fbpx
Wikipedia

Representation (arts)

Representation is the use of signs that stand in for and take the place of something else.[1] It is through representation that people organize the world and reality through the act of naming its elements.[1] Signs are arranged in order to form semantic constructions and express relations.[1]

Bust of Aristotle, Greek philosopher

For many philosophers, both ancient and modern, man is regarded as the "representational animal" or animal symbolicum, the creature whose distinct character is the creation and the manipulation of signs – things that "stand for" or "take the place of" something else.[1]

Representation has been associated with aesthetics (art) and semiotics (signs). Mitchell says "representation is an extremely elastic notion, which extends all the way from a stone representing a man to a novel representing the day in the life of several Dubliners".[1]

The term 'representation' carries a range of meanings and interpretations. In literary theory, 'representation' is commonly defined in three ways.

  1. To look like or resemble
  2. To stand in for something or someone
  3. To present a second time; to re-present[2]

The reflection on representation began with early literary theory in the ideas of Plato and Aristotle, and has evolved into a significant component of language, Saussurian and communication studies.[2]

Defining representation edit

 
Reproduction of the Mona Lisa

To represent is "to bring to mind by description," also "to symbolize, to be the embodiment of;" from representer (12c.), from L. repraesentare, from re-, intensive prefix, + praesentare "to present," lit. "to place before".[original research?]

A representation is a type of recording in which the sensory information about a physical object is described in a medium. The degree to which an artistic representation resembles the object it represents is a function of resolution and does not bear on the denotation of the word. For example, both the Mona Lisa and a child's crayon drawing of Lisa del Giocondo would be considered representational, and any preference for one over the other would need to be understood as a matter of aesthetics.[citation needed]

History edit

 
Greek theatrical masks depicted in Hadrians Villa mosaic

Since ancient times representation has played a central role in understanding literature, aesthetics and semiotics. Plato and Aristotle are key figures in early literary theory who considered literature as simply one form of representation.[3] Aristotle for instance, considered each mode of representation, verbal, visual or musical, as being natural to human beings.[4] Therefore, what distinguishes humans from other animals is their ability to create and manipulate signs.[5] Aristotle deemed mimesis as natural to man, therefore considered representations as necessary for people's learning and being in the world.[4]

Plato, in contrast, looked upon representation with more caution. He recognised that literature is a representation of life, yet also believed that representations intervene between the viewer and the real. This creates worlds of illusion leading one away from the "real things".[6] Plato thus believed that representation needs to be controlled and monitored due to the possible dangers of fostering antisocial emotions or the imitation of evil.[5]

Aristotle went on to say it was a definitively human activity.[1] From childhood man has an instinct for representation, and in this respect man differs from the other animals that he is far more imitative and learns his first lessons though imitating things.[1] Aristotle discusses representation in three ways—

  1. The object: The symbol being represented.
  2. Manner: The way the symbol is represented.
  3. Means: The material that is used to represent it.

The means of literary representation is language. An important part of representation is the relationship between what the material and what it represents. The questions arising from this are, "A stone may represent a man but how? And by what and by what agreement, does this understanding of the representation occur?"[1]

One apprehends reality only through representations of reality, through texts, discourses, images: there is no such thing as direct or unmediated access to reality. But because one can see reality only through representation it does not follow that one does not see reality at all... Reality is always more extensive and complicated than any system of representation can comprehend, and we always sense that this is so-representation never "gets" reality, which is why human history has produced so many and changing ways of trying to get it.[7]

Consequently, throughout the history of human culture, people have become dissatisfied with language's ability to express reality and as a result have developed new modes of representation. It is necessary to construct new ways of seeing reality, as people only know reality through representation.[7] From this arises the contrasting and alternate theories and representational modes of abstraction, realism and modernism, to name a few.

Contemporary ideas about representation edit

It is from Plato's caution that in the modern era many are aware of political and ideological issues and the influences of representations. It is impossible to divorce representations from culture and the society that produces them. In the contemporary world there exist restrictions on subject matter, limiting the kinds of representational signs allowed to be employed, as well as boundaries that limit the audience or viewers of particular representations. In motion picture rating systems, M and R rated films are an example of such restrictions, highlighting also society's attempt to restrict and modify representations to promote a certain set of ideologies and values. Despite these restrictions, representations still have the ability to take on a life of their own once in the public sphere, and can not be given a definitive or concrete meaning; as there will always be a gap between intention and realization, original and copy.[5]

Consequently, for each of the above definitions there exists a process of communication and message sending and receiving. In such a system of communication and representations it is inevitable that potential problems may arise; misunderstandings, errors, and falsehoods. The accuracy of the representations can by no means be guaranteed, as they operate in a system of signs that can never work in isolation from other signs or cultural factors. For instance, the interpretation and reading of representations function in the context of a body of rules for interpreting, and within a society many of these codes or conventions are informally agreed upon and have been established over a number of years. Such understandings however, are not set in stone and may alter between times, places, peoples and contexts. How though, does this 'agreement' or understanding of representation occur? It has generally been agreed by semioticians that representational relationships can be categorised into three distinct headings: icon, symbol and index.[5]

For instance objects and people do not have a constant meaning, but their meanings are fashioned by humans in the context of their culture, as they have the ability to make things mean or signify something.[6] Viewing representation in such a way focuses on understanding how language and systems of knowledge production work to create and circulate meanings. Representation is simply the process in which such meanings are constructed.[6] In much the same way as the post-structuralists, this approach to representation considers it as something larger than any one single representation. A similar perspective is viewing representation as part of a larger field, as Mitchell, saying, "…representation (in memory, in verbal descriptions, in images) not only 'mediates' our knowledge (of slavery and of many other things), but obstructs, fragments, and negates that knowledge"[8] and proposes a move away from the perspective that representations are merely "objects representing", towards a focus on the relationships and processes through which representations are produced, valued, viewed and exchanged.

Peirce and representation edit

 
Charles Sanders Peirce

Charles Sanders Peirce (1839–1914) was an innovative and accomplished logician, mathematician, and scientist, and founded philosophical pragmatism. Peirce's central ideas were focused on logic and representation.

