fbpx
Wikipedia

Constructible universe

In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by , is a particular class of sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. is the union of the constructible hierarchy . It was introduced by Kurt Gödel in his 1938 paper "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis".[1] In this paper, he proved that the constructible universe is an inner model of ZF set theory (that is, of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice excluded), and also that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis are true in the constructible universe. This shows that both propositions are consistent with the basic axioms of set theory, if ZF itself is consistent. Since many other theorems only hold in systems in which one or both of the propositions is true, their consistency is an important result.

What L is Edit

  can be thought of as being built in "stages" resembling the construction of von Neumann universe,  . The stages are indexed by ordinals. In von Neumann's universe, at a successor stage, one takes   to be the set of all subsets of the previous stage,  . By contrast, in Gödel's constructible universe  , one uses only those subsets of the previous stage that are:

By limiting oneself to sets defined only in terms of what has already been constructed, one ensures that the resulting sets will be constructed in a way that is independent of the peculiarities of the surrounding model of set theory and contained in any such model.

Define the Def operator:[2]

 

  is defined by transfinite recursion as follows:

  •  
  •  
  • If   is a limit ordinal, then   Here   means   precedes  .
  •   Here Ord denotes the class of all ordinals.

If   is an element of  , then  .[3] So   is a subset of  , which is a subset of the power set of  . Consequently, this is a tower of nested transitive sets. But   itself is a proper class.

The elements of   are called "constructible" sets; and   itself is the "constructible universe". The "axiom of constructibility", aka " ", says that every set (of  ) is constructible, i.e. in  .

Additional facts about the sets L_alpha Edit

An equivalent definition for   is:

For any ordinal  ,  .

For any finite ordinal  , the sets   and   are the same (whether   equals   or not), and thus   =  : their elements are exactly the hereditarily finite sets. Equality beyond this point does not hold. Even in models of ZFC in which   equals  ,   is a proper subset of  , and thereafter   is a proper subset of the power set of   for all  . On the other hand,   does imply that   equals   if  , for example if   is inaccessible. More generally,   implies   =   for all infinite cardinals  .

If   is an infinite ordinal then there is a bijection between   and  , and the bijection is constructible. So these sets are equinumerous in any model of set theory that includes them.

As defined above,   is the set of subsets of   defined by   formulas (with respect to the Levy hierarchy, i.e., formulas of set theory containing only bounded quantifiers) that use as parameters only   and its elements.[4]

Another definition, due to Gödel, characterizes each   as the intersection of the power set of   with the closure of   under a collection of nine explicit functions, similar to Gödel operations. This definition makes no reference to definability.

All arithmetical subsets of   and relations on   belong to   (because the arithmetic definition gives one in  ). Conversely, any subset of   belonging to   is arithmetical (because elements of   can be coded by natural numbers in such a way that   is definable, i.e., arithmetic). On the other hand,   already contains certain non-arithmetical subsets of  , such as the set of (natural numbers coding) true arithmetical statements (this can be defined from   so it is in  ).

All hyperarithmetical subsets of   and relations on   belong to   (where   stands for the Church–Kleene ordinal), and conversely any subset of   that belongs to   is hyperarithmetical.[5]

L is a standard inner model of ZFC Edit

  is a standard model, i.e.   is a transitive class and the interpretation uses the real element relationship, so it is well-founded.   is an inner model, i.e. it contains all the ordinal numbers of   and it has no "extra" sets beyond those in  . However   might be strictly a subclass of  .   is a model of ZFC, which means that it satisfies the following axioms:

  • Axiom of regularity: Every non-empty set   contains some element   such that   and   are disjoint sets.
  is a substructure of  , which is well founded, so   is well founded. In particular, if  , then by the transitivity of  ,  . If we use this same   as in  , then it is still disjoint from   because we are using the same element relation and no new sets were added.
If   and   are in   and they have the same elements in  , then by  's transitivity, they have the same elements (in  ). So they are equal (in   and thus in  ).
 , which is in  . So  . Since the element relation is the same and no new elements were added, this is the empty set of  .
  • Axiom of pairing: If  ,   are sets, then   is a set.
If   and  , then there is some ordinal   such that   and  . Then  . Thus   and it has the same meaning for   as for  .
  • Axiom of union: For any set   there is a set   whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of  .
If  , then its elements are in   and their elements are also in  . So   is a subset of  . Then  . Thus  .
  • Axiom of infinity: There exists a set   such that   is in   and whenever   is in  , so is the union  .
Transfinite induction can be used to show each ordinal   is in  . In particular,   and thus  .
  • Axiom of separation: Given any set   and any proposition  ,   is a set.
By induction on subformulas of  , one can show that there is an   such that   contains   and   and (  is true in   if and only if   is true in  ), the latter is called the "reflection principle"). So   =  . Thus the subset is in  .[6]
  • Axiom of replacement: Given any set   and any mapping (formally defined as a proposition   where   and   implies  ),   is a set.
Let   be the formula that relativizes   to  , i.e. all quantifiers in   are restricted to  .   is a much more complex formula than  , but it is still a finite formula, and since   was a mapping over  ,   must be a mapping over  ; thus we can apply replacement in   to  . So   =   is a set in   and a subclass of  . Again using the axiom of replacement in  , we can show that there must be an   such that this set is a subset of  . Then one can use the axiom of separation in   to finish showing that it is an element of  
  • Axiom of power set: For any set   there exists a set  , such that the elements of   are precisely the subsets of  .
In general, some subsets of a set in   will not be in   So the whole power set of a set in   will usually not be in  . What we need here is to show that the intersection of the power set with   is in  . Use replacement in   to show that there is an α such that the intersection is a subset of  . Then the intersection is  . Thus the required set is in  .
  • Axiom of choice: Given a set   of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set   (a choice set for  ) containing exactly one element from each member of  .
One can show that there is a definable well-ordering of L, in particular based on ordering all sets in   by their definitions and by the rank they appear at. So one chooses the least element of each member of   to form   using the axioms of union and separation in  

Notice that the proof that   is a model of ZFC only requires that   be a model of ZF, i.e. we do not assume that the axiom of choice holds in  .

L is absolute and minimal Edit

If   is any standard model of ZF sharing the same ordinals as  , then the   defined in   is the same as the   defined in  . In particular,   is the same in   and  , for any ordinal  . And the same formulas and parameters in   produce the same constructible sets in  .

Furthermore, since   is a subclass of   and, similarly,   is a subclass of  ,   is the smallest class containing all the ordinals that is a standard model of ZF. Indeed,   is the intersection of all such classes.

If there is a set   in   that is a standard model of ZF, and the ordinal   is the set of ordinals that occur in  , then   is the   of  . If there is a set that is a standard model of ZF, then the smallest such set is such a  . This set is called the minimal model of ZFC. Using the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, one can show that the minimal model (if it exists) is a countable set.

Of course, any consistent theory must have a model, so even within the minimal model of set theory there are sets that are models of ZF (assuming ZF is consistent). However, those set models are non-standard. In particular, they do not use the normal element relation and they are not well founded.

Because both "  constructed within  " and "  constructed within  " result in the real  , and both the   of   and the   of   are the real  , we get that   is true in   and in any   that is a model of ZF. However,   does not hold in any other standard model of ZF.

L and large cardinals Edit

Since  , properties of ordinals that depend on the absence of a function or other structure (i.e.   formulas) are preserved when going down from   to  . Hence initial ordinals of cardinals remain initial in  . Regular ordinals remain regular in  . Weak limit cardinals become strong limit cardinals in   because the generalized continuum hypothesis holds in  . Weakly inaccessible cardinals become strongly inaccessible. Weakly Mahlo cardinals become strongly Mahlo. And more generally, any large cardinal property weaker than 0# (see the list of large cardinal properties) will be retained in  .

However,   is false in   even if true in  . So all the large cardinals whose existence implies   cease to have those large cardinal properties, but retain the properties weaker than   which they also possess. For example, measurable cardinals cease to be measurable but remain Mahlo in  .

If   holds in  , then there is a closed unbounded class of ordinals that are indiscernible in  . While some of these are not even initial ordinals in  , they have all the large cardinal properties weaker than   in  . Furthermore, any strictly increasing class function from the class of indiscernibles to itself can be extended in a unique way to an elementary embedding of   into  .[citation needed] This gives   a nice structure of repeating segments.

