fbpx
Wikipedia

Logical connective

In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the binary connective can be used to join the two atomic formulas and , rendering the complex formula .

Hasse diagram of logical connectives.

Common connectives include negation, disjunction, conjunction, implication, and equivalence. In standard systems of classical logic, these connectives are interpreted as truth functions, though they receive a variety of alternative interpretations in nonclassical logics. Their classical interpretations are similar to the meanings of natural language expressions such as English "not", "or", "and", and "if", but not identical. Discrepancies between natural language connectives and those of classical logic have motivated nonclassical approaches to natural language meaning as well as approaches which pair a classical compositional semantics with a robust pragmatics.

A logical connective is similar to, but not equivalent to, a syntax commonly used in programming languages called a conditional operator.[1][better source needed]

Overview edit

In formal languages, truth functions are represented by unambiguous symbols. This allows logical statements to not be understood in an ambiguous way. These symbols are called logical connectives, logical operators, propositional operators, or, in classical logic, truth-functional connectives. For the rules which allow new well-formed formulas to be constructed by joining other well-formed formulas using truth-functional connectives, see well-formed formula.

Logical connectives can be used to link zero or more statements, so one can speak about n-ary logical connectives. The boolean constants True and False can be thought of as zero-ary operators. Negation is a 1-ary connective, and so on.

Symbol, name Truth
table
Venn
diagram
Zeroary connectives (constants)
Truth/tautology 1  
Falsity/contradiction 0  
Unary connectives
  = 0 1
Proposition   0 1  
¬ Negation 1 0  
Binary connectives
  = 0 1
  = 0 1 0 1
Proposition   0 0 1 1  
Proposition   0 1 0 1  
Conjunction 0 0 0 1  
Alternative denial 1 1 1 0  
Disjunction 0 1 1 1  
Joint denial 1 0 0 0  
Material conditional 1 1 0 1  
  Exclusive or 0 1 1 0  
Biconditional 1 0 0 1  
Converse implication 1 0 1 1  
More information

List of common logical connectives edit

Commonly used logical connectives include the following ones.[2]

  • Negation (not):  ,  ,   (prefix) in which   is the most modern and widely used, and   is used by many people too;
  • Conjunction (and):  ,  ,   (prefix) in which   is the most modern and widely used;
  • Disjunction (or):  ,   (prefix) in which   is the most modern and widely used;
  • Implication (if...then):  ,  ,  ,   (prefix) in which   is the most modern and widely used, and   is used by many people too;
  • Equivalence (if and only if):  ,  ,  ,  ,   (prefix) in which   is the most modern and widely used, and   may be also a good choice compared to   denoting implication just like   to  .

For example, the meaning of the statements it is raining (denoted by  ) and I am indoors (denoted by  ) is transformed, when the two are combined with logical connectives:

  • It is not raining ( );
  • It is raining and I am indoors ( );
  • It is raining or I am indoors ( );
  • If it is raining, then I am indoors ( );
  • If I am indoors, then it is raining ( );
  • I am indoors if and only if it is raining ( ).

It is also common to consider the always true formula and the always false formula to be connective.

  • True formula:  ,  ,   (prefix), or  ;
  • False formula:  ,  ,   (prefix), or  .

History of notations edit

  • Negation: the symbol   appeared in Heyting in 1930[3][4] (compare to Frege's symbol ⫟ in his Begriffsschrift[5]); the symbol   appeared in Russell in 1908;[6] an alternative notation is to add a horizontal line on top of the formula, as in  ; another alternative notation is to use a prime symbol as in  .
  • Conjunction: the symbol   appeared in Heyting in 1930[3] (compare to Peano's use of the set-theoretic notation of intersection  [7]); the symbol   appeared at least in Schönfinkel in 1924;[8] the symbol   comes from Boole's interpretation of logic as an elementary algebra.
  • Disjunction: the symbol   appeared in Russell in 1908[6] (compare to Peano's use of the set-theoretic notation of union  ); the symbol   is also used, in spite of the ambiguity coming from the fact that the   of ordinary elementary algebra is an exclusive or when interpreted logically in a two-element ring; punctually in the history a   together with a dot in the lower right corner has been used by Peirce.[9]
  • Implication: the symbol   appeared in Hilbert in 1918;[10]: 76    was used by Russell in 1908[6] (compare to Peano's Ɔ the inverted C);   appeared in Bourbaki in 1954.[11]
  • Equivalence: the symbol   in Frege in 1879;[12]   in Becker in 1933 (not the first time and for this see the following);[13]   appeared in Bourbaki in 1954;[14] other symbols appeared punctually in the history, such as   in Gentzen,[15]   in Schönfinkel[8] or   in Chazal, [16]
  • True: the symbol   comes from Boole's interpretation of logic as an elementary algebra over the two-element Boolean algebra; other notations include   (abbreviation for the Latin word "verum") to be found in Peano in 1889.
  • False: the symbol   comes also from Boole's interpretation of logic as a ring; other notations include   (rotated  ) to be found in Peano in 1889.

