fbpx
Wikipedia

Definition of music

A definition of music endeavors to give an accurate and concise explanation of music's basic attributes or essential nature and it involves a process of defining what is meant by the term music. Many authorities have suggested definitions, but defining music turns out to be more difficult than might first be imagined, and there is ongoing debate. A number of explanations start with the notion of music as organized sound, but they also highlight that this is perhaps too broad a definition and cite examples of organized sound that are not defined as music, such as human speech and sounds found in both natural and industrial environments .[1] The problem of defining music is further complicated by the influence of culture in music cognition.

The Concise Oxford Dictionary defines music as "the art of combining vocal or instrumental sounds (or both) to produce beauty of form, harmony, and expression of emotion".[2] However, some music genres, such as noise music and musique concrète, challenge these ideas by using sounds not widely considered as musical, beautiful or harmonious, like randomly produced electronic distortion, feedback, static, cacophony, and sounds produced using compositional processes which utilize indeterminacy.[3][4]

An often-cited example of the dilemma in defining music is the work 4′33″ (1952) by the American composer John Cage (1912–1992). The written score has three movements and directs the performer(s) to appear on stage, indicate by gesture or other means when the piece begins, then make no sound throughout the duration of the piece, marking sections and the end by gesture. The audience hears only whatever ambient sounds may occur in the room. Some argue that 4′33″ is not music because, among other reasons, it contains no sounds that are conventionally considered "musical" and the composer and performer(s) exert no control over the organization of the sounds heard.[5] Others argue it is music because the conventional definitions of musical sounds are unnecessarily and arbitrarily limited, and control over the organization of the sounds is achieved by the composer and performer(s) through their gestures that divide what is heard into specific sections and a comprehensible form.[6]

Concepts of music Edit

Because of differing fundamental concepts of music, the languages of many cultures do not contain a word that can be accurately translated as "music" as that word is generally understood by Western cultures.[7] Inuit and most North American Indian languages do not have a general term for music. Among the Aztecs, the ancient Mexican theory of rhetoric, poetry, dance, and instrumental music used the Nahuatl term In xochitl-in kwikatl to refer to a complex mix of music and other poetic verbal and non-verbal elements, and reserved the word Kwikakayotl (or cuicacayotl) only for the sung expressions.[8] There is no term for music in Nigerian languages Tiv, Yoruba, Igbo, Efik, Birom, Hausa, Idoma, Eggon or Jarawa. Many other languages have terms which only partly cover what Western culture typically means by the term music.([9]) The Mapuche of Argentina do not have a word for music, but they do have words for instrumental versus improvised forms (kantun), European and non-Mapuche music (kantun winka), ceremonial songs (öl), and tayil.[10]

While some languages in West Africa have no term for music, some West African languages accept the general concepts of music.([11]) Musiqi is the Persian word for the science and art of music, muzik being the sound and performance of music,([12]) though some things European-influenced listeners would include, such as Quran chanting, are excluded.

Music vs. noise Edit

Ben Watson points out that Ludwig van Beethoven's Große Fuge (1825) "sounded like noise" to his audience at the time. Indeed, Beethoven's publishers persuaded him to remove it from its original setting as the last movement of a string quartet. He did so, replacing it with a sparkling Allegro. They subsequently published it separately.[13][clarification needed] Musicologist Jean-Jacques Nattiez considers the difference between noise and music nebulous, explaining that "The border between music and noise is always culturally defined—which implies that, even within a single society, this border does not always pass through the same place; in short, there is rarely a consensus ... By all accounts there is no single and intercultural universal concept defining what music might be".[14]

Definitions Edit

Organized sound Edit

An often-cited definition of music is that it is "organized sound", a term originally coined by modernist composer Edgard Varèse[15] in reference to his own musical aesthetic. Varèse's concept of music as "organized sound" fits into his vision of "sound as living matter" and of "musical space as open rather than bounded".[16] He conceived the elements of his music in terms of "sound-masses", likening their organization to the natural phenomenon of crystallization.[17] Varèse thought that "to stubbornly conditioned ears, anything new in music has always been called noise", and he posed the question, "what is music but organized noises?"[18]

The fifteenth edition of the Encyclopædia Britannica states that "while there are no sounds that can be described as inherently unmusical, musicians in each culture have tended to restrict the range of sounds they will admit." A human organizing element is often felt to be implicit in music (sounds produced by non-human agents, such as waterfalls or birds, are often described as "musical", but perhaps less often as "music"). The composer R. Murray[19] states that the sound of classical music "has decays; it is granular; it has attacks; it fluctuates, swollen with impurities—and all this creates a musicality that comes before any 'cultural' musicality." However, in the view of semiologist Jean-Jacques Nattiez, "just as music is whatever people choose to recognize as such, noise is whatever is recognized as disturbing, unpleasant, or both".[20] (See "music as social construct" below.)