Semiotics and logic edit

Peirce distinguished philosophical logic as logic per se from mathematics of logic. He regarded logic (per se) as part of philosophy, as a normative field following esthetics and ethics, as more basic than metaphysics,[9] and as the art of devising methods of research.[10] He argued that, more generally, as inference, "logic is rooted in the social principle", since inference depends on a standpoint that, in a sense, is unlimited.[11]

Peirce held that logic is formal semiotic,[12] the formal study of signs in the broadest sense, not only signs that are artificial, linguistic, or symbolic, but also signs that are semblances or are indexical such as reactions. He held that "all this universe is perfused with signs, if it is not composed exclusively of signs",[13] along with their representational and inferential relations, interpretable by mind or quasi-mind (whatever works like a mind despite perhaps not actually being one);[14] the focus here is on sign action in general, not psychology, linguistics, or social studies).

He argued that, since all thought takes time, "all thought is in signs"[15] and sign processes ("semiosis") and that the three irreducible elements of semiosis are (1) the sign (or representamen), (2) the (semiotic) object, the sign's subject matter, which the sign represents and which can be anything thinkable—quality, brute fact, or law—and even fictional (Prince Hamlet), and (3) the interpretant (or interpretant sign), which is the sign's meaning or ramification as formed into a kind of idea or effect that is a further sign, for example, a translation.[16] Even when a sign represents by a resemblance or factual connection independent of interpretation, the sign is a sign because it is at least potentially interpretable. A sign depends on its object in a way that enables (and, in a sense, determines) interpretation, forming an interpretant which, in turn, depends on the sign and on the object as the sign depends on the object and is thus a further sign, enabling and determining still further interpretation, further interpretants. That essentially triadic process is logically structured to perpetuate itself and is what defines sign, object, and interpretant.

An object either (1) is immediate to a sign, and that is the object as represented in the sign, or (2) is a dynamic object, which is the object as it really is, on which the immediate object is founded. Usually, an object in question, such as Hamlet or the planet Neptune, is a special or partial object. A sign's total object is the object's universe of discourse, the totality of things in that world to which one attributes the object. An interpretant is either (1) immediate to a sign, for example a word's usual meaning, a kind of interpretive quality or possibility present in the sign, or (2) dynamic, an actual interpretant, for example a state of agitation, or (3) final or normal, a question's true settlement, which would be reached if thought or inquiry were pushed far enough, a kind of norm or ideal end with which any actual interpretant may, at most, coincide.

Peirce said that, in order to know to what a sign refers, the mind needs some sort of experience of the sign's object, experience outside, and collateral to, the given sign or sign system. In that context he spoke of collateral experience, collateral observation, collateral acquaintance, all in much the same terms.[17] For example, art work can exploit both the richness and the limits of the audience's experience; a novelist, in disguising a roman à clef, counts on the typical reader's lack of personal experience with the actual individual people portrayed. Then the reader refers the signs and interpretants in a general way to an object or objects of the kind that is represented (intentionally or otherwise) by the novel. In all cases, the object (be it a quality or fact or law or even fictional) determines the sign to an interpretant through one's collateral experience with the object, collateral experience in which the object is newly found or from which it is recalled, even if it is experience with an object of imagination as called into being by the sign, as can happen not only in fiction but in theories and mathematics, all of which can involve mental experimentation with the object under specifiable rules and constraints. Through collateral experience even a sign that consists in a chance semblance of an absent object is determined by that object.

Peirce held that logic has three main parts:

  1. Speculative grammar,[18] on meaningfulness, conditions for meaning. Study of significatory elements and combinations.
  2. Logical critic,[19] on validity, conditions for true representation. Critique of arguments in their various distinct modes.
  3. Speculative rhetoric, or methodeutic,[20] on conditions for determining interpretations. Methodology of inquiry in its mutually interacting modes.

1. Speculative Grammar. By this, Peirce means discovering relations among questions of how signs can be meaningful and of what kinds of signs there are, how they combine, and how some embody or incorporate others. Within this broad area, Peirce developed three interlocked universal trichotomies of signs, depending respectively on (1) the sign itself, (2) how the sign stands for its object, and (3) how the sign stands for its object to its interpretant. Each trichotomy is divided according to the phenomenological category involved: Firstness (quality of feeling, essentially monadic), secondness (reaction or resistance, essentially dyadic), or thirdness (representation or mediation, essentially triadic).[21]

  1. Qualisigns, sinsigns, and legisigns. Every sign is either (qualisign) a quality or possibility, or (sinsign) an actual individual thing, fact, event, state, etc., or (legisign) a norm, habit, rule, law.
  2. Icons, indices, and symbols. Every sign refers either (icon) through similarity to its object, or (index) through factual connection to its object, or (symbol) through interpretive habit or norm of reference to its object.
  3. Rhemes, dicisigns, and arguments. Every sign is interpreted either as (rheme) term-like, standing for its object in respect of quality, or as (dicisign) proposition-like, standing for its object in respect of fact, or as (argument) argumentative, standing for its object in respect of habit or law. This is the trichotomy of all signs as building blocks of inference.
Lines of joint classification of signs.
Every sign is:[22]
1. 2. 3.
I. Qualisign or Sinsign or Legisign
and  
II. Icon or Index or Symbol
and  
III. Rheme or Dicisign or Argument

Some (not all) sign classes from different trichotomies intersect each other. For example, a qualisign is always an icon, and is never an index or a symbol. He held that there were only ten classes of signs logically definable through those three universal trichotomies.[23] He thought that there were further such universal trichotomies as well. Also, some signs need other signs in order to be embodied. For example, a legisign (also called a type), such as the word "the," needs to be embodied in a sinsign (also called a token), for example an individual instance of the word "the", in order to be expressed. Another form of combination is attachment or incorporation: an index may be attached to, or incorporated by, an icon or a symbol.

Peirce called an icon apart from a label, legend, or other index attached to it, a "hypoicon", and divided the hypoicon into three classes: (a) the image, which depends on a simple quality; (b) the diagram, whose internal relations, mainly dyadic or so taken, represent by analogy the relations in something; and (c) the metaphor, which represents the representative character of a sign by representing a parallelism in something else.[24] A diagram can be geometric, or can consist in an array of algebraic expressions, or even in the common form "All __ is ___" which is subjectable, like any diagram, to logical or mathematical transformations.

