fbpx
Wikipedia

Impredicativity

In mathematics, logic and philosophy of mathematics, something that is impredicative is a self-referencing definition. Roughly speaking, a definition is impredicative if it invokes (mentions or quantifies over) the set being defined, or (more commonly) another set that contains the thing being defined. There is no generally accepted precise definition of what it means to be predicative or impredicative. Authors have given different but related definitions.

The opposite of impredicativity is predicativity, which essentially entails building stratified (or ramified) theories where quantification over lower[definition needed] levels[definition needed] results in variables of some new type, distinguished from the lower[definition needed] types that the variable ranges over. A prototypical example is intuitionistic type theory, which retains ramification so as to discard impredicativity.

Russell's paradox is a famous example of an impredicative construction—namely the set of all sets that do not contain themselves. The paradox is that such a set cannot exist: If it would exist, the question could be asked whether it contains itself or not — if it does then by definition it should not, and if it does not then by definition it should.

The greatest lower bound of a set X, glb(X), also has an impredicative definition: y = glb(X) if and only if for all elements x of X, y is less than or equal to x, and any z less than or equal to all elements of X is less than or equal to y. This definition quantifies over the set (potentially infinite, depending on the order in question) whose members are the lower bounds of X, one of which being the glb itself. Hence predicativism would reject this definition.[1]

History

Norms (containing one variable) which do not define classes I propose to call non-predicative; those which do define classes I shall call predicative.

(Russell 1907, p.34) (Russell used "norm" to mean a proposition: roughly something that can take the values "true" or "false".)

The terms "predicative" and "impredicative" were introduced by Russell (1907), though the meaning has changed a little since then.

Solomon Feferman provides a historical review of predicativity, connecting it to current outstanding research problems.[2]

The vicious circle principle was suggested by Henri Poincaré (1905-6, 1908)[3] and Bertrand Russell in the wake of the paradoxes as a requirement on legitimate set specifications. Sets that do not meet the requirement are called impredicative.

The first modern paradox appeared with Cesare Burali-Forti's 1897 A question on transfinite numbers[4] and would become known as the Burali-Forti paradox. Cantor had apparently discovered the same paradox in his (Cantor's) "naive" set theory and this become known as Cantor's paradox. Russell's awareness of the problem originated in June 1901[5] with his reading of Frege's treatise of mathematical logic, his 1879 Begriffsschrift; the offending sentence in Frege is the following:

On the other hand, it may also be that the argument is determinate and the function indeterminate.[6]

In other words, given f(a) the function f is the variable and a is the invariant part. So why not substitute the value f(a) for f itself? Russell promptly wrote Frege a letter pointing out that:

You state ... that a function too, can act as the indeterminate element. This I formerly believed, but now this view seems doubtful to me because of the following contradiction. Let w be the predicate: to be a predicate that cannot be predicated of itself. Can w be predicated of itself? From each answer its opposite follows. Therefore we must conclude that w is not a predicate. Likewise there is no class (as a totality) of those classes which, each taken as a totality, do not belong to themselves. From this I conclude that under certain circumstances a definable collection does not form a totality.[7]

Frege promptly wrote back to Russell acknowledging the problem:

Your discovery of the contradiction caused me the greatest surprise and, I would almost say, consternation, since it has shaken the basis on which I intended to build arithmetic.[8]

While the problem had adverse personal consequences for both men (both had works at the printers that had to be emended), van Heijenoort observes that "The paradox shook the logicians' world, and the rumbles are still felt today. ... Russell's paradox, which uses the bare notions of set and element, falls squarely in the field of logic. The paradox was first published by Russell in The principles of mathematics (1903) and is discussed there in great detail ...".[9] Russell, after six years of false starts, would eventually answer the matter with his 1908 theory of types by "propounding his axiom of reducibility. It says that any function is coextensive with what he calls a predicative function: a function in which the types of apparent variables run no higher than the types of the arguments".[10] But this "axiom" was met with resistance from all quarters.

The rejection of impredicatively defined mathematical objects (while accepting the natural numbers as classically understood) leads to the position in the philosophy of mathematics known as predicativism, advocated by Henri Poincaré and Hermann Weyl in his Das Kontinuum. Poincaré and Weyl argued that impredicative definitions are problematic only when one or more underlying sets are infinite.