Language Edit

Levi R. Bryant defines music not as a language, but as a marked-based, problem-solving method, comparable to mathematics.[21]

Musical universals Edit

Most definitions of music include a reference to sound and a list of universals of music can be generated by stating the elements (or aspects) of sound: pitch, timbre, loudness, duration, spatial location and texture.[22]). However, in terms more specifically relating to music: following Wittgenstein, cognitive psychologist Eleanor Rosch proposes that categories are not clean cut but that something may be more or less a member of a category.[23] As such the search for musical universals would fail and would not provide one with a valid definition.[24] This is primarily because other cultures have different understandings in relation to the sounds that English-language writers refer to as music.

Social construct Edit

Many people do, however, share a general idea of music. The Websters definition of music is a typical example: "the science or art of ordering tones or sounds in succession, in combination, and in temporal relationships to produce a composition having unity and continuity" (Webster's Collegiate Dictionary, online edition).

Subjective experience Edit

This approach to the definition focuses not on the construction but on the experience of music. An extreme statement of the position has been articulated by the Italian composer Luciano Berio: "Music is everything that one listens to with the intention of listening to music".[25] This approach permits the boundary between music and noise to change over time as the conventions of musical interpretation evolve within a culture, to be different in different cultures at any given moment, and to vary from person to person according to their experience and proclivities. It is further consistent with the subjective reality that even what would commonly be considered music is experienced as non-music if the mind is concentrating on other matters and thus not perceiving the sound's essence as music.[26]

Specific definitions Edit

Clifton Edit

In his 1983 book, Music as Heard, which sets out from the phenomenological position of Husserl, Merleau-Ponty, and Ricœur, Thomas Clifton defines music as "an ordered arrangement of sounds and silences whose meaning is presentative rather than denotative ... This definition distinguishes music, as an end in itself, from compositional technique, and from sounds as purely physical objects." More precisely, "music is the actualization of the possibility of any sound whatever to present to some human being a meaning which he experiences with his body—that is to say, with his mind, his feelings, his senses, his will, and his metabolism".[27] It is therefore "a certain reciprocal relation established between a person, his behavior, and a sounding object".[28]

Clifton accordingly differentiates music from non-music on the basis of the human behavior involved, rather than on either the nature of compositional technique or of sounds as purely physical objects. Consequently, the distinction becomes a question of what is meant by musical behavior: "a musically behaving person is one whose very being is absorbed in the significance of the sounds being experienced." However, "It is not altogether accurate to say that this person is listening to the sounds. First, the person is doing more than listening: he is perceiving, interpreting, judging, and feeling. Second, the preposition 'to' puts too much stress on the sounds as such. Thus, the musically behaving person experiences musical significance by means of, or through, the sounds".[29]

In this framework, Clifton finds that there are two things that separate music from non-music: (1) musical meaning is presentative, and (2) music and non-music are distinguished in the idea of personal involvement. "It is the notion of personal involvement which lends significance to the word ordered in this definition of music".[30] This is not to be understood, however, as a sanctification of extreme relativism, since "it is precisely the 'subjective' aspect of experience which lured many writers earlier in this century down the path of sheer opinion-mongering. Later on this trend was reversed by a renewed interest in 'objective,' scientific, or otherwise non-introspective musical analysis. But we have good reason to believe that a musical experience is not a purely private thing, like seeing pink elephants, and that reporting about such an experience need not be subjective in the sense of it being a mere matter of opinion".[31]

Clifton's task, then, is to describe musical experience and the objects of this experience which, together, are called "phenomena", and the activity of describing phenomena is called "phenomenology".[26] It is important to stress that this definition of music says nothing about aesthetic standards.