2. Logical critic or Logic Proper. That is how Peirce refers to logic in the everyday sense. Its main objective, for Peirce, is to classify arguments and determine the validity and force of each kind.[19] He sees three main modes: abductive inference (guessing, inference to a hypothetical explanation); deduction; and induction. A work of art may embody an inference process and be an argument without being an explicit argumentation. That is the difference, for example, between most of War and Peace and its final section.

3. Speculative rhetoric or methodeutic. For Peirce this is the theory of effective use of signs in investigations, expositions, and applications of truth. Here Peirce coincides with Morris's notion of pragmatics, in his interpretation of this term. He also called it "methodeutic", in that it is the analysis of the methods used in inquiry.[20]

Using signs and objects edit

Peirce concluded that there are three ways in which signs represent objects. They underlie his most widely known trichotomy of signs:

  • Icon
  • Index
  • Symbol[25]
Icon

This term refers to signs that represent by resemblance, such as portraits and some paintings though they can also be natural or mathematical. Iconicity is independent of actual connection, even if it occurs because of actual connection. An icon is or embodies a possibility, insofar as its object need not actually exist. A photograph is regarded as an icon because of its resemblance to its object, but is regarded as an index (with icon attached) because of its actual connection to its object. Likewise, with a portrait painted from life. An icon's resemblance is objective and independent of interpretation, but is relative to some mode of apprehension such as sight. An icon need not be sensory; anything can serve as an icon, for example a streamlined argument (itself a complex symbol) is often used as an icon for an argument (another symbol) bristling with particulars.

Index

Peirce explains that an index is a sign that compels attention through a connection of fact, often through cause and effect. For example, if we see smoke we conclude that it is the effect of a cause – fire. It is an index if the connection is factual regardless of resemblance or interpretation. Peirce usually considered personal names and demonstratives such as the word "this" to be indices, for although as words they depend on interpretation, they are indices in depending on the requisite factual relation to their individual objects. A personal name has an actual historical connection, often recorded on a birth certificate, to its named object; the word "this" is like the pointing of a finger.

Symbol

Peirce treats symbols as habits or norms of reference and meaning. Symbols can be natural, cultural, or abstract and logical. They depend as signs on how they will be interpreted, and lack or have lost dependence on resemblance and actual, indexical connection to their represented objects, though the symbol's individual embodiment is an index to your experience of its represented object. Symbols are instantiated by specialized indexical sinsigns. A proposition, considered apart from its expression in a particular language, is already a symbol, but many symbols draw from what is socially accepted and culturally agreed upon. Conventional symbols such as "horse" and caballo, which prescribe qualities of sound or appearance for their instances (for example, individual instances of the word "horse" on the page) are based on what amounts to arbitrary stipulation.[5] Such a symbol uses what is already known and accepted within our society to give meaning. This can be both in spoken and written language.

For example, we can call a large metal object with four wheels, four doors, an engine and seats a "car" because such a term is agreed upon within our culture and it allows us to communicate. In much the same way, as a society with a common set of understandings regarding language and signs, we can also write the word "car" and in the context of Australia and other English speaking nations, know what it symbolises and is trying to represent.[26]

Saussure and representation edit

 
Ferdinand de Saussure

Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure (1857–1913) played a major role in the development of semiotics with his argument that language is a system of signs that needs to be understood in order to fully understand the process of linguistics.[27] The study of semiotics examines the signs and types of representation that humans use to express feelings, ideas, thoughts and ideologies.[28] Although semiotics is often used in the form of textual analysis it also involves the study of representation and the processes involved with representation.

The process of representation is characterised by using signs that we recall mentally or phonetically to comprehend the world.[29] Saussure says before a human can use the word "tree" she or he has to envision the mental concept of a tree.

Two things are fundamental to the study of signs:[30]

  1. The signified: a mental concept, and
  2. The signifier: the verbal manifestation, the sequence of letters or sounds, the linguistic realisation.

The signifier is the word or sound; the signified is the representation.

Saussure points out that signs:

  • Are arbitrary: There is no link between the signifier and the signified
  • Are relational: We understand we take on meaning in relation to other words. Such as we understand "up" in relation to "down" or a dog in relation to other animals, such as a cat.
  • constitute our world – "You cannot get outside of language. We exist inside a system of signs".[30]

Saussure suggests that the meaning of a sign is arbitrary, in effect; there is no link between the signifier and the signified.[31] The signifier is the word or the sound of the word and the signified is the representation of the word or sound. For example, when referring to the term "sister" (signifier) a person from an English speaking country such as Australia, may associate that term as representing someone in their family who is female and born to the same parents (signified). An Aboriginal Australian may associate the term "sister" to represent a close friend that they have a bond with. This means that the representation of a signifier depends completely upon a person's cultural, linguistic and social background.

Saussure argues that if words or sounds were simply labels for existing things in the world, translation from one language or culture to another would be easy, it is the fact that this can be extremely difficult that suggests that words trigger a representation of an object or thought depending on the person that is representing the signifier.[32] The signified triggered from the representation of a signifier in one particular language do not necessarily represent the same signified in another language. Even within one particular language many words refer to the same thing but represent different people's interpretations of it. A person may refer to a particular place as their "work" whereas someone else represents the same signifier as their "favorite restaurant". This can also be subject to historical changes in both the signifier and the way objects are signified.

Saussure claims that an imperative function of all written languages and alphabetic systems is to "represent" spoken language.[33] Most languages do not have writing systems that represent the phonemic sounds they make. For example, in English the written letter "a" represents different phonetic sounds depending on which word it is written in. The letter "a" has a different sound in the word in each of the following words, "apple", "gate", "margarine" and "beat", therefore, how is a person unaware of the phonemic sounds, able to pronounce the word properly by simply looking at alphabetic spelling. The way the word is represented on paper is not always the way the word would be represented phonetically. This leads to common misrepresentations of the phonemic sounds of speech and suggests that the writing system does not properly represent the true nature of the pronunciation of words.

