fbpx
Wikipedia

Principle of bivalence

In logic, the semantic principle (or law) of bivalence states that every declarative sentence expressing a proposition (of a theory under inspection) has exactly one truth value, either true or false. [1][2] A logic satisfying this principle is called a two-valued logic[3] or bivalent logic.[2][4]

In formal logic, the principle of bivalence becomes a property that a semantics may or may not possess. It is not the same as the law of excluded middle, however, and a semantics may satisfy that law without being bivalent.[2]

The principle of bivalence is studied in philosophical logic to address the question of which natural-language statements have a well-defined truth value. Sentences that predict events in the future, and sentences that seem open to interpretation, are particularly difficult for philosophers who hold that the principle of bivalence applies to all declarative natural-language statements.[2] Many-valued logics formalize ideas that a realistic characterization of the notion of consequence requires the admissibility of premises that, owing to vagueness, temporal or quantum indeterminacy, or reference-failure, cannot be considered classically bivalent. Reference failures can also be addressed by free logics.[5]

Relationship to the law of the excluded middle edit

The principle of bivalence is related to the law of excluded middle though the latter is a syntactic expression of the language of a logic of the form "P ∨ ¬P". The difference between the principle of bivalence and the law of excluded middle is important because there are logics that validate the law but not the principle.[2] For example, the three-valued Logic of Paradox (LP) validates the law of excluded middle, but not the law of non-contradiction, ¬(P ∧ ¬P), and its intended semantics is not bivalent.[6] In Intuitionistic logic the law of excluded middle does not hold. In classical two-valued logic both the law of excluded middle and the law of non-contradiction hold.[1]

Classical logic edit

The intended semantics of classical logic is bivalent, but this is not true of every semantics for classical logic. In Boolean-valued semantics (for classical propositional logic), the truth values are the elements of an arbitrary Boolean algebra, "true" corresponds to the maximal element of the algebra, and "false" corresponds to the minimal element. Intermediate elements of the algebra correspond to truth values other than "true" and "false". The principle of bivalence holds only when the Boolean algebra is taken to be the two-element algebra, which has no intermediate elements.

Assigning Boolean semantics to classical predicate calculus requires that the model be a complete Boolean algebra because the universal quantifier maps to the infimum operation, and the existential quantifier maps to the supremum;[7] this is called a Boolean-valued model. All finite Boolean algebras are complete.

Suszko's thesis edit

In order to justify his claim that true and false are the only logical values, Roman Suszko (1977) observes that every structural Tarskian many-valued propositional logic can be provided with a bivalent semantics.[8]

Criticisms edit

Future contingents edit

A famous example[2] is the contingent sea battle case found in Aristotle's work, De Interpretatione, chapter 9:

Imagine P refers to the statement "There will be a sea battle tomorrow."

The principle of bivalence here asserts:

Either it is true that there will be a sea battle tomorrow, or it is false that there will be a sea battle tomorrow.

Aristotle denies to embrace bivalence for such future contingents;[9] Chrysippus, the Stoic logician, did embrace bivalence for this and all other propositions. The controversy continues to be of central importance in both the philosophy of time and the philosophy of logic.[citation needed]

One of the early motivations for the study of many-valued logics has been precisely this issue. In the early 20th century, the Polish formal logician Jan Łukasiewicz proposed three truth-values: the true, the false and the as-yet-undetermined. This approach was later developed by Arend Heyting and L. E. J. Brouwer;[2] see Łukasiewicz logic.

Issues such as this have also been addressed in various temporal logics, where one can assert that "Eventually, either there will be a sea battle tomorrow, or there won't be." (Which is true if "tomorrow" eventually occurs.)

Vagueness edit

Such puzzles as the Sorites paradox and the related continuum fallacy have raised doubt as to the applicability of classical logic and the principle of bivalence to concepts that may be vague in their application. Fuzzy logic and some other multi-valued logics have been proposed as alternatives that handle vague concepts better. Truth (and falsity) in fuzzy logic, for example, comes in varying degrees. Consider the following statement in the circumstance of sorting apples on a moving belt:

This apple is red.[10]

Upon observation, the apple is an undetermined color between yellow and red, or it is mottled both colors. Thus the color falls into neither category " red " nor " yellow ", but these are the only categories available to us as we sort the apples. We might say it is "50% red". This could be rephrased: it is 50% true that the apple is red. Therefore, P is 50% true, and 50% false. Now consider:

This apple is red and it is not-red.

