fbpx
Wikipedia

Many-worlds interpretation

The many-worlds interpretation (MWI) is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that asserts that the universal wavefunction is objectively real, and that there is no wave function collapse.[2] This implies that all possible outcomes of quantum measurements are physically realized in some "world" or universe.[3] In contrast to some other interpretations, such as the Copenhagen interpretation, the evolution of reality as a whole in MWI is rigidly deterministic[2]: 9  and local.[4] Many-worlds is also called the relative state formulation or the Everett interpretation, after physicist Hugh Everett, who first proposed it in 1957.[5][6] Bryce DeWitt popularized the formulation and named it many-worlds in the 1970s.[1][2][7][8]

The quantum-mechanical "Schrödinger's cat" paradox according to the many-worlds interpretation. In this interpretation, every quantum event is a branch point; the cat is both alive and dead, even before the box is opened, but the "alive" and "dead" cats are in different branches of the multiverse, both of which are equally real, but which do not interact with each other.[a]

In many-worlds, the subjective appearance of wavefunction collapse is explained by the mechanism of quantum decoherence. Decoherence approaches to interpreting quantum theory have been widely explored and developed since the 1970s,[9][10][11] and have become quite popular. MWI is now considered a mainstream interpretation along with the other decoherence interpretations, collapse theories (including the Copenhagen interpretation), and hidden variable theories such as Bohmian mechanics.

The many-worlds interpretation implies that there are most likely an uncountably infinite number of universes.[12] It is one of a number of multiverse hypotheses in physics and philosophy. MWI views time as a many-branched tree, wherein every possible quantum outcome is realised. This is intended to resolve the measurement problem and thus some paradoxes of quantum theory, such as the EPR paradox[6]: 462 [2]: 118  and Schrödinger's cat,[1] since every possible outcome of a quantum event exists in its own universe.

Overview of the interpretation

The key idea of the many-worlds interpretation is that the unitary dynamics of quantum mechanics applies everywhere and at all times and so describes the whole universe. In particular, it models a measurement as a unitary transformation, a correlation-inducing interaction, between observer and object, without using a collapse postulate, and models observers as ordinary quantum-mechanical systems.[13]: 35–38  This stands in sharp contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation, in which a measurement is a "primitive" concept, not describable by unitary quantum mechanics; in Copenhagen the universe is divided into a quantum and a classical domain, and the collapse postulate is central.[13]: 29–30  MWI's main conclusion is that the universe (or multiverse in this context) is composed of a quantum superposition of an infinite[12] or undefinable[14]: 14–17  amount or number of increasingly divergent, non-communicating parallel universes or quantum worlds.[2] Sometimes dubbed Everett worlds,[2]: 234  each is a consistent and actualized alternative history or timeline.

The many-worlds interpretation makes use of decoherence to explain the measurement process and the emergence of a quasi-classical world.[14][15] Wojciech H. Zurek, one of decoherence theory's pioneers, stated: "Under scrutiny of the environment, only pointer states remain unchanged. Other states decohere into mixtures of stable pointer states that can persist, and, in this sense, exist: They are einselected."[16] Zurek emphasizes that his work does not depend on a particular interpretation.[b]

The many-worlds interpretation shares many similarities with the decoherent histories interpretation, which also uses decoherence to explain the process of measurement or wavefunction collapse.[15]: 9–11  MWI treats the other histories or worlds as real, since it regards the universal wavefunction as the "basic physical entity"[6]: 455  or "the fundamental entity, obeying at all times a deterministic wave equation".[5]: 115  Decoherent histories, on the other hand, needs only one of the histories (or worlds) to be real.[15]: 10 

Several authors, including Wheeler, Everett and Deutsch, call many-worlds a theory or metatheory, rather than just an interpretation.[12][17]: 328  Everett argued that it was the "only completely coherent approach to explaining both the contents of quantum mechanics and the appearance of the world."[18] Deutsch dismissed the idea that many-worlds is an "interpretation", saying that to call it an interpretation "is like talking about dinosaurs as an 'interpretation' of fossil records."[19]: 382 

Formulation

In his 1957 doctoral dissertation, Everett proposed that, rather than relying on external observation for analysis of isolated quantum systems, one could mathematically model an object, as well as its observers, as purely physical systems within the mathematical framework developed by Paul Dirac, John von Neumann and others, discarding altogether the ad hoc mechanism of wave function collapse.[5][2]

Relative state

Everett's original work introduced the concept of a relative state. Two (or more) subsystems, after a general interaction, become entangled. Everett noted that such entangled systems can be expressed as the sum of products of states, where the two or more subsystems are each in a state relative to each other. After a measurement or observation one of the pair (or triple...) is the measured, object or observed system, and one other member is the measuring apparatus (which may include an observer) having recorded the state of the measured system.

In the example of Schrödinger's cat, after the box is opened, the entangled system is the cat, the poison vial and the observer. One relative triple of states would be the alive cat, the unbroken vial and the observer seeing an alive cat. Another relative triple of states would be the dead cat, the broken vial and the observer seeing a dead cat.

The process of measurement or observation, or any correlation-inducing interaction, splits the system up into sets of relative states, where each set of relative states, forming a branch of the universal wavefunction, is consistent within itself, and all future measurements (including by multiple observers) will confirm this consistency.

The many-worlds interpretation is DeWitt's popularisation of Everett, who had referred to the combined observer–object system as split by an observation, each split corresponding to the different or multiple possible outcomes of an observation. These splits generate a branching tree, where each branch is a set of all the states relative to each other. DeWitt introduced the term "world" to describe a single branch of that tree, which is a consistent history. All observations or measurements in any branch are consistent with each other.[5][2]

Under the many-worlds interpretation, the Schrödinger equation, or its quantum field theory, relativistic analog, holds all the time, everywhere. An observation or measurement is modelled by applying the wave equation to the entire system, comprising the observer and the object being observed. One consequence is that every observation can be thought of as causing the combined observer–object's wavefunction to change into a quantum superposition of two or more non-interacting branches, or split into many "worlds". Since many observation-like events have happened and are constantly happening, there are an enormous and growing number of simultaneously existing states.

If a system is composed of two or more subsystems, the system's state will be a superposition of products of the subsystems' states. Each product of subsystem states in the overall superposition evolves over time independently of other products. Once the subsystems interact, their states have become correlated or entangled and can no longer be considered independent. In Everett's terminology, each subsystem state was now correlated with its relative state, since each subsystem must now be considered relative to the other subsystems with which it has interacted.

Properties

MWI removes the observer-dependent role in the quantum measurement process by replacing wavefunction collapse with quantum decoherence.[16] Since the observer's role lies at the heart of most if not all "quantum paradoxes", this automatically resolves a number of problems, such as Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, the EPR paradox, von Neumann's "boundary problem", and others.[6]

Since the Copenhagen interpretation requires the existence of a classical domain beyond the one described by quantum mechanics, it has been criticized as inadequate for the study of cosmology.[20] MWI was developed with the explicit goal of allowing quantum mechanics to be applied to the universe as a whole, making quantum cosmology possible.[6]

MWI is a realist, deterministic and local theory. It achieves this by removing wave function collapse, which is indeterministic and nonlocal, from the deterministic and local equations of quantum theory.[4]

MWI (like other, broader multiverse theories) provides a context for the anthropic principle, which may provide an explanation for the fine-tuned universe.[21][22]

MWI depends crucially on the linearity of quantum mechanics, which underpins the superposition principle. If the final theory of everything is non-linear with respect to wavefunctions, then many-worlds is invalid.[1][2][6][7][8] All quantum field theories are linear and compatible with the MWI, a point emphasised by Everett as a motivation for the MWI.[6] While quantum gravity or string theory may be non-linear in this respect,[23] there is as yet no evidence of this.[24][25]

Interpreting wavefunction collapse

As with the other interpretations of quantum mechanics, the many-worlds interpretation is motivated by behavior that can be illustrated by the double-slit experiment. When particles of light (or anything else) pass through the double slit, a calculation assuming wavelike behavior of light can be used to identify where the particles are likely to be observed. Yet when the particles are observed in this experiment, they appear as particles (i.e., at definite places) and not as non-localized waves.

Some versions of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics proposed a process of "collapse" in which an indeterminate quantum system would probabilistically collapse down onto, or select, just one determinate outcome to "explain" this phenomenon of observation. Wavefunction collapse was widely regarded as artificial and ad hoc,[26] so an alternative interpretation in which the behavior of measurement could be understood from more fundamental physical principles was considered desirable.

Everett's PhD work provided such an interpretation. He argued that for a composite system—such as a subject (the "observer" or measuring apparatus) observing an object (the "observed" system, such as a particle)—the claim that either the observer or the observed has a well-defined state is meaningless; in modern parlance, the observer and the observed have become entangled: we can only specify the state of one relative to the other, i.e., the state of the observer and the observed are correlated after the observation is made. This led Everett to derive from the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone (i.e., without assuming wavefunction collapse) the notion of a relativity of states.

Everett noticed that the unitary, deterministic dynamics alone entailed that after an observation is made each element of the quantum superposition of the combined subject–object wavefunction contains two "relative states": a "collapsed" object state and an associated observer who has observed the same collapsed outcome; what the observer sees and the state of the object have become correlated by the act of measurement or observation. The subsequent evolution of each pair of relative subject–object states proceeds with complete indifference as to the presence or absence of the other elements, as if wavefunction collapse has occurred,[2]: 67, 78  which has the consequence that later observations are always consistent with the earlier observations. Thus the appearance of the object's wavefunction's collapse has emerged from the unitary, deterministic theory itself. (This answered Einstein's early criticism of quantum theory, that the theory should define what is observed, not for the observables to define the theory.[c]) Since the wavefunction merely appears to have collapsed then, Everett reasoned, there was no need to actually assume that it had collapsed. And so, invoking Occam's razor, he removed the postulate of wavefunction collapse from the theory.[2]: 8 

Testability

In 1985, David Deutsch proposed a variant of the Wigner's friend thought experiment as a test of many-worlds versus the Copenhagen interpretation.[28] It consists of an experimenter (Wigner's friend) making a measurement on a quantum system in an isolated laboratory, and another experimenter (Wigner) who would make a measurement on the first one. According to the many-worlds theory, the first experimenter would end up in a macroscopic superposition of seeing one result of the measurement in one branch, and another result in another branch. The second experimenter could then interfere these two branches in order to test whether it is in fact in a macroscopic superposition or has collapsed into a single branch, as predicted by the Copenhagen interpretation. Since then Lockwood (1989), Vaidman and others have made similar proposals.[29] These proposals require placing macroscopic objects in a coherent superposition and interfering them, a task currently beyond experimental capability.

Probability and the Born rule

Since the many-worlds interpretation's inception, physicists have been puzzled about the role of probability in it. As put by Wallace, there are two facets to the question:[30] the incoherence problem, which asks why we should assign probabilities at all to outcomes that are certain to occur in some worlds, and the quantitative problem, which asks why the probabilities should be given by the Born rule.