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c d e f g h Mitchell, W. 1995, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary Study, 2nd edn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago
  2. ^ a b O'Shaughnessy, M & Stadler J, Media and society: an introduction, 3rd edn, Oxford University Press, South Melbourne, 2005
  3. ^ Childers J (ed.), Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism, Columbia University Press, New York, 1995
  4. ^ a b <Vukcevich, M 2002, "Representation", The University of Chicago, viewed 7 April 2006
  5. ^ a b c d e Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary Study, University of Chicago Press, Chicago 1990
  6. ^ a b c Hall, S (ed.), Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice, Open University Press, London, 1997. ISBN 978-0761954323
  7. ^ a b Dryer 1993, cited in O’Shaughnessy & Stadler 2005
  8. ^ Mitchell, W, Picture Theory, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1994
  9. ^ On his classifications, see Peirce, C.S. (1903), CP 1.180–202 Eprint 2011-11-05 at the Wayback Machine and (1906) "The Basis of Pragmaticism" in The Essential Peirce 2:372–3. For the relevant quotes, see "Philosophy" and "Logic" at Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Bergman and Paavola, editors, U. of Helsinki.
  10. ^ Peirce, C.S., 1882, "Introductory Lecture on the Study of Logic" delivered September 1882, Johns Hopkins University Circulars, vol. 2, no. 19, pp. 11–12, November 1892, Google Book Search Eprint. Reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v. 7, paragraphs 59–76, The Essential Peirce 1:214–214; Writings of Charles S. Peirce 4:378–382.
  11. ^ Peirce, C.S. (1878) "The Doctrine of Chances", Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, pp. 604–615, 1878, reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 2, paragraphs 645–668, Writings of Charles S. Peirce 3:276–290, and The Essential Peirce 1:142–154. "...death makes the number of our risks, the number of our inferences, finite, and so makes their mean result uncertain. The very idea of probability and of reasoning rests on the assumption that this number is indefinitely great. .... ...logicality inexorably requires that our interests shall not be limited. .... Logic is rooted in the social principle."
  12. ^ Peirce, C. S. (written 1902), "MS L75: Logic, Regarded As Semeiotic (The Carnegie application of 1902): Version 1: An Integrated Reconstruction", Joseph Ransdell, ed., Arisbe, see Memoir 12.
  13. ^ Peirce, C.S., The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 5, paragraph 448 footnote, from "The Basis of Pragmaticism" in 1906.
  14. ^ See "Quasi-Mind" at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, eds., University of Helsinki.
  15. ^ Peirce, C.S. (1868), "Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man" (Arisbe Eprint), Journal of Speculative Philosophy vol. 2, pp. 103–114. Reprinted (Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 5, paragraphs 213–263, the quote is from paragraph 253).
  16. ^ For Peirce's definitions of semiosis, sign, representamen, object, interpretant, see the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  17. ^ Ten quotes on collateral observation from Peirce provided by Professor Joseph Ransdell can be viewed here. Also see pp. 404–409 in "Pragmatism" by Peirce in The Essential Peirce v. 2.
  18. ^ See "Grammar: Speculative" in Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  19. ^ a b See "Critic" in Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  20. ^ a b See "Methodeutic" in Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  21. ^ "Categories, Cenopythagorean Categories", Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms, Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola, editors, University of Helsinki.
  22. ^ Peirce (1903 MS), "Nomenclature and Divisions of Triadic Relations, as Far as They Are Determined", under other titles in Collected Papers (CP) v. 2, paragraphs 233–272, and reprinted under the original title in Essential Peirce (EP) v. 2, pp. 289–299. Also see image of MS 339 (August 7, 1904) supplied to peirce-l by Bernard Morand of the Institut Universitaire de Technologie (France), Département Informatique.
  23. ^ See Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, v. 2, paragraphs 254–263, reprinted in Philosophical Writings of Peirce pp. 115–118, and in The Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 294–296.
  24. ^ On image, diagram, and metaphor, see "Hypoicon" in the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms.
  25. ^ For Peirce's definitions of icon, index, symbol, and related terms, see the Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms
  26. ^ Dupriez, B, A Dictionary of Literary Devices, University of Toronto Press, Canada, 1991.
  27. ^ Culler, J 1976, Saussure, Fontana Modern Masters, Britain, 1976.
  28. ^ Ryder, M, Semiotics: Language and Culture, 2004 viewed 6 April 2006 see link below
  29. ^ Klarer, M, An Introduction to Literary Studies, Routledge, London, 1998.
  30. ^ a b Barry, P, Beginning Theory: an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory, Manchester University Press, Great Britain, 2002.
  31. ^ Holdcroft 1991 no details
  32. ^ Chandler, D, Semiotics for Beginners: Modality and representation, viewed 8 April 2006
  33. ^ Arnason, D, Reference material, 2006, viewed 12 April 2006

See also edit

References edit

  • Arnason, D, (via the Wayback Machine)
  • Baldick, C, "New historicism", in The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Literary Terms, 1996, viewed 8 April 2006 [1]
  • Barry, P, Beginning Theory: an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory, Manchester University Press, Great Britain, 2002.
  • Burch, R 2005, "Charles Sanders Peirce", in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, viewed 24 April 2006 [2].
  • Chandler, D, Semiotics for Beginners: Modality and Representation, 2001, viewed 8 April 2006 [3].
  • Childers J. (ed.), Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism, Columbia University Press, New York, 1995.
  • Concise Routledge, Encyclopaedia of Philosophy, Routledge, London, 1999.
  • Culler, J., Saussure, Fontana Modern Masters, Britain, 1976.
  • Dupriez, B, A Dictionary of Literary Devices, University of Toronto Press, Canada 1991.
  • Fuery, P & Mansfield N, Cultural Studies and Critical Theory, Oxford University Press, Australia, 2005. (ISBN 978-0-19-551294-6)
  • Hall, S (ed.), Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice, Open University Press, London, 1997.
  • Holder, D, Saussure – Signs, System, and Arbitrariness, Cambridge, Australia, 1991.
  • Lentricchia, F. & McLaughlin,T (eds.), Critical Terms for Literary Study, University of Chicago Press, London, 1990.
  • Klarer, M, An Introduction to Literary Studies, Routledge, London, 1998.
  • Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary Study, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1990.
  • Mitchell, W, "Representation", in F Lentricchia & T McLaughlin (eds), Critical Terms for Literary Study, 2nd edn, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1995.
  • Mitchell, W, Picture Theory, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1994.
  • Moon, B, Literary terms: a Practical Glossary, 2nd edn, Chalkface Press, Cottesloe, 2001.
  • Murfin, R & Ray, S.M, The Bedford Glossary of Critical and Literary Terms, Bedford Books, Boston, 1997.
  • O'Shaughnessy, M & Stadler J, Media and Society: an Introduction, 3rd edn, Oxford University Press, South Melbourne, 2005. (ISBN 978-0-19-551402-5)
  • Prendergast, C, "Circulating Representations: New Historicism and the Poetics of Culture", Substance: The Review of Theory and Literary Criticism, no. 28, issue 1, pp. 90–105, 1999, (online Humanities International Complete)
  • Ryder, M, Semiotics: Language and Culture, 2004, viewed 6 April 2006 [4].
  • Shook, J, The Pragmatism Cybrary: Charles Morris, in The Pragmatism Cybrary, 2005, viewed 24 April 2006 [5].
  • Vukcevich, M, Representation, The University of Chicago, 2002, viewed 7 April 2006.

