fbpx
Wikipedia

Dynamic semantics

Dynamic semantics is a framework in logic and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context. In static semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true; in dynamic semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing "the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it."[1] In dynamic semantics, sentences are mapped to functions called context change potentials, which take an input context and return an output context. Dynamic semantics was originally developed by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp in 1981 to model anaphora, but has since been applied widely to phenomena including presupposition, plurals, questions, discourse relations, and modality.[2]

Dynamics of anaphora edit

The first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related File Change Semantics and discourse representation theory, developed simultaneously and independently by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp. These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora, which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as Montague grammar.[2][3] Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences, first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by Peter Geach.[4][5]

Donkey sentence (relative clause): Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it.
Donkey sentence (conditional): If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it.

To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in first order logic, one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey" as a universal quantifier scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun "it".

FOL translation of donkey sentence:  :  

While this translation captures (or approximates) the truth conditions of the natural language sentences, its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways. First, indefinites in non-donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification. Second, the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite.

To explain these peculiarities, Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new discourse referent that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it. To cash this idea out, they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate Egli's theorem and its corollary.[6]

Egli's theorem:  
Egli's corollary:  

Update semantics edit

Update semantics is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by Frank Veltman.[1][7] In update semantics, each formula   is mapped to a function   that takes and returns a discourse context. Thus, if   is a context, then   is the context one gets by updating   with  . Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas. The simplest update systems are intersective ones, which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework. However, update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework. In particular, it allows information sensitive semantic entries, in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context.[8] This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to presuppositions, modals, and conditionals.

Intersective update edit

An update with   is called intersective if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by  . Crucially, this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that   always denotes, regardless of the context.[8]

  • Intersective update: Let   be the proposition denoted by  . Then   is intersective if and only if for any  , we have that  

Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion.[9][8] In Stalnaker's original system, a context (or context set) is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation. For instance, if   this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either  ,  , or  . If  , then updating   with   would return a new context  . Thus, an assertion of   would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is  .

From a formal perspective, intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one's preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics. For instance, if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point, this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics.[8]

  • Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic:
  1.  
  2.  
  3.  
  4.  

The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as eliminativity and distributivity. Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context—it can't add them. Distributivity says that updating   with   is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of   with   and then pooling the results.[8]

  • Eliminativity:   is eliminative iff   for all contexts  
  • Distributivity:   is distributive iff  

Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties, as proven by Johan van Benthem.[8][10]

The test semantics for modals edit

The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings. Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context. For instance, if   is intersective, then it will update any input context with the exact same information, namely the information encoded by the proposition  . On the other hand, if   is nonintersective, it could contribute   when it updates some contexts, but some completely different information when it updates other contexts.[8]

Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings. The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of epistemic contradictions.[11][8]

Epistemic contradiction: #It's raining and it might not be raining.

These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions, unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences, which can be given a pragmatic explanation.[12][8]

Epistemic contradiction principle:  

These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic. The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of relational frames such that  . However, such frames also validate an entailment from   to  . Thus, accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that "It might be raining" entails "It is raining".[12][8] Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals. When given such a denotation, the formula   can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that   provides. The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the test semantics proposed by Frank Veltman.[1]

  • The test semantics for modals:  

On this semantics,   tests whether the input context could be updated with   without getting trivialized, i.e. without returning the empty set. If the input context passes the test, it remains unchanged. If it fails the test, the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set. This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context, updating with   will always output a context that fails the test imposed by  .[8][13]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c Veltman, Frank (1996). "Defaults in Update Semantics" (PDF). Journal of Philosophical Logic. 25 (3). doi:10.1007/BF00248150. S2CID 19377671.
  2. ^ a b Nowen, Rick; Brasoveanu, Adrian; van Eijck, Jan; Visser, Albert (2016). "Dynamic Semantics". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
  3. ^ Geurts, Bart; Beaver, David; Maier, Emar (2020). "Discourse Representation Theory". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
  4. ^ Peter Geach (1962). Reference and Generality: An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories.
  5. ^ King, Jeffrey; Lewis, Karen (2018). "Anaphora". In Zalta, Edward (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2020-08-11.
  6. ^ Dekker, Paul (2001). "On If And Only If". In Hastings, R; Jackson, B; Zvolenszky, Z (eds.). Proceedings of SALT XI. Semantics and Linguistic Theory. Vol. 11. Linguistic Society of America.
  7. ^ Goldstein, Simon (2019). "Generalized Update Semantics" (PDF). Mind. 128 (511): 795–835. doi:10.1093/mind/fzy076.
  8. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Goldstein, Simon (2017). "Introduction". Informative Dynamic Semantics (PhD). Rutgers University.
  9. ^ Stalnaker, Robert (1978). "Assertion". In Cole, Peter (ed.). Pragmatics. Brill. pp. 315–332. doi:10.1163/9789004368873_001.
  10. ^ van Benthem, Johan (1986). Essays in logical semantics. Dordrecht: Reidel.
  11. ^ Yalcin, Seth (2007). "Epistemic Modals" (PDF). Mind. 116 (464): 983–1026. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm983.
  12. ^ a b Yalcin, Seth (2007). "Epistemic Modals" (PDF). Mind. 116 (464): 983–1026. doi:10.1093/mind/fzm983.
  13. ^ For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics, see for instance Goldstein (2016), p. 13. This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment, as well as an intersective semantic entry for   and a treatment of   as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order.

