fbpx
Wikipedia

Contradiction

In traditional logic, a contradiction occurs when a proposition conflicts either with itself or established fact. It is often used as a tool to detect disingenuous beliefs and bias. Illustrating a general tendency in applied logic, Aristotle's law of noncontradiction states that "It is impossible that the same thing can at the same time both belong and not belong to the same object and in the same respect."[1]

This diagram shows the contradictory relationships between categorical propositions in the square of opposition of Aristotelian logic.

In modern formal logic and type theory, the term is mainly used instead for a single proposition, often denoted by the falsum symbol ; a proposition is a contradiction if false can be derived from it, using the rules of the logic. It is a proposition that is unconditionally false (i.e., a self-contradictory proposition).[2][3] This can be generalized to a collection of propositions, which is then said to "contain" a contradiction.

History edit

By creation of a paradox, Plato's Euthydemus dialogue demonstrates the need for the notion of contradiction. In the ensuing dialogue, Dionysodorus denies the existence of "contradiction", all the while that Socrates is contradicting him:

... I in my astonishment said: What do you mean Dionysodorus? I have often heard, and have been amazed to hear, this thesis of yours, which is maintained and employed by the disciples of Protagoras and others before them, and which to me appears to be quite wonderful, and suicidal as well as destructive, and I think that I am most likely to hear the truth about it from you. The dictum is that there is no such thing as a falsehood; a man must either say what is true or say nothing. Is not that your position?

Indeed, Dionysodorus agrees that "there is no such thing as false opinion ... there is no such thing as ignorance", and demands of Socrates to "Refute me." Socrates responds "But how can I refute you, if, as you say, to tell a falsehood is impossible?".[4]

In formal logic edit

In classical logic, particularly in propositional and first-order logic, a proposition   is a contradiction if and only if  . Since for contradictory   it is true that   for all   (because  ), one may prove any proposition from a set of axioms which contains contradictions. This is called the "principle of explosion", or "ex falso quodlibet" ("from falsity, anything follows").[5]

In a complete logic, a formula is contradictory if and only if it is unsatisfiable.

Proof by contradiction edit

For a set of consistent premises   and a proposition  , it is true in classical logic that   (i.e.,   proves  ) if and only if   (i.e.,   and   leads to a contradiction). Therefore, a proof that   also proves that   is true under the premises  . The use of this fact forms the basis of a proof technique called proof by contradiction, which mathematicians use extensively to establish the validity of a wide range of theorems. This applies only in a logic where the law of excluded middle   is accepted as an axiom.

Using minimal logic, a logic with similar axioms to classical logic but without ex falso quodlibet and proof by contradiction, we can investigate the axiomatic strength and properties of various rules that treat contradiction by considering theorems of classical logic that are not theorems of minimal logic.[6] Each of these extensions leads to an intermediate logic:

  1. Double-negation elimination (DNE) is the strongest principle, axiomatized  , and when it is added to minimal logic yields classical logic.
  2. Ex falso quodlibet (EFQ), axiomatized  , licenses many consequences of negations, but typically does not help to infer propositions that do not involve absurdity from consistent propositions that do. When added to minimal logic, EFQ yields intuitionistic logic. EFQ is equivalent to ex contradiction quodlibet, axiomatized  , over minimal logic.
  3. Peirce's rule (PR) is an axiom   that captures proof by contradiction without explicitly referring to absurdity. Minimal logic + PR + EFQ yields classical logic.
  4. The Gödel-Dummett (GD) axiom  , whose most simple reading is that there is a linear order on truth values. Minimal logic + GD yields Gödel-Dummett logic. Peirce's rule entails but is not entailed by GD over minimal logic.
  5. Law of the excluded middle (LEM), axiomatised  , is the most often cited formulation of the principle of bivalence, but in the absence of EFQ it does not yield full classical logic. Minimal logic + LEM + EFQ yields classical logic. PR entails but is not entailed by LEM in minimal logic. If the formula B in Peirce's rule is restricted to absurdity, giving the axiom schema  , the scheme is equivalent to LEM over minimal logic.
  6. Weak law of the excluded middle (WLEM) is axiomatised   and yields a system where disjunction behaves more like in classical logic than intuitionistic logic, i.e. the disjunction and existence properties don't hold, but where use of non-intuitionistic reasoning is marked by occurrences of double-negation in the conclusion. LEM entails but is not entailed by WLEM in minimal logic. WLEM is equivalent to the instance of De Morgan's law that distributes negation over conjunction:  .