Some authors used letters for connectives:   for conjunction (German's "und" for "and") and   for disjunction (German's "oder" for "or") in early works by Hilbert (1904);[17]   for negation,   for conjunction,   for alternative denial,   for disjunction,   for implication,   for biconditional in Łukasiewicz in 1929.

Redundancy edit

Such a logical connective as converse implication " " is actually the same as material conditional with swapped arguments; thus, the symbol for converse implication is redundant. In some logical calculi (notably, in classical logic), certain essentially different compound statements are logically equivalent. A less trivial example of a redundancy is the classical equivalence between   and  . Therefore, a classical-based logical system does not need the conditional operator " " if " " (not) and " " (or) are already in use, or may use the " " only as a syntactic sugar for a compound having one negation and one disjunction.

There are sixteen Boolean functions associating the input truth values   and   with four-digit binary outputs.[18] These correspond to possible choices of binary logical connectives for classical logic. Different implementations of classical logic can choose different functionally complete subsets of connectives.

One approach is to choose a minimal set, and define other connectives by some logical form, as in the example with the material conditional above. The following are the minimal functionally complete sets of operators in classical logic whose arities do not exceed 2:

One element
 ,  .
Two elements
 ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  .
Three elements
 ,  ,  ,  ,  ,  .

Another approach is to use with equal rights connectives of a certain convenient and functionally complete, but not minimal set. This approach requires more propositional axioms, and each equivalence between logical forms must be either an axiom or provable as a theorem.

The situation, however, is more complicated in intuitionistic logic. Of its five connectives, {∧, ∨, →, ¬, ⊥}, only negation "¬" can be reduced to other connectives (see False (logic) § False, negation and contradiction for more). Neither conjunction, disjunction, nor material conditional has an equivalent form constructed from the other four logical connectives.

Natural language edit

The standard logical connectives of classical logic have rough equivalents in the grammars of natural languages. In English, as in many languages, such expressions are typically grammatical conjunctions. However, they can also take the form of complementizers, verb suffixes, and particles. The denotations of natural language connectives is a major topic of research in formal semantics, a field that studies the logical structure of natural languages.

The meanings of natural language connectives are not precisely identical to their nearest equivalents in classical logic. In particular, disjunction can receive an exclusive interpretation in many languages. Some researchers have taken this fact as evidence that natural language semantics is nonclassical. However, others maintain classical semantics by positing pragmatic accounts of exclusivity which create the illusion of nonclassicality. In such accounts, exclusivity is typically treated as a scalar implicature. Related puzzles involving disjunction include free choice inferences, Hurford's Constraint, and the contribution of disjunction in alternative questions.

Other apparent discrepancies between natural language and classical logic include the paradoxes of material implication, donkey anaphora and the problem of counterfactual conditionals. These phenomena have been taken as motivation for identifying the denotations of natural language conditionals with logical operators including the strict conditional, the variably strict conditional, as well as various dynamic operators.

The following table shows the standard classically definable approximations for the English connectives.

English word Connective Symbol Logical gate
not negation   NOT
and conjunction   AND
or disjunction   OR
if...then material implication   IMPLY
...if converse implication  
either...or exclusive disjunction   XOR
if and only if biconditional   XNOR
not both alternative denial   NAND
neither...nor joint denial   NOR
but not material nonimplication   NIMPLY

Properties edit

Some logical connectives possess properties that may be expressed in the theorems containing the connective. Some of those properties that a logical connective may have are:

