fbpx
Wikipedia

Morse–Kelley set theory

In the foundations of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), Kelley–Morse set theory (KM), Morse–Tarski set theory (MT), Quine–Morse set theory (QM) or the system of Quine and Morse is a first-order axiomatic set theory that is closely related to von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory restricts the bound variables in the schematic formula appearing in the axiom schema of Class Comprehension to range over sets alone, Morse–Kelley set theory allows these bound variables to range over proper classes as well as sets, as first suggested by Quine in 1940 for his system ML.

Morse–Kelley set theory is named after mathematicians John L. Kelley and Anthony Morse and was first set out by Wang (1949) and later in an appendix to Kelley's textbook General Topology (1955), a graduate level introduction to topology. Kelley said the system in his book was a variant of the systems due to Thoralf Skolem and Morse. Morse's own version appeared later in his book A Theory of Sets (1965).

While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory is a conservative extension of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC, the canonical set theory) in the sense that a statement in the language of ZFC is provable in NBG if and only if it is provable in ZFC, Morse–Kelley set theory is a proper extension of ZFC. Unlike von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory, where the axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances, Morse–Kelley set theory cannot be finitely axiomatized.

MK axioms and ontology Edit

NBG and MK share a common ontology. The universe of discourse consists of classes. Classes that are members of other classes are called sets. A class that is not a set is a proper class. The primitive atomic sentences involve membership or equality.

With the exception of Class Comprehension, the following axioms are the same as those for NBG, inessential details aside. The symbolic versions of the axioms employ the following notational devices:

  • The upper case letters other than M, appearing in Extensionality, Class Comprehension, and Foundation, denote variables ranging over classes. A lower case letter denotes a variable that cannot be a proper class, because it appears to the left of an ∈. As MK is a one-sorted theory, this notational convention is only mnemonic.
  • The monadic predicate   whose intended reading is "the class x is a set", abbreviates  
  • The empty set   is defined by  
  • The class V, the universal class having all possible sets as members, is defined by   V is also the von Neumann universe.

Extensionality: Classes having the same members are the same class.

 

A set and a class having the same extension are identical. Hence MK is not a two-sorted theory, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding.

Foundation: Each nonempty class A is disjoint from at least one of its members.

 

Class Comprehension: Let φ(x) be any formula in the language of MK in which x is a free variable and Y is not free. φ(x) may contain parameters that are either sets or proper classes. More consequentially, the quantified variables in φ(x) may range over all classes and not just over all sets; this is the only way MK differs from NBG. Then there exists a class   whose members are exactly those sets x such that   comes out true. Formally, if Y is not free in φ:

 

Pairing: For any sets x and y, there exists a set   whose members are exactly x and y.

 

Pairing licenses the unordered pair in terms of which the ordered pair,  , may be defined in the usual way, as  . With ordered pairs in hand, Class Comprehension enables defining relations and functions on sets as sets of ordered pairs, making possible the next axiom:

Limitation of Size: C is a proper class if and only if V can be mapped one-to-one into C.

 

The formal version of this axiom resembles the axiom schema of replacement, and embodies the class function F. The next section explains how Limitation of Size is stronger than the usual forms of the axiom of choice.

Power set: Let p be a class whose members are all possible subsets of the set a. Then p is a set.

 

Union: Let   be the sum class of the set a, namely the union of all members of a. Then s is a set.

 

Infinity: There exists an inductive set y, meaning that (i) the empty set is a member of y; (ii) if x is a member of y, then so is  .

 

Note that p and s in Power Set and Union are universally, not existentially, quantified, as Class Comprehension suffices to establish the existence of p and s. Power Set and Union only serve to establish that p and s cannot be proper classes.

The above axioms are shared with other set theories as follows:

  • ZFC and NBG: Pairing, Power Set, Union, Infinity;
  • NBG (and ZFC, if quantified variables were restricted to sets): Extensionality, Foundation;
  • NBG: Limitation of Size.