Everett tried to answer these questions in the paper that introduced many-worlds. To address the incoherence problem, he argued that an observer who makes a sequence of measurements on a quantum system will in general have an apparently random sequence of results in their memory, which justifies the use of probabilities to describe the measurement process.[5]: 69–70  To address the quantitative problem, Everett proposed a derivation of the Born rule based on the properties that a measure on the branches of the wavefunction should have.[5]: 70–72  His derivation has been criticized as relying on unmotivated assumptions.[31] Since then several other derivations of the Born rule in the many-worlds framework have been proposed. There is no consensus on whether this has been successful.[32][33][34]

Frequentism

DeWitt and Graham[2] and Farhi et al.,[35] among others, have proposed derivations of the Born rule based on a frequentist interpretation of probability. They try to show that in the limit of infinitely many measurements no worlds would have relative frequencies that didn't match the probabilities given by the Born rule, but these derivations have been shown to be mathematically incorrect.[36][37]

Decision theory

A decision-theoretic derivation of the Born rule was produced by David Deutsch (1999)[38] and refined by Wallace (2002–2009)[30][39][40][41] and Saunders (2004).[42][43] They consider an agent who takes part in a quantum gamble: the agent makes a measurement on a quantum system, branches as a consequence, and each of the agent's future selves receives a reward that depends on the measurement result. The agent uses decision theory to evaluate the price they would pay to take part in such a gamble, and concludes that the price is given by the utility of the rewards weighted according to the Born rule. Some reviews have been positive, although these arguments remain highly controversial; some theoretical physicists have taken them as supporting the case for parallel universes.[44] For example, a New Scientist story on a 2007 conference about Everettian interpretations[45] quoted physicist Andy Albrecht as saying, "This work will go down as one of the most important developments in the history of science."[44] In contrast, the philosopher Huw Price, also attending the conference, found the Deutsch–Wallace–Saunders approach fundamentally flawed.[46]

Symmetries and invariance

Zurek (2005)[47] has produced a derivation of the Born rule based on the symmetries of entangled states; Schlosshauer and Fine argue that Zurek's derivation is not rigorous, as it does not define what probability is and has several unstated assumptions about how it should behave.[48]

Charles Sebens and Sean M. Carroll, building on work by Lev Vaidman,[49] proposed a similar approach based on self-locating uncertainty.[50] In this approach, decoherence creates multiple identical copies of observers, who can assign credences to being on different branches using the Born rule. The Sebens–Carroll approach has been criticized by Adrian Kent,[51] and Vaidman himself does not find it satisfactory.[52]

The preferred basis problem

As originally formulated by Everett and DeWitt, the many-worlds interpretation had a privileged role for measurements: they determined which basis of a quantum system would give rise to the eponymous worlds. Without this the theory was ambiguous, as a quantum state can equally well be described (e.g.) as having a well-defined position or as being a superposition of two delocalised states. The assumption is that the preferred basis to use is the one which assigns a unique measurement outcome to each world. This special role for measurements is problematic for the theory, as it contradicts Everett and DeWitt's goal of having a reductionist theory and undermines their criticism of the ill-defined measurement postulate of the Copenhagen interpretation.[17][31] This is known today as the preferred basis problem.

The preferred basis problem has been solved, according to Saunders and Wallace, among others,[15] by incorporating decoherence into the many-worlds theory.[20][53][54][55] In this approach, the preferred basis does not have to be postulated, but rather is identified as the basis stable under environmental decoherence. In this way measurements no longer play a special role; rather, any interaction that causes decoherence causes the world to split. Since decoherence is never complete, there will always remain some infinitesimal overlap between two worlds, making it arbitrary whether a pair of worlds has split or not.[56] Wallace argues that this is not problematic: it only shows that worlds are not a part of the fundamental ontology, but rather of the emergent ontology, where these approximate, effective descriptions are routine in the physical sciences.[57][14] Since in this approach the worlds are derived, it follows that they must be present in any other interpretation of quantum mechanics that does not have a collapse mechanism, such as Bohmian mechanics.[58]

This approach to deriving the preferred basis has been criticized as creating a circularity with derivations of probability in the many-worlds interpretation, as decoherence theory depends on probability, and probability depends on the ontology derived from decoherence.[33][47][59] Wallace contends that decoherence theory depends not on probability but only on the notion that one is allowed to do approximations in physics.[13]: 253–254 

History

MWI originated in Everett's Princeton PhD thesis "The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction",[2] developed under his thesis advisor John Archibald Wheeler, a shorter summary of which was published in 1957 under the title "Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics" (Wheeler contributed the title "relative state";[60] Everett originally called his approach the "Correlation Interpretation", where "correlation" refers to quantum entanglement). The phrase "many-worlds" is due to Bryce DeWitt,[2] who was responsible for the wider popularisation of Everett's theory, which had been largely ignored for a decade after publication in 1957.[12]

Everett's proposal was not without precedent. In 1952, Erwin Schrödinger gave a lecture in Dublin in which at one point he jocularly warned his audience that what he was about to say might "seem lunatic". He went on to assert that while the Schrödinger equation seemed to be describing several different histories, they were "not alternatives but all really happen simultaneously". According to David Deutsch, this is the earliest known reference to many-worlds; Jeffrey A. Barrett describes it as indicating the similarity of "general views" between Everett and Schrödinger.[61][62][63] Schrödinger's writings from the period also contain elements resembling the modal interpretation originated by Bas van Fraassen. Because Schrödinger subscribed to a kind of post-Machian neutral monism, in which "matter" and "mind" are only different aspects or arrangements of the same common elements, treating the wavefunction as physical and treating it as information became interchangeable.[64]

Reception

MWI's initial reception was overwhelmingly negative, in the sense that it was ignored, with the notable exception of DeWitt. Wheeler made considerable efforts to formulate the theory in a way that would be palatable to Bohr, visited Copenhagen in 1956 to discuss it with him, and convinced Everett to visit as well, which happened in 1959. Nevertheless, Bohr and his collaborators completely rejected the theory.[d] Everett had already left academia in 1956, never to return, and after his death, Wheeler disavowed the theory.[12]

Support

One of MWI's strongest longtime advocates is David Deutsch.[65] According to Deutsch, the single photon interference pattern observed in the double slit experiment can be explained by interference of photons in multiple universes. Viewed this way, the single photon interference experiment is indistinguishable from the multiple photon interference experiment. In a more practical vein, in one of the earliest papers on quantum computing,[66] he suggested that parallelism that results from MWI could lead to "a method by which certain probabilistic tasks can be performed faster by a universal quantum computer than by any classical restriction of it". Deutsch has also proposed that MWI will be testable (at least against "naive" Copenhagenism) when reversible computers become conscious via the reversible observation of spin.[67]

Equivocal

Philosophers of science James Ladyman and Don Ross say that the MWI could be true, but that they do not embrace it. They note that no quantum theory is yet empirically adequate for describing all of reality, given its lack of unification with general relativity, and so they do not see a reason to regard any interpretation of quantum mechanics as the final word in metaphysics. They also suggest that the multiple branches may be an artifact of incomplete descriptions and of using quantum mechanics to represent the states of macroscopic objects. They argue that macroscopic objects are significantly different from microscopic objects in not being isolated from the environment, and that using quantum formalism to describe them lacks explanatory and descriptive power and accuracy.[68]

Victor J. Stenger remarked that Murray Gell-Mann's published work explicitly rejects the existence of simultaneous parallel universes.[69] Collaborating with James Hartle, Gell-Mann worked toward the development a more "palatable" post-Everett quantum mechanics. Stenger thought it fair to say that most physicists find the MWI too extreme, while noting it "has merit in finding a place for the observer inside the system being analyzed and doing away with the troublesome notion of wave function collapse".[e]

Richard Feynman, described as an Everettian in some sources,[70] said of the MWI in 1982, "It's possible, but I'm not very happy with it."[71]

Rejection

Some scientists consider MWI unfalsifiable and hence unscientific because the multiple parallel universes are non-communicating, in the sense that no information can be passed between them.[72][73] Others claim MWI is directly testable.[67]

Roger Penrose argues that the idea is flawed because it is based on an oversimplified version of quantum mechanics that does not account for gravity. In his view, applying conventional quantum mechanics to the universe implies the MWI, but the lack of a successful theory of quantum gravity negates the claimed universality of conventional quantum mechanics.[23] According to Penrose, "the rules must change when gravity is involved". He further asserts that gravity helps anchor reality and "blurry" events have only one allowable outcome: "electrons, atoms, molecules, etc., are so minute that they require almost no amount of energy to maintain their gravity, and therefore their overlapping states. They can stay in that state forever, as described in standard quantum theory". On the other hand, "in the case of large objects, the duplicate states disappear in an instant due to the fact that these objects create a large gravitational field".[74][75]

Philosopher of science Robert P. Crease says that the MWI is "one of the most implausible and unrealistic ideas in the history of science" because it means that everything conceivable happens.[74] Science writer Philip Ball describes the MWI's implications as fantasies, since "beneath their apparel of scientific equations or symbolic logic, they are acts of imagination, of 'just supposing'".[74]

Theoretical physicist Gerard 't Hooft also dismisses the idea: "I do not believe that we have to live with the many-worlds interpretation. Indeed, it would be a stupendous number of parallel worlds, which are only there because physicists couldn't decide which of them is real."[76]

Asher Peres was an outspoken critic of MWI. A section of his 1993 textbook had the title Everett's interpretation and other bizarre theories. Peres argued that the various many-worlds interpretations merely shift the arbitrariness or vagueness of the collapse postulate to the question of when "worlds" can be regarded as separate, and that no objective criterion for that separation can actually be formulated.[77]

Polls

A poll of 72 "leading quantum cosmologists and other quantum field theorists" conducted before 1991 by L. David Raub showed 58% agreement with "Yes, I think MWI is true".[70]

Max Tegmark reports the result of a "highly unscientific" poll taken at a 1997 quantum mechanics workshop. According to Tegmark, "The many worlds interpretation (MWI) scored second, comfortably ahead of the consistent histories and Bohm interpretations."[78]

In response to Sean M. Carroll's statement "As crazy as it sounds, most working physicists buy into the many-worlds theory",[79] Michael Nielsen counters: "at a quantum computing conference at Cambridge in 1998, a many-worlder surveyed the audience of approximately 200 people... Many-worlds did just fine, garnering support on a level comparable to, but somewhat below, Copenhagen and decoherence." But Nielsen notes that it seemed most attendees found it to be a waste of time: Peres "got a huge and sustained round of applause…when he got up at the end of the polling and asked 'And who here believes the laws of physics are decided by a democratic vote?'"[80]

A 2005 poll of fewer than 40 students and researchers taken after a course on the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics at the Institute for Quantum Computing University of Waterloo found "Many Worlds (and decoherence)" to be the least favored.[81]

A 2011 poll of 33 participants at an Austrian conference found 6 endorsed MWI, 8 "Information-based/information-theoretical", and 14 Copenhagen;[82] the authors remark that MWI received a similar percentage of votes as in Tegmark's 1997 poll.[82]

Debate whether the other worlds are real

Everett believed in the literal reality of the other quantum worlds.[19] His son reported that he "never wavered in his belief over his many-worlds theory".[83]

According to Martin Gardner, the "other" worlds of MWI have two different interpretations: real or unreal; he claimed that Stephen Hawking and Steven Weinberg both favour the unreal interpretation.[84] Gardner also claimed that most physicists favour the unreal interpretation, whereas the "realist" view is supported only by MWI experts such as Deutsch and DeWitt. Gardner reports Hawking saying that MWI is "trivially true".[84] In a 1983 interview, Hawking also said he regarded MWI as "self-evidently correct" but was dismissive of questions about the interpretation of quantum mechanics, saying, "When I hear of Schrödinger's cat, I reach for my gun." In the same interview, he also said, "But, look: All that one does, really, is to calculate conditional probabilities—in other words, the probability of A happening, given B. I think that that's all the many-worlds interpretation is. Some people overlay it with a lot of mysticism about the wave function splitting into different parts. But all that you're calculating is conditional probabilities."[85] Elsewhere Hawking contrasted his attitude towards the "reality" of physical theories with that of his colleague Roger Penrose, saying, "He's a Platonist and I'm a positivist. He's worried that Schrödinger's cat is in a quantum state, where it is half alive and half dead. He feels that can't correspond to reality. But that doesn't bother me. I don't demand that a theory correspond to reality because I don't know what it is. Reality is not a quality you can test with litmus paper. All I'm concerned with is that the theory should predict the results of measurements. Quantum theory does this very successfully."[86]