Music is not a fact or a thing in the world, but a meaning constituted by human beings. ... To talk about such experience in a meaningful way demands several things. First, we have to be willing to let the composition speak to us, to let it reveal its own order and significance. ... Second, we have to be willing to question our assumptions about the nature and role of musical materials. ... Last, and perhaps most important, we have to be ready to admit that describing a meaningful experience is itself meaningful.[32]

Nattiez Edit

"Music, often an art/entertainment, is a total social fact whose definitions vary according to era and culture", according to Jean.[33] It is often contrasted with noise. According to musicologist Jean-Jacques Nattiez: "The border between music and noise is always culturally defined—which implies that, even within a single society, this border does not always pass through the same place; in short, there is rarely a consensus ... By all accounts there is no single and intercultural universal concept defining what music might be".[34] Given the above demonstration that "there is no limit to the number or the genre of variables that might intervene in a definition of the musical",[35] an organization of definitions and elements is necessary.

Nattiez (1990, 17) describes definitions according to a tripartite semiological scheme similar to the following:

Poietic Process Esthesic Process
Composer (Producer) Sound (Trace) Listener (Receiver)

There are three levels of description, the poietic, the neutral, and the esthesic:

  • " By 'poietic' I understand describing the link among the composer's intentions, his creative procedures, his mental schemas, and the result of this collection of strategies; that is, the components that go into the work's material embodiment. Poietic description thus also deals with a quite special form of hearing (Varese called it 'the interior ear'): what the composer hears while imagining the work's sonorous results, or while experimenting at the piano, or with tape."
  • "By 'esthesic' I understand not merely the artificially attentive hearing of a musicologist, but the description of perceptive behaviors within a given population of listeners; that is how this or that aspect of sonorous reality is captured by their perceptive strategies".[36]
  • The neutral level is that of the physical "trace", (Saussere's sound-image, a sonority, a score), created and interpreted by the esthesic level (which corresponds to a perceptive definition; the perceptive and/or "social" construction definitions below) and the poietic level (which corresponds to a creative, as in compositional, definition; the organizational and social construction definitions below).

Table describing types of definitions of music:[37]

poietic level
(choice of the composer)
neutral level
(physical definition)
esthesic level
(perceptive judgment)
music musical sound sound of the
harmonic
spectrum
agreeable sound
non-music noise
(nonmusical)
noise
(complex sound)
disagreeable
noise

Because of this range of definitions, the study of music comes in a wide variety of forms. There is the study of sound and vibration or acoustics, the cognitive study of music, the study of music theory and performance practice or music theory and ethnomusicology and the study of the reception and history of music, generally called musicology.

Xenakis Edit

Composer Iannis Xenakis in "Towards a Metamusic" (chapter 7 of Formalized Music) defined music in the following way:[38]

  1. It is a sort of comportment necessary for whoever thinks it and makes it.
  2. It is an individual pleroma, a realization.
  3. It is a fixing in sound of imagined virtualities (cosmological, philosophical, ..., arguments)
  4. It is normative, that is, unconsciously it is a model for being or for doing by sympathetic drive.
  5. It is catalytic: its mere presence permits internal psychic or mental transformations in the same way as the crystal ball of the hypnotist.
  6. It is the gratuitous play of a child.
  7. It is a mystical (but atheistic) asceticism. Consequently, expressions of sadness, joy, love and dramatic situations are only very limited particular instances.