Ernst Zermelo in his 1908 "A new proof of the possibility of a well-ordering"[full citation needed] presents an entire section "b. Objection concerning nonpredicative definition" where he argued against "Poincaré (1906, p. 307) [who states that] a definition is 'predicative' and logically admissible only if it excludes all objects that are dependent upon the notion defined, that is, that can in any way be determined by it".[11] He gives two examples of impredicative definitions – (i) the notion of Dedekind chains and (ii) "in analysis wherever the maximum or minimum of a previously defined "completed" set of numbers Z is used for further inferences. This happens, for example, in the well-known Cauchy proof...".[12] He ends his section with the following observation: "A definition may very well rely upon notions that are equivalent to the one being defined; indeed, in every definition definiens and definiendum are equivalent notions, and the strict observance of Poincaré's demand would make every definition, hence all of science, impossible".[13]

Zermelo's example of minimum and maximum of a previously defined "completed" set of numbers reappears in Kleene 1952:42-42 where Kleene uses the example of least upper bound in his discussion of impredicative definitions; Kleene does not resolve this problem. In the next paragraphs he discusses Weyl's attempt in his 1918 Das Kontinuum (The Continuum) to eliminate impredicative definitions and his failure to retain the "theorem that an arbitrary non-empty set M of real numbers having an upper bound has a least upper bound (cf. also Weyl 1919)".[14]

Ramsey argued that "impredicative" definitions can be harmless: for instance, the definition of "tallest person in the room" is impredicative, since it depends on a set of things of which it is an element, namely the set of all persons in the room. Concerning mathematics, an example of an impredicative definition is the smallest number in a set, which is formally defined as: y = min(X) if and only if for all elements x of X, y is less than or equal to x, and y is in X.

Burgess (2005) discusses predicative and impredicative theories at some length, in the context of Frege's logic, Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic, and axiomatic set theory.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Kleene 1952:42–43
  2. ^ Solomon Feferman, "Predicativity" (2002)
  3. ^ dates derived from Kleene 1952:42
  4. ^ van Heijenoort's commentary before Burali-Forti's (1897) A question on transfinite numbers in van Heijenoort 1967:104; see also his commentary before Georg Cantor's (1899) Letter to Dedekind in van Heijenoort 1967:113
  5. ^ Commentary by van Heijenoort before Bertrand Russell's Lettern to Frege in van Heijenoort 1967:124
  6. ^ Gottlob Frege (1879) Begriffsschrift in van Heijenoort 1967:23
  7. ^ Bertrand Russell's 1902 Letter to Frege in van Heijenoort 1967:124-125
  8. ^ Gottlob Frege's (1902) Letter to Russell in van Hiejenoort 1967:127
  9. ^ Van Heijenoort's commentary before Bertrand Russell's (1902) Letter to Frege 1967:124
  10. ^ Willard V. Quine's commentary before Bertrand Russell's 1908 Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types
  11. ^ van Heijenoort 1967:190
  12. ^ van Heijenoort 1967:190–191
  13. ^ van Heijenoort 1967:191
  14. ^ Kleene 1952:43

References

  • "Predicative and Impredicative Definitions". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • PlanetMath article on predicativism
  • John Burgess, 2005. Fixing Frege. Princeton Univ. Press.
  • Solomon Feferman, 2005, "Predicativity" in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic. Oxford University Press: 590–624.
  • Russell, B. (1907), "On Some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types", Proc. London Math. Soc., s2–4 (1): 29–53, doi:10.1112/plms/s2-4.1.29
  • Stephen C. Kleene 1952 (1971 edition), Introduction to Metamathematics, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam NY, ISBN 0-7204-2103-9. In particular cf. his §11 The Paradoxes (pp. 36–40) and §12 First inferences from the paradoxes IMPREDICATIVE DEFINITION (p. 42). He states that his 6 or so (famous) examples of paradoxes (antinomies) are all examples of impredicative definition, and says that Poincaré (1905–6, 1908) and Russell (1906, 1910) "enunciated the cause of the paradoxes to lie in these impredicative definitions" (p. 42), however, "parts of mathematics we want to retain, particularly analysis, also contain impredicative definitions." (ibid). Weyl in his 1918 ("Das Kontinuum") attempted to derive as much of analysis as was possible without the use of impredicative definitions, "but not the theorem that an arbitrary non-empty set M of real numbers having an upper bound has a least upper bound (CF. also Weyl 1919)" (p. 43).
  • Hans Reichenbach 1947, Elements of Symbolic Logic, Dover Publications, Inc., NY, ISBN 0-486-24004-5. Cf. his §40. The antinomies and the theory of types (pp. 218 — wherein he demonstrates how to create antinomies, including the definition of impredicable itself ("Is the definition of "impredicable" impredicable?"). He claims to show methods for eliminating the "paradoxes of syntax" ("logical paradoxes") — by use of the theory of types — and "the paradoxes of semantics" — by the use of metalanguage (his "theory of levels of language"). He attributes the suggestion of this notion to Russell and more concretely to Ramsey.
  • Jean van Heijenoort 1967, third printing 1976, From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 (pbk.)

