fbpx
Wikipedia

Attribute substitution

Attribute substitution is a psychological process thought to underlie a number of cognitive biases and perceptual illusions. It occurs when an individual has to make a judgment (of a target attribute) that is computationally complex, and instead substitutes a more easily calculated heuristic attribute.[1] This substitution is thought of as taking place in the automatic intuitive judgment system, rather than the more self-aware reflective system. Hence, when someone tries to answer a difficult question, they may actually answer a related but different question, without realizing that a substitution has taken place. This explains why individuals can be unaware of their own biases, and why biases persist even when the subject is made aware of them. It also explains why human judgments often fail to show regression toward the mean.[2]

The theory of attribute substitution unifies a number of separate explanations of reasoning errors in terms of cognitive heuristics.[1] In turn, the theory is subsumed by an effort-reduction framework proposed by Anuj K. Shah and Daniel M. Oppenheimer, which states that people use a variety of techniques to reduce the effort of making decisions.[3]

History edit

 
Daniel Kahneman

In a 1974 paper, psychologists Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman argued that a broad family of biases (systematic errors in judgment and decision) were explainable in terms of a few heuristics (information-processing shortcuts), including availability and representativeness.

In 1975, psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens proposed that the strength of a stimulus (e.g., the brightness of a light, the severity of a crime) is encoded neurally in a way that is independent of modality.[citation needed] Kahneman and Frederick built on this idea, arguing that the target attribute and heuristic attribute could be unrelated.[2]

In a 2002 revision of the theory, Kahneman and Shane Frederick proposed attribute substitution as a process underlying these and other effects.[2]

Conditions edit

[P]eople are not accustomed to thinking hard, and are often content to trust a plausible judgment that comes to mind.

Daniel Kahneman, American Economic Review 93 (5) December 2003, p. 1450

Kahneman and Frederick propose three conditions for attribute substitution:[2]

  1. The target attribute is relatively inaccessible. Substitution is not expected to take place in answering factual questions that can be retrieved directly from memory ("What is your birthday?") or about current experience ("Do you feel thirsty now?).
  2. An associated attribute is highly accessible. This might be because it is evaluated automatically in normal perception or because it has been primed. For example, someone who has been thinking about their love life who is then asked about their happiness might substitute how happy they are with their love life rather than answer the question as asked.
  3. The substitution is not detected and corrected by the reflective system. For example, when asked "A bat and a ball together cost $1.10. The bat costs $1 more than the ball. How much does the ball cost?" many subjects incorrectly answer $0.10.[4] An explanation in terms of attribute substitution is that, rather than work out the sum, subjects parse the sum of $1.10 into a large amount and a small amount, which is easy to do. Whether they feel that is the right answer will depend on whether they check the calculation with their reflective system.

Examples edit

 
This illusion works because 3D (perspective) size is substituted for 2D size (all pairs are equal in size).

Optical illusions edit

Attribute substitution explains the persistence of some illusions. For example, when subjects judge the size of two figures in a perspective picture, their apparent sizes can be distorted by the 3D context, making a convincing optical illusion. The theory states that the three-dimensional size of the figure (which is accessible because it is automatically computed by the visual system) is substituted for its two-dimensional size on the page. Experienced painters and photographers are less susceptible to this illusion, because the two-dimensional size is more accessible to their perception.[4]

Valuing insurance edit

Kahneman gives an example where some Americans were offered insurance against their own death in a terrorist attack while on a trip to Europe, while another group were offered insurance that would cover death of any kind on the trip. The former group were willing to pay more even though "death of any kind" includes "death in a terrorist attack", Kahneman suggests that the attribute of fear is being substituted for a calculation of the total risks of travel.[5] Fear of terrorism for these subjects was stronger than a general fear of dying on a foreign trip.

Stereotypes edit

Stereotypes can be a source of heuristic attributes.[2] In a face-to-face conversation with a stranger, judging their intelligence is more computationally complex than judging the colour of their skin. So if the subject has a stereotype about the relative intelligence of whites, blacks, and Asians, that racial attribute might substitute for the more intangible attribute of intelligence. The pre-conscious, intuitive nature of attribute substitution explains how subjects can be influenced by the stereotype while thinking that they have made an honest, unbiased evaluation of the other person's intelligence.

