fbpx
Wikipedia

On the Soul

On the Soul (Greek: Περὶ Ψυχῆς, Peri Psychēs; Latin: De Anima) is a major treatise written by Aristotle c. 350 BC.[1] His discussion centres on the kinds of souls possessed by different kinds of living things, distinguished by their different operations. Thus plants have the capacity for nourishment and reproduction, the minimum that must be possessed by any kind of living organism. Lower animals have, in addition, the powers of sense-perception and self-motion (action). Humans have all these as well as intellect.

"Expositio et quaestiones" in Aristoteles De Anima (Jean Buridan, c. 1362)

Aristotle holds that the soul (psyche, ψυχή) is the form, or essence of any living thing; it is not a distinct substance from the body that it is in. It is the possession of a soul (of a specific kind) that makes an organism an organism at all, and thus that the notion of a body without a soul, or of a soul in the wrong kind of body, is simply unintelligible. (He argues that some parts of the soul — the intellect — can exist without the body, but most cannot.)

In 1855, Charles Collier published a translation titled On the Vital Principle. George Henry Lewes, however, found this description also wanting.[2]

Division of chapters edit

The treatise is divided into three books, and each of the books is divided into chapters (five, twelve, and thirteen, respectively). The treatise is near-universally abbreviated "DA", for "De anima", and books and chapters generally referred to by Roman and Arabic numerals, respectively, along with corresponding Bekker numbers. (Thus, "DA I.1, 402a1" means "De anima, book I, chapter 1, Bekker page 402, Bekker column a [the column on the left side of the page], line number 1.)

Book I edit

DA I.1 introduces the theme of the treatise;
DA I.2–5 provide a survey of Aristotle’s predecessors’ views about the soul

Book II edit

DA II.1–3 gives Aristotle's definition of soul and outlines his own study of it,[3] which is then pursued as follows:
DA II.4 discusses nutrition and reproduction;
DA II.5–6 discuss sensation in general;
DA II.7–11 discuss each of the five senses (in the following order: sight, sound, smell, taste, and touch—one chapter for each);
DA II.12 again takes up the general question of sensation;

Book III edit

DA III.1 argues there are no other senses than the five already mentioned;
DA III.2 discusses the problem of what it means to "sense sensing" (i.e., to "be aware" of sensation);
DA III.3 investigates the nature of imagination;
DA III.4–7 discuss thinking and the intellect, or mind;
DA III.8 articulates the definition and nature of soul;
DA III.9–10 discuss the movement of animals possessing all the senses;
DA III.11 discusses the movement of animals possessing only touch;
DA III.12–13 take up the question of what are the minimal constituents of having a soul and being alive.

Summary edit

Book I contains a summary of Aristotle's method of investigation and a dialectical determination of the nature of the soul. He begins by conceding that attempting to define the soul is one of the most difficult questions in the world. But he proposes an ingenious method to tackle the question:

Just as we can come to know the properties and operations of something through scientific demonstration, i.e. a geometrical proof that a triangle has its interior angles equal to two right angles, since the principle of all scientific demonstration is the essence of the object, so too we can come to know the nature of a thing if we already know its properties and operations. It is like finding the middle term to a syllogism with a known conclusion.

Therefore, we must seek out such operations of the soul to determine what kind of nature it has. From a consideration of the opinions of his predecessors, a soul, he concludes, will be that in virtue of which living things have life.

Book II contains his scientific determination of the nature of the soul, an element of his biology. By dividing substance into its three meanings (matter, form, and what is composed of both), he shows that the soul must be the first actuality of a natural, organized body. This is its form or essence. It cannot be matter because the soul is that in virtue of which things have life, and matter is only being in potency. The rest of the book is divided into a determination of the nature of the nutritive and sensitive souls.

(1) All species of living things, plant or animal, must be able to nourish themselves, and reproduce others of the same kind.
(2) All animals have, in addition to the nutritive power, sense-perception, and thus they all have at least the sense of touch, which he argues is presupposed by all other senses, and the ability to feel pleasure and pain, which is the simplest kind of perception. If they can feel pleasure and pain they also have desire.

Some animals in addition have other senses (sight, hearing, taste), and some have more subtle versions of each (the ability to distinguish objects in a complex way, beyond mere pleasure and pain.) He discusses how these function. Some animals have in addition the powers of memory, imagination, and self-motion.

 
Aristotle describes the structure of the souls of plants, animals, and humans in Books II and III.

Book III discusses the mind or rational soul, which belongs to humans alone. He argues that thinking is different from both sense-perception and imagination because the senses can never lie and imagination is a power to make something sensed appear again, while thinking can sometimes be false. And since the mind is able to think when it wishes, it must be divided into two faculties: One which contains all the mind's ideas which are able to be considered, and another which brings them into action, i.e. to be actually thinking about them.