impredicativity, predicativism, redirects, here, other, school, philosophy, also, known, predicativism, ultrafinitism, mathematics, logic, philosophy, mathematics, something, that, impredicative, self, referencing, definition, roughly, speaking, definition, im. Predicativism redirects here For the other school of philosophy also known as predicativism see Ultrafinitism In mathematics logic and philosophy of mathematics something that is impredicative is a self referencing definition Roughly speaking a definition is impredicative if it invokes mentions or quantifies over the set being defined or more commonly another set that contains the thing being defined There is no generally accepted precise definition of what it means to be predicative or impredicative Authors have given different but related definitions The opposite of impredicativity is predicativity which essentially entails building stratified or ramified theories where quantification over lower definition needed levels definition needed results in variables of some new type distinguished from the lower definition needed types that the variable ranges over A prototypical example is intuitionistic type theory which retains ramification so as to discard impredicativity Russell s paradox is a famous example of an impredicative construction namely the set of all sets that do not contain themselves The paradox is that such a set cannot exist If it would exist the question could be asked whether it contains itself or not if it does then by definition it should not and if it does not then by definition it should The greatest lower bound of a set X glb X also has an impredicative definition y glb X if and only if for all elements x of X y is less than or equal to x and any z less than or equal to all elements of X is less than or equal to y This definition quantifies over the set potentially infinite depending on the order in question whose members are the lower bounds of X one of which being the glb itself Hence predicativism would reject this definition 1 Contents 1 History 2 See also 3 Notes 4 ReferencesHistory EditNorms containing one variable which do not define classes I propose to call non predicative those which do define classes I shall call predicative Russell 1907 p 34 Russell used norm to mean a proposition roughly something that can take the values true or false The terms predicative and impredicative were introduced by Russell 1907 though the meaning has changed a little since then Solomon Feferman provides a historical review of predicativity connecting it to current outstanding research problems 2 The vicious circle principle was suggested by Henri Poincare 1905 6 1908 3 and Bertrand Russell in the wake of the paradoxes as a requirement on legitimate set specifications Sets that do not meet the requirement are called impredicative The first modern paradox appeared with Cesare Burali Forti s 1897 A question on transfinite numbers 4 and would become known as the Burali Forti paradox Cantor had apparently discovered the same paradox in his Cantor s naive set theory and this become known as Cantor s paradox Russell s awareness of the problem originated in June 1901 5 with his reading of Frege s treatise of mathematical logic his 1879 Begriffsschrift the offending sentence in Frege is the following On the other hand it may also be that the argument is determinate and the function indeterminate 6 In other words given f a the function f is the variable and a is the invariant part So why not substitute the value f a for f itself Russell promptly wrote Frege a letter pointing out that You state that a function too can act as the indeterminate element This I formerly believed but now this view seems doubtful to me because of the following contradiction Let w be the predicate to be a predicate that cannot be predicated of itself Can w be predicated of itself From each answer its opposite follows Therefore we must conclude that w is not a predicate Likewise there is no class as a totality of those classes which each taken as a totality do not belong to themselves From this I conclude that under certain circumstances a definable collection does not form a totality 7 Frege promptly wrote back to Russell acknowledging the problem Your discovery of the contradiction caused me the greatest surprise and I would almost say consternation since it has shaken the basis on which I intended to build arithmetic 8 While the problem had adverse personal consequences for both men both had works at the printers that had to be emended van Heijenoort observes that The paradox shook the logicians world and the rumbles are still felt today Russell s paradox which uses the bare notions of set and element falls squarely in the field of logic The paradox was first published by Russell in The principles of mathematics 1903 and is discussed there in great detail 9 Russell after six years of false starts would eventually answer the matter with his 1908 theory of types by propounding his axiom of reducibility It says that any function is coextensive with what he calls a predicative function a function in which the types of apparent variables run no higher than the types of the arguments 10 But this axiom was met with resistance from all quarters The rejection of impredicatively defined mathematical objects while accepting the natural numbers as classically understood leads to the position in the philosophy of mathematics known as predicativism advocated by Henri Poincare and Hermann Weyl in his Das Kontinuum