Discussion Edit

Monk (1980) and Rubin (1967) are set theory texts built around MK; Rubin's ontology includes urelements. These authors and Mendelson (1997: 287) submit that MK does what is expected of a set theory while being less cumbersome than ZFC and NBG.

MK is strictly stronger than ZFC and its conservative extension NBG, the other well-known set theory with proper classes. In fact, NBG—and hence ZFC—can be proved consistent in MK. MK's strength stems from its axiom schema of Class Comprehension being impredicative, meaning that φ(x) may contain quantified variables ranging over classes. The quantified variables in NBG's axiom schema of Class Comprehension are restricted to sets; hence Class Comprehension in NBG must be predicative. (Separation with respect to sets is still impredicative in NBG, because the quantifiers in φ(x) may range over all sets.) The NBG axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances; this is not possible in MK. MK is consistent relative to ZFC augmented by an axiom asserting the existence of strongly inaccessible cardinals.

The only advantage of the axiom of limitation of size is that it implies the axiom of global choice. Limitation of Size does not appear in Rubin (1967), Monk (1980), or Mendelson (1997). Instead, these authors invoke a usual form of the local axiom of choice, and an "axiom of replacement,"[1] asserting that if the domain of a class function is a set, its range is also a set. Replacement can prove everything that Limitation of Size proves, except prove some form of the axiom of choice.

Limitation of Size plus I being a set (hence the universe is nonempty) renders provable the sethood of the empty set; hence no need for an axiom of empty set. Such an axiom could be added, of course, and minor perturbations of the above axioms would necessitate this addition. The set I is not identified with the limit ordinal   as I could be a set larger than   In this case, the existence of   would follow from either form of Limitation of Size.

The class of von Neumann ordinals can be well-ordered. It cannot be a set (under pain of paradox); hence that class is a proper class, and all proper classes have the same size as V. Hence V too can be well-ordered.

MK can be confused with second-order ZFC, ZFC with second-order logic (representing second-order objects in set rather than predicate language) as its background logic. The language of second-order ZFC is similar to that of MK (although a set and a class having the same extension can no longer be identified), and their syntactical resources for practical proof are almost identical (and are identical if MK includes the strong form of Limitation of Size). But the semantics of second-order ZFC are quite different from those of MK. For example, if MK is consistent then it has a countable first-order model, while second-order ZFC has no countable models.

Model theory Edit

ZFC, NBG, and MK each have models describable in terms of V, the von Neumann universe of sets in ZFC. Let the inaccessible cardinal κ be a member of V. Also let Def(X) denote the Δ0 definable subsets of X (see constructible universe). Then:

  • Vκ is model of ZFC;
  • Def(Vκ) is a model of Mendelson's version of NBG, which excludes global choice, replacing limitation of size by replacement and ordinary choice;
  • Vκ+1, the power set of Vκ, is a model of MK.

History Edit

MK was first set out in Wang (1949) and popularized in an appendix to J. L. Kelley's (1955) General Topology, using the axioms given in the next section. The system of Anthony Morse's (1965) A Theory of Sets is equivalent to Kelley's, but formulated in an idiosyncratic formal language rather than, as is done here, in standard first-order logic. The first set theory to include impredicative class comprehension was Quine's ML, that built on New Foundations rather than on ZFC.[2] Impredicative class comprehension was also proposed in Mostowski (1951) and Lewis (1991).

The axioms in Kelley's General Topology Edit

The axioms and definitions in this section are, but for a few inessential details, taken from the Appendix to Kelley (1955). The explanatory remarks below are not his. The Appendix states 181 theorems and definitions, and warrants careful reading as an abbreviated exposition of axiomatic set theory by a working mathematician of the first rank. Kelley introduced his axioms gradually, as needed to develop the topics listed after each instance of Develop below.

Notations appearing below and now well-known are not defined. Peculiarities of Kelley's notation include:

  • He did not distinguish variables ranging over classes from those ranging over sets;
  • domain f and range f denote the domain and range of the function f; this peculiarity has been carefully respected below;
  • His primitive logical language includes class abstracts of the form   "the class of all sets x satisfying A(x)."