Symbolic representation edit

In mathematics, the symbol used to represent a contradiction within a proof varies.[7] Some symbols that may be used to represent a contradiction include ↯, Opq,  , ⊥,  / , and ※; in any symbolism, a contradiction may be substituted for the truth value "false", as symbolized, for instance, by "0" (as is common in Boolean algebra). It is not uncommon to see Q.E.D., or some of its variants, immediately after a contradiction symbol. In fact, this often occurs in a proof by contradiction to indicate that the original assumption was proved false—and hence that its negation must be true.

The notion of contradiction in an axiomatic system and a proof of its consistency edit

In general, a consistency proof requires the following two things:

  1. An axiomatic system
  2. A demonstration that it is not the case that both the formula p and its negation ~p can be derived in the system.

But by whatever method one goes about it, all consistency proofs would seem to necessitate the primitive notion of contradiction. Moreover, it seems as if this notion would simultaneously have to be "outside" the formal system in the definition of tautology.

When Emil Post, in his 1921 "Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions", extended his proof of the consistency of the propositional calculus (i.e. the logic) beyond that of Principia Mathematica (PM), he observed that with respect to a generalized set of postulates (i.e. axioms), he would no longer be able to automatically invoke the notion of "contradiction"—such a notion might not be contained in the postulates:

The prime requisite of a set of postulates is that it be consistent. Since the ordinary notion of consistency involves that of contradiction, which again involves negation, and since this function does not appear in general as a primitive in [the generalized set of postulates] a new definition must be given.[8]

Post's solution to the problem is described in the demonstration "An Example of a Successful Absolute Proof of Consistency", offered by Ernest Nagel and James R. Newman in their 1958 Gödel's Proof. They too observed a problem with respect to the notion of "contradiction" with its usual "truth values" of "truth" and "falsity". They observed that:

The property of being a tautology has been defined in notions of truth and falsity. Yet these notions obviously involve a reference to something outside the formula calculus. Therefore, the procedure mentioned in the text in effect offers an interpretation of the calculus, by supplying a model for the system. This being so, the authors have not done what they promised, namely, "to define a property of formulas in terms of purely structural features of the formulas themselves". [Indeed] ... proofs of consistency which are based on models, and which argue from the truth of axioms to their consistency, merely shift the problem.[9]

Given some "primitive formulas" such as PM's primitives S1 V S2 [inclusive OR] and ~S (negation), one is forced to define the axioms in terms of these primitive notions. In a thorough manner, Post demonstrates in PM, and defines (as do Nagel and Newman, see below) that the property of tautologous – as yet to be defined – is "inherited": if one begins with a set of tautologous axioms (postulates) and a deduction system that contains substitution and modus ponens, then a consistent system will yield only tautologous formulas.

On the topic of the definition of tautologous, Nagel and Newman create two mutually exclusive and exhaustive classes K1 and K2, into which fall (the outcome of) the axioms when their variables (e.g. S1 and S2 are assigned from these classes). This also applies to the primitive formulas. For example: "A formula having the form S1 V S2 is placed into class K2, if both S1 and S2 are in K2; otherwise it is placed in K1", and "A formula having the form ~S is placed in K2, if S is in K1; otherwise it is placed in K1".[10]

Hence Nagel and Newman can now define the notion of tautologous: "a formula is a tautology if and only if it falls in the class K1, no matter in which of the two classes its elements are placed".[11] This way, the property of "being tautologous" is described—without reference to a model or an interpretation.