External links edit

  • University of Chicago (archived 14 March 2004)
  • Analysis of Art (Representation) – Encyclopedia Britannica

representation, arts, representation, signs, that, stand, take, place, something, else, through, representation, that, people, organize, world, reality, through, naming, elements, signs, arranged, order, form, semantic, constructions, express, relations, bust,. Representation is the use of signs that stand in for and take the place of something else 1 It is through representation that people organize the world and reality through the act of naming its elements 1 Signs are arranged in order to form semantic constructions and express relations 1 Bust of Aristotle Greek philosopherFor many philosophers both ancient and modern man is regarded as the representational animal or animal symbolicum the creature whose distinct character is the creation and the manipulation of signs things that stand for or take the place of something else 1 Representation has been associated with aesthetics art and semiotics signs Mitchell says representation is an extremely elastic notion which extends all the way from a stone representing a man to a novel representing the day in the life of several Dubliners 1 The term representation carries a range of meanings and interpretations In literary theory representation is commonly defined in three ways To look like or resemble To stand in for something or someone To present a second time to re present 2 The reflection on representation began with early literary theory in the ideas of Plato and Aristotle and has evolved into a significant component of language Saussurian and communication studies 2 Contents 1 Defining representation 2 History 3 Contemporary ideas about representation 4 Peirce and representation 4 1 Semiotics and logic 4 2 Using signs and objects 5 Saussure and representation 6 Notes 7 See also 8 References 9 External linksDefining representation edit nbsp Reproduction of the Mona LisaTo represent is to bring to mind by description also to symbolize to be the embodiment of from representer 12c from L repraesentare from re intensive prefix praesentare to present lit to place before original research A representation is a type of recording in which the sensory information about a physical object is described in a medium The degree to which an artistic representation resembles the object it represents is a function of resolution and does not bear on the denotation of the word For example both the Mona Lisa and a child s crayon drawing of Lisa del Giocondo would be considered representational and any preference for one over the other would need to be understood as a matter of aesthetics citation needed History edit nbsp Greek theatrical masks depicted in Hadrians Villa mosaicSince ancient times representation has played a central role in understanding literature aesthetics and semiotics Plato and Aristotle are key figures in early literary theory who considered literature as simply one form of representation 3 Aristotle for instance considered each mode of representation verbal visual or musical as being natural to human beings 4 Therefore what distinguishes humans from other animals is their ability to create and manipulate signs 5 Aristotle deemed mimesis as natural to man therefore considered representations as necessary for people s learning and being in the world 4 Plato in contrast looked upon representation with more caution He recognised that literature is a representation of life yet also believed that representations intervene between the viewer and the real This creates worlds of illusion leading one away from the real things 6 Plato thus believed that representation needs to be controlled and monitored due to the possible dangers of fostering antisocial emotions or the imitation of evil 5 Aristotle went on to say it was a definitively human activity 1 From childhood man has an instinct for representation and in this respect man differs from the other animals that he is far more imitative and learns his first lessons though imitating things 1 Aristotle discusses representation in three ways The object The symbol being represented Manner The way the symbol is represented Means The material that is used to represent it The means of literary representation is language An important part of representation is the relationship between what the material and what it represents The questions arising from this are A stone may represent a man but how And by what and by what agreement does this understanding of the representation occur 1 One apprehends reality only through representations of reality through texts discourses images there is no such thing as direct or unmediated access to reality But because one can see reality only through representation it does not follow that one does not see reality at all Reality is always more extensive and complicated than any system of representation can comprehend and we always sense that this is so representation never gets reality which is why human history has produced so many and changing ways of trying to get it 7 Consequently throughout the history of human culture people have become dissatisfied with language s ability to express reality and as a result have developed new modes of representation It is necessary to construct new ways of seeing reality as people only know reality through representation 7 From this arises the contrasting and alternate theories and representational modes of abstraction realism and modernism to name a few Contemporary ideas about representation editIt is from Plato s caution that in the modern era many are aware of political and ideological issues and the influences of representations It is impossible to divorce representations from culture and the society that produces them In the contemporary world there exist restrictions on subject matter limiting the kinds of representational signs allowed to be employed as well as boundaries that limit the audience or viewers of particular representations In motion picture rating systems M and R rated films are an example of such restrictions highlighting also society s attempt to restrict and modify representations to promote a certain set of ideologies and values Despite these restrictions representations still have the ability to take on a life of their own once in the public sphere and can not be given a definitive or concrete meaning as there will always be a gap between intention and realization original and copy 5 Consequently for each of the above definitions there exists a process of communication and message sending and receiving In such a system of communication and representations it is inevitable that potential problems may arise misunderstandings errors and falsehoods The accuracy of the representations can by no means be guaranteed as they operate in a system of signs that can never work in isolation from other signs or cultural factors For instance the interpretation and reading of representations function in the context of a body of rules for interpreting and within a society many of these codes or conventions are informally agreed upon and have been established over a number of years Such understandings however are not set in stone and may alter between times places peoples and contexts How though does this agreement or understanding of representation occur It has generally been agreed by semioticians that representational relationships can be categorised into three distinct headings icon symbol and index 5 For instance objects and people do not have a constant meaning but their meanings are fashioned by humans in the context of their culture as they have the ability to make things mean or signify something 6 Viewing representation in such a way focuses on understanding how language and systems of knowledge production work to create and circulate meanings Representation is simply the process in which such meanings are constructed 6 In much the same way as the post structuralists this approach to representation considers it as something larger than any