Morality and fairness edit

Sunstein argued that attribute substitution is pervasive when people reason about moral, political, or legal matters.[6] Given a difficult, novel problem in these areas, people search for a more familiar, related problem (a "prototypical case") and apply its solution as the solution to the harder problem. According to Sunstein, the opinions of trusted political or religious authorities can serve as heuristic attributes when people are asked their own opinions on a matter. Another source of heuristic attributes is emotion: people's moral opinions on sensitive subjects like sexuality and human cloning may be driven by reactions such as disgust, rather than by reasoned principles.[7] Critics demanded more evidence from Sunstein.[3]

The beautiful-is-familiar effect edit

Monin reports a series of experiments in which subjects, looking at photographs of faces, have to judge whether they have seen those faces before. It is repeatedly found that attractive faces are more likely to be mistakenly labeled as familiar.[8] Monin interprets this result in terms of attribute substitution. The heuristic attribute in this case is a "warm glow"; a positive feeling towards someone that might either be due to their being familiar or being attractive. This interpretation has been criticised, because not all the variance in the familiarity data is accounted for by attractiveness.[3]

Evidence edit

The most direct evidence, according to Kahneman,[4] is a 1973 experiment that used a psychological profile of Tom W., a fictional graduate student.[9] One group of subjects had to rate Tom's similarity to a typical student in each of nine academic areas (Law, Engineering, Library Science etc.). Another group had to rate how likely it is that Tom specialised in each area. If these ratings of likelihood are governed by probability, then they should resemble the base rates, i.e., the proportion of students in each of the nine areas (which had been separately estimated by a third group). A probabilistic judgment would say that Tom is more likely to be a Humanities student than Library Science, because many more students study Humanities, and the additional information in the profile is vague and unreliable. Instead, the ratings of likelihood matched the ratings of similarity almost perfectly, both in this study and a similar one where subjects judged the likelihood of a fictional woman taking different careers. This suggests that rather than estimating probability using base rates, subjects had substituted the more accessible attribute of similarity.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Newell, Benjamin R.; Lagnado, David A.; Shanks, David R. (2007). Straight choices: the psychology of decision making. Routledge. pp. 71–74. ISBN 978-1-84169-588-4.
  2. ^ a b c d e Kahneman, Daniel; Frederick, Shane (2002). "Representativeness Revisited: Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgment". In Thomas Gilovich; Dale Griffin; Daniel Kahneman (eds.). Heuristics and Biases: The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 49–81. ISBN 978-0-521-79679-8. OCLC 47364085.
  3. ^ a b c Shah, Anuj K.; Oppenheimer, Daniel M. (March 2008). "Heuristics Made Easy: An Effort-Reduction Framework". Psychological Bulletin. 134 (2): 207–222. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.134.2.207. ISSN 1939-1455. PMID 18298269.
  4. ^ a b c Kahneman, Daniel (December 2003). "Maps of Bounded Rationality: Psychology for Behavioral Economics". American Economic Review. 93 (5): 1449–1475. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.194.6554. doi:10.1257/000282803322655392. ISSN 0002-8282.
  5. ^ Kahneman, Daniel (2007). "Short Course in Thinking About Thinking". Edge.org. Edge Foundation. Retrieved 2009-06-03.
  6. ^ Sunstein, Cass R. (2005). "Moral Heuristics". Behavioral and Brain Sciences. 28 (4): 531–542. doi:10.1017/S0140525X05000099. ISSN 0140-525X. PMID 16209802. S2CID 231738548.
  7. ^ Sunstein, Cass R. (2009). (PDF). Vermont Law Review. 33 (3). Vermont Law School: 405–434. Archived from the original on 2011-06-10. Retrieved 2009-09-15.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: bot: original URL status unknown (link)
  8. ^ Monin, Benoît; Oppenheimer, Daniel M. (2005). (PDF). Social Cognition. 23 (3): 257–278. doi:10.1521/soco.2005.23.3.257. ISSN 0278-016X. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-05-27. Retrieved 2009-06-01.
  9. ^ Kahneman, Daniel; Tversky, Amos (July 1973). "On the Psychology of Prediction". Psychological Review. 80 (4): 237–51. doi:10.1037/h0034747. ISSN 0033-295X.