External links edit

  • Dynamic Semantics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Dynamic Semantics Notes, Daniel Rothschild
  • Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives, ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes

dynamic, semantics, framework, logic, natural, language, semantics, that, treats, meaning, sentence, potential, update, context, static, semantics, knowing, meaning, sentence, amounts, knowing, when, true, dynamic, semantics, knowing, meaning, sentence, means,. Dynamic semantics is a framework in logic and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context In static semantics knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true in dynamic semantics knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it 1 In dynamic semantics sentences are mapped to functions called context change potentials which take an input context and return an output context Dynamic semantics was originally developed by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp in 1981 to model anaphora but has since been applied widely to phenomena including presupposition plurals questions discourse relations and modality 2 Contents 1 Dynamics of anaphora 2 Update semantics 2 1 Intersective update 2 2 The test semantics for modals 3 See also 4 Notes 5 External linksDynamics of anaphora editSee also Discourse representation theory and Donkey anaphora The first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related File Change Semantics and discourse representation theory developed simultaneously and independently by Irene Heim and Hans Kamp These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as Montague grammar 2 3 Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by Peter Geach 4 5 Donkey sentence relative clause Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it Donkey sentence conditional If a farmer owns a donkey he beats it dd To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in first order logic one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase a donkey as a universal quantifier scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun it FOL translation of donkey sentence x y farmer x donkey y own x y beat x y displaystyle forall x forall y text farmer x land text donkey y land text own x y rightarrow text beat x y nbsp dd While this translation captures or approximates the truth conditions of the natural language sentences its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways First indefinites in non donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification Second the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite To explain these peculiarities Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new discourse referent that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it To cash this idea out they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate Egli s theorem and its corollary 6 Egli s theorem x f ps x f ps displaystyle exists x varphi land psi Leftrightarrow exists x varphi land psi nbsp Egli s corollary x ϕ ps x ϕ ps displaystyle exists x phi rightarrow psi Leftrightarrow forall x phi rightarrow psi nbsp dd Update semantics editUpdate semantics is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by Frank Veltman 1 7 In update semantics each formula f displaystyle varphi nbsp is mapped to a function f displaystyle varphi nbsp that takes and returns a discourse context Thus if C displaystyle C nbsp is a context then C f displaystyle C varphi nbsp is the context one gets by updating C displaystyle C nbsp with f displaystyle varphi nbsp Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas The simplest update systems are intersective ones which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework However update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework In particular it allows information sensitive semantic entries in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context 8 This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to presuppositions modals and conditionals Intersective update edit An update with f displaystyle varphi nbsp is called intersective if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by f displaystyle varphi nbsp Crucially this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that f displaystyle varphi nbsp always denotes regardless of the context 8 Intersective update Let f displaystyle varphi nbsp be the proposition denoted by f displaystyle varphi nbsp Then f displaystyle varphi nbsp is intersective if and only if for any C displaystyle C nbsp we have that C f C f displaystyle C varphi C cap varphi nbsp Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion 9 8 In Stalnaker s original system a context or context set is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation For instance if C w v u displaystyle C w v u nbsp this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either w displaystyle w nbsp v displaystyle v nbsp or u displaystyle u nbsp If f w v displaystyle varphi w v nbsp then updating C displaystyle C nbsp with f displaystyle varphi nbsp would return a new context C f w v displaystyle C varphi w v nbsp Thus an assertion of f displaystyle varphi nbsp would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is u displaystyle u nbsp From a formal perspective intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one s preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics For instance if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics 8 Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic C P w C w P 1 displaystyle C P w in C mid w P 1 nbsp C f C C f displaystyle C neg varphi C C varphi nbsp C f ps C f C ps displaystyle C varphi land psi C varphi cap C psi nbsp C f ps C f C ps displaystyle C varphi lor psi C varphi cup C psi nbsp The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as eliminativity and distributivity Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context it can t add them Distributivity says that updating C displaystyle C nbsp with f displaystyle varphi nbsp is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of C displaystyle C nbsp with f displaystyle varphi nbsp and then pooling the results 8 Eliminativity f displaystyle varphi nbsp is eliminative iff C f C displaystyle C varphi subseteq C nbsp for all contexts C displaystyle C nbsp Distributivity f displaystyle varphi nbsp is distributive iff C f w f w C displaystyle C varphi bigcup w varphi mid w in C nbsp Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties as proven by Johan van Benthem 8 10 The test semantics for modals edit The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context For instance if f displaystyle varphi nbsp is intersective then it will update any input context with the exact same information namely the information encoded by the proposition f displaystyle varphi nbsp On the other hand if f displaystyle varphi nbsp is nonintersective it could contribute f displaystyle varphi nbsp when it updates some contexts but some completely different information when it updates other contexts 8 Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of epistemic contradictions 11 8 Epistemic contradiction It s raining and it might not be raining These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences which can be given a pragmatic explanation 12 8 Epistemic contradiction principle f f displaystyle varphi land Diamond neg varphi models bot nbsp These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of relational frames such that R w v w v displaystyle Rwv Rightarrow w v nbsp However such frames also validate an entailment from f displaystyle Diamond varphi nbsp to f displaystyle varphi nbsp Thus accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that It might be raining entails It is raining 12 8 Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals When given such a denotation the formula f displaystyle Diamond neg varphi nbsp can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that f displaystyle varphi nbsp provides The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the test semantics proposed by Frank Veltman 1 The test semantics for modals C f C if C f otherwise displaystyle C Diamond varphi begin cases C amp text if C varphi neq varnothing varnothing amp text otherwise end cases nbsp On this semantics f displaystyle Diamond varphi nbsp tests whether the input context could be updated with f displaystyle varphi nbsp without getting trivialized i e without returning the empty set If the input context passes the test it remains unchanged If it fails the test the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context updating with f displaystyle varphi nbsp will always output a context that fails the test imposed by f displaystyle Diamond neg varphi nbsp 8 13 See also edit nbsp Linguistics portal Conversational scoreboard Donkey anaphora Discourse representation theory Formal semantics of programming languages Hans Kamp Import Export Irene Heim Modal logic Scope formal semantics Notes edit a b c Veltman Frank 1996 Defaults in Update Semantics PDF Journal of Philosophical Logic 25 3 doi 10 1007 BF00248150 S2CID 19377671 a b Nowen Rick Brasoveanu Adrian van Eijck Jan Visser Albert 2016 Dynamic Semantics In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Geurts Bart Beaver David Maier Emar 2020 Discourse Representation Theory In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Peter Geach 1962 Reference and Generality An Examination of Some Medieval and Modern Theories King Jeffrey Lewis Karen 2018 Anaphora In Zalta Edward ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2020 08 11 Dekker Paul 2001 On If And Only If In Hastings R Jackson B Zvolenszky Z eds Proceedings of SALT XI Semantics and Linguistic Theory Vol 11 Linguistic Society of America Goldstein Simon 2019 Generalized Update Semantics PDF Mind 128 511 795 835 doi 10 1093 mind fzy076 a b c d e f g h i j k Goldstein Simon 2017 Introduction Informative Dynamic Semantics PhD Rutgers University Stalnaker Robert 1978 Assertion In Cole Peter ed Pragmatics Brill pp 315 332 doi 10 1163 9789004368873 001 van Benthem Johan 1986 Essays in logical semantics Dordrecht Reidel Yalcin Seth 2007 Epistemic Modals PDF Mind 116 464 983 1026 doi 10 1093 mind fzm983 a b Yalcin Seth 2007 Epistemic Modals PDF Mind 116 464 983 1026 doi 10 1093 mind fzm983 For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics see for instance Goldstein 2016 p 13 This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment as well as an intersective semantic entry for displaystyle neg nbsp and a treatment of displaystyle land nbsp as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order External links editDynamic Semantics Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Dynamic Semantics Notes Daniel Rothschild Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Dynamic semantics amp oldid 1150147926, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.