one single representation A similar perspective is viewing representation as part of a larger field as Mitchell saying representation in memory in verbal descriptions in images not only mediates our knowledge of slavery and of many other things but obstructs fragments and negates that knowledge 8 and proposes a move away from the perspective that representations are merely objects representing towards a focus on the relationships and processes through which representations are produced valued viewed and exchanged Peirce and representation edit nbsp Charles Sanders PeirceCharles Sanders Peirce 1839 1914 was an innovative and accomplished logician mathematician and scientist and founded philosophical pragmatism Peirce s central ideas were focused on logic and representation Semiotics and logic edit Peirce distinguished philosophical logic as logic per se from mathematics of logic He regarded logic per se as part of philosophy as a normative field following esthetics and ethics as more basic than metaphysics 9 and as the art of devising methods of research 10 He argued that more generally as inference logic is rooted in the social principle since inference depends on a standpoint that in a sense is unlimited 11 Peirce held that logic is formal semiotic 12 the formal study of signs in the broadest sense not only signs that are artificial linguistic or symbolic but also signs that are semblances or are indexical such as reactions He held that all this universe is perfused with signs if it is not composed exclusively of signs 13 along with their representational and inferential relations interpretable by mind or quasi mind whatever works like a mind despite perhaps not actually being one 14 the focus here is on sign action in general not psychology linguistics or social studies He argued that since all thought takes time all thought is in signs 15 and sign processes semiosis and that the three irreducible elements of semiosis are 1 the sign or representamen 2 the semiotic object the sign s subject matter which the sign represents and which can be anything thinkable quality brute fact or law and even fictional Prince Hamlet and 3 the interpretant or interpretant sign which is the sign s meaning or ramification as formed into a kind of idea or effect that is a further sign for example a translation 16 Even when a sign represents by a resemblance or factual connection independent of interpretation the sign is a sign because it is at least potentially interpretable A sign depends on its object in a way that enables and in a sense determines interpretation forming an interpretant which in turn depends on the sign and on the object as the sign depends on the object and is thus a further sign enabling and determining still further interpretation further interpretants That essentially triadic process is logically structured to perpetuate itself and is what defines sign object and interpretant An object either 1 is immediate to a sign and that is the object as represented in the sign or 2 is a dynamic object which is the object as it really is on which the immediate object is founded Usually an object in question such as Hamlet or the planet Neptune is a special or partial object A sign s total object is the object s universe of discourse the totality of things in that world to which one attributes the object An interpretant is either 1 immediate to a sign for example a word s usual meaning a kind of interpretive quality or possibility present in the sign or 2 dynamic an actual interpretant for example a state of agitation or 3 final or normal a question s true settlement which would be reached if thought or inquiry were pushed far enough a kind of norm or ideal end with which any actual interpretant may at most coincide Peirce said that in order to know to what a sign refers the mind needs some sort of experience of the sign s object experience outside and collateral to the given sign or sign system In that context he spoke of collateral experience collateral observation collateral acquaintance all in much the same terms 17 For example art work can exploit both the richness and the limits of the audience s experience a novelist in disguising a roman a clef counts on the typical reader s lack of personal experience with the actual individual people portrayed Then the reader refers the signs and interpretants in a general way to an object or objects of the kind that is represented intentionally or otherwise by the novel In all cases the object be it a quality or fact or law or even fictional determines the sign to an interpretant through one s collateral experience with the object collateral experience in which the object is newly found or from which it is recalled even if it is experience with an object of imagination as called into being by the sign as can happen not only in fiction but in theories and mathematics all of which can involve mental experimentation with the object under specifiable rules and constraints Through collateral experience even a sign that consists in a chance semblance of an absent object is determined by that object Peirce held that logic has three main parts Speculative grammar 18 on meaningfulness conditions for meaning Study of significatory elements and combinations Logical critic 19 on validity conditions for true representation Critique of arguments in their various distinct modes Speculative rhetoric or methodeutic 20 on conditions for determining interpretations Methodology of inquiry in its mutually interacting modes 1 Speculative Grammar By this Peirce means discovering relations among questions of how signs can be meaningful and of what kinds of signs there are how they combine and how some embody or incorporate others Within this broad area Peirce developed three interlocked universal trichotomies of signs depending respectively on 1 the sign itself 2 how the sign stands for its object and 3 how the sign stands for its object to its interpretant Each trichotomy is divided according to the phenomenological category involved Firstness quality of feeling essentially monadic secondness reaction or resistance essentially dyadic or thirdness representation or mediation essentially triadic 21 Qualisigns sinsigns and legisigns Every sign is either qualisign a quality or possibility or sinsign an actual individual thing fact event state etc or legisign a norm habit rule law Icons indices and symbols Every sign refers either icon through similarity to its object or index through factual connection to its object or symbol through interpretive habit or norm of reference to its object Rhemes dicisigns and arguments Every sign is interpreted either as rheme term like standing for its object in respect of quality or as dicisign proposition like standing for its object in respect of fact or as argument argumentative standing for its object in respect of habit or law This is the trichotomy of all signs as building blocks of inference Lines of joint classification of signs Every sign is 22 1 2 3 I Qualisign or Sinsign or Legisignand nbsp II Icon or Index or Symboland nbsp III Rheme or Dicisign or ArgumentSome not all sign classes from different trichotomies intersect each other For example a qualisign is always an icon and is never an index or a symbol He held that there were only ten classes of signs logically definable through those three universal trichotomies 23 He thought that there were further such universal trichotomies as well Also some signs need other signs in order to be embodied For example a legisign also called a type such as the word the needs to be embodied in a sinsign also called a token for example an individual instance of the word the in order to be expressed Another form of combination is attachment or incorporation an index may be attached to or incorporated by an icon or a symbol Peirce called an icon apart from a label legend or other index attached to it a hypoicon and divided the hypoicon into three classes a the image which depends on a simple quality b the diagram whose internal relations mainly dyadic or so taken