For example, given a formula such as ~S1 V S2 and an assignment of K1 to S1 and K2 to S2 one can evaluate the formula and place its outcome in one or the other of the classes. The assignment of K1 to S1 places ~S1 in K2, and now we can see that our assignment causes the formula to fall into class K2. Thus by definition our formula is not a tautology.

Post observed that, if the system were inconsistent, a deduction in it (that is, the last formula in a sequence of formulas derived from the tautologies) could ultimately yield S itself. As an assignment to variable S can come from either class K1 or K2, the deduction violates the inheritance characteristic of tautology (i.e., the derivation must yield an evaluation of a formula that will fall into class K1). From this, Post was able to derive the following definition of inconsistency—without the use of the notion of contradiction:

Definition. A system will be said to be inconsistent if it yields the assertion of the unmodified variable p [S in the Newman and Nagel examples].

In other words, the notion of "contradiction" can be dispensed when constructing a proof of consistency; what replaces it is the notion of "mutually exclusive and exhaustive" classes. An axiomatic system need not include the notion of "contradiction".[citation needed]

Philosophy edit

Adherents of the epistemological theory of coherentism typically claim that as a necessary condition of the justification of a belief, that belief must form a part of a logically non-contradictory system of beliefs. Some dialetheists, including Graham Priest, have argued that coherence may not require consistency.[12]

Pragmatic contradictions edit

A pragmatic contradiction occurs when the very statement of the argument contradicts the claims it purports. An inconsistency arises, in this case, because the act of utterance, rather than the content of what is said, undermines its conclusion.[13]

Dialectical materialism edit

In dialectical materialism: Contradiction—as derived from Hegelianism—usually refers to an opposition inherently existing within one realm, one unified force or object. This contradiction, as opposed to metaphysical thinking, is not an objectively impossible thing, because these contradicting forces exist in objective reality, not cancelling each other out, but actually defining each other's existence. According to Marxist theory, such a contradiction can be found, for example, in the fact that:

  • (a) enormous wealth and productive powers coexist alongside:
  • (b) extreme poverty and misery;
  • (c) the existence of (a) being contrary to the existence of (b).

Hegelian and Marxist theories stipulate that the dialectic nature of history will lead to the sublation, or synthesis, of its contradictions. Marx therefore postulated that history would logically make capitalism evolve into a socialist society where the means of production would equally serve the working and producing class of society, thus resolving the prior contradiction between (a) and (b).[14]

Outside formal logic edit

Colloquial usage can label actions or statements as contradicting each other when due (or perceived as due) to presuppositions which are contradictory in the logical sense.

Proof by contradiction is used in mathematics to construct proofs.

The scientific method uses contradiction to falsify bad theory.

See also edit

Notes and references edit

  1. ^ Horn, Laurence R. (2018), "Contradiction", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2019-12-10
  2. ^ "Contradiction (logic)". TheFreeDictionary.com. Retrieved 2020-08-14.
  3. ^ "Tautologies, contradictions, and contingencies". www.skillfulreasoning.com. Retrieved 2020-08-14.
  4. ^ Dialog Euthydemus from The Dialogs of Plato translated by Benjamin Jowett appearing in: BK 7 Plato: Robert Maynard Hutchins, editor in chief, 1952, Great Books of the Western World, Encyclopædia Britannica, Inc., Chicago.
  5. ^ "Ex falso quodlibet - Oxford Reference". www.oxfordreference.com. Retrieved 2019-12-10.
  6. ^ Diener and Maarten McKubre-Jordens, 2020. Classifying Material Implications over Minimal Logic. Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 (7-8):905-924.
  7. ^ Pakin, Scott (January 19, 2017). "The Comprehensive LATEX Symbol List" (PDF). ctan.mirror.rafal.ca. Retrieved 2019-12-10.
  8. ^ Post 1921 "Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions" in van Heijenoort 1967:272.
  9. ^ boldface italics added, Nagel and Newman:109-110.
  10. ^ Nagel and Newman:110-111
  11. ^ Nagel and Newman:111
  12. ^ In Contradiction: A Study of the Transconsistent By Graham Priest
  13. ^ Stoljar, Daniel (2006). Ignorance and Imagination. Oxford University Press - U.S. p. 87. ISBN 0-19-530658-9.
  14. ^ Sørensen, Michael Kuur (2006). "Capital and Labour: Can the Conflict Be Solved?". The Interdisciplinary Journal of International Studies. 4 (1): 29–48. Retrieved 28 May 2017.