These are called the possible and agent intellect. The possible intellect is an "unscribed tablet" and the store-house of all concepts, i.e. universal ideas like "triangle", "tree", "man", "red", etc. When the mind wishes to think, the agent intellect recalls these ideas from the possible intellect and combines them to form thoughts. The agent intellect is also the faculty which abstracts the "whatness" or intelligibility of all sensed objects and stores them in the possible intellect.

For example, when a student learns a proof for the Pythagorean theorem, his agent intellect abstracts the intelligibility of all the images his eye senses (and that are a result of the translation by imagination of sense perceptions into immaterial phantasmata), i.e. the triangles and squares in the diagrams, and stores the concepts that make up the proof in his possible intellect. When he wishes to recall the proof, say, for demonstration in class the next day, his agent intellect recalls the concepts and their relations from the possible intellect and formulates the statements that make up the arguments in the proof.

The argument for the existence of the agent intellect in Chapter V perhaps due to its concision has been interpreted in a variety of ways. One standard scholastic interpretation is given in the Commentary on De anima begun by Thomas Aquinas.[a] Aquinas' commentary is based on the new translation of the text from the Greek completed by Aquinas' Dominican associate William of Moerbeke at Viterbo in 1267.[4]

The argument, as interpreted by Thomas Aquinas, runs something like this: In every nature which is sometimes in potency and act, it is necessary to posit an agent or cause within that genus that, just like art in relation to its suffering matter, brings the object into act. But the soul is sometimes in potency and act. Therefore, the soul must have this difference. In other words, since the mind can move from not understanding to understanding and from knowing to thinking, there must be something to cause the mind to go from knowing nothing to knowing something, and from knowing something but not thinking about it to actually thinking about it.

Aristotle also argues that the mind (only the agent intellect) is immaterial, able to exist without the body, and immortal. His arguments are notoriously concise. This has caused much confusion over the centuries, causing a rivalry between different schools of interpretation, most notably, between the Arabian commentator Averroes and Thomas Aquinas.[citation needed] One argument for its immaterial existence runs like this: if the mind were material, then it would have to possess a corresponding thinking-organ. And since all the senses have their corresponding sense-organs, thinking would then be like sensing. But sensing can never be false, and therefore thinking could never be false. And this is of course untrue. Therefore, Aristotle concludes, the mind is immaterial.

Perhaps the most important but obscure argument in the whole book is Aristotle's demonstration of the immortality of the thinking part of the human soul, also in Chapter V. Taking a premise from his Physics, that as a thing acts, so it is, he argues that since the active principle in our mind acts with no bodily organ, it can exist without the body. And if it exists apart from matter, it therefore cannot be corrupted. And therefore there exists a mind which is immortal. As to what mind Aristotle is referring to in Chapter V (i.e. divine, human, or a kind of world soul), has represented a hot topic of discussion for centuries. The most likely is probably the interpretation of Alexander of Aphrodisias, likening Aristotle's immortal mind to an impersonal activity, ultimately represented by God.

Arabic paraphrase edit

In Late Antiquity, Aristotelian texts became re-interpreted in terms of Neoplatonism. There is a paraphrase of De Anima which survives in the Arabic tradition which reflects such a Neoplatonic synthesis. The text was translated into Persian in the 13th century. It is likely based on a Greek original which is no longer extant, and which was further syncretised in the heterogeneous process of adoption into early Arabic literature.[5]

A later Arabic translation of De Anima into Arabic is due to Ishaq ibn Hunayn (d. 910). Ibn Zura (d. 1008) made a translation into Arabic from Syriac. The Arabic versions show a complicated history of mutual influence. Avicenna (d. 1037) wrote a commentary on De Anima, which was translated into Latin by Michael Scotus. Averroes (d. 1198) used two Arabic translations, mostly relying on the one by Ishaq ibn Hunayn, but occasionally quoting the older one as an alternative. Zerahiah ben Shealtiel Ḥen translated Aristotle's De anima from Arabic into Hebrew in 1284. Both Averroes and Zerahiah used the translation by Ibn Zura.[6]

Some manuscripts edit

Codex Vaticanus 253 edit

Codex Vaticanus 253 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol L. Paleographically it has been assigned to the 13th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript is not complete; it contains only Book III. It belongs to the textual family λ, together with the manuscripts E, Fc, Lc, Kd, and P.

The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library (gr. 253) in Rome.

Codex Vaticanus 260 edit

Codex Vaticanus 260 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol U. Paleographically it has been assigned to the 11th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise. It belongs to the textual family ν, together with the manuscripts X, v, Ud, Ad, and Q.