Associativity
Within an expression containing two or more of the same associative connectives in a row, the order of the operations does not matter as long as the sequence of the operands is not changed.
Commutativity
The operands of the connective may be swapped, preserving logical equivalence to the original expression.
Distributivity
A connective denoted by · distributes over another connective denoted by +, if a · (b + c) = (a · b) + (a · c) for all operands a, b, c.
Idempotence
Whenever the operands of the operation are the same, the compound is logically equivalent to the operand.
Absorption
A pair of connectives ∧, ∨ satisfies the absorption law if   for all operands a, b.
Monotonicity
If f(a1, ..., an) ≤ f(b1, ..., bn) for all a1, ..., an, b1, ..., bn ∈ {0,1} such that a1b1, a2b2, ..., anbn. E.g., ∨, ∧, ⊤, ⊥.
Affinity
Each variable always makes a difference in the truth-value of the operation or it never makes a difference. E.g., ¬, ↔,  , ⊤, ⊥.
Duality
To read the truth-value assignments for the operation from top to bottom on its truth table is the same as taking the complement of reading the table of the same or another connective from bottom to top. Without resorting to truth tables it may be formulated as a1, ..., ¬an) = ¬g(a1, ..., an). E.g., ¬.
Truth-preserving
The compound all those arguments are tautologies is a tautology itself. E.g., ∨, ∧, ⊤, →, ↔, ⊂ (see validity).
Falsehood-preserving
The compound all those argument are contradictions is a contradiction itself. E.g., ∨, ∧,  , ⊥, ⊄, ⊅ (see validity).
Involutivity (for unary connectives)
f(f(a)) = a. E.g. negation in classical logic.

For classical and intuitionistic logic, the "=" symbol means that corresponding implications "...→..." and "...←..." for logical compounds can be both proved as theorems, and the "≤" symbol means that "...→..." for logical compounds is a consequence of corresponding "...→..." connectives for propositional variables. Some many-valued logics may have incompatible definitions of equivalence and order (entailment).

Both conjunction and disjunction are associative, commutative and idempotent in classical logic, most varieties of many-valued logic and intuitionistic logic. The same is true about distributivity of conjunction over disjunction and disjunction over conjunction, as well as for the absorption law.

In classical logic and some varieties of many-valued logic, conjunction and disjunction are dual, and negation is self-dual, the latter is also self-dual in intuitionistic logic.

Order of precedence edit

As a way of reducing the number of necessary parentheses, one may introduce precedence rules: ¬ has higher precedence than ∧, ∧ higher than ∨, and ∨ higher than →. So for example,   is short for  .

Here is a table that shows a commonly used precedence of logical operators.[19]

Operator Precedence
  1
  2
  3
  4
  5

However, not all compilers use the same order; for instance, an ordering in which disjunction is lower precedence than implication or bi-implication has also been used.[20] Sometimes precedence between conjunction and disjunction is unspecified requiring to provide it explicitly in given formula with parentheses. The order of precedence determines which connective is the "main connective" when interpreting a non-atomic formula.

Computer science edit

A truth-functional approach to logical operators is implemented as logic gates in digital circuits. Practically all digital circuits (the major exception is DRAM) are built up from NAND, NOR, NOT, and transmission gates; see more details in Truth function in computer science. Logical operators over bit vectors (corresponding to finite Boolean algebras) are bitwise operations.

But not every usage of a logical connective in computer programming has a Boolean semantic. For example, lazy evaluation is sometimes implemented for P ∧ Q and P ∨ Q, so these connectives are not commutative if either or both of the expressions P, Q have side effects. Also, a conditional, which in some sense corresponds to the material conditional connective, is essentially non-Boolean because for if (P) then Q;, the consequent Q is not executed if the antecedent P is false (although a compound as a whole is successful ≈ "true" in such case). This is closer to intuitionist and constructivist views on the material conditional— rather than to classical logic's views.

Table and Hasse diagram edit

The 16 logical connectives can be partially ordered to produce the following Hasse diagram. The partial order is defined by declaring that   if and only if whenever   holds then so does  

 input Ainput Boutput f(A,B)X and ¬XA and B¬A and BBA and ¬BAA xor BA or B¬A and ¬BA xnor B¬A¬A or B¬BA or ¬B¬A or ¬BX or ¬X
 X or ¬X¬A or ¬BA or ¬B¬A or BA or B¬B¬AA xor BA xnor BAB¬A and ¬BA and ¬B¬A and BA and BX and ¬X
        