L can be well-ordered Edit

There are various ways of well-ordering  . Some of these involve the "fine structure" of  , which was first described by Ronald Bjorn Jensen in his 1972 paper entitled "The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy". Instead of explaining the fine structure, we will give an outline of how   could be well-ordered using only the definition given above.

Suppose   and   are two different sets in   and we wish to determine whether   or  . If   first appears in   and   first appears in   and   is different from  , then let   <   if and only if  . Henceforth, we suppose that  .

The stage   uses formulas with parameters from   to define the sets   and  . If one discounts (for the moment) the parameters, the formulas can be given a standard Gödel numbering by the natural numbers. If   is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define  , and   is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define  , and   is different from  , then let   <   if and only if   in the Gödel numbering. Henceforth, we suppose that  .

Suppose that   uses   parameters from  . Suppose   is the sequence of parameters that can be used with   to define  , and   does the same for  . Then let   if and only if either   or (  and  ) or (  and   and  ), etc. This is called the reverse lexicographic ordering; if there are multiple sequences of parameters that define one of the sets, we choose the least one under this ordering. It being understood that each parameter's possible values are ordered according to the restriction of the ordering of   to  , so this definition involves transfinite recursion on  .

The well-ordering of the values of single parameters is provided by the inductive hypothesis of the transfinite induction. The values of  -tuples of parameters are well-ordered by the product ordering. The formulas with parameters are well-ordered by the ordered sum (by Gödel numbers) of well-orderings. And   is well-ordered by the ordered sum (indexed by  ) of the orderings on  .

Notice that this well-ordering can be defined within   itself by a formula of set theory with no parameters, only the free-variables   and  . And this formula gives the same truth value regardless of whether it is evaluated in  ,  , or   (some other standard model of ZF with the same ordinals) and we will suppose that the formula is false if either   or   is not in  .

It is well known that the axiom of choice is equivalent to the ability to well-order every set. Being able to well-order the proper class   (as we have done here with  ) is equivalent to the axiom of global choice, which is more powerful than the ordinary axiom of choice because it also covers proper classes of non-empty sets.

L has a reflection principle Edit

Proving that the axiom of separation, axiom of replacement, and axiom of choice hold in   requires (at least as shown above) the use of a reflection principle for  . Here we describe such a principle.

By induction on  , we can use ZF in   to prove that for any ordinal  , there is an ordinal   such that for any sentence   with   in   and containing fewer than   symbols (counting a constant symbol for an element of   as one symbol) we get that   holds in   if and only if it holds in  .

The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L Edit

Let  , and let   be any constructible subset of  . Then there is some   with  , so  , for some formula   and some   drawn from  . By the downward Löwenheim–Skolem theorem and Mostowski collapse, there must be some transitive set   containing   and some  , and having the same first-order theory as   with the   substituted for the  ; and this   will have the same cardinal as  . Since   is true in  , it is also true in K, so   for some   having the same cardinal as  . And   because   and   have the same theory. So   is in fact in  .

So all the constructible subsets of an infinite set   have ranks with (at most) the same cardinal   as the rank of  ; it follows that if   is the initial ordinal for  , then   serves as the "power set" of   within   Thus this "power set"  . And this in turn means that the "power set" of   has cardinal at most  . Assuming   itself has cardinal  , the "power set" must then have cardinal exactly  . But this is precisely the generalized continuum hypothesis relativized to  

Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals Edit

There is a formula of set theory that expresses the idea that  . It has only free variables for   and  . Using this we can expand the definition of each constructible set. If  , then   for some formula   and some   in  . This is equivalent to saying that: for all  ,   if and only if [there exists   such that   and   and  ] where   is the result of restricting each quantifier in   to  . Notice that each   for some  . Combine formulas for the  's with the formula for   and apply existential quantifiers over the  's outside and one gets a formula that defines the constructible set   using only the ordinals   that appear in expressions like   as parameters.

Example: The set   is constructible. It is the unique set   that satisfies the formula:

 ,

where   is short for:

 

Actually, even this complex formula has been simplified from what the instructions given in the first paragraph would yield. But the point remains, there is a formula of set theory that is true only for the desired constructible set   and that contains parameters only for ordinals.

Relative constructibility Edit

Sometimes it is desirable to find a model of set theory that is narrow like  , but that includes or is influenced by a set that is not constructible. This gives rise to the concept of relative constructibility, of which there are two flavors, denoted by   and  .