Definition: x is a set (and hence not a proper class) if, for some y,  .

I. Extent: For each x and each y, x=y if and only if for each z,   when and only when  

Identical to Extensionality above. I would be identical to the axiom of extensionality in ZFC, except that the scope of I includes proper classes as well as sets.

II. Classification (schema): An axiom results if in

For each  ,   if and only if   is a set and  

'α' and 'β' are replaced by variables, ' A ' by a formula Æ, and ' B ' by the formula obtained from Æ by replacing each occurrence of the variable that replaced α by the variable that replaced β provided that the variable that replaced β does not appear bound in A.

Develop: Boolean algebra of sets. Existence of the null class and of the universal class V.

III. Subsets: If x is a set, there exists a set y such that for each z, if  , then  

The import of III is that of Power Set above. Sketch of the proof of Power Set from III: for any class z that is a subclass of the set x, the class z is a member of the set y whose existence III asserts. Hence z is a set.

Develop: V is not a set. Existence of singletons. Separation provable.

IV. Union: If x and y are both sets, then   is a set.

The import of IV is that of Pairing above. Sketch of the proof of Pairing from IV: the singleton   of a set x is a set because it is a subclass of the power set of x (by two applications of III). Then IV implies that   is a set if x and y are sets.

Develop: Unordered and ordered pairs, relations, functions, domain, range, function composition.

V. Substitution: If f is a [class] function and domain f is a set, then range f is a set.

The import of V is that of the axiom schema of replacement in NBG and ZFC.

VI. Amalgamation: If x is a set, then   is a set.

The import of VI is that of Union above. IV and VI may be combined into one axiom.[3]

Develop: Cartesian product, injection, surjection, bijection, order theory.

VII. Regularity: If   there is a member y of x such that  

The import of VII is that of Foundation above.

Develop: Ordinal numbers, transfinite induction.

VIII. Infinity: There exists a set y, such that   and   whenever  

This axiom, or equivalents thereto, are included in ZFC and NBG. VIII asserts the unconditional existence of two sets, the infinite inductive set y, and the null set     is a set simply because it is a member of y. Up to this point, everything that has been proved to exist is a class, and Kelley's discussion of sets was entirely hypothetical.

Develop: Natural numbers, N is a set, Peano axioms, integers, rational numbers, real numbers.

Definition: c is a choice function if c is a function and   for each member x of domain c.

IX. Choice: There exists a choice function c whose domain is  .

IX is very similar to the axiom of global choice derivable from Limitation of Size above.

Develop: Equivalents of the axiom of choice. As is the case with ZFC, the development of the cardinal numbers requires some form of choice.

If the scope of all quantified variables in the above axioms is restricted to sets, all axioms except III and the schema IV are ZFC axioms. IV is provable in ZFC. Hence the Kelley treatment of MK makes very clear that all that distinguishes MK from ZFC are variables ranging over proper classes as well as sets, and the Classification schema.

Notes Edit

  1. ^ See, e.g., Mendelson (1997), p. 239, axiom R.
  2. ^ The locus citandum for ML is the 1951 ed. of Quine's Mathematical Logic. However, the summary of ML given in Mendelson (1997), p. 296, is easier to follow. Mendelson's axiom schema ML2 is identical to the above axiom schema of Class Comprehension.
  3. ^ Kelley (1955), p. 261, fn †.