Further reading edit

  • Kahneman, Daniel; Frederick, Shane (2004). "Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgment". In Mie Augier; James G. March (eds.). Models of a man: essays in memory of Herbert A. Simon. MIT Press. pp. 411–432. ISBN 978-0-262-01208-9. OCLC 52257877.
  • Kahneman, Daniel; Frederick, Shane (2005). (PDF). In Keith James Holyoak; Robert G. Morrison (eds.). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. Cambridge University Press. pp. 267–294. ISBN 978-0-521-82417-0. OCLC 56011371. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-07-13.
  • Kahneman, Daniel (December 8, 2002). "Maps of Bounded Rationality: A Perspective on Intuitive Judgement and Choice (Nobel Prize Lecture)". NobelPrize.org. The Nobel Foundation. Retrieved 2009-06-13.
  • Kahneman, Daniel (July 22, 2007). "Short Course in Thinking about Thinking". Edge.org. Edge Foundation. Retrieved 2009-06-13.
  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter; Young, Liane; Cushman, Fiery (2010). "Moral Intuitions". In J. Doris; G. Harman; S. Nichols; J. Prinz; W. Sinnott-Armstrong; S. Stich (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology. Oxford University Press. pp. 246–272. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199582143.003.0008. ISBN 9780199582143.
  • De Neys, Wim; Rossi, Sandrine; Houdé, Olivier (2013). "Bats, balls, and substitution sensitivity: Cognitive misers are no happy fools". Psychonomic Bulletin & Review. 20 (2): 269–273. doi:10.3758/s13423-013-0384-5. PMID 23417270.
  • Frederick, Shane (2005). "Cognitive Reflection and Decision Making". Journal of Economic Perspectives. 19 (4): 25–42. doi:10.1257/089533005775196732.