The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library (Vat. gr. 260) in Rome.

Codex Vaticanus 266 edit

Codex Vaticanus 266 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol V. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 14th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise. It belongs to the textual family κ, but only to Chapter 8. of II book.

Another member of the family κ: Gc W Hc Nc Jd Oc Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td.

The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, and Apelt in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. David Ross did not use the manuscript in his own edition. Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library (gr. 266) in Rome.

Codex Vaticanus 1026 edit

Codex Vaticanus 1026 is a manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by symbol W. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 13th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The Greek text of the manuscript is eclectic. It belongs to the textual family μ[7] to II book, 7 chapter, 419 a 27. Since 419 a 27 it is a representative of the family κ.[8]

The manuscript was not cited by Trendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. It means the manuscript has not high value. Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library (gr. 1026) at Rome.

Codex Vaticanus 1339 edit

Codex Vaticanus 1339 is a manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by symbol P. Paleographically it has been assigned to the 14th or 15th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The text of the manuscript is eclectic. It represents the textual family σ in book II of the treatise, from II, 2, 314b11, to II, 8, 420a2.[9] After book II, chapter 9, 429b16, it belongs to the family λ.[10]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in rheir critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. This means the manuscript is not of high value. Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library (gr. 1339) at Rome.

Codex Ambrosianus 435 edit

Codex Ambrosianus 435 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol X. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 12th or 13th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise. It belongs to the textual family ν, together with the manuscripts v Ud Ad U Q.

The manuscript is one of nine manuscripts that was cited by Trendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and one of five cited by Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. Currently it is housed at the Biblioteca Ambrosiana (435 (H. 50)) in Milan.

Codex Ambrosianus 837 edit

Codex Ambrosianus 837 is a manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol Dc. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 13th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The text of the manuscript is eclectic. It represents to the textual family σ, in I-II books of the treatise.[11] In III book of the treatise it belongs to the family τ.[12]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, or Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. Currently it is housed at the Biblioteca Ambrosiana (837 (B 7 Inf.)) in Milan.

Codex Coislinianus 386 edit

Codex Coislinianus 386 is one of the important manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by the symbol C. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 11th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise. It belongs to the textual family ξ, together with the manuscripts T Ec Xd Pd Hd.

The manuscript was cited by David Ross in his critical edition of the treatise On the Soul. Currently it is housed at the Bibliothèque nationale de France (Coislin 386) in Paris.

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 2 edit

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 2 is a manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by symbol Td. Dated by a Colophon to the year 1496. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The text of the manuscript represents the textual family κ.[13]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. It means the manuscript has not high value. Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library (Philos. 2) at Vienna.

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 75 edit

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 75 is a manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by symbol Sd. Dated by a Colophon to the year 1446. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The text of the manuscript represents to the textual family ρ.[14]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. It means the manuscript has not high value. Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library (Philos. 75) at Vienna.

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 157 edit

Codex Vindobonensis Philos. 157 is a manuscripts of the treatise. It is designated by symbol Rd. Paleographically it had been assigned to the 15th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise.

The text of the manuscript represents the textual family π.[15]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. It means the manuscript has not high value. Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library (Philos. 157) at Vienna.

Codex Marcianus CCXXVIII (406) edit

Codex Marcianus GR. Z. 228 (=406) contains a partial manuscript of the treatise. It is designated by symbol Oc. Paleographically, it has been assigned to the 14th century. It is written in Greek minuscule letters. The manuscript contains the incomplete text of the treatise. The text of Book II ends at 419 a 27. It has not Book III of the treatise. The codex includes commentary on the treatise by Simplicius of Cilicia and Sophonias and paraphrases by Themistius (fourteenth century).

The text of the manuscript represents the textual family κ.[16]

The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg, Torstrik, Biehl, Apelt, and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul. It means the manuscript does not have high value.

The codex also has commentary by Pseudo-Diadochus on Plato's Timaeus, commentary by Simplicius of Cilicia on Aristotle's On the Heavens, commentary by Ammonius Hermiae’s on Plato's Phaedrus, and commentary by Proclus on Plato's Parmenides.

Currently, it is housed at the Biblioteca Marciana (BNM Gr. Z. 228 (=406)) in Venice.