See also Edit

References Edit

Sources

  • Ashby, Arved, ed. 2004. The Pleasure of Modernist Music: Listening, Meaning, Intention, Ideology. Eastman Studies in Music 29. Rochester, New York: University of Rochester Press. ISBN 1-58046-143-3.
  • Berio, Luciano, Rossana Dalmonte, and Bálint András Varga. 1985. Two Interviews, translated and edited by David Osmond-Smith. New York: Marion Boyars. ISBN 0-7145-2829-3.
  • Burton, Russell L. 2015. "The Elements of Music: What Are They, and Who Cares? In Music: Educating for Life: Adelaide, 30 September – 2 October 2015: ASME XXth National Conference Proceedings, edited by Jennifer Rosevear and Susan Harding, 22–28. Parkville, Victoria: The Australian Society for Music Education. ISBN 9780980379242.
  • Chou Wen-chung. 1966a. "Open Rather Than Bounded". Perspectives of New Music 5, no. 1 (Autumn–Winter): 1–6.
  • Chou Wen-chung. 1966b. "Varèse: A Sketch of the Man and His Music". The Musical Quarterly 52, no. 2 (April): 151–170.
  • Clifton, Thomas. 1983. Music as Heard: A Study in Applied Phenomenology. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. ISBN 0-300-02091-0.
  • The Concise Oxford Dictionary. Allen, R. E., ed. 1992. Clarendon Press. Oxford: 781
  • Dodd, Julian. 2013. "Is John Cage's 4′33″ Music?". You Tube/Tedx (accessed 14 July 2014).
  • Gann, Kyle. 2010. No Such Thing as Silence: John Cage's 4′33″. New Haven and London: Yale University Press. ISBN 0300136994.
  • Goldman, Richard Franko. 1961. "Varèse: Ionisation; Density 21.5; Intégrales; Octandre; Hyperprism; Poème Electronique. Instrumentalists, cond. Robert Craft. Columbia MS 6146 (stereo)" (in Reviews of Records). The Musical Quarterly 47, no. 1. (January):133–134.
  • Hegarty, Paul, 2007. Noise/Music: A History. Continuum International Publishing Group. London: 3-19
  • Kania, Andrew. 2014. "The Philosophy of Music", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2014 edition, edited by Edward N. Zalta.
  • Leon-Portilla, Miguel. 2007. "La música de los aztecas / Music Among Aztecs", Pauta, no. 103:7–19.
  • Levitin, Daniel J. 2006. This Is Your Brain on Music: The Science of a Human Obsession. New York: Dutton. ISBN 0-525-94969-0.
  • Molino, Jean. 1975. "Fait musical et sémiologue de la musique", Musique en jeu, no. 17:37–62.
  • Nattiez, Jean-Jacques. 1990. Music and Discourse: Toward a Semiology of Music, translated by Carolyn Abbate. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-09136-6.
  • Nettl, Bruno. 1989. Blackfoot Musical Thought: Comparative Perspectives. Ohio: The Kent State University Press. ISBN 0-87338-370-2.
  • Nettl, Bruno. 2005. "The Art of Combining Tones: The Music Concept". The Study of Ethnomusicology. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, pp. 26–37 ISBN 0-252-07278-2.
  • Priest, Eldritch. 2013. Boring Formless Nonsense: Experimental Music and The Aesthetics of Failure. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 9781441122131.
  • Robertson–de Carbo, Carol Elizabeth. 1976. "Tayil as Category and Communication among the Argentine Mapuche: A Methodological Suggestion". Yearbook of the International Folk Music Council 8:35–42.
  • Rosch, Eleanor. 1973. "Natural Categories". Cognitive Psychology 4, no. 3 (May): 328–350.
  • Sakata, Lorraine. 1983. Music in the Mind, The Concepts of Music and Musicians in Afghanistan. Kent: Kent State University Press. ISBN 087338265X
  • Schafer, R. Murray. 1996. "Music and the Soundscape", in Classic Essays on Twentieth-Century Music: A Continuing Symposium, edited by Richard Kostelanetz and Joseph Darby, with Matthew Santa, pp. 221-231 New York: Schirmer Books; London: Prentice Hall International. ISBN 0-02-864581-2 (pbk).
  • Varèse, Edgard, and Chou Wen-chung. 1966. "The Liberation of Sound". Perspectives of New Music 5, no. 1 (Autumn–Winter): 11–19.
  • Watson, Ben. n.d. "Noise as Permanent Revolution".[full citation needed]
  • Xenakis, Iannis. 1971. Formalized Music: Thought and Mathematics in Composition. Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press.

Further reading Edit

  • Cage, John. "An Autobiographical Statement". johncage.org. Originally published in Southwest Review, 1991.
  • Gutmann, P. (2015). "John Cage and the Avant-Garde: The Sounds of Silence}, classicalnotes.net. Retrieved 2 December 2015.
  • Kennedy, Michael. 1985. The Oxford Dictionary of Music, revised and enlarged edition of The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Music, third edition, 1980. Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-311333-6; ISBN 978-0-19-869162-4.
  • List, George. 1985. "Hopi Melodic Concepts". Journal of the American Musicological Society 38, no. 1 (Spring): 143–152.
  • Little, William, and C. T. Onions, eds. 1965. The Oxford Universal Dictionary Illustrated: An illustrated Edition of the Shorter Oxford Dictionary, third edition, revised, 2 vols. London: The Caxton Publishing Co.
  • Merriam-webster.com,. (2015). music: "sounds that are sung by voices or played on musical instruments." Retrieved 1 December 2015.}
  • Nettl, Bruno. 2001. "Music". The New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians, second edition, edited by Stanley Sadie and John Tyrrell. London: Macmillan Publishers.

