content. MIT Press. pp. 46 ff. ISBN 9780262018548.
  50. ^ a b Daniel D Hutto; Erik Myin (2013). "Chapter 1: Enactivism: The radical line". Radicalizing Enactivism: Minds without content. MIT Press. pp. 12–13. ISBN 9780262018548.
  51. ^ Hanne De Jaegher; Ezequiel Di Paolo; Shaun Gallagher (2010). "Can social interaction constitute social cognition?". Trends in Cognitive Sciences. 14 (10): 441–447. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2010.06.009. PMID 20674467. S2CID 476406.
  52. ^ Leonhard Schilbach; Bert Timmermans; Vasudevi Reddy; Alan Costall; Gary Bente; Tobias Schlicht; Kai Vogeley (2013). "Toward a second-person neuroscience". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 36 (4): 393–414. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.476.2200. doi:10.1017/S0140525X12000660. PMID 23883742. S2CID 54587375.
  53. ^ Hanne De Jaegher (2012). "Embodiment and sense-making in autism". Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience. 7: 15. doi:10.3389/fnint.2013.00015. PMC 3607806. PMID 23532205.
  54. ^ a b Steve Torrance; Tom Froese (2011). "An Inter-Enactive Approach to Agency: Participatory Sense-Making, Dynamics, and Sociality" (PDF). Human Mente. 15: 21–53.
  55. ^ Thomas Fuchs; Hanne De Jaegher (2010). "Non-representational intersubjectivity". In Thomas Fuchs; Heribert C. Sattel; Peter Henningsen (eds.). The Embodied Self: Dimensions, Coherence and Disorders. Schattauer Verlag. p. 206. ISBN 9783794527915.
  56. ^ Cor Baerveldt; Theo Verheggen (May 2012). "Chapter 8: Enactivism". The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology. pp. 165ff. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195396430.013.0009. ISBN 9780195396430. Whereas the enactive approach in general has focused on sense-making as an embodied and situated activity, enactive cultural psychology emphasizes the expressive and dynamically enacted nature of cultural meaning.
  57. ^ Cor Baerveldt; Theo Verheggen (1999). "Enactivism and the experiential reality of culture: Rethinking the epistemological basis of cultural psychology". Culture & Psychology. 5 (2): 183–206. doi:10.1177/1354067x9952006. S2CID 145397218.
  58. ^ Niklas Luhmann (1995). Social systems. Stanford University Press. ISBN 9780804726252.
  59. ^ Hans-Georg Moeller (2011). "Part 1: A new way of thinking about society". Luhmann Explained: From Souls to Systems. Open Court. pp. 12 ff. ISBN 978-0812695984.
  60. ^ Roberto Pugliese; Klaus Lehtonen (2011). "A framework for motion based bodily enaction with virtual characters; §2.1 Enaction". Intelligent Virtual Agents. Springer. p. 163. ISBN 9783642239731.
  61. ^ Stephanie A Hillen (2013). "Chapter III: What can research on technology for learning in vocational educational training teach media didactics?". In Klaus Beck; Olga Zlatkin-Troitschanskaia (eds.). From Diagnostics to Learning Success: Proceedings in Vocational Education and Training (Paperback ed.). Springer Science & Business. p. 104. ISBN 978-9462091894.
  62. ^ Jerome Bruner (1966). Toward a theory of instruction. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674897007.
  63. ^ Jerome Bruner (1968). Processes of cognitive growth: Infancy. Crown Pub. ISBN 978-0517517482. OCLC 84376.
  64. ^ Quote from Jerome Seymour Bruner (1966). (PDF). Harvard University Press. p. 44. ISBN 9780674897014. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2014-05-02. Retrieved 2014-05-01. as quoted from J Bruner (2004). "Chapter 10: Sustaining mathematical activity". In John Mason; Sue Johnston-Wilder (eds.). Fundamental Constructs in Mathematics Education (Paperback ed.). Taylor & Francis. p. 260. ISBN 978-0415326988.
  65. ^ Jeanette Bopry (2007). "Providing a warrant for constructivist practice: the contribution of Francisco Varela". In Joe L. Kincheloe; Raymond A. Horn (eds.). The Praeger Handbook of Education and Psychology, Volume 1. Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 474 ff. ISBN 9780313331237. Varela's enactive framework beginning with his collaboration on autopoiesis theory with his mentor Humberto Maturana [and the development of] enaction as a framework within which these theories work as a matter of course.
  66. ^ a b Bharath Sriraman; Lyn English (2009). "Enactivism". Theories of Mathematics Education: Seeking New Frontiers. Springer. pp. 42 ff. ISBN 978-3642007422.
  67. ^ Wolff-Michael Roth (2012). "Epistemology and psychology: Jean Piaget and modern constructivism". Geometry as Objective Science in Elementary School Classrooms: Mathematics in the Flesh. Routledge. pp. 41 ff. ISBN 978-1136732201.
  68. ^ Gary Cziko (1997). "Chapter 12: Education; The provision and transmission of truth, or the selectionist growth of fallible knowledge?". Without Miracles: Universal Selection Theory and the Second Darwinian Revolution. MIT Press. p. 222. ISBN 9780262531474.
  69. ^ Joe L Kincheloe (2007). "Interpretivists drawing on the power of enactivism". In Joe L. Kincheloe; Raymond A. Horn (eds.). The Praeger Handbook of Education and Psychology, Volume 1. Greenwood Publishing Group. pp. 24 ff. ISBN 978-0313331237.
  70. ^ Chris Breen (2005). "Chapter 9: Dilemmas of change: seeing the complex rather than the complicated?". In Renuka Vithal; Jill Adler; Christine Keitel (eds.). Researching Mathematics Education in South Africa: Perspectives, Practices and Possibilities. HSRC Press. p. 240. ISBN 978-0796920478.
  71. ^ Ad J. W. van de Gevel, Charles N. Noussair (2013). "§3.2.2 Enactive artificial intelligence". The nexus between artificial intelligence and economics. Springer. p. 21. ISBN 978-3642336478. Enactivism may be considered as the most developed model of embodied situated cognition...Knowing is inseparable from doing.
  72. ^ a b John Seely Brown; Allan Collins; Paul Duguid (Jan–Feb 1989). . Educational Researcher. 18 (1): 32–42. doi:10.3102/0013189x018001032. hdl:2142/17979. S2CID 9824073. Archived from the original on 2014-10-08.
  73. ^ Giulio Sandini; Giorgio Metta; David Vernon (2007). "The iCub cognitive humanoid robot: An open-system research platform for enactive cognition". In Max Lungarella; Fumiya Iida; Josh Bongard; Rolf Pfeifer (eds.). 50 Years of Artificial Intelligence: Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence. Springer. ISBN 9783540772958.
  74. ^ Monica Bordegoni (2010). "§4.5.2 Design tools based upon enactive interfaces". In Shuichi Fukuda (ed.). Emotional Engineering: Service Development. Springer. pp. 78 ff. ISBN 9781849964234.
  75. ^ Don Norman (2013). "Affordances". The Design of Everyday Things (Revised and expanded ed.). Basic Books. p. 11. ISBN 978-0465050659. An affordance is a relationship between the properties of an object and the capabilities of the agent that determine just how the object could possibly be used.