Gell-Mann described himself as a "post-Everett investigator"[87] and wrote, "it is not necessary to become queasy trying to conceive of many 'parallel universes,' all equally real". Instead, he advocated the language of "many histories, all treated alike by the theory except for their different probabilities."[88]

Speculative implications

Quantum suicide thought experiment

Quantum suicide is a thought experiment in quantum mechanics and the philosophy of physics. Purportedly, it can distinguish between the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and the many-worlds interpretation by means of a variation of the Schrödinger's cat thought experiment, from the cat's point of view. Quantum immortality refers to the subjective experience of surviving quantum suicide.[89]

Most experts believe that the experiment would not work in the real world, because the world with the surviving experimenter has a lower "measure" than the world before the experiment, making it less likely that the experimenter will experience their survival.[13]: 371 [29][90][91]

Absurdly improbable timelines

DeWitt has stated that "[Everett, Wheeler and Graham] do not in the end exclude any element of the superposition. All the worlds are there, even those in which everything goes wrong and all the statistical laws break down."[92]

Max Tegmark has affirmed that absurd or highly unlikely events are inevitable but rare under MWI. To quote Tegmark, "Things inconsistent with the laws of physics will never happen—everything else will... it's important to keep track of the statistics, since even if everything conceivable happens somewhere, really freak events happen only exponentially rarely."[93]

Ladyman and Ross state that, in general, many of the unrealized possibilities that are discussed in other scientific fields will not have counterparts in other branches, because they are in fact incompatible with the universal wavefunction.[68]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ "every quantum transition taking place on every star, in every galaxy, in every remote corner of the universe is splitting our local world on earth into myriads of copies of itself."[1]
  2. ^ Relative states of Everett come to mind. One could speculate about reality of branches with other outcomes. We abstain from this; our discussion is interpretation-free, and this is a virtue.[16]
  3. ^ "Whether you can observe a thing or not depends on the theory which you use. It is the theory which decides what can be observed."—Albert Einstein to Werner Heisenberg, objecting to placing observables at the heart of the new quantum mechanics, during Heisenberg's 1926 lecture at Berlin; related by Heisenberg in 1968.[27]
  4. ^ Everett recounted his meeting with Bohr as "that was a hell... doomed from the beginning". Léon Rosenfeld, a close collaborator of Bohr, said "With regard to Everett neither I nor even Niels Bohr could have any patience with him, when he visited us in Copenhagen more than 12 years ago in order to sell the hopelessly wrong ideas he had been encouraged, most unwisely, by Wheeler to develop. He was undescribably stupid and could not understand the simplest things in quantum mechanics."[12]: 113 
  5. ^ Gell-Mann and Hartle, along with a score of others, have been working to develop a more palatable interpretation of quantum mechanics that is free of the problems that plague all the interpretations we have considered so far. This new interpretation is called, in its various incarnations, post-Everett quantum mechanics, alternate histories, consistent histories, or decoherent histories. I will not be overly concerned with the detailed differences between these characterizations and will use the terms more or less interchangeably.[69]: 176 