Bibliography edit

  • Józef Maria Bocheński 1960 Précis of Mathematical Logic, translated from the French and German editions by Otto Bird, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, South Holland.
  • Jean van Heijenoort 1967 From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879-1931, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, ISBN 0-674-32449-8 (pbk.)
  • Ernest Nagel and James R. Newman 1958 Gödel's Proof, New York University Press, Card Catalog Number: 58-5610.

External links edit

contradiction, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, news, newspapers, books,. For other uses see Contradiction disambiguation This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Contradiction news newspapers books scholar JSTOR July 2008 Learn how and when to remove this template message In traditional logic a contradiction occurs when a proposition conflicts either with itself or established fact It is often used as a tool to detect disingenuous beliefs and bias Illustrating a general tendency in applied logic Aristotle s law of noncontradiction states that It is impossible that the same thing can at the same time both belong and not belong to the same object and in the same respect 1 This diagram shows the contradictory relationships between categorical propositions in the square of opposition of Aristotelian logic In modern formal logic and type theory the term is mainly used instead for a single proposition often denoted by the falsum symbol displaystyle bot a proposition is a contradiction if false can be derived from it using the rules of the logic It is a proposition that is unconditionally false i e a self contradictory proposition 2 3 This can be generalized to a collection of propositions which is then said to contain a contradiction Contents 1 History 2 In formal logic 2 1 Proof by contradiction 2 2 Symbolic representation 2 3 The notion of contradiction in an axiomatic system and a proof of its consistency 3 Philosophy 3 1 Pragmatic contradictions 3 2 Dialectical materialism 4 Outside formal logic 5 See also 6 Notes and references 7 Bibliography 8 External linksHistory editBy creation of a paradox Plato s Euthydemus dialogue demonstrates the need for the notion of contradiction In the ensuing dialogue Dionysodorus denies the existence of contradiction all the while that Socrates is contradicting him I in my astonishment said What do you mean Dionysodorus I have often heard and have been amazed to hear this thesis of yours which is maintained and employed by the disciples of Protagoras and others before them and which to me appears to be quite wonderful and suicidal as well as destructive and I think that I am most likely to hear the truth about it from you The dictum is that there is no such thing as a falsehood a man must either say what is true or say nothing Is not that your position Indeed Dionysodorus agrees that there is no such thing as false opinion there is no such thing as ignorance and demands of Socrates to Refute me Socrates responds But how can I refute you if as you say to tell a falsehood is impossible 4 In formal logic editNote The symbol displaystyle bot nbsp falsum represents an arbitrary contradiction with the dual tee symbol displaystyle top nbsp used to denote an arbitrary tautology Contradiction is sometimes symbolized by Opq and tautology by Vpq The turnstile symbol displaystyle vdash nbsp is often read as yields or proves In classical logic particularly in propositional and first order logic a proposition f displaystyle varphi nbsp is a contradiction if and only if f displaystyle varphi vdash bot nbsp Since for contradictory f displaystyle varphi nbsp it is true that f ps displaystyle vdash varphi rightarrow psi nbsp for all ps displaystyle psi nbsp because ps displaystyle bot vdash psi nbsp one may prove any proposition from a set of axioms which contains contradictions This is called the principle of explosion or ex falso quodlibet from falsity anything follows 5 In a complete logic a formula is contradictory if and only if it is unsatisfiable Proof by contradiction edit Main article Proof by contradiction For a set of consistent premises S displaystyle Sigma nbsp and a proposition f displaystyle varphi nbsp it is true in classical logic that S f displaystyle Sigma vdash varphi nbsp i e S displaystyle Sigma nbsp proves f displaystyle varphi nbsp if and only if S f displaystyle Sigma cup neg varphi vdash bot nbsp i e S displaystyle Sigma nbsp and f displaystyle neg varphi nbsp leads to a