  76. ^ Georgios S Christou (2006). "The use and evolution of affordance in HCI". In Claude Ghaoui (ed.). Encyclopedia of human computer interaction. Idea Group Inc. pp. 668 ff. ISBN 9781591407980.
  77. ^ Mauri Kaipainen; Niklas Ravaja; Pia Tikka; et al. (October 2011). "Enactive Systems and Enactive Media: Embodied Human-Machine Coupling beyond Interfaces". Leonardo. 44 (5): 433–438. doi:10.1162/LEON_a_00244. S2CID 17294711.
  78. ^ Guy Boy (2012). Orchestrating Human-Centered Design. Springer. p. 118. ISBN 9781447143383. The organization producing the system can itself be defined as an autopoietic system in Maturana and Varela's sense. An autopoietic system is producer and product at the same time. HCD [Human Centered Design] is both the process of design and the design itself.
  79. ^ Markus Thannhuber; Mitchell M Tseng; Hans-Jörg Bullinger (2001). "An autopoietic approach for knowledge management systems in manufacturing enterprises". Annals of the CIRP-Manufacturing Technology. 50 (1): 313 ff. doi:10.1016/s0007-8506(07)62129-5.
  80. ^ Randall D Beer (1995). "A dynamical systems perspective on agent-environment interaction". Artificial Intelligence. 72 (1–2): 173–215. doi:10.1016/0004-3702(94)00005-l.
  81. ^ James AS Kelso (2009). "Coordination dynamics". In R. A. Meyers (ed.). Encyclopedia of complexity and system science. pp. 1537–1564. doi:10.1007/978-0-387-30440-3_101. ISBN 978-0-387-75888-6.
  82. ^ Eliot L. Saltzman (1995). "Dynamics and coordinate systems in skilled sensorimotor activity". In T. van Gelder; R. F. Port (eds.). Mind as motion: Explorations in the dynamics of cognition. MIT Press. p. 151 ff. ISBN 9780262161503.
  83. ^ Marek McGann; Hanne De Jaegher; Ezequiel Di Paolo (2013). "Enaction and psychology". Review of General Psychology. 17 (2): 203–209. doi:10.1037/a0032935. S2CID 8986622. Such modeling techniques allow us to explore the parameter space of coupling between agent and environment...to the point that their basic principles (the universals, if such there are, of enactive psychology) can be brought clearly into view.
  84. ^ Legg, Shane (2008). Machine Super Intelligence (PDF) (Thesis). University of Lugano.
  85. ^ Hutter, Marcus (2005). Universal Artificial Intelligence: Sequential Decisions Based on Algorithmic Probability. Texts in Theoretical Computer Science an EATCS Series. Springer. doi:10.1007/b138233. ISBN 978-3-540-26877-2.
  86. ^ Leike, Jan; Hutter, Marcus (2015). Bad Universal Priors and Notions of Optimality. The 28th Conference on Learning Theory. arXiv:1510.04931.
  87. ^ Val Danilov, Igor (2023). "Low-Frequency Oscillations for Nonlocal Neuronal Coupling in Shared Intentionality Before and After Birth: Toward the Origin of Perception". OBM Neurobiology. 7 (4): 1–17. doi:10.21926/obm.neurobiol.2304192.
  88. ^ Val Danilov, Igor (2023). "Shared Intentionality Modulation at the Cell Level: Low-Frequency Oscillations for Temporal Coordination in Bioengineering Systems". OBM Neurobiology. 7 (4): 1–17. doi:10.21926/obm.neurobiol.2304185.
  89. ^ a b c Val Danilov, I. (2023). "Theoretical Grounds of Shared Intentionality for Neuroscience in Developing Bioengineering Systems." OBM Neurobiology 2023; 7(1): 156; doi:10.21926/obm.neurobiol.2301156. https://www.lidsen.com/journals/neurobiology/neurobiology-07-01-156 .

Further reading edit

  • Clark, Andy (2015). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780190217013.
  • De Jaegher H.; Di Paolo E. A. (2007). "Participatory sense-making: An enactive approach to social cognition". Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 6 (4): 485–507. doi:10.1007/s11097-007-9076-9. S2CID 142842155.
  • Di Paolo, E. A., Rohde, M. and De Jaegher, H., (2010). Horizons for the Enactive Mind: Values, Social Interaction, and Play. In J. Stewart, O. Gapenne and E. A. Di Paolo (eds), Enaction: Towards a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 33 – 87. ISBN 9780262014601
  • Gallagher, Shaun (2017). Enactivist Interventions: Rethinking the Mind. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0198794325
  • Hutto, D. D. (Ed.) (2006). Radical Enactivism: Intentionality, phenomenology, and narrative. In R. D. Ellis & N. Newton (Series Eds.), Consciousness & Emotion, vol. 2. ISBN 90-272-4151-1
  • McGann, M. & Torrance, S. (2005). Doing it and meaning it (and the relationship between the two). In R. D. Ellis & N. Newton, Consciousness & Emotion, vol. 1: Agency, conscious choice, and selective perception. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. ISBN 1-58811-596-8
  • Merleau-Ponty, Maurice (2005). Phenomenology of Perception. Routledge. ISBN 9780415278416 (Originally published 1945)
  • Noë, Alva (2010). Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from the Biology of Consciousness. Hill and Wang. ISBN 978-0809016488
  • Tom Froese; Ezequiel A DiPaolo (2011). "The enactive approach: Theoretical sketches from cell to society". Pragmatics & Cognition. 19 (1): 1–36. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.224.5504. doi:10.1075/pc.19.1.01fro.
  • Steve Torrance; Tom Froese (2011). "An inter-enactive approach to agency: participatory sense-making, dynamics, and sociality". Humana. Mente. 15: 21–53. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.187.1151.
  • (fr) Domenico Masciotra. (2023) Une approche énactive des formations, Théorie et Méthode. En devenir compétent et connaisseur. ASCAR Inc.

Notes edit

  1. ^ Cognition as information processing like that of a digital computer. From Evan Thompson (2010-09-30). Mind in Life. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674057517. Cognitivism, p. 4; See also Steven Horst (December 10, 2009). "The computational theory of mind". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition).
  2. ^ Cognition as emergent patterns of activity in a neural network. From Evan Thompson (2010-09-30). Mind in Life. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0674057517. Connectionism, p. 8; See also James Garson (July 27, 2010). Edward N. Zalta (ed.). "Connectionism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition).

External links edit

  • "Enactivism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Pietro Morasso (2005). (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2006-05-08. Slides related to a chapter on haptic perception (recognition through touch): Pietro Morasso (2007). "Chapter 14: The crucial role of haptic perception". In Antonio Chella; Riccardo Manzotti (eds.). Artificial Consciousness. Academic. p. 234 ff. ISBN 978-1845400705.
  • John Stewart. Olivier Gapenne; Bruno Bachimont (eds.). . Enaction Series: Online Collaborative Publishing. Enaction Series. Archived from the original on April 27, 2014. Retrieved April 27, 2014.