References

  1. ^ a b c d Bryce S. DeWitt (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331. See also Leslie E. Ballentine; Philip Pearle; Evan Harris Walker; Mendel Sachs; Toyoki Koga; Joseph Gerver; Bryce DeWitt (1971). "Quantum‐mechanics debate". Physics Today. 24 (4): 36–44. Bibcode:1971PhT....24d..36.. doi:10.1063/1.3022676.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Everett, Hugh; Wheeler, J. A.; DeWitt, B. S.; Cooper, L. N.; Van Vechten, D.; Graham, N. (1973). DeWitt, Bryce; Graham, R. Neill (eds.). The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton Series in Physics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. p. v. ISBN 0-691-08131-X.
  3. ^ Tegmark, Max (1998). "The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Many Worlds or Many Words?". Fortschritte der Physik. 46 (6–8): 855–862. arXiv:quant-ph/9709032. Bibcode:1998ForPh..46..855T. doi:10.1002/(SICI)1521-3978(199811)46:6/8<855::AID-PROP855>3.0.CO;2-Q. S2CID 212466.
  4. ^ a b Harvey R. Brown; Christopher G. Timpson (2016). "Bell on Bell's Theorem: The Changing Face of Nonlocality". In Mary Bell; Shan Gao (eds.). Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 years of Bell's theorem. Cambridge University Press. pp. 91–123. arXiv:1501.03521. doi:10.1017/CBO9781316219393.008. ISBN 9781316219393. S2CID 118686956. On locality:"Amongst those who have taken Everett's approach to quantum theory at all seriously as an option, it is a commonplace that—given an Everettian interpretation—quantum theory is (dynamically) local-there is no action-at-a-distance" on determinism:"But zooming-out (in a God's-eye view) from a particular branch will be seen all the other branches, each with a different result of measurement being recorded and observed, all coexisting equally; and all underpinned by (supervenient on) the deterministically, unitarily, evolving universal wavefunction"
  5. ^ a b c d e f Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction, Thesis, Princeton University, (1956, 1973), pp 1–140
  6. ^ a b c d e f g Everett, Hugh (1957). . Reviews of Modern Physics. 29 (3): 454–462. Bibcode:1957RvMP...29..454E. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.29.454. Archived from the original on 2011-10-27. Retrieved 2011-10-24.
  7. ^ a b Cecile M. DeWitt, John A. Wheeler eds, The Everett–Wheeler Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Battelle Rencontres: 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics (1968)
  8. ^ a b Bryce Seligman DeWitt, The Many-Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, Proceedings of the International School of Physics "Enrico Fermi" Course IL: Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Academic Press (1972)
  9. ^ H. Dieter Zeh, On the Interpretation of Measurement in Quantum Theory, Foundations of Physics, vol. 1, pp. 69–76, (1970).
  10. ^ Wojciech Hubert Zurek, Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical, Physics Today, vol. 44, issue 10, pp. 36–44, (1991).
  11. ^ Wojciech Hubert Zurek, Decoherence, einselection, and the quantum origins of the classical, Reviews of Modern Physics, 75, pp 715–775, (2003)
  12. ^ a b c d e f Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). "The Origin of the Everettian Heresy". Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002.
  13. ^ a b c d Wallace, David (2012). The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-954696-1.
  14. ^ a b c David Wallace (2010). "Decoherence and Ontology, or: How I Learned To Stop Worrying And Love FAPP". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:1111.2189.
  15. ^ a b c d Saunders, Simon (2010). "Many Worlds? An Introduction". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality (PDF). Oxford University Press.
  16. ^ a b c Zurek, Wojciech (March 2009). "Quantum Darwinism". Nature Physics. 5 (3): 181–188. arXiv:0903.5082. Bibcode:2009NatPh...5..181Z. doi:10.1038/nphys1202. S2CID 119205282.
  17. ^ a b Brian Skyrms (1976). "Possible Worlds, Physics and Metaphysics". Philosophical Studies. 30 (5): 323–332. doi:10.1007/BF00357930. S2CID 170852547.
  18. ^ Letter from Everett to David Raub, 1980-04-07, UCI. Accessed 12 April 2020.
  19. ^ a b Peter Byrne (2010). The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-955227-6.
  20. ^ a b M Gell-Mann; J.B. Hartle (1990). "Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum cosmology". In W.H. Zurek (ed.). Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Addison-Wesley. arXiv:1803.04605.
  21. ^ Paul C.W. Davies, Other Worlds, chapters 8 & 9 The Anthropic Principle & Is the Universe an accident?, (1980) ISBN 0-460-04400-1
  22. ^ Paul C.W. Davies, The Accidental Universe, (1982) ISBN 0-521-28692-1
  23. ^ a b Penrose, Roger (August 1991). . Sciencewatch. Archived from the original on 2007-10-23. Retrieved 2007-10-21.
  24. ^ Steven Weinberg, Dreams of a Final Theory: The Search for the Fundamental Laws of Nature (1993), ISBN 0-09-922391-0, pg 68–69
  25. ^ Steven Weinberg Testing Quantum Mechanics, Annals of Physics Vol 194 #2 (1989), pg 336–386
  26. ^ Wimmel Hermann. Quantum Physics And Observed Reality: A Critical Interpretation Of Quantum Mechanics, p.45, World Scientific, May 26, 1992
  27. ^ Abdus Salam, Unification of Fundamental Forces, Cambridge University Press (1990) ISBN 0-521-37140-6, pp 98–101
  28. ^ Deutsch, D. (1985). "Quantum theory as a universal physical theory". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 24 (1): 1–41. Bibcode:1985IJTP...24....1D. doi:10.1007/BF00670071. S2CID 17530632.
  29. ^ a b Vaidman, Lev (2018). Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  30. ^ a b Wallace, David (2003). "Everettian Rationality: defending Deutsch's approach to probability in the Everett interpretation". Stud. Hist. Phil. Mod. Phys. 34 (3): 415–438. arXiv:quant-ph/0303050. Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34..415W. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(03)00036-4. S2CID 1921913.
  31. ^ a b L. E. Ballentine (1973). "Can the statistical postulate of quantum theory be derived?—A critique of the many-universes interpretation". Foundations of Physics. 3 (2): 229–240. Bibcode:1973FoPh....3..229B. doi:10.1007/BF00708440. S2CID 121747282.
  32. ^ N.P. Landsman, "The conclusion seems to be that no generally accepted derivation of the Born rule has been given to date, but this does not imply that such a derivation is impossible in principle.", in Compendium of Quantum Physics (eds.) F. Weinert, K. Hentschel, D.Greenberger and B. Falkenburg (Springer, 2008), ISBN 3-540-70622-4
  33. ^ a b Kent, Adrian (2010). "One world versus many: The inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution, probability, and scientific confirmation". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:0905.0624. Bibcode:2009arXiv0905.0624K.
  34. ^ Kent, Adrian (1990). "Against Many-Worlds Interpretations". Int. J. Mod. Phys. A. 5 (9): 1745–1762. arXiv:gr-qc/9703089. Bibcode:1990IJMPA...5.1745K. doi:10.1142/S0217751X90000805. S2CID 14523184.
  35. ^ Edward Farhi; Jeffrey Goldstone; Sam Gutmann (1989). "How probability arises in quantum mechanics". Annals of Physics. 192 (2): 368–382. Bibcode:1989AnPhy.192..368F. doi:10.1016/0003-4916(89)90141-3.
  36. ^ Benioff, Paul (October 1978). "A note on the Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics". Foundations of Physics. 8 (9–10): 709–720. Bibcode:1978FoPh....8..709B. doi:10.1007/BF00717501. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 123279967.
  37. ^ Carlton M. Caves; Rüdiger Schack (2005). "Properties of the frequency operator do not imply the quantum probability postulate". Annals of Physics. 315 (1): 123–146. arXiv:quant-ph/0409144. Bibcode:2005AnPhy.315..123C. doi:10.1016/j.aop.2004.09.009. S2CID 33263618.
  38. ^ Deutsch, David (1999). "Quantum Theory of Probability and Decisions". Proceedings of the Royal Society A: Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences. 455 (1988): 3129–3137. arXiv:quant-ph/9906015. Bibcode:1999RSPSA.455.3129D. doi:10.1098/rspa.1999.0443. S2CID 5217034.
  39. ^ Wallace, David (2002). "Quantum Probability and Decision Theory, Revisited". arXiv:quant-ph/0211104.
  40. ^ Wallace, David (2003). "Quantum Probability from Subjective Likelihood: Improving on Deutsch's proof of the probability rule". arXiv:quant-ph/0312157.
  41. ^ Wallace, David (2009). "A formal proof of the Born rule from decision-theoretic assumptions". arXiv:0906.2718 [quant-ph].
  42. ^ Saunders, Simon (2004). "Derivation of the Born rule from operational assumptions". Proc. R. Soc. Lond. A. 460 (2046): 1771–1788. arXiv:quant-ph/0211138. Bibcode:2004RSPSA.460.1771S. doi:10.1098/rspa.2003.1230. S2CID 1459183.
  43. ^ Saunders, Simon (2004). "What is Probability?". Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics?. The Frontiers Collection. pp. 209–238. arXiv:quant-ph/0412194. doi:10.1007/3-540-26669-0_12. ISBN 978-3-540-22188-3. S2CID 117218061.
  44. ^ a b Merali, Zeeya (2007-09-21). "Parallel universes make quantum sense". New Scientist. No. 2622. Retrieved 2013-11-22. (Summary only).
  45. ^ "Perimeter Institute, Many worlds at 50 conference, September 21–24, 2007"."Videos".
  46. ^ Price, Huw (2010). "Decisions, Decisions, Decisions: Can Savage Salvage Everettian Probability?". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press. arXiv:0802.1390.
  47. ^ a b Zurek, Wojciech H. (2005). "Probabilities from entanglement, Born's rule from envariance". Phys. Rev. A. 71 (5): 052105. arXiv:quant-ph/0405161. Bibcode:2005PhRvA..71e2105Z. doi:10.1103/physreva.71.052105. S2CID 18210481.
  48. ^ Schlosshauer, M.; Fine, A. (2005). "On Zurek's derivation of the Born rule". Found. Phys. 35 (2): 197–213. arXiv:quant-ph/0312058. Bibcode:2005FoPh...35..197S. doi:10.1007/s10701-004-1941-6. S2CID 119100306.
  49. ^ Vaidman, L. "Probability in the Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics." In: Ben-Menahem, Y., & Hemmo, M. (eds), The Probable and the Improbable: Understanding Probability in Physics, Essays in Memory of Itamar Pitowsky. Springer.
  50. ^ Sebens, Charles T; Carroll, Sean M (2016). "Self-Locating Uncertainty and the Origin of Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics". The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. 69 (1): 25–74. arXiv:1405.7577. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw004. S2CID 53648469.
  51. ^ Kent, Adrian (February 2015). "Does it Make Sense to Speak of Self-Locating Uncertainty in the Universal Wave Function? Remarks on Sebens and Carroll". Foundations of Physics. 45 (2): 211–217. arXiv:1408.1944. Bibcode:2015FoPh...45..211K. doi:10.1007/s10701-014-9862-5. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 118471198.
  52. ^ Vaidman, Lev (2020). "Derivations of the Born Rule". In Meir Hemmo; Orly Shenker (eds.). Quantum, Probability, Logic: Itamar Pitowsky's Work and Influence. Springer Nature Switzerland. PhilSci:15943.
  53. ^ Simon Saunders (1993). "Decoherence, relative states, and evolutionary adaptation". Foundations of Physics. 23 (12): 1553–1585. Bibcode:1993FoPh...23.1553S. doi:10.1007/BF00732365. S2CID 119754481.
  54. ^ Simon Saunders (1995). "Time, quantum mechanics, and decoherence" (PDF). Synthese. 102 (2): 235–266. doi:10.1007/BF01089802. S2CID 14550985.
  55. ^ James B. Hartle (2011). "The quasiclassical realms of this quantum universe". Foundations of Physics. 41 (6): 982–1006. arXiv:0806.3776. Bibcode:2011FoPh...41..982H. doi:10.1007/s10701-010-9460-0. S2CID 118469123.
  56. ^ Stapp, Henry (2002). "The basis problem in many-world theories" (PDF). Canadian Journal of Physics. 80 (9): 1043–1052. arXiv:quant-ph/0110148. Bibcode:2002CaJPh..80.1043S. doi:10.1139/p02-068. S2CID 18634782.
  57. ^ David Wallace (2003). "Everett and structure". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 34 (1): 87–105. arXiv:quant-ph/0107144. Bibcode:2003SHPMP..34...87W. doi:10.1016/S1355-2198(02)00085-0. S2CID 15222560.
  58. ^ Brown, Harvey R; Wallace, David (2005). "Solving the measurement problem: de Broglie–Bohm loses out to Everett" (PDF). Foundations of Physics. 35 (4): 517–540. arXiv:quant-ph/0403094. Bibcode:2005FoPh...35..517B. doi:10.1007/s10701-004-2009-3. S2CID 412240.
  59. ^ David J Baker (2007). "Measurement outcomes and probability in Everettian quantum mechanics" (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 38 (1): 153–169. Bibcode:2007SHPMP..38..153B. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2006.05.003.
  60. ^ Wheeler, John Archibald (2000). Geons, Black Holes and Quantum Foam. W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 268–270. ISBN 0-393-31991-1.
  61. ^ Deutsch, David (2010). "Apart from Universes". In S. Saunders; J. Barrett; A. Kent; D. Wallace (eds.). Many Worlds? Everett, Quantum Theory and Reality. Oxford University Press.
  62. ^ Schrödinger, Erwin (1996). Bitbol, Michel (ed.). The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Dublin Seminars (1949–1955) and other unpublished essays. OxBow Press.
  63. ^ Barrett, Jeffrey A. (1999). The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds. Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780191583254.
  64. ^ Bitbol, Michel (1996). Schrödinger's Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. ISBN 978-94-009-1772-9. OCLC 851376153.
  65. ^ David Deutsch, The Fabric of Reality: The Science of Parallel Universes And Its Implications, Penguin Books (1998), ISBN 0-14-027541-X
  66. ^ Deutsch, David (1985). "Quantum theory, the Church–Turing principle and the universal quantum computer". Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A. 400 (1818): 97–117. Bibcode:1985RSPSA.400...97D. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.144.7936. doi:10.1098/rspa.1985.0070. S2CID 1438116.
  67. ^ a b Paul C.W. Davies, J.R. Brown, The Ghost in the Atom (1986) ISBN 0-521-31316-3, pp. 34–38: "The Many-Universes Interpretation", pp 83–105 for David Deutsch's test of MWI and reversible quantum memories
  68. ^ a b Ladyman, James; Ross, Don (2007). Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized. Clarendon Press. pp. 179–183. ISBN 978-0-19-927619-6.
  69. ^ a b Stenger, V.J. (1995). The Unconscious Quantum: Metaphysics in Modern Physics and Cosmology. Prometheus Books. ISBN 978-1-57392-022-3. LCCN lc95032599.
  70. ^ a b Tipler, Frank (1994). The Physics of Immortality. pp. 170–171. In the "yes" column were Stephen Hawking, Richard Feynman, and Murray Gell-Mann
  71. ^ Feynman, Richard P. (June 1982). "Simulating physics with computers". International Journal of Theoretical Physics. 21 (6–7): 467–488. Bibcode:1982IJTP...21..467F. doi:10.1007/BF02650179. ISSN 0020-7748. S2CID 124545445.
  72. ^ Bunge, M. (2012). "Parallel Universes? Digital Physics?". Evaluating Philosophies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. Vol. 295. New York: Springer. pp. 152–153. doi:10.1007/978-94-007-4408-0. ISBN 978-94-007-4407-3.
  73. ^ Ellis, G.; Silk, J. (2014). "Scientific method: Defend the integrity of physics". Nature. 516 (7531): 321–323. Bibcode:2014Natur.516..321E. doi:10.1038/516321a. PMID 25519115.
  74. ^ a b c Ball, Philip (2015-02-17). "Too many worlds". Aeon.co. Retrieved 2021-09-23.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  75. ^ "If an Electron Can Be in Two Places at Once, Why Can't You?". Discover Magazine.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: url-status (link)
  76. ^ Melinda, Baldwin (2017-07-11). "Q&A: Gerard 't Hooft on the future of quantum mechanics". Physics Today. doi:10.1063/PT.6.4.20170711a.
  77. ^ Peres, Asher (1995). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer Academic Publishers. p. 374. ISBN 0-7923-2549-4.
  78. ^ "Max Tegmark on many-worlds (contains MWI poll)".
  79. ^ Caroll, Sean (1 April 2004). . Archived from the original on 8 September 2004.
  80. ^ Nielsen, Michael (3 April 2004). . Archived from the original on 20 May 2004.
  81. ^ Survey Results 2010-11-04 at the Wayback Machine
  82. ^ a b Schlosshauer, Maximilian; Kofler, Johannes; Zeilinger, Anton (2013). "A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 44 (3): 222–230. arXiv:1301.1069. Bibcode:2013SHPMP..44..222S. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2013.04.004. S2CID 55537196.
  83. ^ Aldhous, Peter (2007-11-24). "Parallel lives can never touch". New Scientist. No. 2631. Retrieved 2007-11-21.
  84. ^ a b Gardner, Martin (2003). Are universes thicker than blackberries?. W.W. Norton. p. 10. ISBN 978-0-393-05742-3.
  85. ^ Ferris, Timothy (1997). The Whole Shebang. Simon & Schuster. pp. 345. ISBN 978-0-684-81020-1.
  86. ^ Hawking, Stephen; Roger Penrose (1996). The Nature of Space and Time. Princeton University Press. pp. 121. ISBN 978-0-691-03791-2.
  87. ^ Halliwell, J. J.; Pérez-Mercader, J.; Zurek, Wojciech Hubert, eds. (1996). Physical origins of time asymmetry (1st paperback ed.). Cambridge [England]: Cambridge University Press. p. 231. ISBN 0-521-56837-4. OCLC 36415828.
  88. ^ Gell-Mann, Murray (1994). The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the Complex. New York: Owl Books. p. 138. ISBN 0-8050-7253-5. OCLC 56388449.
  89. ^ Tegmark, Max (November 1998). "Quantum immortality". Retrieved 25 October 2010.
  90. ^ Carroll, Sean (2019). "The Human Side - Living and Thinking in a Quantum Universe". Something Deeply Hidden: Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime. Penguin. ISBN 9781524743024. At Google Books.
  91. ^ Deutsch, David (2011). "The Beginning". The Beginning of Infinity. Penguin Group.
  92. ^ DeWitt, Bryce S. (1970). "Quantum mechanics and reality". Physics Today. 23 (9): 30–35. Bibcode:1970PhT....23i..30D. doi:10.1063/1.3022331.
  93. ^ Max Tegmark: "Max' multiverse FAQ: frequently asked questions" > "Multiverse philosophy" > "Will I rob a gas station?"