contradiction Therefore a proof that S f displaystyle Sigma cup neg varphi vdash bot nbsp also proves that f displaystyle varphi nbsp is true under the premises S displaystyle Sigma nbsp The use of this fact forms the basis of a proof technique called proof by contradiction which mathematicians use extensively to establish the validity of a wide range of theorems This applies only in a logic where the law of excluded middle A A displaystyle A vee neg A nbsp is accepted as an axiom Using minimal logic a logic with similar axioms to classical logic but without ex falso quodlibet and proof by contradiction we can investigate the axiomatic strength and properties of various rules that treat contradiction by considering theorems of classical logic that are not theorems of minimal logic 6 Each of these extensions leads to an intermediate logic Double negation elimination DNE is the strongest principle axiomatized A A displaystyle neg neg A implies A nbsp and when it is added to minimal logic yields classical logic Ex falso quodlibet EFQ axiomatized A displaystyle bot implies A nbsp licenses many consequences of negations but typically does not help to infer propositions that do not involve absurdity from consistent propositions that do When added to minimal logic EFQ yields intuitionistic logic EFQ is equivalent to ex contradiction quodlibet axiomatized A A B displaystyle A land neg A implies B nbsp over minimal logic Peirce s rule PR is an axiom A B A A displaystyle A implies B implies A implies A nbsp that captures proof by contradiction without explicitly referring to absurdity Minimal logic PR EFQ yields classical logic The Godel Dummett GD axiom A B B A displaystyle A implies B vee B implies A nbsp whose most simple reading is that there is a linear order on truth values Minimal logic GD yields Godel Dummett logic Peirce s rule entails but is not entailed by GD over minimal logic Law of the excluded middle LEM axiomatised A A displaystyle A vee neg A nbsp is the most often cited formulation of the principle of bivalence but in the absence of EFQ it does not yield full classical logic Minimal logic LEM EFQ yields classical logic PR entails but is not entailed by LEM in minimal logic If the formula B in Peirce s rule is restricted to absurdity giving the axiom schema A A A displaystyle neg A implies A implies A nbsp the scheme is equivalent to LEM over minimal logic Weak law of the excluded middle WLEM is axiomatised A A displaystyle neg A vee neg neg A nbsp and yields a system where disjunction behaves more like in classical logic than intuitionistic logic i e the disjunction and existence properties don t hold but where use of non intuitionistic reasoning is marked by occurrences of double negation in the conclusion LEM entails but is not entailed by WLEM in minimal logic WLEM is equivalent to the instance of De Morgan s law that distributes negation over conjunction A B A B displaystyle neg A land B iff neg A vee neg B nbsp Symbolic representation edit In mathematics the symbol used to represent a contradiction within a proof varies 7 Some symbols that may be used to represent a contradiction include Opq displaystyle Rightarrow Leftarrow nbsp displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp and in any symbolism a contradiction may be substituted for the truth value false as symbolized for instance by 0 as is common in Boolean algebra It is not uncommon to see Q E D or some of its variants immediately after a contradiction symbol In fact this often occurs in a proof by contradiction to indicate that the original assumption was proved false and hence that its negation must be true The notion of contradiction in an axiomatic system and a proof of its consistency edit In general a consistency proof requires the following two things An axiomatic system A demonstration that it is not the case that both the formula p and its negation p can be derived in the system But by whatever method one goes about it all consistency proofs would seem to necessitate the primitive notion of contradiction Moreover it seems as if this notion would simultaneously have to be outside the formal system in the definition of tautology When Emil Post in his 1921 Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions extended his proof of the consistency of the propositional calculus i e the logic beyond that of Principia Mathematica PM he observed that with respect to a generalized set of postulates i e axioms he would no longer be able to automatically invoke the notion of contradiction