  • George-Louis Baron; Eric Bruillard; Christophe Dansac (January 1999). "Educational Multimedia Task Force – MM 1045, REPRESENTATION" (PDF). An overview of the rationale and means and methods for the study of representations that the learner constructs in his/her attempt to understand knowledge in a given field. See in particular §1.2.1.4 Toward social representations (p. 24)
  • Randall Whittaker (2001). . Observer Web. Archived from the original on 2007-08-24. Retrieved 2014-05-23. An extensive but uncritical introduction to the work of Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana
  • "Enactivism: Arguments & Applications". Avant. V (2/2014). Autumn 2014. doi:10.12849/50202014.0109.0002 (inactive 31 January 2024). Retrieved 27 November 2014.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024 (link) Entire journal issue on enactivism's status and current debates.

enactivism, this, article, contains, many, overly, lengthy, quotations, please, help, summarize, quotations, consider, transferring, direct, quotations, wikiquote, excerpts, wikisource, september, 2022, position, cognitive, science, that, argues, that, cogniti. This article contains too many or overly lengthy quotations Please help summarize the quotations Consider transferring direct quotations to Wikiquote or excerpts to Wikisource September 2022 Enactivism is a position in cognitive science that argues that cognition arises through a dynamic interaction between an acting organism and its environment 1 It claims that the environment of an organism is brought about or enacted by the active exercise of that organism s sensorimotor processes The key point then is that the species brings forth and specifies its own domain of problems this domain does not exist out there in an environment that acts as a landing pad for organisms that somehow drop or parachute into the world Instead living beings and their environments stand in relation to each other through mutual specification or codetermination p 198 2 Organisms do not passively receive information from their environments which they then translate into internal representations Natural cognitive systems participate in the generation of meaning engaging in transformational and not merely informational interactions they enact a world 3 These authors suggest that the increasing emphasis upon enactive terminology presages a new era in thinking about cognitive science 3 How the actions involved in enactivism relate to age old questions about free will remains a topic of active debate 4 The term enactivism is close in meaning to enaction defined as the manner in which a subject of perception creatively matches its actions to the requirements of its situation 5 The introduction of the term enaction in this context is attributed to Francisco Varela Evan Thompson and Eleanor Rosch in The Embodied Mind 1991 5 6 who proposed the name to emphasize the growing conviction that cognition is not the representation of a pre given world by a pre given mind but is rather the enactment of a world and a mind on the basis of a history of the variety of actions that a being in the world performs 2 This was further developed by Thompson and others 1 to place emphasis upon the idea that experience of the world is a result of mutual interaction between the sensorimotor capacities of the organism and its environment 6 However some writers maintain that there remains a need for some degree of the mediating function of representation in this new approach to the science of the mind 7 The initial emphasis of enactivism upon sensorimotor skills has been criticized as cognitively marginal 8 but it has been extended to apply to higher level cognitive activities such as social interactions 3 In the enactive view knowledge is constructed it is constructed by an agent through its sensorimotor interactions with its environment co constructed between and within living species through their meaningful interaction with each other In its most abstract form knowledge is co constructed between human individuals in socio linguistic interactions Science is a particular form of social knowledge construction that allows us to perceive and predict events beyond our immediate cognitive grasp and also to construct further even more powerful scientific knowledge 9 Enactivism is closely related to situated cognition and embodied cognition and is presented as an alternative to cognitivism computationalism and Cartesian dualism Contents 1 Philosophical aspects 2 Psychological aspects 2 1 Enactive views of perception 2 2 Participatory sense making 3 Educational aspects 4 Artificial intelligence aspects 4 1 Mathematical formalisms 5 Criticism 6 See also 7 References 8 Further reading 9 Notes 10 External linksPhilosophical aspects editEnactivism is one of a cluster of related theories sometimes known as the 4Es 10 As described by Mark Rowlands mental processes are Embodied involving more than the brain including a more general involvement of bodily structures and processes Embedded functioning only in a related external environment Enacted involving not only neural processes but also things an organism does Extended into the organism s environment Enactivism proposes an alternative to dualism as a philosophy of mind in that it emphasises the interactions between mind body and the environment seeing them all as inseparably intertwined in mental processes 11 The self arises as part of the process of an embodied entity interacting with the environment in precise ways determined by its physiology In this sense individuals can be seen to grow into or arise from their interactive role with the world 12 Enaction is the idea that organisms create their own experience through their actions Organisms are not passive receivers of input from the environment but are actors in the environment such that what they experience is shaped by how they act 13 In The Tree of Knowledge Maturana amp Varela proposed the term enactive 14 to evoke the view of knowledge that what is known is brought forth in contraposition to the more classical views of either cognitivism Note 1 or connectionism Note 2 They see enactivism as providing a middle ground between the two extremes of representationalism and solipsism They seek to confront the problem of understanding how our existence the praxis of our living is coupled to a surrounding world which appears filled with regularities that are at every instant the result of our biological and social histories to find a via media to understand the regularity of the world we are experiencing at every moment but without any point of reference independent of ourselves that would give certainty to our descriptions and cognitive assertions Indeed the whole mechanism of generating ourselves as describers and observers tells us that our world as the world which we bring forth in our coexistence with others will always have precisely that mixture of regularity and mutability that combination of solidity and shifting sand so typical of human experience when we look at it up close Tree of Knowledge p 241 Another important notion relating to enactivism is autopoiesis The word refers to a system that is able to reproduce and maintain itself Maturana amp Varela describe that This was a word without a history a word that could directly mean what takes place in the dynamics of the autonomy proper to living systems 15 Using the term autopoiesis they argue that any closed system that has autonomy self reference and self construction or that has autopoietic activities has cognitive capacities Therefore cognition is present in all living systems 15 This view is also called autopoietic enactivism Radical enactivism is another form of enactivist view of cognition Radical enactivists often adopt a thoroughly non representational enactive account of basic cognition Basic cognitive capacities mentioned by Hutto and Myin include perceiving imagining and remembering 16 17 They argue that those forms of basic cognition can be explained without positing mental representations With regard to complex forms of cognition such as language they think mental representations are needed because there needs explanations of content In human being s public practices they claim that such intersubjective practices and sensitivity to the relevant norms comes with the mastery of the use of public symbol systems 2017 p 120 and so as it happens this appears only to have occurred in