represent by analogy the relations in something and c the metaphor which represents the representative character of a sign by representing a parallelism in something else 24 A diagram can be geometric or can consist in an array of algebraic expressions or even in the common form All is which is subjectable like any diagram to logical or mathematical transformations 2 Logical critic or Logic Proper That is how Peirce refers to logic in the everyday sense Its main objective for Peirce is to classify arguments and determine the validity and force of each kind 19 He sees three main modes abductive inference guessing inference to a hypothetical explanation deduction and induction A work of art may embody an inference process and be an argument without being an explicit argumentation That is the difference for example between most of War and Peace and its final section 3 Speculative rhetoric or methodeutic For Peirce this is the theory of effective use of signs in investigations expositions and applications of truth Here Peirce coincides with Morris s notion of pragmatics in his interpretation of this term He also called it methodeutic in that it is the analysis of the methods used in inquiry 20 Using signs and objects edit Peirce concluded that there are three ways in which signs represent objects They underlie his most widely known trichotomy of signs Icon Index Symbol 25 IconThis term refers to signs that represent by resemblance such as portraits and some paintings though they can also be natural or mathematical Iconicity is independent of actual connection even if it occurs because of actual connection An icon is or embodies a possibility insofar as its object need not actually exist A photograph is regarded as an icon because of its resemblance to its object but is regarded as an index with icon attached because of its actual connection to its object Likewise with a portrait painted from life An icon s resemblance is objective and independent of interpretation but is relative to some mode of apprehension such as sight An icon need not be sensory anything can serve as an icon for example a streamlined argument itself a complex symbol is often used as an icon for an argument another symbol bristling with particulars IndexPeirce explains that an index is a sign that compels attention through a connection of fact often through cause and effect For example if we see smoke we conclude that it is the effect of a cause fire It is an index if the connection is factual regardless of resemblance or interpretation Peirce usually considered personal names and demonstratives such as the word this to be indices for although as words they depend on interpretation they are indices in depending on the requisite factual relation to their individual objects A personal name has an actual historical connection often recorded on a birth certificate to its named object the word this is like the pointing of a finger SymbolPeirce treats symbols as habits or norms of reference and meaning Symbols can be natural cultural or abstract and logical They depend as signs on how they will be interpreted and lack or have lost dependence on resemblance and actual indexical connection to their represented objects though the symbol s individual embodiment is an index to your experience of its represented object Symbols are instantiated by specialized indexical sinsigns A proposition considered apart from its expression in a particular language is already a symbol but many symbols draw from what is socially accepted and culturally agreed upon Conventional symbols such as horse and caballo which prescribe qualities of sound or appearance for their instances for example individual instances of the word horse on the page are based on what amounts to arbitrary stipulation 5 Such a symbol uses what is already known and accepted within our society to give meaning This can be both in spoken and written language For example we can call a large metal object with four wheels four doors an engine and seats a car because such a term is agreed upon within our culture and it allows us to communicate In much the same way as a society with a common set of understandings regarding language and signs we can also write the word car and in the context of Australia and other English speaking nations know what it symbolises and is trying to represent 26 Saussure and representation edit nbsp Ferdinand de SaussureSwiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure 1857 1913 played a major role in the development of semiotics with his argument that language is a system of signs that needs to be understood in order to fully understand the process of linguistics 27 The study of semiotics examines the signs and types of representation that humans use to express feelings ideas thoughts and ideologies 28 Although semiotics is often used in the form of textual analysis it also involves the study of representation and the processes involved with representation The process of representation is characterised by using signs that we recall mentally or phonetically to comprehend the world 29 Saussure says before a human can use the word tree she or he has to envision the mental concept of a tree Two things are fundamental to the study of signs 30 The signified a mental concept and The signifier the verbal manifestation the sequence of letters or sounds the linguistic realisation The signifier is the word or sound the signified is the representation Saussure points out that signs Are arbitrary There is no link between the signifier and the signified Are relational We understand we take on meaning in relation to other words Such as we understand up in relation to down or a dog in relation to other animals such as a cat constitute our world You cannot get outside of language We exist inside a system of signs 30 Saussure suggests that the meaning of a sign is arbitrary in effect there is no link between the signifier and the signified 31 The signifier is the word or the sound of the word and the signified is the representation of the word or sound For example when referring to the term sister signifier a person from an English speaking country such as Australia may associate that term as representing someone in their family who is female and born to the same parents signified An Aboriginal Australian may associate the term sister to represent a close friend that they have a bond with This means that the representation of a signifier depends completely upon a person s cultural linguistic and social background Saussure argues that if words or sounds were simply labels for existing things in the world translation from one language or culture to another would be easy it is the fact that this can be extremely difficult that suggests that words trigger a representation of an object or thought depending on the person that is representing the signifier 32 The signified triggered from the representation of a signifier in one particular language do not necessarily represent the same signified in another language Even within one particular language many words refer to the same thing but represent different people s interpretations of it A person may refer to a particular place as their work whereas someone else represents the same signifier as their favorite restaurant This can also be subject to historical changes in both the signifier and the way objects are signified Saussure claims that an imperative function of all written languages and alphabetic systems is to represent spoken language 33 Most languages do not have writing systems that represent the phonemic sounds they make For example in English the written letter a represents different phonetic sounds depending on which word it is written in The letter a has a different sound in the word in each of the following words apple gate margarine and beat therefore how is a person unaware of the phonemic sounds able to pronounce the word properly by simply looking at alphabetic spelling The way the word is represented on paper is not always the way the word would be represented