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Cogwheel. "What is the difference between logical and conditional /operator/". Stack Overflow. Retrieved 9 April 2015.
  2. ^ Chao, C. (2023). 数理逻辑:形式化方法的应用 [Mathematical Logic: Applications of the Formalization Method] (in Chinese). Beijing: Preprint. pp. 15–28.
  3. ^ a b Heyting, A. (1930). "Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik". Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-mathematische Klasse (in German): 42–56.
  4. ^ Denis Roegel (2002), A brief survey of 20th century logical notations (see chart on page 2).
  5. ^ Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens. Halle a/S.: Verlag von Louis Nebert. p. 10.
  6. ^ a b c Russell (1908) Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types (American Journal of Mathematics 30, p222–262, also in From Frege to Gödel edited by van Heijenoort).
  7. ^ Peano (1889) Arithmetices principia, nova methodo exposita.
  8. ^ a b Schönfinkel (1924) Über die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik, translated as On the building blocks of mathematical logic in From Frege to Gödel edited by van Heijenoort.
  9. ^ Peirce (1867) On an improvement in Boole's calculus of logic.
  10. ^ Hilbert, D. (1918). Bernays, P. (ed.). Prinzipien der Mathematik. Lecture notes at Universität Göttingen, Winter Semester, 1917-1918; Reprinted as Hilbert, D. (2013). "Prinzipien der Mathematik". In Ewald, W.; Sieg, W. (eds.). David Hilbert's Lectures on the Foundations of Arithmetic and Logic 1917–1933. Heidelberg, New York, Dordrecht and London: Springer. pp. 59–221.
  11. ^ Bourbaki, N. (1954). Théorie des ensembles. Paris: Hermann & Cie, Éditeurs. p. 14.
  12. ^ Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens (in German). Halle a/S.: Verlag von Louis Nebert. p. 15.
  13. ^ Becker, A. (1933). Die Aristotelische Theorie der Möglichkeitsschlösse: Eine logisch-philologische Untersuchung der Kapitel 13-22 von Aristoteles' Analytica priora I (in German). Berlin: Junker und Dünnhaupt Verlag. p. 4.
  14. ^ Bourbaki, N. (1954). Théorie des ensembles (in French). Paris: Hermann & Cie, Éditeurs. p. 32.
  15. ^ Gentzen (1934) Untersuchungen über das logische Schließen.
  16. ^ Chazal (1996) : Éléments de logique formelle.
  17. ^ Hilbert, D. (1905) [1904]. "Über die Grundlagen der Logik und der Arithmetik". In Krazer, K. (ed.). Verhandlungen des Dritten Internationalen Mathematiker Kongresses in Heidelberg vom 8. bis 13. August 1904. pp. 174–185.
  18. ^ Bocheński (1959), A Précis of Mathematical Logic, passim.
  19. ^ O'Donnell, John; Hall, Cordelia; Page, Rex (2007), Discrete Mathematics Using a Computer, Springer, p. 120, ISBN 9781846285981.
  20. ^ Jackson, Daniel (2012), Software Abstractions: Logic, Language, and Analysis, MIT Press, p. 263, ISBN 9780262017152.