The class   for a non-constructible set   is the intersection of all classes that are standard models of set theory and contain   and all the ordinals.

  is defined by transfinite recursion as follows:

  •   = the smallest transitive set containing   as an element, i.e. the transitive closure of  .
  •   =  
  • If   is a limit ordinal, then  .
  •  .

If   contains a well-ordering of the transitive closure of  , then this can be extended to a well-ordering of  . Otherwise, the axiom of choice will fail in  .

A common example is  , the smallest model that contains all the real numbers, which is used extensively in modern descriptive set theory.

The class   is the class of sets whose construction is influenced by  , where   may be a (presumably non-constructible) set or a proper class. The definition of this class uses  , which is the same as   except instead of evaluating the truth of formulas   in the model  , one uses the model   where   is a unary predicate. The intended interpretation of

constructible, universe, confused, with, gödel, metric, mathematics, theory, constructible, universe, gödel, constructible, universe, denoted, displaystyle, particular, class, sets, that, described, entirely, terms, simpler, sets, displaystyle, union, construc. Not to be confused with Godel metric In mathematics in set theory the constructible universe or Godel s constructible universe denoted by L displaystyle L is a particular class of sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets L displaystyle L is the union of the constructible hierarchy L a displaystyle L alpha It was introduced by Kurt Godel in his 1938 paper The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum Hypothesis 1 In this paper he proved that the constructible universe is an inner model of ZF set theory that is of Zermelo Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice excluded and also that the axiom of choice and the generalized continuum hypothesis are true in the constructible universe This shows that both propositions are consistent with the basic axioms of set theory if ZF itself is consistent Since many other theorems only hold in systems in which one or both of the propositions is true their consistency is an important result Contents 1 What L is 2 Additional facts about the sets L alpha 3 L is a standard inner model of ZFC 4 L is absolute and minimal 4 1 L and large cardinals 5 L can be well ordered 6 L has a reflection principle 7 The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L 8 Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals 9 Relative constructibility 10 See also 11 Notes 12 ReferencesWhat L is EditL displaystyle L nbsp can be thought of as being built in stages resembling the construction of von Neumann universe V displaystyle V nbsp The stages are indexed by ordinals In von Neumann s universe at a successor stage one takes V a 1 displaystyle V alpha 1 nbsp to be the set of all subsets of the previous stage V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp By contrast in Godel s constructible universe L displaystyle L nbsp one uses only those subsets of the previous stage that are definable by a formula in the formal language of set theory with parameters from the previous stage and with the quantifiers interpreted to range over the previous stage By limiting oneself to sets defined only in terms of what has already been constructed one ensures that the resulting sets will be constructed in a way that is independent of the peculiarities of the surrounding model of set theory and contained in any such model Define the Def operator 2 Def X y y X and X F y z 1 z n F is a first order formula and z 1 z n X displaystyle operatorname Def X Bigl y mid y in X text and X in models Phi y z 1 ldots z n Big Phi text is a first order formula and z 1 ldots z n in X Bigr nbsp L displaystyle L nbsp is defined by transfinite recursion as follows L 0 displaystyle L 0 varnothing nbsp L a 1 Def L a displaystyle L alpha 1 operatorname Def L alpha nbsp If l displaystyle lambda nbsp is a limit ordinal then L l a lt l L a displaystyle L lambda bigcup alpha lt lambda L alpha nbsp Here a lt l displaystyle alpha lt lambda nbsp means a displaystyle alpha nbsp precedes l displaystyle lambda nbsp L a O r d L a displaystyle L bigcup alpha in mathbf Ord L alpha nbsp Here Ord denotes the class of all ordinals If z displaystyle z nbsp is an element of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp then z y L a and y z Def L a L a 1 displaystyle z y in L alpha text and y in z in textrm Def L alpha L alpha 1 nbsp 3 So L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp is a subset of L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp which is a subset of the power set of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp Consequently this is a tower of nested transitive