Further reading

  • Jeffrey A. Barrett, The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999.
  • Peter Byrne, The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III: Multiple Universes, Mutual Assured Destruction, and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family, Oxford University Press, 2010.
  • Jeffrey A. Barrett and Peter Byrne, eds., "The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Collected Works 1955–1980 with Commentary", Princeton University Press, 2012.
  • Julian Brown, Minds, Machines, and the Multiverse, Simon & Schuster, 2000, ISBN 0-684-81481-1
  • Sean M. Carroll, Something deeply hidden, Penguin Random House, (2019)
  • Paul C.W. Davies, Other Worlds, (1980) ISBN 0-460-04400-1
  • Osnaghi, Stefano; Freitas, Fabio; Olival Freire, Jr (2009). (PDF). Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 40 (2): 97–123. Bibcode:2009SHPMP..40...97O. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.3933. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2008.10.002. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-05-28. Retrieved 2009-08-07. A study of the painful three-way relationship between Hugh Everett, John A Wheeler and Niels Bohr and how this affected the early development of the many-worlds theory.
  • David Wallace, Worlds in the Everett Interpretation, Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 33, (2002), pp. 637–661, arXiv:quant-ph/0103092
  • John A. Wheeler and Wojciech Hubert Zurek (eds), Quantum Theory and Measurement, Princeton University Press, (1983), ISBN 0-691-08316-9