In other words, P and not-P. This violates the law of noncontradiction and, by extension, bivalence. However, this is only a partial rejection of these laws because P is only partially true. If P were 100% true, not-P would be 100% false, and there is no contradiction because P and not-P no longer holds.

However, the law of the excluded middle is retained, because P and not-P implies P or not-P, since "or" is inclusive. The only two cases where P and not-P is false (when P is 100% true or false) are the same cases considered by two-valued logic, and the same rules apply.

Example of a 3-valued logic applied to vague (undetermined) cases: Kleene 1952[11] (§64, pp. 332–340) offers a 3-valued logic for the cases when algorithms involving partial recursive functions may not return values, but rather end up with circumstances "u" = undecided. He lets "t" = "true", "f" = "false", "u" = "undecided" and redesigns all the propositional connectives. He observes that:

We were justified intuitionistically in using the classical 2-valued logic, when we were using the connectives in building primitive and general recursive predicates, since there is a decision procedure for each general recursive predicate; i.e. the law of the excluded middle is proved intuitionistically to apply to general recursive predicates.

Now if Q(x) is a partial recursive predicate, there is a decision procedure for Q(x) on its range of definition, so the law of the excluded middle or excluded "third" (saying that, Q(x) is either t or f) applies intuitionistically on the range of definition. But there may be no algorithm for deciding, given x, whether Q(x) is defined or not. [...] Hence it is only classically and not intuitionistically that we have a law of the excluded fourth (saying that, for each x, Q(x) is either t, f, or u).

The third "truth value" u is thus not on par with the other two t and f in our theory. Consideration of its status will show that we are limited to a special kind of truth table".

The following are his "strong tables":[12]

~Q QVR R t f u Q&R R t f u Q→R R t f u Q=R R t f u
Q t f Q t t t t Q t t f u Q t t f u Q t t f u
f t f t f u f f f f f t t t f f t u
u u u t u u u u f u u t u u u u u u

For example, if a determination cannot be made as to whether an apple is red or not-red, then the truth value of the assertion Q: " This apple is red " is " u ". Likewise, the truth value of the assertion R " This apple is not-red " is " u ". Thus the AND of these into the assertion Q AND R, i.e. " This apple is red AND this apple is not-red " will, per the tables, yield " u ". And, the assertion Q OR R, i.e. " This apple is red OR this apple is not-red " will likewise yield " u ".