External links Edit

  •   Media related to Definition of music at Wikimedia Commons
  • What is Music? A brief sketch of some definitions found throughout history by Marcel Cobussen
  • MusicNovatory.com The Science of Music, a generative music theory

definition, music, organized, sound, redirects, here, journal, organised, sound, definition, music, endeavors, give, accurate, concise, explanation, music, basic, attributes, essential, nature, involves, process, defining, what, meant, term, music, many, autho. Organized sound redirects here For the journal see Organised Sound A definition of music endeavors to give an accurate and concise explanation of music s basic attributes or essential nature and it involves a process of defining what is meant by the term music Many authorities have suggested definitions but defining music turns out to be more difficult than might first be imagined and there is ongoing debate A number of explanations start with the notion of music as organized sound but they also highlight that this is perhaps too broad a definition and cite examples of organized sound that are not defined as music such as human speech and sounds found in both natural and industrial environments 1 The problem of defining music is further complicated by the influence of culture in music cognition The Concise Oxford Dictionary defines music as the art of combining vocal or instrumental sounds or both to produce beauty of form harmony and expression of emotion 2 However some music genres such as noise music and musique concrete challenge these ideas by using sounds not widely considered as musical beautiful or harmonious like randomly produced electronic distortion feedback static cacophony and sounds produced using compositional processes which utilize indeterminacy 3 4 An often cited example of the dilemma in defining music is the work 4 33 1952 by the American composer John Cage 1912 1992 The written score has three movements and directs the performer s to appear on stage indicate by gesture or other means when the piece begins then make no sound throughout the duration of the piece marking sections and the end by gesture The audience hears only whatever ambient sounds may occur in the room Some argue that 4 33 is not music because among other reasons it contains no sounds that are conventionally considered musical and the composer and performer s exert no control over the organization of the sounds heard 5 Others argue it is music because the conventional definitions of musical sounds are unnecessarily and arbitrarily limited and control over the organization of the sounds is achieved by the composer and performer s through their gestures that divide what is heard into specific sections and a comprehensible form 6 Contents 1 Concepts of music 2 Music vs noise 3 Definitions 3 1 Organized sound 3 1 1 Language 3 2 Musical universals 3 3 Social construct 3 4 Subjective experience 4 Specific definitions 4 1 Clifton 4 2 Nattiez 4 3 Xenakis 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksConcepts of music EditBecause of differing fundamental concepts of music the languages of many cultures do not contain a word that can be accurately translated as music as that word is generally understood by Western cultures 7 Inuit and most North American Indian languages do not have a general term for music Among the Aztecs the ancient Mexican theory of rhetoric poetry dance and instrumental music used the Nahuatl term In xochitl in kwikatl to refer to a complex mix of music and other poetic verbal and non verbal elements and reserved the word Kwikakayotl or cuicacayotl only for the sung expressions 8 There is no term for music in Nigerian languages Tiv Yoruba Igbo Efik Birom Hausa Idoma Eggon or Jarawa Many other languages have terms which only partly cover what Western culture typically means by the term music 9 The Mapuche of Argentina do not have a word for music but they do have words for instrumental versus improvised forms kantun European and non Mapuche music kantun winka ceremonial songs ol and tayil 10 While some languages in West Africa have no term for music some West African languages accept the general concepts of music 11 Musiqi is the Persian word for the science and art of music muzik being the sound and performance of music 12 though some things European influenced listeners would include such as Quran chanting are excluded Music vs noise EditBen Watson points out that Ludwig van Beethoven s Grosse Fuge 1825 sounded like noise to his audience at the time Indeed Beethoven s publishers persuaded him to remove it from its original setting as the last movement of a string quartet He did so replacing it with a sparkling Allegro They subsequently published it separately 13 clarification needed Musicologist Jean Jacques Nattiez considers the difference between noise and music nebulous explaining that The border between music and noise is always culturally defined which implies that even within a single society this border does not always pass through the same place in short there is rarely a consensus By all accounts there is no single and intercultural universal concept defining what music might be 14 Definitions EditOrganized sound Edit See also Musique concrete Acousmatic music and Spectral music An often cited definition of music is that it is organized sound a term