References Edit

  • John L. Kelley 1975 (1955) General Topology. Springer. Earlier ed., Van Nostrand. Appendix, "Elementary Set Theory."
  • Lemmon, E. J. (1986) Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory. Routledge & Kegan Paul.
  • David K. Lewis (1991) Parts of Classes. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
  • Mendelson, Elliott (1987). Introduction to Mathematical Logic. Chapman & Hall. ISBN 0-534-06624-0. The definitive treatment of the closely related set theory NBG, followed by a page on MK. Harder than Monk or Rubin.
  • Monk, J. Donald (1980) Introduction to Set Theory. Krieger. Easier and less thorough than Rubin.
  • Morse, A. P., (1965) A Theory of Sets. Academic Press.
  • Mostowski, Andrzej (1950), "Some impredicative definitions in the axiomatic set theory" (PDF), Fundamenta Mathematicae, 37: 111–124, doi:10.4064/fm-37-1-111-124.
  • Rubin, Jean E. (1967) Set Theory for the Mathematician. San Francisco: Holden Day. More thorough than Monk; the ontology includes urelements.
  • Wang, Hao (1949), "On Zermelo's and von Neumann's axioms for set theory", Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A., 35 (3): 150–155, doi:10.1073/pnas.35.3.150, JSTOR 88430, MR 0029850, PMC 1062986, PMID 16588874.

External links Edit

  • Download General Topology (1955) by John L. Kelley in various formats. The appendix contains Kelley's axiomatic development of MK.

From Foundations of Mathematics (FOM) discussion group:

  • Allen Hazen on set theory with classes.
  • Joseph Shoenfield's doubts about MK.