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Lou Goble (2001). The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 309. ISBN 978-0-631-20693-4.
  2. ^ a b c d e f g Paul Tomassi (1999). Logic. Routledge. p. 124. ISBN 978-0-415-16696-6.
  3. ^ Lou Goble (2001). The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic. Wiley-Blackwell. p. 4. ISBN 978-0-631-20693-4.
  4. ^ Mark Hürlimann (2009). Dealing with Real-World Complexity: Limits, Enhancements and New Approaches for Policy Makers. Gabler Verlag. p. 42. ISBN 978-3-8349-1493-4.
  5. ^ Dov M. Gabbay; John Woods (2007). The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic. The handbook of the history of logic. Vol. 8. Elsevier. p. vii. ISBN 978-0-444-51623-7.
  6. ^ Graham Priest (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: from if to is. Cambridge University Press. pp. 124–125. ISBN 978-0-521-85433-7.
  7. ^ Morten Heine Sørensen; Paweł Urzyczyn (2006). Lectures on the Curry-Howard isomorphism. Elsevier. pp. 206–207. ISBN 978-0-444-52077-7.
  8. ^ Shramko, Y.; Wansing, H. (2015). "Truth Values, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  9. ^ Jones, Russell E. (2010). "Truth and Contradiction in Aristotle's De Interpretatione 6-9". Phronesis. 55 (1): 26–67. doi:10.1163/003188610X12589452898804. JSTOR 20720827. S2CID 53398648 – via JSTOR.
  10. ^ Note the use of the (extremely) definite article: "This" as opposed to a more-vague "The". If "The" is used, it would have to be accompanied with a pointing-gesture to make it definitive. Ff Principia Mathematica (2nd edition), p. 91. Russell & Whitehead observe that this " this " indicates "something given in sensation" and as such it shall be considered "elementary".
  11. ^ Stephen C. Kleene 1952 Introduction to Metamathematics, 6th Reprint 1971, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam NY, ISBN 0-7294-2130-9.
  12. ^ "Strong tables" is Kleene's choice of words. Note that even though " u " may appear for the value of Q or R, " t " or " f " may, in those occasions, appear as a value in " Q V R ", " Q & R " and " Q → R ". "Weak tables" on the other hand, are "regular", meaning they have " u " appear in all cases when the value " u " is applied to either Q or R or both. Kleene notes that these tables are not the same as the original values of the tables of Łukasiewicz 1920. (Kleene gives these differences on page 335). He also concludes that " u " can mean any or all of the following: "undefined", "unknown (or value immaterial)", "value disregarded for the moment", i.e. it is a third category that does not (ultimately) exclude " t " and " f " (page 335).

Further reading edit

  • Devidi, D.; Solomon, G. (1999). "On Confusions About Bivalence and Excluded Middle". Dialogue (in French). 38 (4): 785–799. doi:10.1017/S0012217300006715. S2CID 170829533..
  • Betti Arianna (2002) in T. Childers (ed.) The Logica 2002 Yearbook, Prague: The Czech Academy of Sciences—Filosofia, pp. 21–26
  • Jean-Yves Béziau (2003) "Bivalence, excluded middle and non contradiction", in The Logica Yearbook 2003, L.Behounek (ed), Academy of Sciences, Prague, pp. 73–84.
  • Font, J. M. (2009). "Taking Degrees of Truth Seriously". Studia Logica. 91 (3): 383–406. doi:10.1007/s11225-009-9180-7. S2CID 12721181.