English translations edit

  • Mark Shiffman, De Anima: On the Soul, (Newburyport, MA: Focus Publishing/R. Pullins Co, 2011). ISBN 978-1585102488
  • Joe Sachs, Aristotle's On the Soul and On Memory and Recollection (Green Lion Press, 2001). ISBN 1-888009-17-9
  • Hugh Lawson-Tancred, De Anima (On the Soul) (Penguin Classics, 1986). ISBN 978-0140444711
  • Hippocrates Apostle, Aristotle's On the Soul, (Grinell, Iowa: Peripatetic Press, 1981). ISBN 0-9602870-8-6
  • D.W. Hamlyn, Aristotle De Anima, Books II and III (with passages from Book I), translated with Introduction and Notes by D.W. Hamlyn, with a Report on Recent Work and a Revised Bibliography by Christopher Shields (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1968).
  • Walter Stanley Hett, On the Soul (Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press "Loeb Classical Library", 1957).
  • John Alexander Smith, On the Soul (1931)
    • MIT Internet Classics Archive
    • Google Books
    • Classics in the History of Psychology
    • UVa EText Center
    • Georgetown
  • R. D. Hicks, Aristotle De Anima with Translation, Introduction, and Notes (Cambridge University Press, 1907).
    • Archive.org
    • Free Audiobook (Public Domain) of De Anima at Archive.org
  • Edwin Wallace, Aristotle's Psychology in Greek and English, with Introduction and Notes by Edwin Wallace (Cambridge University Press, 1882).
    • Archive.org
  • Thomas Taylor, On the Soul (Prometheus Trust, 2003, 1808). ISBN 1-898910-23-5

Footnotes edit

  1. ^ Commentary on De anima was begun when Thomas Aquinas was regent at the studium provinciale at Santa Sabina in Rome, the forerunner of the Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas, Angelicum.

References edit

  1. ^ On the Soul, by Aristotle written c.350 B.C.E, translation: J. A. Smith, The Internet Classics Archive, MIT, Retrieved 2 February 2016
  2. ^ George Henry Lewes (1864). Aristotle: A Chapter from the History of Science, Including Analyses of Aristotle's Scientific Writings. OCLC 15174038.
  3. ^ In chapter 3 of Book II he enumerates five psychic powers: the nutritive (θρεπτικόν), the sensory (αἰσθητικόν), the appetitive (ὀρεκτικόν), the locomotive (κινητικὸν), and the power of thinking (διανοητικόν).
  4. ^ Torrell, 161 ff.[full citation needed]
  5. ^ Rüdiger Arnzen (ed.), Aristoteles' De anima, Volume 9 of Aristoteles Semitico-Latinus, 1998. Alfred L. Ivry, The Arabic Text of Aristotle's "De anima" and Its Translator, Oriens Vol. 36 (2001), pp. 59-77. On the reception of De Anima in Arabic tradition in general see Rafael Ramo Guerrero, La recepcion arabe del DE ANIMA de Aristoteles: Al Kindi y Al Farabi, Madrid (1992) for an overview of literature. Compare also the Arabic text known as Theologia Aristotelis, which is in fact a paraphrase of Plotinus Six Enneads.
  6. ^ Josep Puig Montada, Aristotle's On the Soul in the Arabic tradition, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2012).
  7. ^ Another manuscripts of that family: Hd Yd Jd Ga Q.
  8. ^ Another manuscripts of that family: Gc Hc Nc Jd Oc V Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td.
  9. ^ Other members of this group are Dc, m, Rc, Xc, Fd, and Hd.
  10. ^ Other manuscripts of this family are E, L, Fc, Lc, and Kd.
  11. ^ Another members of this group m Rc Xc Fd Hd P.
  12. ^ Another manuscripts of this family: Md Ld Bd Bc Vc.
  13. ^ Gc W Hc Nc Jd Oc V Zc Vc Wc f Nd.
  14. ^ Another members of this group Kc i Pc Cc l Wd y Mc.
  15. ^ Another members of this group S Od Ed Tc c Dd Sc Uc Vd Yc Qa.
  16. ^ Together with the manuscripts: Gc W Hc Nc Jd V Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td.

Further reading edit

  • Rüdiger Arnzen, Aristoteles' De anima : eine verlorene spätantike Paraphrase in arabischer und persischer Überlieferung, Leiden, Brill, 1998 ISBN 90-04-10699-5.
  • J. Barnes, M. Schofield, & R. Sorabji, Articles on Aristotle, vol. 4, 'Psychology and Aesthetics'. London, 1979.
  • M. Durrant, Aristotle's De Anima in Focus. London, 1993.
  • M. Nussbaum & A. O. Rorty, Essays on Aristotle's De Anima. Oxford, 1992.
  • F. Nuyens, L'évolution de la psychologie d'Aristote. Louvain, 1973.
  • Paweł Siwek, Aristotelis tractatus De anima graece et latine, Desclée, Romae 1965.