sets But L displaystyle L nbsp itself is a proper class The elements of L displaystyle L nbsp are called constructible sets and L displaystyle L nbsp itself is the constructible universe The axiom of constructibility aka V L displaystyle V L nbsp says that every set of V displaystyle V nbsp is constructible i e in L displaystyle L nbsp Additional facts about the sets L alpha EditAn equivalent definition for L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp is For any ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp L a b lt a Def L b displaystyle L alpha bigcup beta lt alpha operatorname Def L beta nbsp For any finite ordinal n displaystyle n nbsp the sets L n displaystyle L n nbsp and V n displaystyle V n nbsp are the same whether V displaystyle V nbsp equals L displaystyle L nbsp or not and thus L w displaystyle L omega nbsp V w displaystyle V omega nbsp their elements are exactly the hereditarily finite sets Equality beyond this point does not hold Even in models of ZFC in which V displaystyle V nbsp equals L displaystyle L nbsp L w 1 displaystyle L omega 1 nbsp is a proper subset of V w 1 displaystyle V omega 1 nbsp and thereafter L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp is a proper subset of the power set of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp for all a gt w displaystyle alpha gt omega nbsp On the other hand V L displaystyle V L nbsp does imply that V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp equals L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp if a w a displaystyle alpha omega alpha nbsp for example if a displaystyle alpha nbsp is inaccessible More generally V L displaystyle V L nbsp implies H a displaystyle H alpha nbsp L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp for all infinite cardinals a displaystyle alpha nbsp If a displaystyle alpha nbsp is an infinite ordinal then there is a bijection between L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp and a displaystyle alpha nbsp and the bijection is constructible So these sets are equinumerous in any model of set theory that includes them As defined above Def X displaystyle textrm Def X nbsp is the set of subsets of X displaystyle X nbsp defined by D 0 displaystyle Delta 0 nbsp formulas with respect to the Levy hierarchy i e formulas of set theory containing only bounded quantifiers that use as parameters only X displaystyle X nbsp and its elements 4 Another definition due to Godel characterizes each L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp as the intersection of the power set of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp with the closure of L a L a displaystyle L alpha cup L alpha nbsp under a collection of nine explicit functions similar to Godel operations This definition makes no reference to definability All arithmetical subsets of w displaystyle omega nbsp and relations on w displaystyle omega nbsp belong to L w 1 displaystyle L omega 1 nbsp because the arithmetic definition gives one in L w 1 displaystyle L omega 1 nbsp Conversely any subset of w displaystyle omega nbsp belonging to L w 1 displaystyle L omega 1 nbsp is arithmetical because elements of L w displaystyle L omega nbsp can be coded by natural numbers in such a way that displaystyle in nbsp is definable i e arithmetic On the other hand L w 2 displaystyle L omega 2 nbsp already contains certain non arithmetical subsets of w displaystyle omega nbsp such as the set of natural numbers coding true arithmetical statements this can be defined from L w 1 displaystyle L omega 1 nbsp displaystyle so it is in L w 2 displaystyle L omega 2 nbsp All hyperarithmetical subsets of w displaystyle omega nbsp and relations on w displaystyle omega nbsp belong to L w 1 C K displaystyle L omega 1 mathrm CK nbsp where w 1 C K displaystyle omega 1 mathrm CK nbsp stands for the Church Kleene ordinal and conversely any subset of w displaystyle omega nbsp that belongs to L w 1 C K displaystyle L omega 1 mathrm CK nbsp is hyperarithmetical 5 L is a standard inner model of ZFC Edit L displaystyle L in nbsp is a standard model i e L displaystyle L nbsp is a transitive class and the interpretation uses the real element relationship so it is well founded L displaystyle L nbsp is an inner model i e it contains all the ordinal numbers of V displaystyle V nbsp and it has no extra sets beyond those in V displaystyle V nbsp However L displaystyle L nbsp might be strictly a subclass of V displaystyle V nbsp L displaystyle L nbsp is a model of ZFC which means that it satisfies the following axioms Axiom of regularity Every non empty set x displaystyle x nbsp contains some element y displaystyle y nbsp such that x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are disjoint sets L displaystyle L in nbsp is a substructure of V displaystyle V in nbsp which is well founded so L