External links edit

principle, bivalence, bivalence, redirects, here, other, uses, bivalent, disambiguation, logic, semantic, principle, bivalence, states, that, every, declarative, sentence, expressing, proposition, theory, under, inspection, exactly, truth, value, either, true,. Bivalence redirects here For other uses see Bivalent disambiguation In logic the semantic principle or law of bivalence states that every declarative sentence expressing a proposition of a theory under inspection has exactly one truth value either true or false 1 2 A logic satisfying this principle is called a two valued logic 3 or bivalent logic 2 4 In formal logic the principle of bivalence becomes a property that a semantics may or may not possess It is not the same as the law of excluded middle however and a semantics may satisfy that law without being bivalent 2 The principle of bivalence is studied in philosophical logic to address the question of which natural language statements have a well defined truth value Sentences that predict events in the future and sentences that seem open to interpretation are particularly difficult for philosophers who hold that the principle of bivalence applies to all declarative natural language statements 2 Many valued logics formalize ideas that a realistic characterization of the notion of consequence requires the admissibility of premises that owing to vagueness temporal or quantum indeterminacy or reference failure cannot be considered classically bivalent Reference failures can also be addressed by free logics 5 Contents 1 Relationship to the law of the excluded middle 2 Classical logic 3 Suszko s thesis 4 Criticisms 4 1 Future contingents 4 2 Vagueness 5 See also 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksRelationship to the law of the excluded middle editThe principle of bivalence is related to the law of excluded middle though the latter is a syntactic expression of the language of a logic of the form P P The difference between the principle of bivalence and the law of excluded middle is important because there are logics that validate the law but not the principle 2 For example the three valued Logic of Paradox LP validates the law of excluded middle but not the law of non contradiction P P and its intended semantics is not bivalent 6 In Intuitionistic logic the law of excluded middle does not hold In classical two valued logic both the law of excluded middle and the law of non contradiction hold 1 Classical logic editThe intended semantics of classical logic is bivalent but this is not true of every semantics for classical logic In Boolean valued semantics for classical propositional logic the truth values are the elements of an arbitrary Boolean algebra true corresponds to the maximal element of the algebra and false corresponds to the minimal element Intermediate elements of the algebra correspond to truth values other than true and false The principle of bivalence holds only when the Boolean algebra is taken to be the two element algebra which has no intermediate elements Assigning Boolean semantics to classical predicate calculus requires that the model be a complete Boolean algebra because the universal quantifier maps to the infimum operation and the existential quantifier maps to the supremum 7 this is called a Boolean valued model All finite Boolean algebras are complete Suszko s thesis editIn order to justify his claim that true and false are the only logical values Roman Suszko 1977 observes that every structural Tarskian many valued propositional logic can be provided with a bivalent semantics 8 Criticisms editFuture contingents edit Main article Problem of future contingents A famous example 2 is the contingent sea battle case found in Aristotle s work De Interpretatione chapter 9 Imagine P refers to the statement There will be a sea battle tomorrow The principle of bivalence here asserts Either it is true that there will be a sea battle tomorrow or it is false that there will be a sea battle tomorrow Aristotle denies to embrace bivalence for such future contingents 9 Chrysippus the Stoic logician did embrace bivalence for this and all other propositions The controversy continues to be of central importance in both the philosophy of time and the philosophy of logic citation needed One of the early motivations for the study of many valued logics has been precisely this issue In the early 20th century the Polish formal logician Jan Lukasiewicz proposed three truth values the true the false and the as yet undetermined This approach was later developed by Arend Heyting and L E J Brouwer 2 see Lukasiewicz logic Issues such as this have also been addressed in various temporal logics where one can assert that Eventually either there will be a sea battle tomorrow or there won t be Which is true if tomorrow eventually occurs Vagueness edit Such puzzles as the Sorites paradox and the related continuum fallacy have raised doubt as to the applicability of classical logic and the principle of bivalence to concepts that may be vague in their application Fuzzy logic and some other multi valued logics have been proposed as alternatives that handle vague concepts better Truth and falsity in fuzzy logic for example comes in varying degrees Consider the following statement in the circumstance of sorting apples on a moving belt This apple is red 10 Upon observation the apple is an undetermined color between yellow and red or it is mottled both colors Thus the color falls into neither category red nor yellow but these are the only categories available to us as we sort the apples We might say it is 50 red This could be rephrased it is 50 true that the apple is red Therefore P is 50 true and 50 false Now consider This apple is red and it is not red In other words P and not P This violates the law of noncontradiction and by extension bivalence However this is only a partial rejection of