morse, kelley, theory, foundations, mathematics, kelley, morse, theory, morse, tarski, theory, quine, morse, theory, system, quine, morse, first, order, axiomatic, theory, that, closely, related, neumann, bernays, gödel, theory, while, neumann, bernays, gödel,. In the foundations of mathematics Morse Kelley set theory MK Kelley Morse set theory KM Morse Tarski set theory MT Quine Morse set theory QM or the system of Quine and Morse is a first order axiomatic set theory that is closely related to von Neumann Bernays Godel set theory NBG While von Neumann Bernays Godel set theory restricts the bound variables in the schematic formula appearing in the axiom schema of Class Comprehension to range over sets alone Morse Kelley set theory allows these bound variables to range over proper classes as well as sets as first suggested by Quine in 1940 for his system ML Morse Kelley set theory is named after mathematicians John L Kelley and Anthony Morse and was first set out by Wang 1949 and later in an appendix to Kelley s textbook General Topology 1955 a graduate level introduction to topology Kelley said the system in his book was a variant of the systems due to Thoralf Skolem and Morse Morse s own version appeared later in his book A Theory of Sets 1965 While von Neumann Bernays Godel set theory is a conservative extension of Zermelo Fraenkel set theory ZFC the canonical set theory in the sense that a statement in the language of ZFC is provable in NBG if and only if it is provable in ZFC Morse Kelley set theory is a proper extension of ZFC Unlike von Neumann Bernays Godel set theory where the axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances Morse Kelley set theory cannot be finitely axiomatized Contents 1 MK axioms and ontology 2 Discussion 2 1 Model theory 2 2 History 3 The axioms in Kelley s General Topology 4 Notes 5 References 6 External linksMK axioms and ontology EditNBG and MK share a common ontology The universe of discourse consists of classes Classes that are members of other classes are called sets A class that is not a set is a proper class The primitive atomic sentences involve membership or equality With the exception of Class Comprehension the following axioms are the same as those for NBG inessential details aside The symbolic versions of the axioms employ the following notational devices The upper case letters other than M appearing in Extensionality Class Comprehension and Foundation denote variables ranging over classes A lower case letter denotes a variable that cannot be a proper class because it appears to the left of an As MK is a one sorted theory this notational convention is only mnemonic The monadic predicate M x displaystyle Mx nbsp whose intended reading is the class x is a set abbreviates W x W displaystyle exists W x in W nbsp The empty set displaystyle varnothing nbsp is defined by x x displaystyle forall x x not in varnothing nbsp The class V the universal class having all possible sets as members is defined by x M x x V displaystyle forall x Mx to x in V nbsp V is also the von Neumann universe Extensionality Classes having the same members are the same class X Y z z X z Y X Y displaystyle forall X forall Y forall z z in X leftrightarrow z in Y rightarrow X Y nbsp A set and a class having the same extension are identical Hence MK is not a two sorted theory appearances to the contrary notwithstanding Foundation Each nonempty class A is disjoint from at least one of its members A A b b A c c b c A displaystyle forall A A not varnothing rightarrow exists b b in A land forall c c in b rightarrow c not in A nbsp Class Comprehension Let f x be any formula in the language of MK in which x is a free variable and Y is not free f x may contain parameters that are either sets or proper classes More consequentially the quantified variables in f x may range over all classes and not just over all sets this is the only way MK differs from NBG Then there exists a class Y x ϕ x displaystyle Y x mid phi x nbsp whose members are exactly those sets x such that ϕ x displaystyle phi x nbsp comes out true Formally if Y is not free in f W 1 W n Y x x Y ϕ x W 1 W n M x displaystyle forall W 1 W n exists Y forall x x in Y leftrightarrow phi x W 1 W n land Mx nbsp Pairing For any sets x and y there exists a set z x y displaystyle z x y nbsp whose members are exactly x and y x y M x M y z M z s s z s x s y displaystyle forall x forall y Mx land My rightarrow exists z Mz land forall s s in z leftrightarrow s x lor s y nbsp Pairing licenses the unordered pair in terms of which the ordered pair x y displaystyle langle x y rangle nbsp may be defined in the usual way as x x y displaystyle x x y nbsp With ordered pairs in hand Class Comprehension enables defining relations and functions on sets as sets of ordered pairs making possible the next axiom Limitation of Size C is a proper class if and only if V can be mapped one to one into C C M C F x M x s s C x s F x y s x s F y s F x y displaystyle begin array l forall C lnot MC leftrightarrow exists F forall x Mx rightarrow exists s s in C land langle x s rangle in F land qquad forall x forall y forall s langle x s rangle in F land langle y s rangle in F rightarrow x y end array nbsp The formal version of this axiom resembles the axiom schema of replacement and embodies the class function F The next section explains how Limitation of Size is stronger than the usual forms of the axiom of choice Power set Let p be a class whose members are all possible subsets of the set a Then p is a set a p M a x x p y y x y a M p displaystyle forall a forall p Ma land forall x x in p leftrightarrow forall y y in x rightarrow y in a rightarrow Mp nbsp Union Let s a displaystyle s bigcup a nbsp be the sum