Poincare and Weyl argued that impredicative definitions are problematic only when one or more underlying sets are infinite Ernst Zermelo in his 1908 A new proof of the possibility of a well ordering full citation needed presents an entire section b Objection concerning nonpredicative definition where he argued against Poincare 1906 p 307 who states that a definition is predicative and logically admissible only if it excludes all objects that are dependent upon the notion defined that is that can in any way be determined by it 11 He gives two examples of impredicative definitions i the notion of Dedekind chains and ii in analysis wherever the maximum or minimum of a previously defined completed set of numbers Z is used for further inferences This happens for example in the well known Cauchy proof 12 He ends his section with the following observation A definition may very well rely upon notions that are equivalent to the one being defined indeed in every definition definiens and definiendum are equivalent notions and the strict observance of Poincare s demand would make every definition hence all of science impossible 13 Zermelo s example of minimum and maximum of a previously defined completed set of numbers reappears in Kleene 1952 42 42 where Kleene uses the example of least upper bound in his discussion of impredicative definitions Kleene does not resolve this problem In the next paragraphs he discusses Weyl s attempt in his 1918 Das Kontinuum The Continuum to eliminate impredicative definitions and his failure to retain the theorem that an arbitrary non empty set M of real numbers having an upper bound has a least upper bound cf also Weyl 1919 14 Ramsey argued that impredicative definitions can be harmless for instance the definition of tallest person in the room is impredicative since it depends on a set of things of which it is an element namely the set of all persons in the room Concerning mathematics an example of an impredicative definition is the smallest number in a set which is formally defined as y min X if and only if for all elements x of X y is less than or equal to x and y is in X Burgess 2005 discusses predicative and impredicative theories at some length in the context of Frege s logic Peano arithmetic second order arithmetic and axiomatic set theory See also EditGodel Escher Bach Impredicative polymorphism Logicism Richard s paradoxNotes Edit Kleene 1952 42 43 Solomon Feferman Predicativity 2002 dates derived from Kleene 1952 42 van Heijenoort s commentary before Burali Forti s 1897 A question on transfinite numbers in van Heijenoort 1967 104 see also his commentary before Georg Cantor s 1899 Letter to Dedekind in van Heijenoort 1967 113 Commentary by van Heijenoort before Bertrand Russell s Lettern to Frege in van Heijenoort 1967 124 Gottlob Frege 1879 Begriffsschrift in van Heijenoort 1967 23 Bertrand Russell s 1902 Letter to Frege in van Heijenoort 1967 124 125 Gottlob Frege s 1902 Letter to Russell in van Hiejenoort 1967 127 Van Heijenoort s commentary before Bertrand Russell s 1902 Letter to Frege 1967 124 Willard V Quine s commentary before Bertrand Russell s 1908 Mathematical logic as based on the theory of types van Heijenoort 1967 190 van Heijenoort 1967 190 191 van Heijenoort 1967 191 Kleene 1952 43References Edit Predicative and Impredicative Definitions Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy PlanetMath article on predicativism John Burgess 2005 Fixing Frege Princeton Univ Press Solomon Feferman 2005 Predicativity in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic Oxford University Press 590 624 Russell B 1907 On Some Difficulties in the Theory of Transfinite Numbers and Order Types Proc London Math Soc s2 4 1 29 53 doi 10 1112 plms s2 4 1 29 Stephen C Kleene 1952 1971 edition Introduction to Metamathematics North Holland Publishing Company Amsterdam NY ISBN 0 7204 2103 9 In particular cf his 11 The Paradoxes pp 36 40 and 12 First inferences from the paradoxes IMPREDICATIVE DEFINITION p 42 He states that his 6 or so famous examples of paradoxes antinomies are all examples of impredicative definition and says that Poincare 1905 6 1908 and Russell 1906 1910 enunciated the cause of the paradoxes to lie in these impredicative definitions p 42 however parts of mathematics we want to retain particularly analysis also contain impredicative definitions ibid Weyl in his 1918 Das Kontinuum attempted to derive as much of analysis as was possible without the use of impredicative definitions but not the theorem that an arbitrary non empty set M of real numbers having an upper bound has a least upper bound CF also Weyl 1919 p 43 Hans Reichenbach 1947 Elements of Symbolic Logic Dover Publications Inc NY ISBN 0 486 24004 5 Cf his 40 The antinomies and the theory of types pp 218 wherein he demonstrates how to create antinomies including the definition of impredicable itself Is the definition of impredicable impredicable He claims to show methods for eliminating the paradoxes of syntax logical paradoxes by use of the theory of types and the paradoxes of semantics by the use of metalanguage his theory of levels of language He attributes the suggestion of this notion to Russell and more concretely to Ramsey Jean van Heijenoort 1967 third printing 1976 From Frege to Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press Cambridge MA ISBN 0 674 32449 8 pbk Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Impredicativity amp oldid 1138074069, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.