External links

many, worlds, interpretation, many, worlds, interpretation, interpretation, quantum, mechanics, that, asserts, that, universal, wavefunction, objectively, real, that, there, wave, function, collapse, this, implies, that, possible, outcomes, quantum, measuremen. The many worlds interpretation MWI is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that asserts that the universal wavefunction is objectively real and that there is no wave function collapse 2 This implies that all possible outcomes of quantum measurements are physically realized in some world or universe 3 In contrast to some other interpretations such as the Copenhagen interpretation the evolution of reality as a whole in MWI is rigidly deterministic 2 9 and local 4 Many worlds is also called the relative state formulation or the Everett interpretation after physicist Hugh Everett who first proposed it in 1957 5 6 Bryce DeWitt popularized the formulation and named it many worlds in the 1970s 1 2 7 8 The quantum mechanical Schrodinger s cat paradox according to the many worlds interpretation In this interpretation every quantum event is a branch point the cat is both alive and dead even before the box is opened but the alive and dead cats are in different branches of the multiverse both of which are equally real but which do not interact with each other a In many worlds the subjective appearance of wavefunction collapse is explained by the mechanism of quantum decoherence Decoherence approaches to interpreting quantum theory have been widely explored and developed since the 1970s 9 10 11 and have become quite popular MWI is now considered a mainstream interpretation along with the other decoherence interpretations collapse theories including the Copenhagen interpretation and hidden variable theories such as Bohmian mechanics The many worlds interpretation implies that there are most likely an uncountably infinite number of universes 12 It is one of a number of multiverse hypotheses in physics and philosophy MWI views time as a many branched tree wherein every possible quantum outcome is realised This is intended to resolve the measurement problem and thus some paradoxes of quantum theory such as the EPR paradox 6 462 2 118 and Schrodinger s cat 1 since every possible outcome of a quantum event exists in its own universe Contents 1 Overview of the interpretation 1 1 Formulation 1 2 Relative state 1 3 Properties 1 4 Interpreting wavefunction collapse 1 5 Testability 2 Probability and the Born rule 2 1 Frequentism 2 2 Decision theory 2 3 Symmetries and invariance 3 The preferred basis problem 4 History 5 Reception 5 1 Support 5 2 Equivocal 5 3 Rejection 5 4 Polls 6 Debate whether the other worlds are real 7 Speculative implications 7 1 Quantum suicide thought experiment 7 2 Absurdly improbable timelines 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further reading 12 External linksOverview of the interpretation EditThe key idea of the many worlds interpretation is that the unitary dynamics of quantum mechanics applies everywhere and at all times and so describes the whole universe In particular it models a measurement as a unitary transformation a correlation inducing interaction between observer and object without using a collapse postulate and models observers as ordinary quantum mechanical systems 13 35 38 This stands in sharp contrast to the Copenhagen interpretation in which a measurement is a primitive concept not describable by unitary quantum mechanics in Copenhagen the universe is divided into a quantum and a classical domain and the collapse postulate is central 13 29 30 MWI s main conclusion is that the universe or multiverse in this context is composed of a quantum superposition of an infinite 12 or undefinable 14 14 17 amount or number of increasingly divergent non communicating parallel universes or quantum worlds 2 Sometimes dubbed Everett worlds 2 234 each is a consistent and actualized alternative history or timeline The many worlds interpretation makes use of decoherence to explain the measurement process and the emergence of a quasi classical world 14 15 Wojciech H Zurek one of decoherence theory s pioneers stated Under scrutiny of the environment only pointer states remain unchanged Other states decohere into mixtures of stable pointer states that can persist and in this sense exist They are einselected 16 Zurek emphasizes that his work does not depend on a particular interpretation b The many worlds interpretation shares many similarities with the decoherent histories interpretation which also uses decoherence to explain the process of measurement or wavefunction collapse 15 9 11 MWI treats the other histories or worlds as real since it regards the universal wavefunction as the basic physical entity 6 455 or the fundamental entity obeying at all times a deterministic wave equation 5 115 Decoherent histories on the other hand needs only one of the histories or worlds to be real 15 10 Several authors including Wheeler Everett and Deutsch call many worlds a theory or metatheory rather than just an interpretation 12 17 328 Everett argued that it was the only completely coherent approach to explaining both the contents of quantum mechanics and the appearance of the world 18 Deutsch dismissed the idea that many worlds is an interpretation saying that to call it an interpretation is like talking about dinosaurs as an interpretation of fossil records 19 382 Formulation Edit In his 1957 doctoral dissertation Everett proposed that rather than relying on external observation for analysis of isolated quantum systems one could mathematically model an object as well as its observers as purely physical systems within the mathematical framework developed by Paul Dirac John von Neumann and others discarding altogether the ad hoc mechanism of wave function collapse 5 2 Relative state Edit Everett s original work introduced the concept of a relative state Two or more subsystems after a general interaction become entangled Everett noted that such entangled systems can be expressed as the sum of products of states where the two or more subsystems are each in a state relative to each other After a measurement or observation one of the pair or triple is the measured object or observed system and one other member is the measuring apparatus which may include an observer having recorded the state of the measured system In the example of Schrodinger s cat after the box is opened the entangled system is the cat the poison vial and the observer One relative triple of states would be the alive cat the unbroken vial and the observer seeing an alive cat Another relative triple of states would be the dead cat the broken vial and the observer seeing a dead cat The process of measurement or observation or any correlation inducing interaction splits the system up into sets of relative states where each set of relative states forming a branch of the universal wavefunction is consistent within itself and all future measurements including by multiple observers will confirm this consistency The many worlds interpretation is DeWitt s popularisation of Everett who had referred to the combined observer object system as split by an observation each split corresponding to the different or multiple possible outcomes of an observation These splits generate a branching tree where each branch is a set of all the states relative to each other DeWitt introduced the term world to describe a single branch of that tree which is a consistent history All observations or measurements in any branch are consistent with each other 5 2 Under the many worlds interpretation the Schrodinger equation or its quantum field theory relativistic analog holds all the time everywhere An observation or measurement is modelled by applying the wave equation to the entire system comprising the observer and the object being observed One consequence is that every observation can be thought of as causing the combined observer object s wavefunction to change into a quantum superposition of two or more non interacting branches or split into many worlds Since many observation like events have happened and are constantly happening there are an enormous and growing number of simultaneously existing states If a system is composed of two or more subsystems the system s state will be a superposition of products of the subsystems states Each product of subsystem states in the overall superposition evolves over time independently of other products Once the subsystems interact their states have become correlated or entangled and can no longer be considered independent In Everett s terminology each subsystem state was now correlated with its relative state since each subsystem must now be considered relative to the other subsystems with which it has interacted Properties Edit MWI removes the observer dependent role in the quantum measurement process by replacing wavefunction collapse with quantum decoherence 16 Since the observer s role lies at the heart of most if not all quantum paradoxes this automatically resolves a number of problems such as Schrodinger s cat thought experiment the EPR paradox von Neumann s boundary problem and others 6 Since the Copenhagen interpretation requires the existence of a classical domain beyond the one described by quantum mechanics it has been criticized as inadequate for the study of cosmology 20 MWI was developed with the explicit goal of allowing quantum mechanics to be applied to the universe as a whole making quantum cosmology possible 6 MWI is a realist deterministic and local theory It achieves this by removing wave function collapse which is indeterministic and nonlocal from the deterministic and local equations of quantum theory 4 MWI like other broader multiverse theories provides a context for the anthropic principle which may provide an explanation for the fine tuned universe 21 22 MWI depends crucially on the linearity of quantum mechanics which underpins the superposition principle If the final theory of everything is non linear with respect to wavefunctions then many worlds is invalid 1 2 6 7 8 All quantum field theories are linear and compatible with the MWI a point emphasised by Everett as a motivation for the MWI 6 While quantum gravity or string theory may be non linear in this respect 23 there is as yet no evidence of this 24 25 Interpreting wavefunction collapse Edit As with the other interpretations of quantum mechanics the many worlds interpretation is motivated by behavior that can be illustrated by the double slit experiment When particles of light or anything else pass through the double slit a calculation assuming wavelike behavior of light can be used to identify where the particles are likely to be observed Yet when the particles are observed in this experiment they appear as particles i e at definite places and not as non localized waves Some versions of the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics proposed a process of collapse in which an indeterminate quantum system would probabilistically collapse down onto or select just one determinate outcome to explain this phenomenon of observation Wavefunction collapse was widely regarded as artificial and ad hoc 26 so an alternative interpretation in which the behavior of measurement could be understood from more fundamental physical principles was considered desirable Everett s PhD work provided such an interpretation He argued that for a composite system such as a subject the observer or measuring apparatus observing an object the observed system such as a particle the claim that either the observer or the observed has a well defined state is meaningless in modern parlance the observer and the observed have become entangled we can only specify the state of one relative to the other i e the state of the observer and the observed are correlated after the observation is made This led Everett to derive from the unitary deterministic dynamics alone i e without assuming wavefunction collapse the notion of a relativity of states Everett noticed that the unitary deterministic dynamics alone entailed that after an observation is made each element of the quantum superposition of the combined subject object wavefunction contains two relative states a collapsed object state and an associated observer who has observed the same collapsed outcome what the observer sees and the state of the object have become correlated by the act of measurement or observation The subsequent evolution of each pair of relative subject object states proceeds with complete indifference as to the presence or absence of the other elements as if wavefunction collapse has occurred 2 67 78 which has the consequence that later observations are always consistent with the earlier observations Thus the appearance of the object s wavefunction s collapse has emerged from the unitary deterministic theory itself This answered Einstein s early criticism of quantum theory that the theory should define what is observed not for the observables to define the theory c Since the wavefunction merely appears to have collapsed then Everett reasoned there was no need to actually assume that it had collapsed And so invoking Occam s razor he removed the postulate of wavefunction collapse from the theory 2 8 Testability Edit In 1985 David Deutsch proposed a variant of the Wigner s friend thought experiment as a test of many worlds versus the Copenhagen interpretation 28 It consists of an experimenter Wigner s friend making a measurement on a quantum system in an isolated laboratory and another experimenter Wigner who would make a measurement on the first one According to the many worlds theory the first experimenter would end up in a macroscopic superposition of seeing one result of the measurement in one branch and another result in another branch The second experimenter could then interfere these two branches in order to test whether it is in fact in a macroscopic superposition or has collapsed into a single branch as predicted by the Copenhagen interpretation Since then Lockwood 1989 Vaidman and others have made similar proposals 29 These proposals require placing macroscopic objects in a coherent superposition and interfering them a task currently beyond experimental capability Probability and the Born rule EditSince the many worlds interpretation s inception physicists have been puzzled about the role of probability in it As put by Wallace there are two facets to the question 30 the incoherence problem which asks why we should assign probabilities at all to outcomes that are certain to occur in some worlds and the quantitative problem which asks why the probabilities should be given by the Born rule Everett tried to answer these questions in the paper that introduced many worlds To address the incoherence problem he argued that an observer who makes a sequence of measurements on a quantum system will in general have an apparently random sequence of results in their memory which justifies the use of probabilities to describe the measurement process 5 69 70 To address the quantitative problem Everett proposed a derivation of the Born rule based on the properties that a measure on the branches of the wavefunction should have 5 70 72 His derivation has been criticized as relying on unmotivated assumptions 31 Since then several other derivations of the Born rule in the many worlds framework have been proposed There is no consensus on whether this has been successful 32 33 34 Frequentism Edit DeWitt and Graham 2 and Farhi et al 35 among others have proposed derivations of the Born rule based on a frequentist interpretation of probability They try to show that in the limit of infinitely many measurements no worlds would have relative frequencies that didn t match the probabilities given by the Born rule but these derivations have been shown to be mathematically incorrect 36 37 Decision theory Edit A decision theoretic derivation of the Born rule was produced by David Deutsch 1999 38 and refined by Wallace 2002 2009 30 39 40 41 and Saunders 2004 42 43 They consider an agent who takes part in a quantum gamble the agent makes a measurement on a quantum system branches as a consequence and each of the agent s future selves receives a reward that depends on the measurement result The agent uses decision theory to evaluate the price they would pay to take part in such a gamble and concludes that the price is given by the utility of the rewards weighted according to the Born rule Some reviews have been positive although these arguments remain highly controversial some theoretical physicists have taken them as supporting the case for parallel universes 44 For example a New Scientist story on a 2007 conference about Everettian interpretations 45 quoted physicist Andy Albrecht as saying This work will go down as one of the most important developments in the history of science 44 In contrast the philosopher Huw Price also attending the conference found the Deutsch Wallace Saunders approach fundamentally flawed 46 Symmetries and invariance Edit Zurek 2005 47 has produced a derivation of the Born rule based on the symmetries of entangled states Schlosshauer and Fine argue that Zurek s derivation is not rigorous as it does not define what probability is and has several unstated assumptions about how it should behave 48 Charles Sebens and Sean M Carroll building on work by Lev Vaidman 49 proposed a similar approach based on self locating uncertainty 50 In this approach decoherence creates multiple identical copies of