full form with construction of sociocultural cognitive niches in the human lineage 2017 p 134 16 They conclude that basic cognition as well as cognition in simple organisms such as bacteria are best characterized as non representational 18 16 17 Enactivism also addresses the hard problem of consciousness referred to by Thompson as part of the explanatory gap in explaining how consciousness and subjective experience are related to brain and body 19 The problem with the dualistic concepts of consciousness and life in standard formulations of the hard problem is that they exclude each other by construction 20 Instead according to Thompson s view of enactivism the study of consciousness or phenomenology as exemplified by Husserl and Merleau Ponty is to complement science and its objectification of the world The whole universe of science is built upon the world as directly experienced and if we want to subject science itself to rigorous scrutiny and arrive at a precise assessment of its meaning and scope we must begin by reawakening the basic experience of the world of which science is the second order expression Merleau Ponty The phenomenology of perception as quoted by Thompson p 165 In this interpretation enactivism asserts that science is formed or enacted as part of humankind s interactivity with its world and by embracing phenomenology science itself is properly situated in relation to the rest of human life and is thereby secured on a sounder footing 21 22 Enaction has been seen as a move to conjoin representationalism with phenomenalism that is as adopting a constructivist epistemology an epistemology centered upon the active participation of the subject in constructing reality 23 24 However constructivism focuses upon more than a simple interactivity that could be described as a minor adjustment to assimilate reality or accommodate to it 25 Constructivism looks upon interactivity as a radical creative revisionist process in which the knower constructs a personal knowledge system based upon their experience and tested by its viability in practical encounters with their environment Learning is a result of perceived anomalies that produce dissatisfaction with existing conceptions 26 Shaun Gallagher also points out that pragmatism is a forerunner of enactive and extended approaches to cognition 27 According to him enactive conceptions of cognition can be found in many pragmatists such as Charles Sanders Peirce and John Dewey For example Dewey says that The brain is essentially an organ for effecting the reciprocal adjustment to each other of the stimuli received from the environment and responses directed upon it 1916 pp 336 337 28 This view is fully consistent with enactivist arguments that cognition is not just a matter of brain processes and brain is one part of the body consisting of the dynamical regulation 27 29 Robert Brandom a neo pragmatist comments that A founding idea of pragmatism is that the most fundamental kind of intentionality in the sense of directedness towards objects is the practical involvement with objects exhibited by a sentient creature dealing skillfully with its world 2008 p 178 30 How does constructivism relate to enactivism From the above remarks it can be seen that Glasersfeld expresses an interactivity between the knower and the known quite acceptable to an enactivist but does not emphasize the structured probing of the environment by the knower that leads to the perturbation relative to some expected result that then leads to a new understanding 26 It is this probing activity especially where it is not accidental but deliberate that characterizes enaction and invokes affect 31 that is the motivation and planning that lead to doing and to fashioning the probing both observing and modifying the environment so that perceptions and nature condition one another through generating one another 32 The questioning nature of this probing activity is not an emphasis of Piaget and Glasersfeld Sharing enactivism s stress upon both action and embodiment in the incorporation of knowledge but giving Glasersfeld s mechanism of viability an evolutionary emphasis 33 is evolutionary epistemology Inasmuch as an organism must reflect its environment well enough for the organism to be able to survive in it and to be competitive enough to be able to reproduce at sustainable rate the structure and reflexes of the organism itself embody knowledge of its environment This biology inspired theory of the growth of knowledge is closely tied to universal Darwinism and is associated with evolutionary epistemologists such as Karl Popper Donald T Campbell Peter Munz and Gary Cziko 34 According to Munz an organism is an embodied theory about its environment Embodied theories are also no longer expressed in language but in anatomical structures or reflex responses etc 34 35 One objection to enactive approaches to cognition is the so called scale up objection According to this objection enactive theories only have limited value because they cannot scale up to explain more complex cognitive capacities like human thoughts Those phenomena are extremely difficult to explain without positing representation 36 But recently some philosophers are trying to respond to such objection For example Adrian Downey 2020 provides a non representational account of Obsessive compulsive disorder and then argues that ecological enactive approaches can respond to the scaling up objection 37 Psychological aspects editMcGann amp others 38 argue that enactivism attempts to mediate between the explanatory role of the coupling between cognitive agent and environment and the traditional emphasis on brain mechanisms found in neuroscience and psychology In the interactive approach to social cognition developed by De Jaegher amp others 39 40 41 the dynamics of interactive processes are seen to play significant roles in coordinating interpersonal understanding processes that in part include what they call participatory sense making 42 43 Recent developments of enactivism in the area of social neuroscience involve the proposal of The Interactive Brain Hypothesis 44 where social cognition brain mechanisms even those used in non interactive situations are proposed to have interactive origins Enactive views of perception edit In the enactive view perception is not conceived as the transmission of information but more as an exploration of the world by various means Cognition is not tied into the workings of an inner mind some cognitive core but occurs in directed interaction between the body and the world it inhabits 45 Alva Noe in advocating an enactive view of perception 46 sought to resolve how we perceive three dimensional objects on the basis of two dimensional input He argues that we perceive this solidity or volumetricity by appealing to patterns of sensorimotor expectations These arise from our agent active movements and interaction with objects or object active changes in the object itself The solidity is perceived through our expectations and skills in knowing how the object s appearance would change with changes in how we relate to it He saw all perception as an active exploration of the world rather than being a passive process something which happens to us Noe s idea of the role of expectations in three dimensional perception has been opposed by several philosophers notably by Andy Clark 47 Clark points to difficulties of the enactive approach He points to internal processing of visual signals for example in the ventral and dorsal pathways the two streams hypothesis This results in an integrated perception of objects their recognition and location respectively yet this processing cannot be described as an action or actions In a more general criticism Clark suggests that perception is not a matter of expectations about sensorimotor mechanisms guiding perception Rather although the limitations of sensorimotor mechanisms constrain perception this sensorimotor activity is drastically filtered to fit current needs and purposes of the organism and it is these imposed expectations that govern perception filtering for the relevant details of sensorimotor input called sensorimotor summarizing 47 These sensorimotor centered and purpose centered views appear to agree on the general scheme but disagree on the dominance issue is the dominant component peripheral or central Another view the closed loop perception one assigns equal a priori dominance to the