External links edit

  • Greek text: Mikros Apoplous (HTML)
  • English text: Electronic Text Center, University of Virginia Library (HTML)
  •   De Anima public domain audiobook at LibriVox
  • BNM Gr. Z. 228 (=406) on-line

soul, greek, Περὶ, Ψυχῆς, peri, psychēs, latin, anima, major, treatise, written, aristotle, discussion, centres, kinds, souls, possessed, different, kinds, living, things, distinguished, their, different, operations, thus, plants, have, capacity, nourishment, . On the Soul Greek Perὶ PSyxῆs Peri Psyches Latin De Anima is a major treatise written by Aristotle c 350 BC 1 His discussion centres on the kinds of souls possessed by different kinds of living things distinguished by their different operations Thus plants have the capacity for nourishment and reproduction the minimum that must be possessed by any kind of living organism Lower animals have in addition the powers of sense perception and self motion action Humans have all these as well as intellect Expositio et quaestiones in Aristoteles De Anima Jean Buridan c 1362 Aristotle holds that the soul psyche psyxh is the form or essence of any living thing it is not a distinct substance from the body that it is in It is the possession of a soul of a specific kind that makes an organism an organism at all and thus that the notion of a body without a soul or of a soul in the wrong kind of body is simply unintelligible He argues that some parts of the soul the intellect can exist without the body but most cannot In 1855 Charles Collier published a translation titled On the Vital Principle George Henry Lewes however found this description also wanting 2 Contents 1 Division of chapters 1 1 Book I 1 2 Book II 1 3 Book III 1 4 Summary 2 Arabic paraphrase 3 Some manuscripts 3 1 Codex Vaticanus 253 3 2 Codex Vaticanus 260 3 3 Codex Vaticanus 266 3 4 Codex Vaticanus 1026 3 5 Codex Vaticanus 1339 3 6 Codex Ambrosianus 435 3 7 Codex Ambrosianus 837 3 8 Codex Coislinianus 386 3 9 Codex Vindobonensis Philos 2 3 10 Codex Vindobonensis Philos 75 3 11 Codex Vindobonensis Philos 157 3 12 Codex Marcianus CCXXVIII 406 4 English translations 5 Footnotes 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksDivision of chapters editThe treatise is divided into three books and each of the books is divided into chapters five twelve and thirteen respectively The treatise is near universally abbreviated DA for De anima and books and chapters generally referred to by Roman and Arabic numerals respectively along with corresponding Bekker numbers Thus DA I 1 402a1 means De anima book I chapter 1 Bekker page 402 Bekker column a the column on the left side of the page line number 1 Book I edit DA I 1 introduces the theme of the treatise DA I 2 5 provide a survey of Aristotle s predecessors views about the soul Book II edit DA II 1 3 gives Aristotle s definition of soul and outlines his own study of it 3 which is then pursued as follows DA II 4 discusses nutrition and reproduction DA II 5 6 discuss sensation in general DA II 7 11 discuss each of the five senses in the following order sight sound smell taste and touch one chapter for each DA II 12 again takes up the general question of sensation Book III edit DA III 1 argues there are no other senses than the five already mentioned DA III 2 discusses the problem of what it means to sense sensing i e to be aware of sensation DA III 3 investigates the nature of imagination DA III 4 7 discuss thinking and the intellect or mind DA III 8 articulates the definition and nature of soul DA III 9 10 discuss the movement of animals possessing all the senses DA III 11 discusses the movement of animals possessing only touch DA III 12 13 take up the question of what are the minimal constituents of having a soul and being alive Summary edit Book I contains a summary of Aristotle s method of investigation and a dialectical determination of the nature of the soul He begins by conceding that attempting to define the soul is one of the most difficult questions in the world But he proposes an ingenious method to tackle the question Just as we can come to know the properties and operations of something through scientific demonstration i e a geometrical proof that a triangle has its interior angles equal to two right angles since the principle of all scientific demonstration is the essence of the object so too we can come to know the nature of a thing if we already know its properties and operations It is like finding the middle term to a syllogism with a known conclusion Therefore we must seek out such operations of the soul to determine what kind of nature it has From a consideration of the opinions of his predecessors a soul he concludes will be that in virtue of which living things have life Book II contains his scientific determination of the nature of the soul an element of his biology By dividing substance into its three meanings matter form and what is composed of both he shows that the soul must be the first actuality of a natural organized body This is its form or essence It cannot be matter because the soul is that in virtue of which things have life and matter is only being in potency The rest of the book is divided into a determination of the nature of the nutritive and sensitive souls 1 All species of living things plant or animal must be able to nourish themselves and reproduce others of the same kind 2 All animals have in addition to the nutritive power sense perception and thus they all have at least the sense of touch which he argues is presupposed by all other senses and the ability to feel pleasure and pain which is the simplest