such a notion might not be contained in the postulates The prime requisite of a set of postulates is that it be consistent Since the ordinary notion of consistency involves that of contradiction which again involves negation and since this function does not appear in general as a primitive in the generalized set of postulates a new definition must be given 8 Post s solution to the problem is described in the demonstration An Example of a Successful Absolute Proof of Consistency offered by Ernest Nagel and James R Newman in their 1958 Godel s Proof They too observed a problem with respect to the notion of contradiction with its usual truth values of truth and falsity They observed that The property of being a tautology has been defined in notions of truth and falsity Yet these notions obviously involve a reference to something outside the formula calculus Therefore the procedure mentioned in the text in effect offers an interpretation of the calculus by supplying a model for the system This being so the authors have not done what they promised namely to define a property of formulas in terms of purely structural features of the formulas themselves Indeed proofs of consistency which are based on models and which argue from the truth of axioms to their consistency merely shift the problem 9 Given some primitive formulas such as PM s primitives S1 V S2 inclusive OR and S negation one is forced to define the axioms in terms of these primitive notions In a thorough manner Post demonstrates in PM and defines as do Nagel and Newman see below that the property of tautologous as yet to be defined is inherited if one begins with a set of tautologous axioms postulates and a deduction system that contains substitution and modus ponens then a consistent system will yield only tautologous formulas On the topic of the definition of tautologous Nagel and Newman create two mutually exclusive and exhaustive classes K1 and K2 into which fall the outcome of the axioms when their variables e g S1 and S2 are assigned from these classes This also applies to the primitive formulas For example A formula having the form S1 V S2 is placed into class K2 if both S1 and S2 are in K2 otherwise it is placed in K1 and A formula having the form S is placed in K2 if S is in K1 otherwise it is placed in K1 10 Hence Nagel and Newman can now define the notion of tautologous a formula is a tautology if and only if it falls in the class K1 no matter in which of the two classes its elements are placed 11 This way the property of being tautologous is described without reference to a model or an interpretation For example given a formula such as S1 V S2 and an assignment of K1 to S1 and K2 to S2 one can evaluate the formula and place its outcome in one or the other of the classes The assignment of K1 to S1 places S1 in K2 and now we can see that our assignment causes the formula to fall into class K2 Thus by definition our formula is not a tautology Post observed that if the system were inconsistent a deduction in it that is the last formula in a sequence of formulas derived from the tautologies could ultimately yield S itself As an assignment to variable S can come from either class K1 or K2 the deduction violates the inheritance characteristic of tautology i e the derivation must yield an evaluation of a formula that will fall into class K1 From this Post was able to derive the following definition of inconsistency without the use of the notion of contradiction Definition A system will be said to be inconsistent if it yields the assertion of the unmodified variable p S in the Newman and Nagel examples In other words the notion of contradiction can be dispensed when constructing a proof of consistency what replaces it is the notion of mutually exclusive and exhaustive classes An axiomatic system need not include the notion of contradiction citation needed Philosophy editAdherents of the epistemological theory of coherentism typically claim that as a necessary condition of the justification of a belief that belief must form a part of a logically non contradictory system of beliefs Some dialetheists including Graham Priest have argued that coherence may not require consistency 12 Pragmatic contradictions edit A pragmatic contradiction occurs when the very statement of the argument contradicts the claims it purports An inconsistency arises in this case because the act of utterance rather than the content of what is said undermines its conclusion 13 Dialectical materialism edit In dialectical materialism