class of the set a namely the union of all members of a Then s is a set a s M a x x s y x y y a M s displaystyle forall a forall s Ma land forall x x in s leftrightarrow exists y x in y land y in a rightarrow Ms nbsp Infinity There exists an inductive set y meaning that i the empty set is a member of y ii if x is a member of y then so is x x displaystyle x cup x nbsp y M y y z z y x x y w w x w z w z displaystyle exists y My land varnothing in y land forall z z in y rightarrow exists x x in y land forall w w in x leftrightarrow w z lor w in z nbsp Note that p and s in Power Set and Union are universally not existentially quantified as Class Comprehension suffices to establish the existence of p and s Power Set and Union only serve to establish that p and s cannot be proper classes The above axioms are shared with other set theories as follows ZFC and NBG Pairing Power Set Union Infinity NBG and ZFC if quantified variables were restricted to sets Extensionality Foundation NBG Limitation of Size Discussion EditMonk 1980 and Rubin 1967 are set theory texts built around MK Rubin s ontology includes urelements These authors and Mendelson 1997 287 submit that MK does what is expected of a set theory while being less cumbersome than ZFC and NBG MK is strictly stronger than ZFC and its conservative extension NBG the other well known set theory with proper classes In fact NBG and hence ZFC can be proved consistent in MK MK s strength stems from its axiom schema of Class Comprehension being impredicative meaning that f x may contain quantified variables ranging over classes The quantified variables in NBG s axiom schema of Class Comprehension are restricted to sets hence Class Comprehension in NBG must be predicative Separation with respect to sets is still impredicative in NBG because the quantifiers in f x may range over all sets The NBG axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances this is not possible in MK MK is consistent relative to ZFC augmented by an axiom asserting the existence of strongly inaccessible cardinals The only advantage of the axiom of limitation of size is that it implies the axiom of global choice Limitation of Size does not appear in Rubin 1967 Monk 1980 or Mendelson 1997 Instead these authors invoke a usual form of the local axiom of choice and an axiom of replacement 1 asserting that if the domain of a class function is a set its range is also a set Replacement can prove everything that Limitation of Size proves except prove some form of the axiom of choice Limitation of Size plus I being a set hence the universe is nonempty renders provable the sethood of the empty set hence no need for an axiom of empty set Such an axiom could be added of course and minor perturbations of the above axioms would necessitate this addition The set I is not identified with the limit ordinal w displaystyle omega nbsp as I could be a set larger than w displaystyle omega nbsp In this case the existence of w displaystyle omega nbsp would follow from either form of Limitation of Size The class of von Neumann ordinals can be well ordered It cannot be a set under pain of paradox hence that class is a proper class and all proper classes have the same size as V Hence V too can be well ordered MK can be confused with second order ZFC ZFC with second order logic representing second order objects in set rather than predicate language as its background logic The language of second order ZFC is similar to that of MK although a set and a class having the same extension can no longer be identified and their syntactical resources for practical proof are almost identical and are identical if MK includes the strong form of Limitation of Size But the semantics of second order ZFC are quite different from those of MK For example if MK is consistent then it has a countable first order model while second order ZFC has no countable models Model theory Edit ZFC NBG and MK each have models describable in terms of V the von Neumann universe of sets in ZFC Let the inaccessible cardinal k be a member of V Also let Def X denote the D0 definable subsets of X see constructible universe Then Vk is model of ZFC Def Vk is a model of Mendelson s version of NBG which excludes global choice replacing limitation of size by replacement and ordinary choice Vk 1 the power set of Vk is a model of MK History Edit MK was first set out in Wang 1949 and popularized in an appendix to J L Kelley s 1955 General Topology using the axioms given in the next section The system of Anthony Morse s 1965 A Theory of Sets is equivalent to Kelley s but formulated in an idiosyncratic formal language rather than as is done here in standard first order logic The first set theory to include impredicative class comprehension was Quine s ML that built on New Foundations rather than on ZFC 2 Impredicative class comprehension was also proposed in Mostowski 1951 and Lewis 1991 The axioms in Kelley s General Topology EditThe axioms and definitions in this section are but for a few inessential details taken from the Appendix to Kelley 1955 The explanatory remarks below are not his The Appendix states 181 theorems and definitions and warrants careful reading as an abbreviated exposition of axiomatic set theory by a working mathematician of the first rank Kelley introduced his axioms gradually as needed to develop the topics listed after each instance of Develop below Notations appearing below and now well known are not defined Peculiarities of Kelley s notation include He did not distinguish variables ranging over classes from those ranging over sets domain f and range f denote the domain and range of the function f this peculiarity has been carefully respected below His primitive logical language