kind of perception If they can feel pleasure and pain they also have desire Some animals in addition have other senses sight hearing taste and some have more subtle versions of each the ability to distinguish objects in a complex way beyond mere pleasure and pain He discusses how these function Some animals have in addition the powers of memory imagination and self motion nbsp Aristotle describes the structure of the souls of plants animals and humans in Books II and III Book III discusses the mind or rational soul which belongs to humans alone He argues that thinking is different from both sense perception and imagination because the senses can never lie and imagination is a power to make something sensed appear again while thinking can sometimes be false And since the mind is able to think when it wishes it must be divided into two faculties One which contains all the mind s ideas which are able to be considered and another which brings them into action i e to be actually thinking about them These are called the possible and agent intellect The possible intellect is an unscribed tablet and the store house of all concepts i e universal ideas like triangle tree man red etc When the mind wishes to think the agent intellect recalls these ideas from the possible intellect and combines them to form thoughts The agent intellect is also the faculty which abstracts the whatness or intelligibility of all sensed objects and stores them in the possible intellect For example when a student learns a proof for the Pythagorean theorem his agent intellect abstracts the intelligibility of all the images his eye senses and that are a result of the translation by imagination of sense perceptions into immaterial phantasmata i e the triangles and squares in the diagrams and stores the concepts that make up the proof in his possible intellect When he wishes to recall the proof say for demonstration in class the next day his agent intellect recalls the concepts and their relations from the possible intellect and formulates the statements that make up the arguments in the proof The argument for the existence of the agent intellect in Chapter V perhaps due to its concision has been interpreted in a variety of ways One standard scholastic interpretation is given in the Commentary on De anima begun by Thomas Aquinas a Aquinas commentary is based on the new translation of the text from the Greek completed by Aquinas Dominican associate William of Moerbeke at Viterbo in 1267 4 The argument as interpreted by Thomas Aquinas runs something like this In every nature which is sometimes in potency and act it is necessary to posit an agent or cause within that genus that just like art in relation to its suffering matter brings the object into act But the soul is sometimes in potency and act Therefore the soul must have this difference In other words since the mind can move from not understanding to understanding and from knowing to thinking there must be something to cause the mind to go from knowing nothing to knowing something and from knowing something but not thinking about it to actually thinking about it Aristotle also argues that the mind only the agent intellect is immaterial able to exist without the body and immortal His arguments are notoriously concise This has caused much confusion over the centuries causing a rivalry between different schools of interpretation most notably between the Arabian commentator Averroes and Thomas Aquinas citation needed One argument for its immaterial existence runs like this if the mind were material then it would have to possess a corresponding thinking organ And since all the senses have their corresponding sense organs thinking would then be like sensing But sensing can never be false and therefore thinking could never be false And this is of course untrue Therefore Aristotle concludes the mind is immaterial Perhaps the most important but obscure argument in the whole book is Aristotle s demonstration of the immortality of the thinking part of the human soul also in Chapter V Taking a premise from his Physics that as a thing acts so it is he argues that since the active principle in our mind acts with no bodily organ it can exist without the body And if it exists apart from matter it therefore cannot be corrupted And therefore there exists a mind which is immortal As to what mind Aristotle is referring to in Chapter V i e divine human or a kind of world soul has represented a hot topic of discussion for centuries The most likely is probably the interpretation of Alexander of Aphrodisias likening Aristotle s immortal mind to an impersonal activity ultimately represented by God Arabic paraphrase editIn Late Antiquity Aristotelian texts became re interpreted in terms of Neoplatonism There is a paraphrase of De Anima which survives in the Arabic tradition which reflects such a Neoplatonic synthesis The text was translated into Persian in the 13th century It is likely based on a Greek original which is no longer extant and which was further syncretised in the heterogeneous process of adoption into early Arabic literature 5 A later Arabic translation of De Anima into Arabic is due to Ishaq ibn Hunayn d 910 Ibn Zura d 1008 made a translation into Arabic from Syriac The Arabic versions show a complicated history of mutual influence Avicenna d 1037 wrote a commentary on De Anima which was translated into Latin by Michael Scotus Averroes d 1198 used two Arabic translations mostly relying on the one by Ishaq ibn Hunayn but occasionally quoting the older one as an alternative Zerahiah ben Shealtiel Ḥen translated