Sources edit

External links edit

logical, connective, other, logical, symbols, list, logic, symbols, logic, logical, connective, also, called, logical, operator, sentential, connective, sentential, operator, logical, constant, connectives, used, connect, logical, formulas, instance, syntax, p. For other logical symbols see List of logic symbols In logic a logical connective also called a logical operator sentential connective or sentential operator is a logical constant Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas For instance in the syntax of propositional logic the binary connective displaystyle lor can be used to join the two atomic formulas P displaystyle P and Q displaystyle Q rendering the complex formula P Q displaystyle P lor Q Hasse diagram of logical connectives Common connectives include negation disjunction conjunction implication and equivalence In standard systems of classical logic these connectives are interpreted as truth functions though they receive a variety of alternative interpretations in nonclassical logics Their classical interpretations are similar to the meanings of natural language expressions such as English not or and and if but not identical Discrepancies between natural language connectives and those of classical logic have motivated nonclassical approaches to natural language meaning as well as approaches which pair a classical compositional semantics with a robust pragmatics A logical connective is similar to but not equivalent to a syntax commonly used in programming languages called a conditional operator 1 better source needed Contents 1 Overview 1 1 List of common logical connectives 1 2 History of notations 1 3 Redundancy 2 Natural language 3 Properties 4 Order of precedence 5 Computer science 6 Table and Hasse diagram 7 See also 8 References 9 Sources 10 External linksOverview editIn formal languages truth functions are represented by unambiguous symbols This allows logical statements to not be understood in an ambiguous way These symbols are called logical connectives logical operators propositional operators or in classical logic truth functional connectives For the rules which allow new well formed formulas to be constructed by joining other well formed formulas using truth functional connectives see well formed formula Logical connectives can be used to link zero or more statements so one can speak about n ary logical connectives The boolean constants True and False can be thought of as zero ary operators Negation is a 1 ary connective and so on Symbol name Truth table Venn diagramZeroary connectives constants Truth tautology 1 nbsp Falsity contradiction 0 nbsp Unary connectivesp displaystyle p nbsp 0 1Proposition p displaystyle p nbsp 0 1 nbsp Negation 1 0 nbsp Binary connectivesp displaystyle p nbsp 0 1q displaystyle q nbsp 0 1 0 1Proposition p displaystyle p nbsp 0 0 1 1 nbsp Proposition q displaystyle q nbsp 0 1 0 1 nbsp Conjunction 0 0 0 1 nbsp Alternative denial 1 1 1 0 nbsp Disjunction 0 1 1 1 nbsp Joint denial 1 0 0 0 nbsp Material conditional 1 1 0 1 nbsp displaystyle nleftrightarrow nbsp Exclusive or 0 1 1 0 nbsp Biconditional 1 0 0 1 nbsp Converse implication 1 0 1 1 nbsp More informationList of common logical connectives edit Commonly used logical connectives include the following ones 2 Negation not displaystyle neg nbsp displaystyle sim nbsp N displaystyle N nbsp prefix in which displaystyle neg nbsp is the most modern and widely used and displaystyle sim nbsp is used by many people too Conjunction and displaystyle wedge nbsp amp displaystyle amp nbsp K displaystyle K nbsp prefix in which displaystyle wedge nbsp is the most modern and widely used Disjunction or displaystyle vee nbsp A displaystyle A nbsp prefix in which displaystyle vee nbsp is the most modern and widely used Implication if then displaystyle to nbsp displaystyle supset nbsp displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp C displaystyle C nbsp prefix in which displaystyle to nbsp is the most modern and widely used and displaystyle supset nbsp is used by many people too Equivalence if and only if displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle subset supset nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle equiv nbsp E displaystyle E nbsp prefix in which displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp is the most modern and widely used and displaystyle subset supset nbsp may be also a good choice compared to displaystyle supset nbsp denoting implication just like displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp to displaystyle to nbsp For example the meaning of the statements it is raining denoted by p displaystyle p nbsp and I am indoors denoted by q displaystyle q nbsp is transformed when the two are combined with logical connectives It is not raining p displaystyle neg p nbsp It is raining and I am indoors p q displaystyle p wedge q nbsp It is raining or I am indoors p q displaystyle p lor q nbsp If it is raining then I am indoors p q displaystyle p rightarrow q nbsp If I am indoors then it is raining q p displaystyle q rightarrow p nbsp I am indoors if and only if it is raining p q displaystyle p leftrightarrow q nbsp It is also common to consider the always true formula and the always false formula to be connective True formula displaystyle top nbsp 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp V displaystyle V nbsp prefix or T displaystyle mathrm T nbsp False formula displaystyle bot nbsp 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp O displaystyle O nbsp prefix or F displaystyle mathrm F nbsp History of notations edit Negation the symbol displaystyle neg nbsp appeared in Heyting in 1930 3 4 compare to Frege s symbol in his Begriffsschrift 