includes class abstracts of the form x A x displaystyle x A x nbsp the class of all sets x satisfying A x Definition x is a set and hence not a proper class if for some y x y displaystyle x in y nbsp I Extent For each x and each y x y if and only if for each z z x displaystyle z in x nbsp when and only when z y displaystyle z in y nbsp Identical to Extensionality above I would be identical to the axiom of extensionality in ZFC except that the scope of I includes proper classes as well as sets II Classification schema An axiom results if in For each b displaystyle beta nbsp b a A displaystyle beta in alpha A nbsp if and only if b displaystyle beta nbsp is a set and B displaystyle B nbsp a and b are replaced by variables A by a formula AE and B by the formula obtained from AE by replacing each occurrence of the variable that replaced a by the variable that replaced b provided that the variable that replaced b does not appear bound in A Develop Boolean algebra of sets Existence of the null class and of the universal class V III Subsets If x is a set there exists a set y such that for each z if z x displaystyle z subseteq x nbsp then z y displaystyle z in y nbsp The import of III is that of Power Set above Sketch of the proof of Power Set from III for any class z that is a subclass of the set x the class z is a member of the set y whose existence III asserts Hence z is a set Develop V is not a set Existence of singletons Separation provable IV Union If x and y are both sets then x y displaystyle x cup y nbsp is a set The import of IV is that of Pairing above Sketch of the proof of Pairing from IV the singleton x displaystyle x nbsp of a set x is a set because it is a subclass of the power set of x by two applications of III Then IV implies that x y displaystyle x y nbsp is a set if x and y are sets Develop Unordered and ordered pairs relations functions domain range function composition V Substitution If f is a class function and domain f is a set then range f is a set The import of V is that of the axiom schema of replacement in NBG and ZFC VI Amalgamation If x is a set then x displaystyle bigcup x nbsp is a set The import of VI is that of Union above IV and VI may be combined into one axiom 3 Develop Cartesian product injection surjection bijection order theory VII Regularity If x displaystyle x neq varnothing nbsp there is a member y of x such that x y displaystyle x cap y varnothing nbsp The import of VII is that of Foundation above Develop Ordinal numbers transfinite induction VIII Infinity There exists a set y such that y displaystyle varnothing in y nbsp and x x y displaystyle x cup x in y nbsp whenever x y displaystyle x in y nbsp This axiom or equivalents thereto are included in ZFC and NBG VIII asserts the unconditional existence of two sets the infinite inductive set y and the null set displaystyle varnothing nbsp displaystyle varnothing nbsp is a set simply because it is a member of y Up to this point everything that has been proved to exist is a class and Kelley s discussion of sets was entirely hypothetical Develop Natural numbers N is a set Peano axioms integers rational numbers real numbers Definition c is a choice function if c is a function and c x x displaystyle c x in x nbsp for each member x of domain c IX Choice There exists a choice function c whose domain is V displaystyle V varnothing nbsp IX is very similar to the axiom of global choice derivable from Limitation of Size above Develop Equivalents of the axiom of choice As is the case with ZFC the development of the cardinal numbers requires some form of choice If the scope of all quantified variables in the above axioms is restricted to sets all axioms except III and the schema IV are ZFC axioms IV is provable in ZFC Hence the Kelley treatment of MK makes very clear that all that distinguishes MK from ZFC are variables ranging over proper classes as well as sets and the Classification schema Notes Edit See e g Mendelson 1997 p 239 axiom R The locus citandum for ML is the 1951 ed of Quine s Mathematical Logic However the summary of ML given in Mendelson 1997 p 296 is easier to follow Mendelson s axiom schema ML2 is identical to the above axiom schema of Class Comprehension Kelley 1955 p 261 fn References EditJohn L Kelley 1975 1955 General Topology Springer Earlier ed Van Nostrand Appendix Elementary Set Theory Lemmon E J 1986 Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory Routledge amp Kegan Paul David K Lewis 1991 Parts of Classes Oxford Basil Blackwell Mendelson Elliott 1987 Introduction to Mathematical Logic Chapman amp Hall ISBN 0 534 06624 0 The definitive treatment of the closely related set theory NBG followed by a page on MK Harder than Monk or Rubin Monk J Donald 1980 Introduction to Set Theory Krieger Easier and less thorough than Rubin Morse A P 1965 A Theory of Sets Academic Press Mostowski Andrzej 1950 Some impredicative definitions in the axiomatic set theory PDF Fundamenta Mathematicae 37 111 124 doi 10 4064 fm 37 1 111 124 Rubin Jean E 1967 Set Theory for the Mathematician San Francisco Holden Day More thorough than Monk the ontology includes urelements Wang Hao 1949 On Zermelo s and von Neumann s axioms for set theory Proc Natl Acad Sci U S A 35 3 150 155 doi 10 1073 pnas 35 3 150 JSTOR 88430 MR 0029850 PMC 1062986 PMID 16588874 External links EditDownload General Topology 1955 by John L Kelley in various formats The appendix contains Kelley s axiomatic development of MK From Foundations of Mathematics FOM discussion group Allen Hazen on set theory with classes Joseph Shoenfield s doubts about MK Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Morse Kelley set theory amp oldid 1158272367, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.