peripheral and central components In closed loop perception perception emerges through the process of inclusion of an item in a motor sensory motor loop i e a loop or loops connecting the peripheral and central components that are relevant to that item 48 The item can be a body part in which case the loops are in steady state or an external object in which case the loops are perturbed and gradually converge to a steady state These enactive loops are always active switching dominance by the need Another application of enaction to perception is analysis of the human hand The many remarkably demanding uses of the hand are not learned by instruction but through a history of engagements that lead to the acquisition of skills According to one interpretation it is suggested that the hand is an organ of cognition not a faithful subordinate working under top down instruction but a partner in a bi directional interplay between manual and brain activity 49 According to Daniel Hutto Enactivists are concerned to defend the view that our most elementary ways of engaging with the world and others including our basic forms of perception and perceptual experience are mindful in the sense of being phenomenally charged and intentionally directed despite being non representational and content free 50 Hutto calls this position REC Radical Enactive Cognition According to REC there is no way to distinguish neural activity that is imagined to be genuinely content involving and thus truly mental truly cognitive from other non neural activity that merely plays a supporting or enabling role in making mind and cognition possible 50 Participatory sense making edit Hanne De Jaegher and Ezequiel Di Paolo 2007 42 have extended the enactive concept of sense making 20 into the social domain The idea takes as its departure point the process of interaction between individuals in a social encounter 51 De Jaegher and Di Paolo argue that the interaction process itself can take on a form of autonomy operationally defined This allows them to define social cognition as the generation of meaning and its transformation through interacting individuals The notion of participatory sense making has led to the proposal that interaction processes can sometimes play constitutive roles in social cognition De Jaegher Di Paolo Gallagher 2010 43 It has been applied to research in social neuroscience 44 52 and autism 53 In a similar vein an inter enactive approach to agency holds that the behavior of agents in a social situation unfolds not only according to their individual abilities and goals but also according to the conditions and constraints imposed by the autonomous dynamics of the interaction process itself 54 According to Torrance enactivism involves five interlocking themes related to the question What is it to be a cognizing conscious agent It is 54 1 to be a biologically autonomous autopoietic organism 2 to generate significance or meaning rather than to act via updated internal representations of the external world 3 to engage in sense making via dynamic coupling with the environment 4 to enact or bring forth a world of significances by mutual co determination of the organism with its enacted world 5 to arrive at an experiential awareness via lived embodiment in the world Torrance adds that many kinds of agency in particular the agency of human beings cannot be understood separately from understanding the nature of the interaction that occurs between agents That view introduces the social applications of enactivism Social cognition is regarded as the result of a special form of action namely social interaction the enactive approach looks at the circular dynamic within a dyad of embodied agents 55 In cultural psychology enactivism is seen as a way to uncover cultural influences upon feeling thinking and acting 56 Baerveldt and Verheggen argue that It appears that seemingly natural experience is thoroughly intertwined with sociocultural realities They suggest that the social patterning of experience is to be understood through enactivism the idea that the reality we have in common and in which we find ourselves is neither a world that exists independently from us nor a socially shared way of representing such a pregiven world but a world itself brought forth by our ways of communicating and our joint action The world we inhabit is manufactured of meaning rather than information 57 Luhmann attempted to apply Maturana and Varela s notion of autopoiesis to social systems 58 A core concept of social systems theory is derived from biological systems theory the concept of autopoiesis Chilean biologist Humberto Maturana come up with the concept to explain how biological systems such as cells are a product of their own production Systems exist by way of operational closure and this means that they each construct themselves and their own realities 59 Educational aspects editThe first definition of enaction was introduced by psychologist Jerome Bruner 60 61 who introduced enaction as learning by doing in his discussion of how children learn and how they can best be helped to learn 62 63 He associated enaction with two other ways of knowledge organization Iconic and Symbolic 64 Any domain of knowledge or any problem within that domain of knowledge can be represented in three ways by a set of actions appropriate for achieving a certain result enactive representation by a set of summary images or graphics that stand for a concept without defining it fully iconic representation and by a set of symbolic or logical propositions drawn from a symbolic system that is governed by rules or laws for forming and transforming propositions symbolic representation The term enactive framework was elaborated upon by Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana 65 Sriramen argues that enactivism provides a rich and powerful explanatory theory for learning and being 66 and that it is closely related to both the ideas of cognitive development of Piaget and also the social constructivism of Vygotsky 66 Piaget focused on the child s immediate environment and suggested cognitive structures like spatial perception emerge as a result of the child s interaction with the world 67 According to Piaget children construct knowledge using what they know in new ways and testing it and the environment provides feedback concerning the adequacy of their construction 68 In a cultural context Vygotsky suggested that the kind of cognition that can take place is not dictated by the engagement of the isolated child but is also a function of social interaction and dialogue that is contingent upon a sociohistorical context 69 Enactivism in educational theory looks at each learning situation as a complex system consisting of teacher learner and context all of which frame and co create the learning situation 70 Enactivism in education is very closely related to situated cognition 71 which holds that knowledge is situated being in part a product of the activity context and culture in which it is developed and used 72 This approach challenges the separating of what is learned from how it is learned and used 72 Artificial intelligence aspects editMain article Enactive interfaces The ideas of enactivism regarding how organisms engage with their environment have interested those involved in robotics and man machine interfaces The analogy is drawn that a robot can be designed to interact and learn from its environment in a manner similar to the way an organism does 73 and a human can interact with a computer aided design tool or data base using an interface that creates an enactive environment for the user that is all the user s tactile auditory and visual capabilities are enlisted in a mutually explorative engagement capitalizing upon all the user s abilities and not at all limited to cerebral engagement 74 In these areas it is common to refer to affordances as a design concept the idea that an environment or an interface affords opportunities for enaction and good design involves optimizing the role of such affordances 75 76 77 78 79 The activity in the AI community has influenced enactivism as a whole Referring extensively to modeling techniques for evolutionary robotics by Beer 80 the modeling of learning behavior by Kelso 81 and to modeling of sensorimotor activity by Saltzman 82 McGann De Jaegher and Di Paolo discuss how this work makes the dynamics of coupling between an agent and its environment the foundation