5 the symbol displaystyle sim nbsp appeared in Russell in 1908 6 an alternative notation is to add a horizontal line on top of the formula as in p displaystyle overline p nbsp another alternative notation is to use a prime symbol as in p displaystyle p nbsp Conjunction the symbol displaystyle wedge nbsp appeared in Heyting in 1930 3 compare to Peano s use of the set theoretic notation of intersection displaystyle cap nbsp 7 the symbol amp displaystyle amp nbsp appeared at least in Schonfinkel in 1924 8 the symbol displaystyle cdot nbsp comes from Boole s interpretation of logic as an elementary algebra Disjunction the symbol displaystyle vee nbsp appeared in Russell in 1908 6 compare to Peano s use of the set theoretic notation of union displaystyle cup nbsp the symbol displaystyle nbsp is also used in spite of the ambiguity coming from the fact that the displaystyle nbsp of ordinary elementary algebra is an exclusive or when interpreted logically in a two element ring punctually in the history a displaystyle nbsp together with a dot in the lower right corner has been used by Peirce 9 Implication the symbol displaystyle to nbsp appeared in Hilbert in 1918 10 76 displaystyle supset nbsp was used by Russell in 1908 6 compare to Peano s Ɔ the inverted C displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp appeared in Bourbaki in 1954 11 Equivalence the symbol displaystyle equiv nbsp in Frege in 1879 12 displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp in Becker in 1933 not the first time and for this see the following 13 displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp appeared in Bourbaki in 1954 14 other symbols appeared punctually in the history such as displaystyle supset subset nbsp in Gentzen 15 displaystyle sim nbsp in Schonfinkel 8 or displaystyle subset supset nbsp in Chazal 16 True the symbol 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp comes from Boole s interpretation of logic as an elementary algebra over the two element Boolean algebra other notations include V displaystyle mathrm V nbsp abbreviation for the Latin word verum to be found in Peano in 1889 False the symbol 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp comes also from Boole s interpretation of logic as a ring other notations include L displaystyle Lambda nbsp rotated V displaystyle mathrm V nbsp to be found in Peano in 1889 Some authors used letters for connectives u displaystyle operatorname u nbsp for conjunction German s und for and and o displaystyle operatorname o nbsp for disjunction German s oder for or in early works by Hilbert 1904 17 N p displaystyle Np nbsp for negation K p q displaystyle Kpq nbsp for conjunction D p q displaystyle Dpq nbsp for alternative denial A p q displaystyle Apq nbsp for disjunction C p q displaystyle Cpq nbsp for implication E p q displaystyle Epq nbsp for biconditional in Lukasiewicz in 1929 Redundancy edit Such a logical connective as converse implication displaystyle leftarrow nbsp is actually the same as material conditional with swapped arguments thus the symbol for converse implication is redundant In some logical calculi notably in classical logic certain essentially different compound statements are logically equivalent A less trivial example of a redundancy is the classical equivalence between p q displaystyle neg p vee q nbsp and p q displaystyle p to q nbsp Therefore a classical based logical system does not need the conditional operator displaystyle to nbsp if displaystyle neg nbsp not and displaystyle vee nbsp or are already in use or may use the displaystyle to nbsp only as a syntactic sugar for a compound having one negation and one disjunction There are sixteen Boolean functions associating the input truth values p displaystyle p nbsp and q displaystyle q nbsp with four digit binary outputs 18 These correspond to possible choices of binary logical connectives for classical logic Different implementations of classical logic can choose different functionally complete subsets of connectives One approach is to choose a minimal set and define other connectives by some logical form as in the example with the material conditional above The following are the minimal functionally complete sets of operators in classical logic whose arities do not exceed 2 One element displaystyle uparrow nbsp displaystyle downarrow nbsp Two elements displaystyle vee neg nbsp displaystyle wedge neg nbsp displaystyle to neg nbsp displaystyle gets neg nbsp displaystyle to bot nbsp displaystyle gets bot nbsp displaystyle to nleftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle gets nleftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle to nrightarrow nbsp displaystyle to nleftarrow nbsp displaystyle gets nrightarrow nbsp displaystyle gets nleftarrow nbsp displaystyle nrightarrow neg nbsp displaystyle nleftarrow neg nbsp displaystyle nrightarrow top nbsp displaystyle nleftarrow top nbsp displaystyle nrightarrow leftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle nleftarrow leftrightarrow nbsp Three elements displaystyle lor leftrightarrow bot nbsp displaystyle lor leftrightarrow nleftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle lor nleftrightarrow top nbsp displaystyle land leftrightarrow bot nbsp displaystyle land leftrightarrow nleftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle land nleftrightarrow top nbsp Another approach is to use with equal rights connectives of a certain convenient and functionally complete but not minimal set This approach requires more propositional axioms and each equivalence between logical forms must be either an axiom or provable as a theorem The situation however is more complicated in intuitionistic logic Of its five connectives only