observers who can assign credences to being on different branches using the Born rule The Sebens Carroll approach has been criticized by Adrian Kent 51 and Vaidman himself does not find it satisfactory 52 The preferred basis problem EditAs originally formulated by Everett and DeWitt the many worlds interpretation had a privileged role for measurements they determined which basis of a quantum system would give rise to the eponymous worlds Without this the theory was ambiguous as a quantum state can equally well be described e g as having a well defined position or as being a superposition of two delocalised states The assumption is that the preferred basis to use is the one which assigns a unique measurement outcome to each world This special role for measurements is problematic for the theory as it contradicts Everett and DeWitt s goal of having a reductionist theory and undermines their criticism of the ill defined measurement postulate of the Copenhagen interpretation 17 31 This is known today as the preferred basis problem The preferred basis problem has been solved according to Saunders and Wallace among others 15 by incorporating decoherence into the many worlds theory 20 53 54 55 In this approach the preferred basis does not have to be postulated but rather is identified as the basis stable under environmental decoherence In this way measurements no longer play a special role rather any interaction that causes decoherence causes the world to split Since decoherence is never complete there will always remain some infinitesimal overlap between two worlds making it arbitrary whether a pair of worlds has split or not 56 Wallace argues that this is not problematic it only shows that worlds are not a part of the fundamental ontology but rather of the emergent ontology where these approximate effective descriptions are routine in the physical sciences 57 14 Since in this approach the worlds are derived it follows that they must be present in any other interpretation of quantum mechanics that does not have a collapse mechanism such as Bohmian mechanics 58 This approach to deriving the preferred basis has been criticized as creating a circularity with derivations of probability in the many worlds interpretation as decoherence theory depends on probability and probability depends on the ontology derived from decoherence 33 47 59 Wallace contends that decoherence theory depends not on probability but only on the notion that one is allowed to do approximations in physics 13 253 254 History EditMWI originated in Everett s Princeton PhD thesis The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction 2 developed under his thesis advisor John Archibald Wheeler a shorter summary of which was published in 1957 under the title Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics Wheeler contributed the title relative state 60 Everett originally called his approach the Correlation Interpretation where correlation refers to quantum entanglement The phrase many worlds is due to Bryce DeWitt 2 who was responsible for the wider popularisation of Everett s theory which had been largely ignored for a decade after publication in 1957 12 Everett s proposal was not without precedent In 1952 Erwin Schrodinger gave a lecture in Dublin in which at one point he jocularly warned his audience that what he was about to say might seem lunatic He went on to assert that while the Schrodinger equation seemed to be describing several different histories they were not alternatives but all really happen simultaneously According to David Deutsch this is the earliest known reference to many worlds Jeffrey A Barrett describes it as indicating the similarity of general views between Everett and Schrodinger 61 62 63 Schrodinger s writings from the period also contain elements resembling the modal interpretation originated by Bas van Fraassen Because Schrodinger subscribed to a kind of post Machian neutral monism in which matter and mind are only different aspects or arrangements of the same common elements treating the wavefunction as physical and treating it as information became interchangeable 64 Reception EditMWI s initial reception was overwhelmingly negative in the sense that it was ignored with the notable exception of DeWitt Wheeler made considerable efforts to formulate the theory in a way that would be palatable to Bohr visited Copenhagen in 1956 to discuss it with him and convinced Everett to visit as well which happened in 1959 Nevertheless Bohr and his collaborators completely rejected the theory d Everett had already left academia in 1956 never to return and after his death Wheeler disavowed the theory 12 Support Edit One of MWI s strongest longtime advocates is David Deutsch 65 According to Deutsch the single photon interference pattern observed in the double slit experiment can be explained by interference of photons in multiple universes Viewed this way the single photon interference experiment is indistinguishable from the multiple photon interference experiment In a more practical vein in one of the earliest papers on quantum computing 66 he suggested that parallelism that results from MWI could lead to a method by which certain probabilistic tasks can be performed faster by a universal quantum computer than by any classical restriction of it Deutsch has also proposed that MWI will be testable at least against naive Copenhagenism when reversible computers become conscious via the reversible observation of spin 67 Equivocal Edit Philosophers of science James Ladyman and Don Ross say that the MWI could be true but that they do not embrace it They note that no quantum theory is yet empirically adequate for describing all of reality given its lack of unification with general relativity and so they do not see a reason to regard any interpretation of quantum mechanics as the final word in metaphysics They also suggest that the multiple branches may be an artifact of incomplete descriptions and of using quantum mechanics to represent the states of macroscopic objects They argue that macroscopic objects are significantly different from microscopic objects in not being isolated from the environment and that using quantum formalism to describe them lacks explanatory and descriptive power and accuracy 68 Victor J Stenger remarked that Murray Gell Mann s published work explicitly rejects the existence of simultaneous parallel universes 69 Collaborating with James Hartle Gell Mann worked toward the development a more palatable post Everett quantum mechanics Stenger thought it fair to say that most physicists find the MWI too extreme while noting it has merit in finding a place for the observer inside the system being analyzed and doing away with the troublesome notion of wave function collapse e Richard Feynman described as an Everettian in some sources 70 said of the MWI in 1982 It s possible but I m not very happy with it 71 Rejection Edit Some scientists consider MWI unfalsifiable and hence unscientific because the multiple parallel universes are non communicating in the sense that no information can be passed between them 72 73 Others claim MWI is directly testable 67 Roger Penrose argues that the idea is flawed because it is based on an oversimplified version of quantum mechanics that does not account for gravity In his view applying conventional quantum mechanics to the universe implies the MWI but the lack of a successful theory of quantum gravity negates the claimed universality of conventional quantum mechanics 23 According to Penrose the rules must change when gravity is involved He further asserts that gravity helps anchor reality and blurry events have only one allowable outcome electrons atoms molecules etc are so minute that they require almost no amount of energy to maintain their gravity and therefore their overlapping states They can stay in that state forever as described in standard quantum theory On the other hand in the case of large objects the duplicate states disappear in an instant due to the fact that these objects create a large gravitational field 74 75 Philosopher of science Robert P Crease says that the MWI is one of the most implausible and unrealistic ideas in the history of science because it means that everything conceivable happens 74 Science writer Philip Ball describes the MWI s implications as fantasies since beneath their apparel of scientific equations or symbolic logic they are acts of imagination of just supposing 74 Theoretical physicist Gerard t Hooft also dismisses the idea I do not believe that we have to live with the many worlds interpretation Indeed it would be a stupendous number of parallel worlds which are only there because physicists couldn t decide which of them is real 76 Asher Peres was an outspoken critic of MWI A section of his 1993 textbook had the title Everett s interpretation and other bizarre theories Peres argued that the various many worlds interpretations merely shift the arbitrariness or vagueness of the collapse postulate to the question of when worlds can be regarded as separate and that no objective criterion for that separation can actually be formulated 77 Polls Edit A poll of 72 leading quantum cosmologists and other quantum field theorists conducted before 1991 by L David Raub showed 58 agreement with Yes I think MWI is true 70 Max Tegmark reports the result of a highly unscientific poll taken at a 1997 quantum mechanics workshop According to Tegmark The many worlds interpretation MWI scored second comfortably ahead of the consistent histories and Bohm interpretations 78 In response to Sean M Carroll s statement As crazy as it sounds most working physicists buy into the many worlds theory 79 Michael Nielsen counters at a quantum computing conference at Cambridge in 1998 a many worlder surveyed the audience of approximately 200 people Many worlds did just fine garnering support on a level comparable to but somewhat below Copenhagen and decoherence But Nielsen notes that it seemed most attendees found it to be a waste of time Peres got a huge and sustained round of applause when he got up at the end of the polling and asked And who here believes the laws of physics are decided by a democratic vote 80 A 2005 poll of fewer than 40 students and researchers taken after a course on the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics at the Institute for Quantum Computing University of Waterloo found Many Worlds and decoherence to be the least favored 81 A 2011 poll of 33 participants at an Austrian conference found 6 endorsed MWI 8 Information based information theoretical and 14 Copenhagen 82 the authors remark that MWI received a similar percentage of votes as in Tegmark s 1997 poll 82 Debate whether the other worlds are real EditEverett believed in the literal reality of the other quantum worlds 19 His son reported that he never wavered in his belief over his many worlds theory 83 According to Martin Gardner the other worlds of MWI have two different interpretations real or unreal he claimed that Stephen Hawking and Steven Weinberg both favour the unreal interpretation 84 Gardner also claimed that most physicists favour the unreal interpretation whereas the realist view is supported only by MWI experts such as Deutsch and DeWitt Gardner reports Hawking saying that MWI is trivially true 84 In a 1983 interview Hawking also said he regarded MWI as self evidently correct but was dismissive of questions about the interpretation of quantum mechanics saying When I hear of Schrodinger s cat I reach for my gun In the same interview he also said But look All that one does really is to calculate conditional probabilities in other words the probability of A happening given B I think that that s all the many worlds interpretation is Some people overlay it with a lot of mysticism about the wave function splitting into different parts But all that you re calculating is conditional probabilities 85 Elsewhere Hawking contrasted his attitude towards the reality of physical theories with that of his colleague Roger Penrose saying He s a Platonist and I m a positivist He s worried that Schrodinger s cat is in a quantum state where it is half alive and half dead He feels that can t correspond to reality But that doesn t bother me I don t demand that a theory correspond to reality because I don t know what it is Reality is not a quality you can test with litmus paper All I m concerned with is that the theory should predict the results of measurements Quantum theory does this very successfully 86 Gell Mann described himself as a post Everett investigator 87 and wrote it is not necessary to become queasy trying to conceive of many parallel universes all equally real Instead he advocated the language of many histories all treated alike by the theory except for their different probabilities 88 Speculative implications EditQuantum suicide thought experiment Edit Main article Quantum suicide and immortality Quantum suicide is a thought experiment in quantum mechanics and the philosophy of physics Purportedly it can distinguish between the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics and the many worlds interpretation by means of a variation of the Schrodinger s cat thought experiment from the cat s point of view Quantum immortality refers to the subjective experience of surviving quantum suicide 89 Most experts believe that the experiment would not work in the real world because the world with the surviving experimenter has a lower measure than the world before the experiment making it less likely that the experimenter will experience their survival 13 371 29 90 91 Absurdly improbable timelines Edit DeWitt has stated that Everett Wheeler and Graham do not in the end exclude any element of the superposition All the worlds are there even those in which everything goes wrong and all the statistical laws break down 92 Max Tegmark has affirmed that absurd or highly unlikely events are inevitable but rare under MWI To quote Tegmark Things inconsistent with the laws of physics will never happen everything else will it s important to keep track of the statistics since even if everything conceivable happens somewhere really freak events happen only exponentially rarely 93 Ladyman and Ross state that in general many of the unrealized possibilities that are discussed in other scientific fields will not have counterparts in other branches because they are in fact incompatible with the universal wavefunction 68 See also EditConsistent histories Many minds interpretation The Garden of Forking Paths Parallel universes in fiction The Beginning of Infinity Mathematical universe hypothesisNotes Edit every quantum transition taking place on every star in every galaxy in every remote corner of the universe is splitting our local world on earth into myriads of copies of itself 1 Relative states of Everett come to mind One could speculate about reality of branches with other outcomes We abstain from this our discussion is interpretation free and this is a virtue 16 Whether you can observe a thing or not depends on the theory which you use It is the theory which decides what can be observed Albert Einstein to Werner Heisenberg objecting to placing observables at the heart of the new quantum mechanics during Heisenberg s 1926 lecture at Berlin related by Heisenberg in 1968 27 Everett recounted his meeting with Bohr as that was a hell doomed from the beginning Leon Rosenfeld a close collaborator of Bohr said With regard to Everett neither I nor even Niels Bohr could have any patience with him when he visited us in Copenhagen more than 12 years ago in order to sell the hopelessly wrong ideas he had been encouraged most unwisely by Wheeler to develop He was undescribably stupid and could not understand the simplest things in quantum mechanics 12 113 Gell Mann and Hartle along with a score of others have been working to develop a more palatable interpretation of quantum mechanics that is free of the problems that plague all the interpretations we have considered so far This new interpretation is called in its various incarnations post Everett quantum mechanics alternate histories consistent histories or decoherent histories I will not be overly concerned with the detailed differences between these characterizations and will use the terms more or less interchangeably 69 176 References Edit a b c d Bryce S DeWitt 1970 Quantum mechanics and reality Physics Today 23 9 30 35 Bibcode 1970PhT 23i 30D doi 10 1063 1 3022331 See also Leslie E Ballentine Philip Pearle Evan Harris Walker Mendel Sachs Toyoki Koga Joseph Gerver Bryce DeWitt 1971 Quantum mechanics debate Physics Today 24 4 36 44 Bibcode 1971PhT 24d 36 doi 10 1063 1 3022676 a b c d e f g h i j k l m n Everett Hugh Wheeler J A DeWitt B S Cooper L N Van Vechten D Graham N 1973 DeWitt Bryce Graham R Neill eds The Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Princeton Series in Physics Princeton NJ Princeton University Press p v ISBN 0 691 08131 X Tegmark Max 1998 The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Many Worlds or Many Words Fortschritte der Physik 46 6 8 855 862 arXiv quant ph 9709032 Bibcode 1998ForPh 46 855T doi 10 1002 SICI 1521 3978 199811 46 6 8 lt 855 AID PROP855 gt 3 0 CO 2 Q S2CID 212466 a b Harvey R Brown Christopher G Timpson 2016 Bell on Bell s Theorem The Changing Face of Nonlocality In Mary Bell Shan Gao eds Quantum Nonlocality and Reality 50 years of Bell s theorem Cambridge University Press pp 91 123 arXiv 1501 03521 doi 10 1017 CBO9781316219393 008 ISBN 9781316219393 S2CID 118686956 On locality