of enactivism an operational empirically observable phenomenon 83 That is the AI environment invents examples of enactivism using concrete examples that although not as complex as living organisms isolate and illuminate basic principles Mathematical formalisms edit Main article artificial general intelligence Enactive cognition has been formalised in order to address subjectivity in artificial general intelligence A mathematical formalism of AGI is an agent proven to maximise a measure of intelligence 84 Prior to 2022 the only such formalism was AIXI which maximised the ability to satisfy goals in a wide range of environments 85 In 2015 Jan Lieke and Marcus Hutter showed that Legg Hutter intelligence is measured with respect to a fixed UTM AIXI is the most intelligent policy if it uses the same UTM a result which undermines all existing optimality properties for AIXI rendering them subjective 86 Criticism editOne of the essential theses of this approach is that biological systems generate meanings engaging in transformational and not merely informational interactions 3 Since this thesis raised the problems of beginning cognition for organisms in the developmental stage of only simple reflexes the binding problem and the problem of primary data entry 87 88 enactivists proposed the concept of embodied information that serves to start cognition 1 However critics highlight that this idea requires introducing the nature of intentionality before engaging embodied information 89 In a natural environment the stimulus reaction pair causation is unpredictable due to many irrelevant stimuli claiming to be randomly associated with the embodied information 89 While embodied information is only beneficial when intentionality is already in place enactivists introduced the notion of the generation of meanings by biological systems engaging in transformational interactions without introducing a neurophysiological basis of intentionality 89 See also editAction specific perception Autopoesis Biosemiotics Cognitive science Cognitive psychology Computational theory of mind Connectivism Cultural psychology Distributed cognition Embodied cognition Embodied embedded cognition Enactive interfaces Extended cognition Extended mind Externalism Enactivism and embodied cognition Mind body problem Phenomenology philosophy Practopoiesis Representationalism Situated cognition Social cognitionReferences edit a b c Evan Thompson 2010 Chapter 1 The enactive approach PDF Mind in life Biology phenomenology and the sciences of mind Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674057517 ToC first 65 pages and index found here a b Francisco J Varela Evan Thompson Eleanor Rosch 1992 The embodied mind Cognitive science and human experience MIT Press p 9 ISBN 978 0262261234 a b c d Ezequiel A Di Paolo Marieke Rhohde Hanne De Jaegher 2014 Horizons for the enactive mind Values social interaction and play In John Stewart Oliver Gapenne Ezequiel A Di Paolo eds Enaction Toward a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science MIT Press pp 33 ff ISBN 978 0262526012 A collection of papers on this topic is introduced by Duccio Manetti Silvano Zipoli Caiani January 2011 Agency From embodied cognition to free will PDF Humana Mente 15 V XIII Archived from the original PDF on 2018 04 09 Retrieved 2014 05 07 a b John Protevi ed 2006 Enaction A Dictionary of Continental Philosophy Yale University Press pp 169 170 ISBN 9780300116052 a b Robert A Wilson Lucia Foglia 25 July 2011 Embodied Cognition 2 2 Enactive cognition In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2017 Edition Mark Rowlands 2010 Chapter 3 The mind embedded 5 The mind enacted The new science of the mind From extended mind to embodied phenomenology MIT Press pp 70 ff ISBN 978 0262014557 Rowlands attributes this idea to D M MacKay 1967 Ways of looking at perception In W Watthen Dunn ed Models for the perception of speech and visual form Proceedings of a symposium MIT Press pp 25 ff ISBN 9780262230261 Andy Clark Josefa Toribio 1994 Doing without representing PDF Synthese 101 3 401 434 doi 10 1007 bf01063896 hdl 1842 1301 S2CID 17136030 Marieke Rohde 2010 3 1 The scientist as observing subject Enaction Embodiment Evolutionary Robotics Simulation Models for a Post Cognitivist Science of Mind Atlantis Press pp 30 ff ISBN 978 9078677239 Mark Rowlands 2010 p 3 attributes the term 4Es to Shaun Gallagher Evan Thompson 2007 The enactive approach Mind in life Paperback ed Harvard University Press pp 13 ff ISBN 978 0674057517 ToC first 65 pages and index found here Jeremy Trevelyan Burman 2006 Book reviews Consciousness amp Emotion PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 13 12 115 124 Archived from the original PDF on 2007 09 27 Retrieved 2006 12 30 From a review of Ralph D Ellis Natika Newton eds 2005 Consciousness amp Emotion Agency conscious choice and selective perception John Benjamins Publishing ISBN 9789027294616 Edwin Hutchins 1996 Cognition in the Wild MIT Press p 428 ISBN 9780262581462 Quoted by Marcio Rocha 2011 Cognitive embodied or enacted Contemporary perspectives for HCI and interaction PDF Transtechnology Research Reader ISBN 978 0 9538332 2 1 Archived from the original PDF on 2014 05 24 Retrieved 2014 05 23 Humberto R Maturana Francisco J Varela 1992 Afterword The tree of knowledge the biological roots of human understanding Revised ed Shambhala Publications Inc p 255 ISBN 978 0877736424 a b Maturana Humberto R Varela Francisco 1980 Autopoiesis and cognition the realization of the living Dordrecht Holland D Reidel Pub Co ISBN 90 277 1015 5 OCLC 5726379 a b c Hutto Daniel D Myin Erik Evolving enactivism basic minds meet content Cambridge MA ISBN 978 0 262 33977 3 OCLC 988028776 a b Schlicht Tobias Starzak Tobias 2019 09 07 Prospects of enactivist approaches to intentionality and cognition Synthese 198 89 113 doi 10 1007 s11229 019 02361 z ISSN 0039 7857 S2CID 201868153 Hutto Daniel D Myin Erik 2013 Radicalizing enactivism basic minds without content Cambridge Mass MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 31217 2 OCLC 822894365 Evan Thompson 2007 Autonomy and emergence Mind in life Paperback ed Harvard University Press pp 37 ff ISBN 978 0674057517 See also the Introduction p x a b Evan Thompson 2007 Chapter 8 Life beyond the gap Mind in life Paperback ed Harvard University Press p 225 ISBN 978 0674057517 Evan Thompson 2007 Life can be known only by life Mind in life Paperback ed Harvard University Press p 165 ISBN 978 0674057517 Thomas Baldwin 2003 Part One Merleau Ponty s prospectus of his work Maurice Merleau Ponty Basic Writings Routledge p 65 ISBN 978 0415315869 Science has not and never will have by its nature the same significance qua form of being as the world which we perceive for the simple reason that it is a rationale or explanation of that world Edmond Mutelesi November 15 2006 Radical constructivism seen with Edmund Husserl as starting point Constructivist Foundations 2 1 6 16 Gabriele Chiari M Laura Nuzzo Constructivism The Internet Encyclopaedia of Personal Construct Psychology Ernst von Glasersfeld 1974 Report no 14 Piaget and the Radical Constructivist Epistemology In CD Smock E von Glaserfeld eds Epistemology and education Follow Through Publications pp 1 24 a b Ernst von Glasersfeld 1989 Cognition construction of knowledge and teaching PDF Synthese 80 1 121 140 doi 10 1007 bf00869951 S2CID 46967038 a b Gallagher Shaun October 2014 Pragmatic Interventions into Enactive and Extended Conceptions of Cognition Pragmatic Interventions into Enactive and Extended Conceptions of Cognition Philosophical Issues 24 1 110 126 doi 10 1111 phis 12027 Hoernle R F Alfred Dewey John July 1917 Essays in Experimental Logic The Philosophical Review 26 4 421 doi 10 2307 2178488 hdl 2027 hvd 32044005126057 JSTOR 2178488 Cosmelli Diego Thompson Evan 2010 11 24 Stewart John Gapenne Olivier Di Paolo Ezequiel A eds Embodiment or Envatment Reflections on the Bodily Basis of Consciousness The MIT Press pp 360 385 doi 10 7551 mitpress 9780262014601 003 0014 ISBN 978 0 262 01460 1 Brandom Robert 2008 Between saying and doing towards an analytic pragmatism Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 156226 6 OCLC 258378350 The underpinnings of cognition are inextricable from those of affect that the phenomenon of cognition itself is essentially bound up with affect See p 104 Dave Ward Mog Stapleton 2012 Es are good Cognition as enacted embodied embedded