originally coined by modernist composer Edgard Varese 15 in reference to his own musical aesthetic Varese s concept of music as organized sound fits into his vision of sound as living matter and of musical space as open rather than bounded 16 He conceived the elements of his music in terms of sound masses likening their organization to the natural phenomenon of crystallization 17 Varese thought that to stubbornly conditioned ears anything new in music has always been called noise and he posed the question what is music but organized noises 18 The fifteenth edition of the Encyclopaedia Britannica states that while there are no sounds that can be described as inherently unmusical musicians in each culture have tended to restrict the range of sounds they will admit A human organizing element is often felt to be implicit in music sounds produced by non human agents such as waterfalls or birds are often described as musical but perhaps less often as music The composer R Murray 19 states that the sound of classical music has decays it is granular it has attacks it fluctuates swollen with impurities and all this creates a musicality that comes before any cultural musicality However in the view of semiologist Jean Jacques Nattiez just as music is whatever people choose to recognize as such noise is whatever is recognized as disturbing unpleasant or both 20 See music as social construct below Language Edit Main article Musical language Levi R Bryant defines music not as a language but as a marked based problem solving method comparable to mathematics 21 Musical universals Edit Main article Elements of music Most definitions of music include a reference to sound and a list of universals of music can be generated by stating the elements or aspects of sound pitch timbre loudness duration spatial location and texture 22 However in terms more specifically relating to music following Wittgenstein cognitive psychologist Eleanor Rosch proposes that categories are not clean cut but that something may be more or less a member of a category 23 As such the search for musical universals would fail and would not provide one with a valid definition 24 This is primarily because other cultures have different understandings in relation to the sounds that English language writers refer to as music Social construct Edit Main article Ethnomusicology Many people do however share a general idea of music The Websters definition of music is a typical example the science or art of ordering tones or sounds in succession in combination and in temporal relationships to produce a composition having unity and continuity Webster s Collegiate Dictionary online edition Subjective experience Edit Main article Aesthetics of music This approach to the definition focuses not on the construction but on the experience of music An extreme statement of the position has been articulated by the Italian composer Luciano Berio Music is everything that one listens to with the intention of listening to music 25 This approach permits the boundary between music and noise to change over time as the conventions of musical interpretation evolve within a culture to be different in different cultures at any given moment and to vary from person to person according to their experience and proclivities It is further consistent with the subjective reality that even what would commonly be considered music is experienced as non music if the mind is concentrating on other matters and thus not perceiving the sound s essence as music 26 Specific definitions EditClifton Edit In his 1983 book Music as Heard which sets out from the phenomenological position of Husserl Merleau Ponty and Ricœur Thomas Clifton defines music as an ordered arrangement of sounds and silences whose meaning is presentative rather than denotative This definition distinguishes music as an end in itself from compositional technique and from sounds as purely physical objects More precisely music is the actualization of the possibility of any sound whatever to present to some human being a meaning which he experiences with his body that is to say with his mind his feelings his senses his will and his metabolism 27 It is therefore a certain reciprocal relation established between a person his behavior and a sounding object 28 Clifton accordingly differentiates music from non music on the basis of the human behavior involved rather than on either the nature of compositional technique or of sounds as purely physical objects Consequently the distinction becomes a question of what is meant by musical behavior a musically behaving person is one whose very being is absorbed in the significance of the sounds being experienced However It is not altogether accurate to say that this person is listening to the sounds First the person is doing more than listening he is perceiving interpreting judging and feeling Second the preposition to puts too much stress on the sounds as such Thus the musically behaving person experiences musical significance by means of or through the sounds 29 In this framework Clifton finds that there are two things that separate music from non music 1 musical meaning is presentative and 2 music and non music are distinguished in the idea of personal involvement It is the notion of personal involvement which lends significance to the word ordered in this definition of music 