Aristotle s De anima from Arabic into Hebrew in 1284 Both Averroes and Zerahiah used the translation by Ibn Zura 6 Some manuscripts editCodex Vaticanus 253 edit Codex Vaticanus 253 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by the symbol L Paleographically it has been assigned to the 13th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript is not complete it contains only Book III It belongs to the textual family l together with the manuscripts E Fc Lc Kd and P The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library gr 253 in Rome Codex Vaticanus 260 edit Codex Vaticanus 260 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by the symbol U Paleographically it has been assigned to the 11th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise It belongs to the textual family n together with the manuscripts X v Ud Ad and Q The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library Vat gr 260 in Rome Codex Vaticanus 266 edit Codex Vaticanus 266 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by the symbol V Paleographically it had been assigned to the 14th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise It belongs to the textual family k but only to Chapter 8 of II book Another member of the family k Gc W Hc Nc Jd Oc Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td The manuscript was cited by Trendelenburg Torstrik Biehl and Apelt in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul David Ross did not use the manuscript in his own edition Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library gr 266 in Rome Codex Vaticanus 1026 edit Codex Vaticanus 1026 is a manuscript of the treatise It is designated by symbol W Paleographically it had been assigned to the 13th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The Greek text of the manuscript is eclectic It belongs to the textual family m 7 to II book 7 chapter 419 a 27 Since 419 a 27 it is a representative of the family k 8 The manuscript was not cited by Trendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul It means the manuscript has not high value Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library gr 1026 at Rome Codex Vaticanus 1339 edit Codex Vaticanus 1339 is a manuscript of the treatise It is designated by symbol P Paleographically it has been assigned to the 14th or 15th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The text of the manuscript is eclectic It represents the textual family s in book II of the treatise from II 2 314b11 to II 8 420a2 9 After book II chapter 9 429b16 it belongs to the family l 10 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in rheir critical editions of the treatise On the Soul This means the manuscript is not of high value Currently it is housed at the Vatican Library gr 1339 at Rome Codex Ambrosianus 435 edit Codex Ambrosianus 435 is one of the most important manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by the symbol X Paleographically it had been assigned to the 12th or 13th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise It belongs to the textual family n together with the manuscripts v Ud Ad U Q The manuscript is one of nine manuscripts that was cited by Trendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and one of five cited by Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul Currently it is housed at the Biblioteca Ambrosiana 435 H 50 in Milan Codex Ambrosianus 837 edit Codex Ambrosianus 837 is a manuscript of the treatise It is designated by the symbol Dc Paleographically it had been assigned to the 13th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The text of the manuscript is eclectic It represents to the textual family s in I II books of the treatise 11 In III book of the treatise it belongs to the family t 12 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt or Ross in their critical editions of the treatise On the Soul Currently it is housed at the Biblioteca Ambrosiana 837 B 7 Inf in Milan Codex Coislinianus 386 edit Codex Coislinianus 386 is one of the important manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by the symbol C Paleographically it had been assigned to the 11th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains the complete text of the treatise It belongs to the textual family 3 together with the manuscripts T Ec Xd Pd Hd The manuscript was cited by David Ross in his critical edition of the treatise On the Soul Currently it is housed at the Bibliotheque nationale de France Coislin 386 in Paris Codex Vindobonensis Philos 2 edit Codex Vindobonensis Philos 2 is a manuscript of the treatise It is designated by symbol Td Dated by a Colophon to the year 1496 It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The text of the manuscript represents the textual family k 13 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul It means the manuscript has not high value Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library Philos 2 at Vienna Codex Vindobonensis Philos 75 edit Codex Vindobonensis Philos 75 is a manuscript of the treatise It is designated by symbol Sd Dated by a Colophon to the year 1446 It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The text of the manuscript represents to the textual family r 14 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul It means the manuscript has not high value Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library Philos 75 at Vienna Codex Vindobonensis Philos 157 edit Codex Vindobonensis Philos 157 is a manuscripts of the treatise It is designated by symbol Rd Paleographically it had been