affective and extended In Fabio Paglieri ed Consciousness in Interaction The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness John Benjamins Publishing pp 89 ff ISBN 978 9027213525 On line version here Olaf Diettrich 2006 The biological boundary conditions for our classical physical world view In Nathalie Gontier Jean Paul van Bendegem Diederik Aerts eds Evolutionary Epistemology Language and Culture Springer p 88 ISBN 9781402033957 The notion of truth is replaced with viability within the subjects experiential world From Olaf Diettrich 2008 Cognitive evolution footnote 2 In Franz M Wuketits Christoph Antweiler eds The handbook of evolution The evolution of human societies and culture Wiley Blackwell p 61 ISBN 9783527620333 and in Evolutionary Epistemology Language and Culture cited above p 90 a b Nathalie Gontier 2006 Evolutionary Epistemology Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Peter Munz 2002 Philosophical Darwinism On the Origin of Knowledge by Means of Natural Selection Routledge p 154 ISBN 9781134884841 Clark Andy Toribio Josefa December 1994 Doing without representing Synthese 101 3 401 431 doi 10 1007 BF01063896 hdl 1842 1301 ISSN 0039 7857 S2CID 17136030 Downey Adrian September 2020 It Just Doesn t Feel Right OCD and the Scaling Up Problem Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 19 4 705 727 doi 10 1007 s11097 019 09644 3 ISSN 1568 7759 S2CID 214154577 Marek McGann Hanne De Jaegher Ezequiel Di Paolo 2013 Enaction and psychology Review of General Psychology 17 2 203 209 doi 10 1037 a0032935 S2CID 8986622 Shaun Gallagher 2001 The practice of mind PDF Journal of Consciousness Studies 8 5 7 83 107 Shaun Gallagher 2006 How the Body Shapes the Mind Paperback ed Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0199204168 Matthew Ratcliffe 2008 Rethinking Commonsense Psychology A Critique of Folk Psychology Theory of Mind and Simulation Palgrave Macmillan ISBN 978 0230221208 a b Hanne De Jaegher Ezequiel Di Paolo 2007 Participatory Sense Making An enactive approach to social cognition PDF Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 4 485 507 doi 10 1007 s11097 007 9076 9 S2CID 142842155 a b Hanne De Jaegher Ezequiel Di Paolo Shaun Gallagher 2010 Can social interaction constitute social cognition PDF Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 10 441 447 doi 10 1016 j tics 2010 06 009 PMID 20674467 S2CID 476406 a b Ezequiel Di Paolo Hanne De Jaegher June 2012 The Interactive Brain Hypothesis Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 7 6 163 doi 10 3389 fnhum 2012 00163 PMC 3369190 PMID 22701412 Marek McGann Steve Torrance 2005 Doing It and Meaning It And the relation between the two In Ralph D Ellis Natika Newton eds Consciousness amp Emotion Agency conscious choice and selective perception John Benjamins Publishing p 184 ISBN 9789027294616 Alva Noe 2004 Chapter 1 The enactive approach to perception An introduction Action in Perception MIT Press pp 1 ff ISBN 9780262140881 a b Andy Clark March 2006 Vision as Dance Three Challenges for Sensorimotor Contingency Theory PDF Psyche 12 1 Ahissar E and E Assa 2016 Perception as a closed loop convergence process eLife 5 e12830 DOI https dx doi org 10 7554 eLife 12830 Daniel D Hutto Erik Myin 2013 A helping hand Radicalizing Enactivism Minds without content MIT Press pp 46 ff ISBN 9780262018548 a b Daniel D Hutto Erik Myin 2013 Chapter 1 Enactivism The radical line Radicalizing Enactivism Minds without content MIT Press pp 12 13 ISBN 9780262018548 Hanne De Jaegher Ezequiel Di Paolo Shaun Gallagher 2010 Can social interaction constitute social cognition Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14 10 441 447 doi 10 1016 j tics 2010 06 009 PMID 20674467 S2CID 476406 Leonhard Schilbach Bert Timmermans Vasudevi Reddy Alan Costall Gary Bente Tobias Schlicht Kai Vogeley 2013 Toward a second person neuroscience Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 4 393 414 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 476 2200 doi 10 1017 S0140525X12000660 PMID 23883742 S2CID 54587375 Hanne De Jaegher 2012 Embodiment and sense making in autism Frontiers in Integrative Neuroscience 7 15 doi 10 3389 fnint 2013 00015 PMC 3607806 PMID 23532205 a b Steve Torrance Tom Froese 2011 An Inter Enactive Approach to Agency Participatory Sense Making Dynamics and Sociality PDF Human Mente 15 21 53 Thomas Fuchs Hanne De Jaegher 2010 Non representational intersubjectivity In Thomas Fuchs Heribert C Sattel Peter Henningsen eds The Embodied Self Dimensions Coherence and Disorders Schattauer Verlag p 206 ISBN 9783794527915 Cor Baerveldt Theo Verheggen May 2012 Chapter 8 Enactivism The Oxford Handbook of Culture and Psychology pp 165ff doi 10 1093 oxfordhb 9780195396430 013 0009 ISBN 9780195396430 Whereas the enactive approach in general has focused on sense making as an embodied and situated activity enactive cultural psychology emphasizes the expressive and dynamically enacted nature of cultural meaning Cor Baerveldt Theo Verheggen 1999 Enactivism and the experiential reality of culture Rethinking the epistemological basis of cultural psychology Culture amp Psychology 5 2 183 206 doi 10 1177 1354067x9952006 S2CID 145397218 Niklas Luhmann 1995 Social systems Stanford University Press ISBN 9780804726252 Hans Georg Moeller 2011 Part 1 A new way of thinking about society Luhmann Explained From Souls to Systems Open Court pp 12 ff ISBN 978 0812695984 Roberto Pugliese Klaus Lehtonen 2011 A framework for motion based bodily enaction with virtual characters 2 1 Enaction Intelligent Virtual Agents Springer p 163 ISBN 9783642239731 Stephanie A Hillen 2013 Chapter III What can research on technology for learning in vocational educational training teach media didactics In Klaus Beck Olga Zlatkin Troitschanskaia eds From Diagnostics to Learning Success Proceedings in Vocational Education and Training Paperback ed Springer Science amp Business p 104 ISBN 978 9462091894 Jerome Bruner 1966 Toward a theory of instruction Belknap Press of Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674897007 Jerome Bruner 1968 Processes of cognitive growth Infancy Crown Pub ISBN 978 0517517482 OCLC 84376 Quote from Jerome Seymour Bruner 1966 Toward a Theory of Instruction PDF Harvard University Press p 44 ISBN 9780674897014 Archived from the original PDF on 2014 05 02 Retrieved 2014 05 01 as quoted from J Bruner 2004 Chapter 10 Sustaining mathematical activity In John Mason Sue Johnston Wilder eds Fundamental Constructs in Mathematics Education Paperback ed Taylor amp Francis p 260 ISBN 978 0415326988 Jeanette Bopry 2007 Providing a warrant for constructivist practice the contribution of Francisco Varela In Joe L Kincheloe Raymond A Horn eds The Praeger Handbook of Education and Psychology Volume 1 Greenwood Publishing Group pp 474 ff ISBN 9780313331237 Varela s enactive framework beginning with his collaboration on autopoiesis theory with his mentor Humberto Maturana and the development of enaction as a framework within which these theories work as a matter of course a b Bharath Sriraman Lyn English 2009 Enactivism Theories of Mathematics Education Seeking New Frontiers Springer pp 42 ff ISBN 978 3642007422 Wolff Michael Roth 2012 Epistemology and psychology Jean Piaget and modern constructivism Geometry as Objective Science in Elementary School Classrooms Mathematics in the Flesh Routledge pp 41 ff ISBN 978 1136732201 Gary Cziko 1997 Chapter 12 Education The provision and transmission of truth or the selectionist growth of fallible knowledge Without Miracles Universal Selection Theory and the Second Darwinian Revolution MIT Press p 222 ISBN 9780262531474 Joe L Kincheloe 2007 Interpretivists drawing on the power of enactivism In Joe L Kincheloe Raymond A Horn eds The Praeger Handbook of Education and Psychology Volume 1 Greenwood Publishing Group pp 24 ff ISBN 978 0313331237 Chris Breen 2005 Chapter 9 Dilemmas of change seeing the complex rather than the complicated In Renuka Vithal Jill Adler Christine Keitel eds Researching Mathematics Education in South Africa Perspectives Practices and Possibilities HSRC Press p 240 ISBN 978 0796920478 Ad J W van de Gevel Charles N Noussair 2013 3 2 2 Enactive artificial intelligence The nexus between artificial intelligence and economics Springer p 21 ISBN 978 3642336478 Enactivism may be considered as the most developed model of embodied situated cognition Knowing is inseparable from doing a b John