negation can be reduced to other connectives see False logic False negation and contradiction for more Neither conjunction disjunction nor material conditional has an equivalent form constructed from the other four logical connectives Natural language editThe standard logical connectives of classical logic have rough equivalents in the grammars of natural languages In English as in many languages such expressions are typically grammatical conjunctions However they can also take the form of complementizers verb suffixes and particles The denotations of natural language connectives is a major topic of research in formal semantics a field that studies the logical structure of natural languages The meanings of natural language connectives are not precisely identical to their nearest equivalents in classical logic In particular disjunction can receive an exclusive interpretation in many languages Some researchers have taken this fact as evidence that natural language semantics is nonclassical However others maintain classical semantics by positing pragmatic accounts of exclusivity which create the illusion of nonclassicality In such accounts exclusivity is typically treated as a scalar implicature Related puzzles involving disjunction include free choice inferences Hurford s Constraint and the contribution of disjunction in alternative questions Other apparent discrepancies between natural language and classical logic include the paradoxes of material implication donkey anaphora and the problem of counterfactual conditionals These phenomena have been taken as motivation for identifying the denotations of natural language conditionals with logical operators including the strict conditional the variably strict conditional as well as various dynamic operators The following table shows the standard classically definable approximations for the English connectives English word Connective Symbol Logical gatenot negation displaystyle neg nbsp NOTand conjunction displaystyle wedge nbsp ANDor disjunction displaystyle vee nbsp ORif then material implication displaystyle to nbsp IMPLY if converse implication displaystyle leftarrow nbsp either or exclusive disjunction displaystyle oplus nbsp XORif and only if biconditional displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp XNORnot both alternative denial displaystyle uparrow nbsp NANDneither nor joint denial displaystyle downarrow nbsp NORbut not material nonimplication displaystyle not to nbsp NIMPLYProperties editSome logical connectives possess properties that may be expressed in the theorems containing the connective Some of those properties that a logical connective may have are Associativity Within an expression containing two or more of the same associative connectives in a row the order of the operations does not matter as long as the sequence of the operands is not changed Commutativity The operands of the connective may be swapped preserving logical equivalence to the original expression Distributivity A connective denoted by distributes over another connective denoted by if a b c a b a c for all operands a b c Idempotence Whenever the operands of the operation are the same the compound is logically equivalent to the operand Absorption A pair of connectives satisfies the absorption law if a a b a displaystyle a land a lor b a nbsp for all operands a b Monotonicity If f a1 an f b1 bn for all a1 an b1 bn 0 1 such that a1 b1 a2 b2 an bn E g Affinity Each variable always makes a difference in the truth value of the operation or it never makes a difference E g displaystyle nleftrightarrow nbsp Duality To read the truth value assignments for the operation from top to bottom on its truth table is the same as taking the complement of reading the table of the same or another connective from bottom to top Without resorting to truth tables it may be formulated as g a1 an g a1 an E g Truth preserving The compound all those arguments are tautologies is a tautology itself E g see validity Falsehood preserving The compound all those argument are contradictions is a contradiction itself E g displaystyle nleftrightarrow nbsp see validity Involutivity for unary connectives f f a a E g negation in classical logic For classical and intuitionistic logic the symbol means that corresponding implications and for logical compounds can be both proved as theorems and the symbol means that for logical compounds is a consequence of corresponding connectives for propositional variables Some many valued logics may have incompatible definitions of equivalence and order entailment Both conjunction and disjunction are associative commutative and idempotent in classical logic most varieties of many valued logic and intuitionistic logic The same is true about distributivity of conjunction over disjunction and disjunction over conjunction as well as for the absorption law In classical logic and some varieties of many valued logic conjunction and disjunction are dual and negation is self dual the latter is also self dual in intuitionistic logic This section needs expansion You can help by adding to it March 2012 Order of precedence editAs a way of reducing the number of necessary parentheses one may introduce precedence rules has higher precedence than higher than and higher than So for example P Q R S displaystyle P vee Q wedge neg R rightarrow S nbsp is short for P Q R S displaystyle P vee Q wedge neg R rightarrow S nbsp Here is a table that shows a commonly used precedence of logical operators 19 Operator Precedence displaystyle neg nbsp 1 displaystyle land nbsp 2 displaystyle lor nbsp 3 displaystyle to nbsp 4 displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp 5However not all compilers use the same order for instance an ordering