phonetically This leads to common misrepresentations of the phonemic sounds of speech and suggests that the writing system does not properly represent the true nature of the pronunciation of words Notes edit a b c d e f g h Mitchell W 1995 Representation in F Lentricchia amp T McLaughlin eds Critical Terms for Literary Study 2nd edn University of Chicago Press Chicago a b O Shaughnessy M amp Stadler J Media and society an introduction 3rd edn Oxford University Press South Melbourne 2005 Childers J ed Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism Columbia University Press New York 1995 a b lt Vukcevich M 2002 Representation The University of Chicago viewed 7 April 2006 a b c d e Mitchell W Representation in F Lentricchia amp T McLaughlin eds Critical Terms for Literary Study University of Chicago Press Chicago 1990 a b c Hall S ed Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice Open University Press London 1997 ISBN 978 0761954323 a b Dryer 1993 cited in O Shaughnessy amp Stadler 2005 Mitchell W Picture Theory University of Chicago Press Chicago 1994 On his classifications see Peirce C S 1903 CP 1 180 202 Eprint Archived 2011 11 05 at the Wayback Machine and 1906 The Basis of Pragmaticism in The Essential Peirce 2 372 3 For the relevant quotes see Philosophy and Logic at Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Bergman and Paavola editors U of Helsinki Peirce C S 1882 Introductory Lecture on the Study of Logic delivered September 1882 Johns Hopkins University Circulars vol 2 no 19 pp 11 12 November 1892 Google Book Search Eprint Reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 7 paragraphs 59 76 The Essential Peirce 1 214 214 Writings of Charles S Peirce 4 378 382 Peirce C S 1878 The Doctrine of Chances Popular Science Monthly v 12 pp 604 615 1878 reprinted in Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 2 paragraphs 645 668 Writings of Charles S Peirce 3 276 290 and The Essential Peirce 1 142 154 death makes the number of our risks the number of our inferences finite and so makes their mean result uncertain The very idea of probability and of reasoning rests on the assumption that this number is indefinitely great logicality inexorably requires that our interests shall not be limited Logic is rooted in the social principle Peirce C S written 1902 MS L75 Logic Regarded As Semeiotic The Carnegie application of 1902 Version 1 An Integrated Reconstruction Joseph Ransdell ed Arisbe see Memoir 12 Peirce C S The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 5 paragraph 448 footnote from The Basis of Pragmaticism in 1906 See Quasi Mind at the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola eds University of Helsinki Peirce C S 1868 Questions Concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man Arisbe Eprint Journal of Speculative Philosophy vol 2 pp 103 114 Reprinted Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 5 paragraphs 213 263 the quote is from paragraph 253 For Peirce s definitions of semiosis sign representamen object interpretant see the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Ten quotes on collateral observation from Peirce provided by Professor Joseph Ransdell can be viewed here Also see pp 404 409 in Pragmatism by Peirce in The Essential Peirce v 2 See Grammar Speculative in Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms a b See Critic in Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms a b See Methodeutic in Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Categories Cenopythagorean Categories Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Mats Bergman and Sami Paavola editors University of Helsinki Peirce 1903 MS Nomenclature and Divisions of Triadic Relations as Far as They Are Determined under other titles in Collected Papers CP v 2 paragraphs 233 272 and reprinted under the original title in Essential Peirce EP v 2 pp 289 299 Also see image of MS 339 August 7 1904 supplied to peirce l by Bernard Morand of the Institut Universitaire de Technologie France Departement Informatique See Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce v 2 paragraphs 254 263 reprinted in Philosophical Writings of Peirce pp 115 118 and in The Essential Peirce v 2 pp 294 296 On image diagram and metaphor see Hypoicon in the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms For Peirce s definitions of icon index symbol and related terms see the Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms Dupriez B A Dictionary of Literary Devices University of Toronto Press Canada 1991 Culler J 1976 Saussure Fontana Modern Masters Britain 1976 Ryder M Semiotics Language and Culture 2004 viewed 6 April 2006 see link below Klarer M An Introduction to Literary Studies Routledge London 1998 a b Barry P Beginning Theory an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory Manchester University Press Great Britain 2002 Holdcroft 1991 no details Chandler D Semiotics for Beginners Modality and representation viewed 8 April 2006 Arnason D Reference material 2006 viewed 12 April 2006See also editAspectism Cultural artifact Culture theory Figurative art Media influence Mimesis Painting Program music Realism arts Representative realism Social representation Symbol Western painting Work of art Conceptual artReferences editArnason D Semiotics the system of signs via the Wayback Machine Baldick C New historicism in The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Literary Terms 1996 viewed 8 April 2006 1 Barry P Beginning Theory an Introduction to Literary and Cultural Theory Manchester University Press Great Britain 2002 Burch R 2005 Charles Sanders Peirce in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy viewed 24 April 2006 2 Chandler D Semiotics for Beginners Modality and Representation 2001 viewed 8 April 2006 3 Childers J ed Columbia Dictionary of Modern Literary and Cultural Criticism Columbia University Press New York 1995 Concise Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy Routledge London 1999 Culler J Saussure Fontana Modern Masters Britain 1976 Dupriez B A Dictionary of Literary Devices University of Toronto Press Canada 1991 Fuery P amp Mansfield N Cultural Studies and Critical Theory Oxford University Press Australia 2005 ISBN 978 0 19 551294 6 Hall S ed Cultural Representations and Signifying Practice Open University Press London 1997 Holder D Saussure Signs System and Arbitrariness Cambridge Australia 1991 Lentricchia F amp McLaughlin T eds Critical Terms for Literary Study University of Chicago Press London 1990 Klarer M An Introduction to Literary Studies Routledge London 1998 Mitchell W Representation in F Lentricchia amp T McLaughlin eds Critical Terms for Literary Study University of Chicago Press Chicago 1990 Mitchell W Representation in F Lentricchia amp T McLaughlin eds Critical Terms for Literary Study 2nd edn University of Chicago Press Chicago 1995 Mitchell W Picture Theory University of Chicago Press Chicago 1994 Moon B Literary terms a Practical Glossary 2nd edn Chalkface Press Cottesloe 2001 Murfin R amp Ray S M The Bedford Glossary of Critical and Literary Terms Bedford Books Boston 1997 O Shaughnessy M amp Stadler J Media and Society an Introduction 3rd edn Oxford University Press South Melbourne 2005 ISBN 978 0 19 551402 5 Prendergast C Circulating Representations New Historicism and the Poetics of Culture Substance The Review of Theory and Literary Criticism no 28 issue 1 pp 90 105 1999 online Humanities International Complete Ryder M Semiotics Language and Culture 2004 viewed 6 April 2006 4 Shook J The Pragmatism Cybrary Charles Morris in The Pragmatism Cybrary 2005 viewed 24 April 2006 5 Vukcevich M Representation The University of Chicago 2002 viewed 7 April 2006 External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Artistic representation Representation University of Chicago archived 14 March 2004 Analysis of Art Representation Encyclopedia Britannica Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Representation arts amp oldid 1199064158, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.