Seely Brown Allan Collins Paul Duguid Jan Feb 1989 Situated cognition and the culture of learning Educational Researcher 18 1 32 42 doi 10 3102 0013189x018001032 hdl 2142 17979 S2CID 9824073 Archived from the original on 2014 10 08 Giulio Sandini Giorgio Metta David Vernon 2007 The iCub cognitive humanoid robot An open system research platform for enactive cognition In Max Lungarella Fumiya Iida Josh Bongard Rolf Pfeifer eds 50 Years of Artificial Intelligence Essays Dedicated to the 50th Anniversary of Artificial Intelligence Springer ISBN 9783540772958 Monica Bordegoni 2010 4 5 2 Design tools based upon enactive interfaces In Shuichi Fukuda ed Emotional Engineering Service Development Springer pp 78 ff ISBN 9781849964234 Don Norman 2013 Affordances The Design of Everyday Things Revised and expanded ed Basic Books p 11 ISBN 978 0465050659 An affordance is a relationship between the properties of an object and the capabilities of the agent that determine just how the object could possibly be used Georgios S Christou 2006 The use and evolution of affordance in HCI In Claude Ghaoui ed Encyclopedia of human computer interaction Idea Group Inc pp 668 ff ISBN 9781591407980 Mauri Kaipainen Niklas Ravaja Pia Tikka et al October 2011 Enactive Systems and Enactive Media Embodied Human Machine Coupling beyond Interfaces Leonardo 44 5 433 438 doi 10 1162 LEON a 00244 S2CID 17294711 Guy Boy 2012 Orchestrating Human Centered Design Springer p 118 ISBN 9781447143383 The organization producing the system can itself be defined as an autopoietic system in Maturana and Varela s sense An autopoietic system is producer and product at the same time HCD Human Centered Design is both the process of design and the design itself Markus Thannhuber Mitchell M Tseng Hans Jorg Bullinger 2001 An autopoietic approach for knowledge management systems in manufacturing enterprises Annals of the CIRP Manufacturing Technology 50 1 313 ff doi 10 1016 s0007 8506 07 62129 5 Randall D Beer 1995 A dynamical systems perspective on agent environment interaction Artificial Intelligence 72 1 2 173 215 doi 10 1016 0004 3702 94 00005 l James AS Kelso 2009 Coordination dynamics In R A Meyers ed Encyclopedia of complexity and system science pp 1537 1564 doi 10 1007 978 0 387 30440 3 101 ISBN 978 0 387 75888 6 Eliot L Saltzman 1995 Dynamics and coordinate systems in skilled sensorimotor activity In T van Gelder R F Port eds Mind as motion Explorations in the dynamics of cognition MIT Press p 151 ff ISBN 9780262161503 Marek McGann Hanne De Jaegher Ezequiel Di Paolo 2013 Enaction and psychology Review of General Psychology 17 2 203 209 doi 10 1037 a0032935 S2CID 8986622 Such modeling techniques allow us to explore the parameter space of coupling between agent and environment to the point that their basic principles the universals if such there are of enactive psychology can be brought clearly into view Legg Shane 2008 Machine Super Intelligence PDF Thesis University of Lugano Hutter Marcus 2005 Universal Artificial Intelligence Sequential Decisions Based on Algorithmic Probability Texts in Theoretical Computer Science an EATCS Series Springer doi 10 1007 b138233 ISBN 978 3 540 26877 2 Leike Jan Hutter Marcus 2015 Bad Universal Priors and Notions of Optimality The 28th Conference on Learning Theory arXiv 1510 04931 Val Danilov Igor 2023 Low Frequency Oscillations for Nonlocal Neuronal Coupling in Shared Intentionality Before and After Birth Toward the Origin of Perception OBM Neurobiology 7 4 1 17 doi 10 21926 obm neurobiol 2304192 Val Danilov Igor 2023 Shared Intentionality Modulation at the Cell Level Low Frequency Oscillations for Temporal Coordination in Bioengineering Systems OBM Neurobiology 7 4 1 17 doi 10 21926 obm neurobiol 2304185 a b c Val Danilov I 2023 Theoretical Grounds of Shared Intentionality for Neuroscience in Developing Bioengineering Systems OBM Neurobiology 2023 7 1 156 doi 10 21926 obm neurobiol 2301156 https www lidsen com journals neurobiology neurobiology 07 01 156 Further reading editClark Andy 2015 Surfing uncertainty Prediction action and the embodied mind Oxford University Press ISBN 9780190217013 De Jaegher H Di Paolo E A 2007 Participatory sense making An enactive approach to social cognition Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 6 4 485 507 doi 10 1007 s11097 007 9076 9 S2CID 142842155 Di Paolo E A Rohde M and De Jaegher H 2010 Horizons for the Enactive Mind Values Social Interaction and Play In J Stewart O Gapenne and E A Di Paolo eds Enaction Towards a New Paradigm for Cognitive Science Cambridge MA MIT Press pp 33 87 ISBN 9780262014601 Gallagher Shaun 2017 Enactivist Interventions Rethinking the Mind Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0198794325 Hutto D D Ed 2006 Radical Enactivism Intentionality phenomenology and narrative In R D Ellis amp N Newton Series Eds Consciousness amp Emotion vol 2 ISBN 90 272 4151 1 McGann M amp Torrance S 2005 Doing it and meaning it and the relationship between the two In R D Ellis amp N Newton Consciousness amp Emotion vol 1 Agency conscious choice and selective perception Amsterdam John Benjamins ISBN 1 58811 596 8 Merleau Ponty Maurice 2005 Phenomenology of Perception Routledge ISBN 9780415278416 Originally published 1945 Noe Alva 2010 Out of Our Heads Why You Are Not Your Brain and Other Lessons from the Biology of Consciousness Hill and Wang ISBN 978 0809016488 Tom Froese Ezequiel A DiPaolo 2011 The enactive approach Theoretical sketches from cell to society Pragmatics amp Cognition 19 1 1 36 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 224 5504 doi 10 1075 pc 19 1 01fro Steve Torrance Tom Froese 2011 An inter enactive approach to agency participatory sense making dynamics and sociality Humana Mente 15 21 53 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 187 1151 fr Domenico Masciotra 2023 Une approche enactive des formations Theorie et Methode En devenir competent et connaisseur ASCAR Inc Notes edit Cognition as information processing like that of a digital computer From Evan Thompson 2010 09 30 Mind in Life Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674057517 Cognitivism p 4 See also Steven Horst December 10 2009 The computational theory of mind In Edward N Zalta ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2011 Edition Cognition as emergent patterns of activity in a neural network From Evan Thompson 2010 09 30 Mind in Life Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0674057517 Connectionism p 8 See also James Garson July 27 2010 Edward N Zalta ed Connectionism The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2011 Edition External links edit Enactivism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Pietro Morasso 2005 Consciousness as the emergent property of the interaction between brain body amp environment the crucial role of haptic perception PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2006 05 08 Slides related to a chapter on haptic perception recognition through touch Pietro Morasso 2007 Chapter 14 The crucial role of haptic perception In Antonio Chella Riccardo Manzotti eds Artificial Consciousness Academic p 234 ff ISBN 978 1845400705 John Stewart Olivier Gapenne Bruno Bachimont eds Questioning Life and Cognition Some Foundational Issues in the Paradigm of Enaction Enaction Series Online Collaborative Publishing Enaction Series Archived from the original on April 27 2014 Retrieved April 27 2014 George Louis Baron Eric Bruillard Christophe Dansac January 1999 Educational Multimedia Task Force MM 1045 REPRESENTATION PDF An overview of the rationale and means and methods for the study of representations that the learner constructs in his her attempt to understand knowledge in a given field See in particular 1 2 1 4 Toward social representations p 24 Randall Whittaker 2001 Autopoiesis and enaction Observer Web Archived from the original on 2007 08 24 Retrieved 2014 05 23 An extensive but uncritical introduction to the work of Francisco Varela and Humberto Maturana Enactivism Arguments amp Applications Avant V 2 2014 Autumn 2014 doi 10 12849 50202014 0109 0002 inactive 31 January 2024 Retrieved 27 November 2014 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint DOI inactive as of January 2024 link Entire journal issue on enactivism s status and current debates Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Enactivism amp oldid 1212564369, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.