30 This is not to be understood however as a sanctification of extreme relativism since it is precisely the subjective aspect of experience which lured many writers earlier in this century down the path of sheer opinion mongering Later on this trend was reversed by a renewed interest in objective scientific or otherwise non introspective musical analysis But we have good reason to believe that a musical experience is not a purely private thing like seeing pink elephants and that reporting about such an experience need not be subjective in the sense of it being a mere matter of opinion 31 Clifton s task then is to describe musical experience and the objects of this experience which together are called phenomena and the activity of describing phenomena is called phenomenology 26 It is important to stress that this definition of music says nothing about aesthetic standards Music is not a fact or a thing in the world but a meaning constituted by human beings To talk about such experience in a meaningful way demands several things First we have to be willing to let the composition speak to us to let it reveal its own order and significance Second we have to be willing to question our assumptions about the nature and role of musical materials Last and perhaps most important we have to be ready to admit that describing a meaningful experience is itself meaningful 32 Nattiez Edit Music often an art entertainment is a total social fact whose definitions vary according to era and culture according to Jean 33 It is often contrasted with noise According to musicologist Jean Jacques Nattiez The border between music and noise is always culturally defined which implies that even within a single society this border does not always pass through the same place in short there is rarely a consensus By all accounts there is no single and intercultural universal concept defining what music might be 34 Given the above demonstration that there is no limit to the number or the genre of variables that might intervene in a definition of the musical 35 an organization of definitions and elements is necessary Nattiez 1990 17 describes definitions according to a tripartite semiological scheme similar to the following Poietic Process Esthesic ProcessComposer Producer Sound Trace Listener Receiver There are three levels of description the poietic the neutral and the esthesic By poietic I understand describing the link among the composer s intentions his creative procedures his mental schemas and the result of this collection of strategies that is the components that go into the work s material embodiment Poietic description thus also deals with a quite special form of hearing Varese called it the interior ear what the composer hears while imagining the work s sonorous results or while experimenting at the piano or with tape By esthesic I understand not merely the artificially attentive hearing of a musicologist but the description of perceptive behaviors within a given population of listeners that is how this or that aspect of sonorous reality is captured by their perceptive strategies 36 The neutral level is that of the physical trace Saussere s sound image a sonority a score created and interpreted by the esthesic level which corresponds to a perceptive definition the perceptive and or social construction definitions below and the poietic level which corresponds to a creative as in compositional definition the organizational and social construction definitions below Table describing types of definitions of music 37 poietic level choice of the composer neutral level physical definition esthesic level perceptive judgment music musical sound sound of theharmonicspectrum agreeable soundnon music noise nonmusical noise complex sound disagreeablenoiseBecause of this range of definitions the study of music comes in a wide variety of forms There is the study of sound and vibration or acoustics the cognitive study of music the study of music theory and performance practice or music theory and ethnomusicology and the study of the reception and history of music generally called musicology Xenakis Edit Composer Iannis Xenakis in Towards a Metamusic chapter 7 of Formalized Music defined music in the following way 38 It is a sort of comportment necessary for whoever thinks it and makes it It is an individual pleroma a realization It is a fixing in sound of imagined virtualities cosmological philosophical arguments It is normative that is unconsciously it is a model for being or for doing by sympathetic drive It is catalytic its mere presence permits internal psychic or mental transformations in the same way as the crystal ball of the hypnotist It is the gratuitous play of a child It is a mystical but atheistic asceticism Consequently expressions of sadness joy love and dramatic situations are only very limited particular instances See also EditZoomusicology Sound artReferences Edit Kania 2014 Concise Oxford Dictionary 1992 Priest 2013 132 Hagerty 2007 Dodd 2013 Gann 2010 Nettl 2005 Leon Portilla 2007 11 Schafer 1996 222 223 Robertson de Carbo 1976 39 Nettl 1989 48 Sakata 1983 39 Watson n d 109 110 Nattiez 1990 48 55 Goldman 1961 133 Chou 1966a 1 4 Chou 1966b 157 Varese and Chou 1966 18 Schafer 1996 284 Nattiez 1990 47 48 Ashby 2004 4 Burton 2015 22 28 Rosch 1973 328 Levitin 2006 136 139 Berio Dalmonte amp Varga 1985 19 