assigned to the 15th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains a complete text of the treatise The text of the manuscript represents the textual family p 15 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul It means the manuscript has not high value Currently it is housed at the Austrian National Library Philos 157 at Vienna Codex Marcianus CCXXVIII 406 edit Codex Marcianus GR Z 228 406 contains a partial manuscript of the treatise It is designated by symbol Oc Paleographically it has been assigned to the 14th century It is written in Greek minuscule letters The manuscript contains the incomplete text of the treatise The text of Book II ends at 419 a 27 It has not Book III of the treatise The codex includes commentary on the treatise by Simplicius of Cilicia and Sophonias and paraphrases by Themistius fourteenth century The text of the manuscript represents the textual family k 16 The manuscript was not cited by Tiendelenburg Torstrik Biehl Apelt and Ross in his critical editions of the treatise On the Soul It means the manuscript does not have high value The codex also has commentary by Pseudo Diadochus on Plato s Timaeus commentary by Simplicius of Cilicia on Aristotle s On the Heavens commentary by Ammonius Hermiae s on Plato s Phaedrus and commentary by Proclus on Plato s Parmenides Currently it is housed at the Biblioteca Marciana BNM Gr Z 228 406 in Venice English translations editMark Shiffman De Anima On the Soul Newburyport MA Focus Publishing R Pullins Co 2011 ISBN 978 1585102488 Joe Sachs Aristotle s On the Soul and On Memory and Recollection Green Lion Press 2001 ISBN 1 888009 17 9 Hugh Lawson Tancred De Anima On the Soul Penguin Classics 1986 ISBN 978 0140444711 Hippocrates Apostle Aristotle s On the Soul Grinell Iowa Peripatetic Press 1981 ISBN 0 9602870 8 6 D W Hamlyn Aristotle De Anima Books II and III with passages from Book I translated with Introduction and Notes by D W Hamlyn with a Report on Recent Work and a Revised Bibliography by Christopher Shields Oxford Clarendon Press 1968 Walter Stanley Hett On the Soul Cambridge Mass Harvard University Press Loeb Classical Library 1957 John Alexander Smith On the Soul 1931 MIT Internet Classics Archive Adelaide Google Books Classics in the History of Psychology UVa EText Center Georgetown R D Hicks Aristotle De Anima with Translation Introduction and Notes Cambridge University Press 1907 Archive org Free Audiobook Public Domain of De Anima at Archive org Edwin Wallace Aristotle s Psychology in Greek and English with Introduction and Notes by Edwin Wallace Cambridge University Press 1882 Archive org Thomas Taylor On the Soul Prometheus Trust 2003 1808 ISBN 1 898910 23 5Footnotes edit Commentary on De anima was begun when Thomas Aquinas was regent at the studium provinciale at Santa Sabina in Rome the forerunner of the Pontifical University of Saint Thomas Aquinas Angelicum References edit On the Soul by Aristotle written c 350 B C E translation J A Smith The Internet Classics Archive MIT Retrieved 2 February 2016 George Henry Lewes 1864 Aristotle A Chapter from the History of Science Including Analyses of Aristotle s Scientific Writings OCLC 15174038 In chapter 3 of Book II he enumerates five psychic powers the nutritive 8reptikon the sensory aἰs8htikon the appetitive ὀrektikon the locomotive kinhtikὸn and the power of thinking dianohtikon Torrell 161 ff full citation needed Rudiger Arnzen ed Aristoteles De anima Volume 9 of Aristoteles Semitico Latinus 1998 Alfred L Ivry The Arabic Text of Aristotle s De anima and Its Translator Oriens Vol 36 2001 pp 59 77 On the reception of De Anima in Arabic tradition in general see Rafael Ramo Guerrero La recepcion arabe del DE ANIMA de Aristoteles Al Kindi y Al Farabi Madrid 1992 for an overview of literature Compare also the Arabic text known as Theologia Aristotelis which is in fact a paraphrase of Plotinus Six Enneads Josep Puig Montada Aristotle s On the Soul in the Arabic tradition Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy 2012 Another manuscripts of that family Hd Yd Jd Ga Q Another manuscripts of that family Gc Hc Nc Jd Oc V Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td Other members of this group are Dc m Rc Xc Fd and Hd Other manuscripts of this family are E L Fc Lc and Kd Another members of this group m Rc Xc Fd Hd P Another manuscripts of this family Md Ld Bd Bc Vc Gc W Hc Nc Jd Oc V Zc Vc Wc f Nd Another members of this group Kc i Pc Cc l Wd y Mc Another members of this group S Od Ed Tc c Dd Sc Uc Vd Yc Qa Together with the manuscripts Gc W Hc Nc Jd V Zc Vc Wc f Nd Td Further reading editRudiger Arnzen Aristoteles De anima eine verlorene spatantike Paraphrase in arabischer und persischer Uberlieferung Leiden Brill 1998 ISBN 90 04 10699 5 J Barnes M Schofield amp R Sorabji Articles on Aristotle vol 4 Psychology and Aesthetics London 1979 M Durrant Aristotle s De Anima in Focus London 1993 M Nussbaum amp A O Rorty Essays on Aristotle s De Anima Oxford 1992 F Nuyens L evolution de la psychologie d Aristote Louvain 1973 Pawel Siwek Aristotelis tractatus De anima graece et latine Desclee Romae 1965 External links edit nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article On the Soul nbsp Wikiversity has learning resources about On the Soul Greek text Mikros Apoplous HTML English text Electronic Text Center University of Virginia Library HTML nbsp De Anima public domain audiobook at LibriVox BNM Gr Z 228 406 on line Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title On the Soul amp oldid 1195269466, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.