attribute, substitution, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar, jstor, ma. This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Attribute substitution news newspapers books scholar JSTOR March 2023 Learn how and when to remove this message Attribute substitution is a psychological process thought to underlie a number of cognitive biases and perceptual illusions It occurs when an individual has to make a judgment of a target attribute that is computationally complex and instead substitutes a more easily calculated heuristic attribute 1 This substitution is thought of as taking place in the automatic intuitive judgment system rather than the more self aware reflective system Hence when someone tries to answer a difficult question they may actually answer a related but different question without realizing that a substitution has taken place This explains why individuals can be unaware of their own biases and why biases persist even when the subject is made aware of them It also explains why human judgments often fail to show regression toward the mean 2 The theory of attribute substitution unifies a number of separate explanations of reasoning errors in terms of cognitive heuristics 1 In turn the theory is subsumed by an effort reduction framework proposed by Anuj K Shah and Daniel M Oppenheimer which states that people use a variety of techniques to reduce the effort of making decisions 3 Contents 1 History 2 Conditions 3 Examples 3 1 Optical illusions 3 2 Valuing insurance 3 3 Stereotypes 3 4 Morality and fairness 3 5 The beautiful is familiar effect 4 Evidence 5 See also 6 References 7 Further readingHistory edit nbsp Daniel Kahneman In a 1974 paper psychologists Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman argued that a broad family of biases systematic errors in judgment and decision were explainable in terms of a few heuristics information processing shortcuts including availability and representativeness In 1975 psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens proposed that the strength of a stimulus e g the brightness of a light the severity of a crime is encoded neurally in a way that is independent of modality citation needed Kahneman and Frederick built on this idea arguing that the target attribute and heuristic attribute could be unrelated 2 In a 2002 revision of the theory Kahneman and Shane Frederick proposed attribute substitution as a process underlying these and other effects 2 Conditions edit P eople are not accustomed to thinking hard and are often content to trust a plausible judgment that comes to mind Daniel Kahneman American Economic Review 93 5 December 2003 p 1450 Kahneman and Frederick propose three conditions for attribute substitution 2 The target attribute is relatively inaccessible Substitution is not expected to take place in answering factual questions that can be retrieved directly from memory What is your birthday or about current experience Do you feel thirsty now An associated attribute is highly accessible This might be because it is evaluated automatically in normal perception or because it has been primed For example someone who has been thinking about their love life who is then asked about their happiness might substitute how happy they are with their love life rather than answer the question as asked The substitution is not detected and corrected by the reflective system For example when asked A bat and a ball together cost 1 10 The bat costs 1 more than the ball How much does the ball cost many subjects incorrectly answer 0 10 4 An explanation in terms of attribute substitution is that rather than work out the sum subjects parse the sum of 1 10 into a large amount and a small amount which is easy to do Whether they feel that is the right answer will depend on whether they check the calculation with their reflective system Examples edit nbsp This illusion works because 3D perspective size is substituted for 2D size all pairs are equal in size Optical illusions edit Attribute substitution explains the persistence of some illusions For example when subjects judge the size of two figures in a perspective picture their apparent sizes can be distorted by the 3D context making a convincing optical illusion The theory states that the three dimensional size of the figure which is accessible because it is automatically computed by the visual system is substituted for its two dimensional size on the page Experienced painters and photographers are less susceptible to this illusion because the two dimensional size is more accessible to their perception 4 Valuing insurance edit Kahneman gives an example where some Americans were offered insurance against their own death in a terrorist attack while on a trip to Europe while another group were offered insurance that would cover death of any kind on the trip The former group were willing to pay more even though death of any kind includes death in a terrorist attack Kahneman suggests that the attribute of fear is being substituted for a calculation of the total risks of travel 5 Fear of terrorism for these subjects was stronger than a general fear of dying on a foreign trip Stereotypes edit Stereotypes can be a source of heuristic attributes 2 In a face to face conversation with a stranger judging their intelligence is more computationally complex than judging the colour of their skin So if the subject has a stereotype about the relative intelligence of whites blacks and Asians that racial attribute might substitute for the more intangible attribute of intelligence The pre conscious intuitive nature of attribute substitution explains how subjects can be influenced by the stereotype while thinking that they have made an honest unbiased evaluation of the other person s intelligence Morality and fairness edit Sunstein argued that attribute substitution is pervasive when people reason about moral political or legal matters 6 Given a difficult novel problem in these areas people search for a more familiar related