in which disjunction is lower precedence than implication or bi implication has also been used 20 Sometimes precedence between conjunction and disjunction is unspecified requiring to provide it explicitly in given formula with parentheses The order of precedence determines which connective is the main connective when interpreting a non atomic formula Computer science editThis section needs expansion You can help by adding to it March 2012 A truth functional approach to logical operators is implemented as logic gates in digital circuits Practically all digital circuits the major exception is DRAM are built up from NAND NOR NOT and transmission gates see more details in Truth function in computer science Logical operators over bit vectors corresponding to finite Boolean algebras are bitwise operations But not every usage of a logical connective in computer programming has a Boolean semantic For example lazy evaluation is sometimes implemented for P Q and P Q so these connectives are not commutative if either or both of the expressions P Q have side effects Also a conditional which in some sense corresponds to the material conditional connective is essentially non Boolean because for if P then Q the consequent Q is not executed if the antecedent P is false although a compound as a whole is successful true in such case This is closer to intuitionist and constructivist views on the material conditional rather than to classical logic s views Table and Hasse diagram editThe 16 logical connectives can be partially ordered to produce the following Hasse diagram The partial order is defined by declaring that x y displaystyle x leq y nbsp if and only if whenever x displaystyle x nbsp holds then so does y displaystyle y nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portalBoolean domain Boolean function Boolean logic Boolean valued function Four valued logic List of Boolean algebra topics Logical constant Modal operator Propositional calculus Truth function Truth table Truth valuesReferences edit Cogwheel What is the difference between logical and conditional operator Stack Overflow Retrieved 9 April 2015 Chao C 2023 数理逻辑 形式化方法的应用 Mathematical Logic Applications of the Formalization Method in Chinese Beijing Preprint pp 15 28 a b Heyting A 1930 Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften Physikalisch mathematische Klasse in German 42 56 Denis Roegel 2002 A brief survey of 20th century logical notations see chart on page 2 Frege G 1879 Begriffsschrift eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens Halle a S Verlag von Louis Nebert p 10 a b c Russell 1908 Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types American Journal of Mathematics 30 p222 262 also in From Frege to Godel edited by van Heijenoort Peano 1889 Arithmetices principia nova methodo exposita a b Schonfinkel 1924 Uber die Bausteine der mathematischen Logik translated as On the building blocks of mathematical logic in From Frege to Godel edited by van Heijenoort Peirce 1867 On an improvement in Boole s calculus of logic Hilbert D 1918 Bernays P ed Prinzipien der Mathematik Lecture notes at Universitat Gottingen Winter Semester 1917 1918 Reprinted as Hilbert D 2013 Prinzipien der Mathematik In Ewald W Sieg W eds David Hilbert s Lectures on the Foundations of Arithmetic and Logic 1917 1933 Heidelberg New York Dordrecht and London Springer pp 59 221 Bourbaki N 1954 Theorie des ensembles Paris Hermann amp Cie Editeurs p 14 Frege G 1879 Begriffsschrift eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete Formelsprache des reinen Denkens in German Halle a S Verlag von Louis Nebert p 15 Becker A 1933 Die Aristotelische Theorie der Moglichkeitsschlosse Eine logisch philologische Untersuchung der Kapitel 13 22 von Aristoteles Analytica priora I in German Berlin Junker und Dunnhaupt Verlag p 4 Bourbaki N 1954 Theorie des ensembles in French Paris Hermann amp Cie Editeurs p 32 Gentzen 1934 Untersuchungen uber das logische Schliessen Chazal 1996 Elements de logique formelle Hilbert D 1905 1904 Uber die Grundlagen der Logik und der Arithmetik In Krazer K ed Verhandlungen des Dritten Internationalen Mathematiker Kongresses in Heidelberg vom 8 bis 13 August 1904 pp 174 185 Bochenski 1959 A Precis of Mathematical Logic passim O Donnell John Hall Cordelia Page Rex 2007 Discrete Mathematics Using a Computer Springer p 120 ISBN 9781846285981 Jackson Daniel 2012 Software Abstractions Logic Language and Analysis MIT Press p 263 ISBN 9780262017152 Sources editBochenski Jozef Maria 1959 A Precis of Mathematical Logic translated from the French and German editions by Otto Bird D Reidel Dordrecht South Holland Chao C 2023 数理逻辑 形式化方法的应用 Mathematical Logic Applications of the Formalization Method in Chinese Beijing Preprint pp 15 28 Enderton Herbert 2001 A Mathematical Introduction to Logic 2nd ed Boston MA Academic Press ISBN 978 0 12 238452 3 Gamut L T F 1991 Chapter 2 Logic Language and Meaning vol 1 University of Chicago Press pp 54 64 OCLC 21372380 Rautenberg W 2010 A Concise Introduction to Mathematical Logic 3rd ed New York Springer Science Business Media doi 10 1007 978 1 4419 1221 3 ISBN 978 1 4419 1220 6 Humberstone Lloyd 2011 The Connectives MIT Press ISBN 978 0 262 01654 4 External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Logical connectives Propositional connective Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Lloyd Humberstone 2010 Sentence Connectives in Formal Logic Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy An abstract algebraic logic approach to connectives John MacFarlane 2005 Logical constants Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Logical connective amp oldid 1205222122, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.