Amongst those who have taken Everett s approach to quantum theory at all seriously as an option it is a commonplace that given an Everettian interpretation quantum theory is dynamically local there is no action at a distance on determinism But zooming out in a God s eye view from a particular branch will be seen all the other branches each with a different result of measurement being recorded and observed all coexisting equally and all underpinned by supervenient on the deterministically unitarily evolving universal wavefunction a b c d e f Hugh Everett Theory of the Universal Wavefunction Thesis Princeton University 1956 1973 pp 1 140 a b c d e f g Everett Hugh 1957 Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics Reviews of Modern Physics 29 3 454 462 Bibcode 1957RvMP 29 454E doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 29 454 Archived from the original on 2011 10 27 Retrieved 2011 10 24 a b Cecile M DeWitt John A Wheeler eds The Everett Wheeler Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Battelle Rencontres 1967 Lectures in Mathematics and Physics 1968 a b Bryce Seligman DeWitt The Many Universes Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Proceedings of the International School of Physics Enrico Fermi Course IL Foundations of Quantum Mechanics Academic Press 1972 H Dieter Zeh On the Interpretation of Measurement in Quantum Theory Foundations of Physics vol 1 pp 69 76 1970 Wojciech Hubert Zurek Decoherence and the transition from quantum to classical Physics Today vol 44 issue 10 pp 36 44 1991 Wojciech Hubert Zurek Decoherence einselection and the quantum origins of the classical Reviews of Modern Physics 75 pp 715 775 2003 a b c d e f Osnaghi Stefano Freitas Fabio Olival Freire Jr 2009 The Origin of the Everettian Heresy Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 2 97 123 Bibcode 2009SHPMP 40 97O CiteSeerX 10 1 1 397 3933 doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2008 10 002 a b c d Wallace David 2012 The Emergent Multiverse Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 954696 1 a b c David Wallace 2010 Decoherence and Ontology or How I Learned To Stop Worrying And Love FAPP In S Saunders J Barrett A Kent D Wallace eds Many Worlds Everett Quantum Theory and Reality Oxford University Press arXiv 1111 2189 a b c d Saunders Simon 2010 Many Worlds An Introduction In S Saunders J Barrett A Kent D Wallace eds Many Worlds Everett Quantum Theory and Reality PDF Oxford University Press a b c Zurek Wojciech March 2009 Quantum Darwinism Nature Physics 5 3 181 188 arXiv 0903 5082 Bibcode 2009NatPh 5 181Z doi 10 1038 nphys1202 S2CID 119205282 a b Brian Skyrms 1976 Possible Worlds Physics and Metaphysics Philosophical Studies 30 5 323 332 doi 10 1007 BF00357930 S2CID 170852547 Letter from Everett to David Raub 1980 04 07 UCI Accessed 12 April 2020 a b Peter Byrne 2010 The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III Multiple Universes Mutual Assured Destruction and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 955227 6 a b M Gell Mann J B Hartle 1990 Quantum mechanics in the light of quantum cosmology In W H Zurek ed Complexity Entropy and the Physics of Information Addison Wesley arXiv 1803 04605 Paul C W Davies Other Worlds chapters 8 amp 9 The Anthropic Principle amp Is the Universe an accident 1980 ISBN 0 460 04400 1 Paul C W Davies The Accidental Universe 1982 ISBN 0 521 28692 1 a b Penrose Roger August 1991 Roger Penrose Looks Beyond the Classic Quantum Dichotomy Sciencewatch Archived from the original on 2007 10 23 Retrieved 2007 10 21 Steven Weinberg Dreams of a Final Theory The Search for the Fundamental Laws of Nature 1993 ISBN 0 09 922391 0 pg 68 69 Steven Weinberg Testing Quantum Mechanics Annals of Physics Vol 194 2 1989 pg 336 386 Wimmel Hermann Quantum Physics And Observed Reality A Critical Interpretation Of Quantum Mechanics p 45 World Scientific May 26 1992 Abdus Salam Unification of Fundamental Forces Cambridge University Press 1990 ISBN 0 521 37140 6 pp 98 101 Deutsch D 1985 Quantum theory as a universal physical theory International Journal of Theoretical Physics 24 1 1 41 Bibcode 1985IJTP 24 1D doi 10 1007 BF00670071 S2CID 17530632 a b Vaidman Lev 2018 Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Wallace David 2003 Everettian Rationality defending Deutsch s approach to probability in the Everett interpretation Stud Hist Phil Mod Phys 34 3 415 438 arXiv quant ph 0303050 Bibcode 2003SHPMP 34 415W doi 10 1016 S1355 2198 03 00036 4 S2CID 1921913 a b L E Ballentine 1973 Can the statistical postulate of quantum theory be derived A critique of the many universes interpretation Foundations of Physics 3 2 229 240 Bibcode 1973FoPh 3 229B doi 10 1007 BF00708440 S2CID 121747282 N P Landsman The conclusion seems to be that no generally accepted derivation of the Born rule has been given to date but this does not imply that such a derivation is impossible in principle in Compendium of Quantum Physics eds F Weinert K Hentschel D Greenberger and B Falkenburg Springer 2008 ISBN 3 540 70622 4 a b Kent Adrian 2010 One world versus many The inadequacy of Everettian accounts of evolution probability and scientific confirmation In S Saunders J Barrett A Kent D Wallace eds Many Worlds Everett Quantum Theory and Reality Oxford University Press arXiv 0905 0624 Bibcode 2009arXiv0905 0624K Kent Adrian 1990 Against Many Worlds Interpretations Int J Mod Phys A 5 9 1745 1762 arXiv gr qc 9703089 Bibcode 1990IJMPA 5 1745K doi 10 1142 S0217751X90000805 S2CID 14523184 Edward Farhi Jeffrey Goldstone Sam Gutmann 1989 How probability arises in quantum mechanics Annals of Physics 192 2 368 382 Bibcode 1989AnPhy 192 368F doi 10 1016 0003 4916 89 90141 3 Benioff Paul October 1978 A note on the Everett interpretation of quantum mechanics Foundations of Physics 8 9 10 709 720 Bibcode 1978FoPh 8 709B doi 10 1007 BF00717501 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 123279967 Carlton M Caves Rudiger Schack 2005 Properties of the frequency operator do not imply the quantum probability postulate Annals of Physics 315 1 123 146 arXiv quant ph 0409144 Bibcode 2005AnPhy 315 123C doi 10 1016 j aop 2004 09 009 S2CID 33263618 Deutsch David 1999 Quantum Theory of Probability and Decisions Proceedings of the Royal Society A Mathematical Physical and Engineering Sciences 455 1988 3129 3137 arXiv quant ph 9906015 Bibcode 1999RSPSA 455 3129D doi 10 1098 rspa 1999 0443 S2CID 5217034 Wallace David 2002 Quantum Probability and Decision Theory Revisited arXiv quant ph 0211104 Wallace David 2003 Quantum Probability from Subjective Likelihood Improving on Deutsch s proof of the probability rule arXiv quant ph 0312157 Wallace David 2009 A formal proof of the Born rule from decision theoretic assumptions arXiv 0906 2718 quant ph Saunders Simon 2004 Derivation of the Born rule from operational assumptions Proc R Soc Lond A 460 2046 1771 1788 arXiv quant ph 0211138 Bibcode 2004RSPSA 460 1771S doi 10 1098 rspa 2003 1230 S2CID 1459183 Saunders Simon 2004 What is Probability Quo Vadis Quantum Mechanics The Frontiers Collection pp 209 238 arXiv quant ph 0412194 doi 10 1007 3 540 26669 0 12 ISBN 978 3 540 22188 3 S2CID 117218061 a b Merali Zeeya 2007 09 21 Parallel universes make quantum sense New Scientist No 2622 Retrieved 2013 11 22 Summary only Perimeter Institute Many worlds at 50 conference September 21 24 2007 Videos Price Huw 2010 Decisions Decisions Decisions Can Savage Salvage Everettian Probability In S Saunders J Barrett A Kent D Wallace eds Many Worlds Everett Quantum Theory and Reality Oxford University Press arXiv 0802 1390 a b Zurek Wojciech H 2005 Probabilities from entanglement Born s rule from envariance Phys Rev A 71 5 052105 arXiv quant ph 0405161 Bibcode 2005PhRvA 71e2105Z doi 10 1103 physreva 71 052105 S2CID 18210481 Schlosshauer M Fine A 2005 On Zurek s derivation of the Born rule Found Phys 35 2 197 213 arXiv quant ph 0312058 Bibcode 2005FoPh 35 197S doi 10 1007 s10701 004 1941 6 S2CID 119100306 Vaidman L Probability in the Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics In Ben Menahem Y amp Hemmo M eds The Probable and the Improbable Understanding Probability in Physics Essays in Memory of Itamar Pitowsky Springer Sebens Charles T Carroll Sean M 2016 Self Locating Uncertainty and the Origin of Probability in Everettian Quantum Mechanics The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 69 1 25 74 arXiv 1405 7577 doi 10 1093 bjps axw004 S2CID 53648469 Kent Adrian February 2015 Does it Make Sense to Speak of Self Locating Uncertainty in the Universal Wave Function Remarks on Sebens and Carroll Foundations of Physics 45 2 211 217 arXiv 1408 1944 Bibcode 2015FoPh 45 211K doi 10 1007 s10701 014 9862 5 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 118471198 Vaidman Lev 2020 Derivations of the Born Rule In Meir Hemmo Orly Shenker eds Quantum Probability Logic Itamar Pitowsky s Work and Influence Springer Nature Switzerland PhilSci 15943 Simon Saunders 1993 Decoherence relative states and evolutionary adaptation Foundations of Physics 23 12 1553 1585 Bibcode 1993FoPh 23 1553S doi 10 1007 BF00732365 S2CID 119754481 Simon Saunders 1995 Time quantum mechanics and decoherence PDF Synthese 102 2 235 266 doi 10 1007 BF01089802 S2CID 14550985 James B Hartle 2011 The quasiclassical realms of this quantum universe Foundations of Physics 41 6 982 1006 arXiv 0806 3776 Bibcode 2011FoPh 41 982H doi 10 1007 s10701 010 9460 0 S2CID 118469123 Stapp Henry 2002 The basis problem in many world theories PDF Canadian Journal of Physics 80 9 1043 1052 arXiv quant ph 0110148 Bibcode 2002CaJPh 80 1043S doi 10 1139 p02 068 S2CID 18634782 David Wallace 2003 Everett and structure Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 34 1 87 105 arXiv quant ph 0107144 Bibcode 2003SHPMP 34 87W doi 10 1016 S1355 2198 02 00085 0 S2CID 15222560 Brown Harvey R Wallace David 2005 Solving the measurement problem de Broglie Bohm loses out to Everett PDF Foundations of Physics 35 4 517 540 arXiv quant ph 0403094 Bibcode 2005FoPh 35 517B doi 10 1007 s10701 004 2009 3 S2CID 412240 David J Baker 2007 Measurement outcomes and probability in Everettian quantum mechanics PDF Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 38 1 153 169 Bibcode 2007SHPMP 38 153B doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2006 05 003 Wheeler John Archibald 2000 Geons Black Holes and Quantum Foam W W Norton amp Company pp 268 270 ISBN 0 393 31991 1 Deutsch David 2010 Apart from Universes In S Saunders J Barrett A Kent D Wallace eds Many Worlds Everett Quantum Theory and Reality Oxford University Press Schrodinger Erwin 1996 Bitbol Michel ed The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Dublin Seminars 1949 1955 and other unpublished essays OxBow Press Barrett Jeffrey A 1999 The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds Oxford University Press ISBN 9780191583254 Bitbol Michel 1996 Schrodinger s Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics Dordrecht Springer Netherlands ISBN 978 94 009 1772 9 OCLC 851376153 David Deutsch The Fabric of Reality The Science of Parallel Universes And Its Implications Penguin Books 1998 ISBN 0 14 027541 X Deutsch David 1985 Quantum theory the Church Turing principle and the universal quantum computer Proceedings of the Royal Society of London A 400 1818 97 117 Bibcode 1985RSPSA 400 97D CiteSeerX 10 1 1 144 7936 doi 10 1098 rspa 1985 0070 S2CID 1438116 a b Paul C W Davies J R Brown The Ghost in the Atom 1986 ISBN 0 521 31316 3 pp 34 38 The Many Universes Interpretation pp 83 105 for David Deutsch s test of MWI and reversible quantum memories a b Ladyman James Ross Don 2007 Every Thing Must Go Metaphysics Naturalized Clarendon Press pp 179 183 ISBN 978 0 19 927619 6 a b Stenger V J 1995 The Unconscious Quantum Metaphysics in Modern Physics and Cosmology Prometheus Books ISBN 978 1 57392 022 3 LCCN lc95032599 a b Tipler Frank 1994 The Physics of Immortality pp 170 171 In the yes column were Stephen Hawking Richard Feynman and Murray Gell Mann Feynman Richard P June 1982 Simulating physics with computers International Journal of Theoretical Physics 21 6 7 467 488 Bibcode 1982IJTP 21 467F doi 10 1007 BF02650179 ISSN 0020 7748 S2CID 124545445 Bunge M 2012 Parallel Universes Digital Physics Evaluating Philosophies Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science Vol 295 New York Springer pp 152 153 doi 10 1007 978 94 007 4408 0 ISBN 978 94 007 4407 3 Ellis G Silk J 2014 Scientific method Defend the integrity of physics Nature 516 7531 321 323 Bibcode 2014Natur 516 321E doi 10 1038 516321a PMID 25519115 a b c Ball Philip 2015 02 17 Too many worlds Aeon co Retrieved 2021 09 23 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link If an Electron Can Be in Two Places at Once Why Can t You Discover Magazine a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint url status link Melinda Baldwin 2017 07 11 Q amp A Gerard t Hooft on the future of quantum mechanics Physics Today doi 10 1063 PT 6 4 20170711a Peres Asher 1995 Quantum Theory Concepts and Methods Kluwer Academic Publishers p 374 ISBN 0 7923 2549 4 Max Tegmark on many worlds contains MWI poll Caroll Sean 1 April 2004 Preposterous Universe Archived from the original on 8 September 2004 Nielsen Michael 3 April 2004 Michael Nielsen The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Archived from the original on 20 May 2004 Survey Results Archived 2010 11 04 at the Wayback Machine a b Schlosshauer Maximilian Kofler Johannes Zeilinger Anton 2013 A Snapshot of Foundational Attitudes Toward Quantum Mechanics Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44 3 222 230 arXiv 1301 1069 Bibcode 2013SHPMP 44 222S doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2013 04 004 S2CID 55537196 Aldhous Peter 2007 11 24 Parallel lives can never touch New Scientist No 2631 Retrieved 2007 11 21 a b Gardner Martin 2003 Are universes thicker than blackberries W W Norton p 10 ISBN 978 0 393 05742 3 Ferris Timothy 1997 The Whole Shebang Simon amp Schuster pp 345 ISBN 978 0 684 81020 1 Hawking Stephen Roger Penrose 1996 The Nature of Space and Time Princeton University Press pp 121 ISBN 978 0 691 03791 2 Halliwell J J Perez Mercader J Zurek Wojciech Hubert eds 1996 Physical origins of time asymmetry 1st paperback ed Cambridge England Cambridge University Press p 231 ISBN 0 521 56837 4 OCLC 36415828 Gell Mann Murray 1994 The Quark and the Jaguar Adventures in the Simple and the Complex New York Owl Books p 138 ISBN 0 8050 7253 5 OCLC 56388449 Tegmark Max November 1998 Quantum immortality Retrieved 25 October 2010 Carroll Sean 2019 The Human Side Living and Thinking in a Quantum Universe Something Deeply Hidden Quantum Worlds and the Emergence of Spacetime Penguin ISBN 9781524743024 At Google Books Deutsch David 2011 The Beginning The Beginning of Infinity Penguin Group DeWitt Bryce S 1970 Quantum mechanics and reality Physics Today 23 9 30 35 Bibcode 1970PhT 23i 30D doi 10 1063 1 3022331 Max Tegmark Max multiverse FAQ frequently asked questions gt Multiverse philosophy gt Will I rob a gas station Further reading EditJeffrey A Barrett The Quantum Mechanics of Minds and Worlds Oxford University Press Oxford 1999 Peter Byrne The Many Worlds of Hugh Everett III Multiple Universes Mutual Assured Destruction and the Meltdown of a Nuclear Family Oxford University Press 2010 Jeffrey A Barrett and Peter Byrne eds The Everett Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Collected Works 1955 1980 with Commentary Princeton University Press 2012 Julian Brown Minds Machines and the Multiverse Simon amp Schuster 2000 ISBN 0 684 81481 1 Sean M Carroll Something deeply hidden Penguin Random House 2019 Paul C W Davies Other Worlds 1980 ISBN 0 460 04400 1 Osnaghi Stefano Freitas Fabio Olival Freire Jr 2009 The Origin of the Everettian Heresy PDF Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 2 97 123 Bibcode 2009SHPMP 40 97O CiteSeerX 10 1 1 397 3933 doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2008 10 002 Archived from the original PDF on 2016 05 28 Retrieved 2009 08 07 A study of the painful three way relationship between Hugh Everett John A Wheeler and Niels Bohr and how this affected the early development of the many worlds theory David Wallace Worlds in the Everett Interpretation Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 33 2002 pp 637 661 arXiv quant ph 0103092 John A Wheeler and Wojciech Hubert Zurek eds Quantum Theory and Measurement Princeton University Press 1983 ISBN 0 691 08316 9External links EditMany worlds interpretation at Wikipedia s sister projects Definitions from Wiktionary Quotations from Wikiquote Textbooks from Wikibooks Resources from Wikiversity Travel information from Wikivoyage Everettian Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Everett s Relative State Formulation of Quantum Mechanics Jeffrey A Barrett s article on Everett s formulation of quantum mechanics in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Many Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics Lev Vaidman s article on the many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Hugh Everett III Manuscript Archive UC Irvine Jeffrey A Barrett Peter Byrne and James O Weatherall eds Henry Stapp s critique of MWI focusing on the basis problem Canadian J Phys 80 1043 1052 2002 Scientific American report on the Many Worlds 50th anniversary conference at Oxford Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Many worlds interpretation amp oldid 1137118283, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.