these laws because P is only partially true If P were 100 true not P would be 100 false and there is no contradiction because P and not P no longer holds However the law of the excluded middle is retained because P and not P implies P or not P since or is inclusive The only two cases where P and not P is false when P is 100 true or false are the same cases considered by two valued logic and the same rules apply Example of a 3 valued logic applied to vague undetermined cases Kleene 1952 11 64 pp 332 340 offers a 3 valued logic for the cases when algorithms involving partial recursive functions may not return values but rather end up with circumstances u undecided He lets t true f false u undecided and redesigns all the propositional connectives He observes that We were justified intuitionistically in using the classical 2 valued logic when we were using the connectives in building primitive and general recursive predicates since there is a decision procedure for each general recursive predicate i e the law of the excluded middle is proved intuitionistically to apply to general recursive predicates Now if Q x is a partial recursive predicate there is a decision procedure for Q x on its range of definition so the law of the excluded middle or excluded third saying that Q x is either t or f applies intuitionistically on the range of definition But there may be no algorithm for deciding given x whether Q x is defined or not Hence it is only classically and not intuitionistically that we have a law of the excluded fourth saying that for each x Q x is either t f or u The third truth value u is thus not on par with the other two t and f in our theory Consideration of its status will show that we are limited to a special kind of truth table The following are his strong tables 12 Q QVR R t f u Q amp R R t f u Q R R t f u Q R R t f u Q t f Q t t t t Q t t f u Q t t f u Q t t f u f t f t f u f f f f f t t t f f t u u u u t u u u u f u u t u u u u u u For example if a determination cannot be made as to whether an apple is red or not red then the truth value of the assertion Q This apple is red is u Likewise the truth value of the assertion R This apple is not red is u Thus the AND of these into the assertion Q AND R i e This apple is red AND this apple is not red will per the tables yield u And the assertion Q OR R i e This apple is red OR this apple is not red will likewise yield u See also edit nbsp Philosophy portal nbsp Psychology portal Dualism Exclusive disjunction Degrees of truth Anekantavada Extensionality False dilemma Fuzzy logic Logical disjunction Logical equality Logical value Multi valued logic Propositional logic Relativism Supervaluationism Truthbearer Truthmaker Truth value link Quantum logic Perspectivism True and falseReferences edit a b Lou Goble 2001 The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic Wiley Blackwell p 309 ISBN 978 0 631 20693 4 a b c d e f g Paul Tomassi 1999 Logic Routledge p 124 ISBN 978 0 415 16696 6 Lou Goble 2001 The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic Wiley Blackwell p 4 ISBN 978 0 631 20693 4 Mark Hurlimann 2009 Dealing with Real World Complexity Limits Enhancements and New Approaches for Policy Makers Gabler Verlag p 42 ISBN 978 3 8349 1493 4 Dov M Gabbay John Woods 2007 The Many Valued and Nonmonotonic Turn in Logic The handbook of the history of logic Vol 8 Elsevier p vii ISBN 978 0 444 51623 7 Graham Priest 2008 An introduction to non classical logic from if to is Cambridge University Press pp 124 125 ISBN 978 0 521 85433 7 Morten Heine Sorensen Pawel Urzyczyn 2006 Lectures on the Curry Howard isomorphism Elsevier pp 206 207 ISBN 978 0 444 52077 7 Shramko Y Wansing H 2015 Truth Values Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Jones Russell E 2010 Truth and Contradiction in Aristotle s De Interpretatione 6 9 Phronesis 55 1 26 67 doi 10 1163 003188610X12589452898804 JSTOR 20720827 S2CID 53398648 via JSTOR Note the use of the extremely definite article This as opposed to a more vague The If The is used it would have to be accompanied with a pointing gesture to make it definitive Ff Principia Mathematica 2nd edition p 91 Russell amp Whitehead observe that this this indicates something given in sensation and as such it shall be considered elementary Stephen C Kleene 1952 Introduction to Metamathematics 6th Reprint 1971 North Holland Publishing Company Amsterdam NY ISBN 0 7294 2130 9 Strong tables is Kleene s choice of words Note that even though u may appear for the value of Q or R t or f may in those occasions appear as a value in Q V R Q amp R and Q R Weak tables on the other hand are regular meaning they have u appear in all cases when the value u is applied to either Q or R or both Kleene notes that these tables are not the same as the original values of the tables of Lukasiewicz 1920 Kleene gives these differences on page 335 He also concludes that u can mean any or all of the following undefined unknown or value immaterial value disregarded for the moment i e it is a third category that does not ultimately exclude t and f page 335 Further reading editDevidi D Solomon G 1999 On Confusions About Bivalence and Excluded Middle Dialogue in French 38 4 785 799 doi 10 1017 S0012217300006715 S2CID 170829533 Betti Arianna 2002 The Incomplete Story of Lukasiewicz and Bivalence in T Childers ed The Logica 2002 Yearbook Prague The Czech Academy of Sciences Filosofia pp 21 26 Jean Yves Beziau 2003 Bivalence excluded middle and non contradiction in The Logica Yearbook 2003 L Behounek ed Academy of Sciences Prague pp 73 84 Font J M 2009 Taking Degrees of Truth Seriously Studia Logica 91 3 383 406 doi 10 1007 s11225 009 9180 7 S2CID 12721181 External links editShramko Yaroslav Wansing Heinrich Truth Values In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Principle of bivalence amp oldid 1190021769, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.