Contradiction as derived from Hegelianism usually refers to an opposition inherently existing within one realm one unified force or object This contradiction as opposed to metaphysical thinking is not an objectively impossible thing because these contradicting forces exist in objective reality not cancelling each other out but actually defining each other s existence According to Marxist theory such a contradiction can be found for example in the fact that a enormous wealth and productive powers coexist alongside b extreme poverty and misery c the existence of a being contrary to the existence of b Hegelian and Marxist theories stipulate that the dialectic nature of history will lead to the sublation or synthesis of its contradictions Marx therefore postulated that history would logically make capitalism evolve into a socialist society where the means of production would equally serve the working and producing class of society thus resolving the prior contradiction between a and b 14 Outside formal logic editColloquial usage can label actions or statements as contradicting each other when due or perceived as due to presuppositions which are contradictory in the logical sense Proof by contradiction is used in mathematics to construct proofs The scientific method uses contradiction to falsify bad theory See also edit Argument Clinic Monty Python sketch in which one of the two disputants repeatedly uses only contradictions in his argument Auto antonym Word that has two opposing meaningsPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Contrary logic Type of logic diagramPages displaying short descriptions of redirect targets Dialetheism View that there are statements that are both true and false Double standard Inconsistent application of principles Doublethink Simultaneously accepting two mutually contradictory beliefs as correct Graham s hierarchy of disagreement Irony Rhetorical device and literary technique Law of noncontradiction On Contradiction 1937 essay by Mao Zedong Oxymoron Figure of speech Paraconsistent logic Type of formal logic without explosion principle Paradox Statement that apparently contradicts itself Tautology In logic a statement which is always true TRIZ Problem solving toolsNotes and references edit Horn Laurence R 2018 Contradiction in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Winter 2018 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2019 12 10 Contradiction logic TheFreeDictionary com Retrieved 2020 08 14 Tautologies contradictions and contingencies www skillfulreasoning com Retrieved 2020 08 14 Dialog Euthydemus from The Dialogs of Plato translated by Benjamin Jowett appearing in BK 7 Plato Robert Maynard Hutchins editor in chief 1952 Great Books of the Western World Encyclopaedia Britannica Inc Chicago Ex falso quodlibet Oxford Reference www oxfordreference com Retrieved 2019 12 10 Diener and Maarten McKubre Jordens 2020 Classifying Material Implications over Minimal Logic Archive for Mathematical Logic 59 7 8 905 924 Pakin Scott January 19 2017 The Comprehensive LATEX Symbol List PDF ctan mirror rafal ca Retrieved 2019 12 10 Post 1921 Introduction to a General Theory of Elementary Propositions in van Heijenoort 1967 272 boldface italics added Nagel and Newman 109 110 Nagel and Newman 110 111 Nagel and Newman 111 In Contradiction A Study of the Transconsistent By Graham Priest Stoljar Daniel 2006 Ignorance and Imagination Oxford University Press U S p 87 ISBN 0 19 530658 9 Sorensen Michael Kuur 2006 Capital and Labour Can the Conflict Be Solved The Interdisciplinary Journal of International Studies 4 1 29 48 Retrieved 28 May 2017 Bibliography editJozef Maria Bochenski 1960 Precis of Mathematical Logic translated from the French and German editions by Otto Bird D Reidel Dordrecht South Holland Jean van Heijenoort 1967 From Frege to Godel A Source Book in Mathematical Logic 1879 1931 Harvard University Press Cambridge MA ISBN 0 674 32449 8 pbk Ernest Nagel and James R Newman 1958 Godel s Proof New York University Press Card Catalog Number 58 5610 External links edit nbsp Look up contradiction or although in Wiktionary the free dictionary nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Contradiction Contradiction inconsistency Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Contradiction law of Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Horn Laurence R Contradiction In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Contradiction amp oldid 1193584083, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.