problem a prototypical case and apply its solution as the solution to the harder problem According to Sunstein the opinions of trusted political or religious authorities can serve as heuristic attributes when people are asked their own opinions on a matter Another source of heuristic attributes is emotion people s moral opinions on sensitive subjects like sexuality and human cloning may be driven by reactions such as disgust rather than by reasoned principles 7 Critics demanded more evidence from Sunstein 3 The beautiful is familiar effect edit Monin reports a series of experiments in which subjects looking at photographs of faces have to judge whether they have seen those faces before It is repeatedly found that attractive faces are more likely to be mistakenly labeled as familiar 8 Monin interprets this result in terms of attribute substitution The heuristic attribute in this case is a warm glow a positive feeling towards someone that might either be due to their being familiar or being attractive This interpretation has been criticised because not all the variance in the familiarity data is accounted for by attractiveness 3 Evidence editThe most direct evidence according to Kahneman 4 is a 1973 experiment that used a psychological profile of Tom W a fictional graduate student 9 One group of subjects had to rate Tom s similarity to a typical student in each of nine academic areas Law Engineering Library Science etc Another group had to rate how likely it is that Tom specialised in each area If these ratings of likelihood are governed by probability then they should resemble the base rates i e the proportion of students in each of the nine areas which had been separately estimated by a third group A probabilistic judgment would say that Tom is more likely to be a Humanities student than Library Science because many more students study Humanities and the additional information in the profile is vague and unreliable Instead the ratings of likelihood matched the ratings of similarity almost perfectly both in this study and a similar one where subjects judged the likelihood of a fictional woman taking different careers This suggests that rather than estimating probability using base rates subjects had substituted the more accessible attribute of similarity See also edit nbsp Psychology portal nbsp Philosophy portal Bounded rationality Inattentional blindness Labeling theory List of cognitive biases Neglect of probability Self deceptionReferences edit a b Newell Benjamin R Lagnado David A Shanks David R 2007 Straight choices the psychology of decision making Routledge pp 71 74 ISBN 978 1 84169 588 4 a b c d e Kahneman Daniel Frederick Shane 2002 Representativeness Revisited Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgment In Thomas Gilovich Dale Griffin Daniel Kahneman eds Heuristics and Biases The Psychology of Intuitive Judgment Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 49 81 ISBN 978 0 521 79679 8 OCLC 47364085 a b c Shah Anuj K Oppenheimer Daniel M March 2008 Heuristics Made Easy An Effort Reduction Framework Psychological Bulletin 134 2 207 222 doi 10 1037 0033 2909 134 2 207 ISSN 1939 1455 PMID 18298269 a b c Kahneman Daniel December 2003 Maps of Bounded Rationality Psychology for Behavioral Economics American Economic Review 93 5 1449 1475 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 194 6554 doi 10 1257 000282803322655392 ISSN 0002 8282 Kahneman Daniel 2007 Short Course in Thinking About Thinking Edge org Edge Foundation Retrieved 2009 06 03 Sunstein Cass R 2005 Moral Heuristics Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 4 531 542 doi 10 1017 S0140525X05000099 ISSN 0140 525X PMID 16209802 S2CID 231738548 Sunstein Cass R 2009 Some Effects of Moral Indignation on Law PDF Vermont Law Review 33 3 Vermont Law School 405 434 Archived from the original on 2011 06 10 Retrieved 2009 09 15 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint bot original URL status unknown link Monin Benoit Oppenheimer Daniel M 2005 Correlated Averages vs Averaged Correlations Demonstrating the Warm Glow Heuristic Beyond Aggregation PDF Social Cognition 23 3 257 278 doi 10 1521 soco 2005 23 3 257 ISSN 0278 016X Archived from the original PDF on 2016 05 27 Retrieved 2009 06 01 Kahneman Daniel Tversky Amos July 1973 On the Psychology of Prediction Psychological Review 80 4 237 51 doi 10 1037 h0034747 ISSN 0033 295X Further reading editKahneman Daniel Frederick Shane 2004 Attribute Substitution in Intuitive Judgment In Mie Augier James G March eds Models of a man essays in memory of Herbert A Simon MIT Press pp 411 432 ISBN 978 0 262 01208 9 OCLC 52257877 Kahneman Daniel Frederick Shane 2005 A Model of Heuristic Judgment PDF In Keith James Holyoak Robert G Morrison eds The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning Cambridge University Press pp 267 294 ISBN 978 0 521 82417 0 OCLC 56011371 Archived from the original PDF on 2018 07 13 Kahneman Daniel December 8 2002 Maps of Bounded Rationality A Perspective on Intuitive Judgement and Choice Nobel Prize Lecture NobelPrize org The Nobel Foundation Retrieved 2009 06 13 Kahneman Daniel July 22 2007 Short Course in Thinking about Thinking Edge org Edge Foundation Retrieved 2009 06 13 Sinnott Armstrong Walter Young Liane Cushman Fiery 2010 Moral Intuitions In J Doris G Harman S Nichols J Prinz W Sinnott Armstrong S Stich eds The Oxford Handbook of Moral Psychology Oxford University Press pp 246 272 doi 10 1093 acprof oso 9780199582143 003 0008 ISBN 9780199582143 De Neys Wim Rossi Sandrine Houde Olivier 2013 Bats balls and substitution sensitivity Cognitive misers are no happy fools Psychonomic Bulletin amp Review 20 2 269 273 doi 10 3758 s13423 013 0384 5 PMID 23417270 Frederick Shane 2005 Cognitive Reflection and Decision Making Journal of Economic Perspectives 19 4 25 42 doi 10 1257 089533005775196732 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Attribute substitution amp oldid 1210257461, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.