a b Clifton 1983 9 Clifton 1983 1 Clifton 1983 10 Clifton 1983 2 Clifton 1983 3 4 Clifton 1983 8 9 Clifton 1983 5 6 Molino 1975 37 Nattiez 1990 47 48 55 Molino 1975 42 Nattiez 1990 90 Nattiez 1990 46 Xenakis 1971 181 Sources Ashby Arved ed 2004 The Pleasure of Modernist Music Listening Meaning Intention Ideology Eastman Studies in Music 29 Rochester New York University of Rochester Press ISBN 1 58046 143 3 Berio Luciano Rossana Dalmonte and Balint Andras Varga 1985 Two Interviews translated and edited by David Osmond Smith New York Marion Boyars ISBN 0 7145 2829 3 Burton Russell L 2015 The Elements of Music What Are They and Who Cares In Music Educating for Life Adelaide 30 September 2 October 2015 ASME XXth National Conference Proceedings edited by Jennifer Rosevear and Susan Harding 22 28 Parkville Victoria The Australian Society for Music Education ISBN 9780980379242 Chou Wen chung 1966a Open Rather Than Bounded Perspectives of New Music 5 no 1 Autumn Winter 1 6 Chou Wen chung 1966b Varese A Sketch of the Man and His Music The Musical Quarterly 52 no 2 April 151 170 Clifton Thomas 1983 Music as Heard A Study in Applied Phenomenology New Haven and London Yale University Press ISBN 0 300 02091 0 The Concise Oxford Dictionary Allen R E ed 1992 Clarendon Press Oxford 781 Dodd Julian 2013 Is John Cage s 4 33 Music You Tube Tedx accessed 14 July 2014 Gann Kyle 2010 No Such Thing as Silence John Cage s 4 33 New Haven and London Yale University Press ISBN 0300136994 Goldman Richard Franko 1961 Varese Ionisation Density 21 5 Integrales Octandre Hyperprism Poeme Electronique Instrumentalists cond Robert Craft Columbia MS 6146 stereo in Reviews of Records The Musical Quarterly 47 no 1 January 133 134 Hegarty Paul 2007 Noise Music A History Continuum International Publishing Group London 3 19 Kania Andrew 2014 The Philosophy of Music The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2014 edition edited by Edward N Zalta Leon Portilla Miguel 2007 La musica de los aztecas Music Among Aztecs Pauta no 103 7 19 Levitin Daniel J 2006 This Is Your Brain on Music The Science of a Human Obsession New York Dutton ISBN 0 525 94969 0 Molino Jean 1975 Fait musical et semiologue de la musique Musique en jeu no 17 37 62 Nattiez Jean Jacques 1990 Music and Discourse Toward a Semiology of Music translated by Carolyn Abbate Princeton Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 09136 6 Nettl Bruno 1989 Blackfoot Musical Thought Comparative Perspectives Ohio The Kent State University Press ISBN 0 87338 370 2 Nettl Bruno 2005 The Art of Combining Tones The Music Concept The Study of Ethnomusicology 2nd ed Chicago University of Illinois Press pp 26 37 ISBN 0 252 07278 2 Priest Eldritch 2013 Boring Formless Nonsense Experimental Music and The Aesthetics of Failure New York Bloomsbury Publishing ISBN 9781441122131 Robertson de Carbo Carol Elizabeth 1976 Tayil as Category and Communication among the Argentine Mapuche A Methodological Suggestion Yearbook of the International Folk Music Council 8 35 42 Rosch Eleanor 1973 Natural Categories Cognitive Psychology 4 no 3 May 328 350 Sakata Lorraine 1983 Music in the Mind The Concepts of Music and Musicians in Afghanistan Kent Kent State University Press ISBN 087338265X Schafer R Murray 1996 Music and the Soundscape in Classic Essays on Twentieth Century Music A Continuing Symposium edited by Richard Kostelanetz and Joseph Darby with Matthew Santa pp 221 231 New York Schirmer Books London Prentice Hall International ISBN 0 02 864581 2 pbk Varese Edgard and Chou Wen chung 1966 The Liberation of Sound Perspectives of New Music 5 no 1 Autumn Winter 11 19 Watson Ben n d Noise as Permanent Revolution full citation needed Xenakis Iannis 1971 Formalized Music Thought and Mathematics in Composition Bloomington and London Indiana University Press Further reading EditCage John An Autobiographical Statement johncage org Originally published in Southwest Review 1991 Gutmann P 2015 John Cage and the Avant Garde The Sounds of Silence classicalnotes net Retrieved 2 December 2015 Kennedy Michael 1985 The Oxford Dictionary of Music revised and enlarged edition of The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Music third edition 1980 Oxford and New York Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 311333 6 ISBN 978 0 19 869162 4 List George 1985 Hopi Melodic Concepts Journal of the American Musicological Society 38 no 1 Spring 143 152 Little William and C T Onions eds 1965 The Oxford Universal Dictionary Illustrated An illustrated Edition of the Shorter Oxford Dictionary third edition revised 2 vols London The Caxton Publishing Co Merriam webster com 2015 music sounds that are sung by voices or played on musical instruments Retrieved 1 December 2015 Nettl Bruno 2001 Music The New Grove Dictionary of Music and Musicians second edition edited by Stanley Sadie and John Tyrrell London Macmillan Publishers External links Edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Definitions of music nbsp Media related to Definition of music at Wikimedia Commons What is Music A brief sketch of some definitions found throughout history by Marcel Cobussen MusicNovatory com The Science of Music a generative music theory Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Definition of music amp oldid 1177789631, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.