displaystyle L nbsp is well founded In particular if y x L displaystyle y in x in L nbsp then by the transitivity of L displaystyle L nbsp y L displaystyle y in L nbsp If we use this same y displaystyle y nbsp as in V displaystyle V nbsp then it is still disjoint from x displaystyle x nbsp because we are using the same element relation and no new sets were added Axiom of extensionality Two sets are the same if they have the same elements If x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are in L displaystyle L nbsp and they have the same elements in L displaystyle L nbsp then by L displaystyle L nbsp s transitivity they have the same elements in V displaystyle V nbsp So they are equal in V displaystyle V nbsp and thus in L displaystyle L nbsp Axiom of empty set is a set L 0 y y L 0 y y displaystyle L 0 y mid y in L 0 land y y nbsp which is in L 1 displaystyle L 1 nbsp So L displaystyle in L nbsp Since the element relation is the same and no new elements were added this is the empty set of L displaystyle L nbsp Axiom of pairing If x displaystyle x nbsp y displaystyle y nbsp are sets then x y displaystyle x y nbsp is a set If x L displaystyle x in L nbsp and y L displaystyle y in L nbsp then there is some ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp such that x L a displaystyle x in L alpha nbsp and y L a displaystyle y in L alpha nbsp Then x y s s L a a n d s x o r s y L a 1 displaystyle x y s mid s in L alpha mathrm and s x mathrm or s y in L alpha 1 nbsp Thus x y L displaystyle x y in L nbsp and it has the same meaning for L displaystyle L nbsp as for V displaystyle V nbsp Axiom of union For any set x displaystyle x nbsp there is a set y displaystyle y nbsp whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of x displaystyle x nbsp If x L a displaystyle x in L alpha nbsp then its elements are in L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp and their elements are also in L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp So y displaystyle y nbsp is a subset of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp Then y s s L a a n d t h e r e e x i s t s z x s u c h t h a t s z L a 1 displaystyle y s mid s in L alpha mathrm and mathrm there mathrm exists z in x mathrm such mathrm that s in z in L alpha 1 nbsp Thus y L displaystyle y in L nbsp Axiom of infinity There exists a set x displaystyle x nbsp such that displaystyle varnothing nbsp is in x displaystyle x nbsp and whenever y displaystyle y nbsp is in x displaystyle x nbsp so is the union y y displaystyle y cup y nbsp Transfinite induction can be used to show each ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp is in L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp In particular w L w 1 displaystyle omega in L omega 1 nbsp and thus w L displaystyle omega in L nbsp Axiom of separation Given any set S displaystyle S nbsp and any proposition P x z 1 z n displaystyle P x z 1 ldots z n nbsp x x S a n d P x z 1 z n displaystyle x mid x in S mathrm and P x z 1 ldots z n nbsp is a set By induction on subformulas of P displaystyle P nbsp one can show that there is an a displaystyle alpha nbsp such that L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp contains S displaystyle S nbsp and z 1 z n displaystyle z 1 ldots z n nbsp and P displaystyle P nbsp is true in L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp if and only if P displaystyle P nbsp is true in L displaystyle L nbsp the latter is called the reflection principle So x x S a n d P x z 1 z n h o l d s i n L displaystyle x mid x in S mathrm and P x z 1 ldots z n mathrm holds mathrm in L nbsp x x L a a n d x S a n d P x z 1 z n h o l d s i n L a L a 1 displaystyle x mid x in L alpha mathrm and x in S mathrm and P x z 1 ldots z n mathrm holds mathrm in L alpha in L alpha 1 nbsp Thus the subset is in L displaystyle L nbsp 6 Axiom of replacement Given any set S displaystyle S nbsp and any mapping formally defined as a proposition P x y displaystyle P x y nbsp where P x y displaystyle P x y nbsp and P x z displaystyle P x z nbsp implies y z displaystyle y z nbsp y t h e r e e x i s t s x S s u c h t h a t P x y displaystyle y mid mathrm there mathrm exists x in S mathrm such mathrm that P x y nbsp is a set Let Q x y displaystyle Q x y nbsp be the formula that relativizes P displaystyle P nbsp to L displaystyle L nbsp i e all quantifiers in P displaystyle P nbsp are restricted to L displaystyle L nbsp Q displaystyle Q nbsp is a much more complex formula than Q displaystyle Q nbsp but it is still a finite formula and since P displaystyle P nbsp was a mapping over L displaystyle L nbsp Q displaystyle Q nbsp must be a mapping over V displaystyle V nbsp thus we can apply replacement in V displaystyle V nbsp to Q displaystyle Q nbsp So y y L a n d t h e r e e x i s t s x S s u c h t h a t P x y h o l d s i n L displaystyle y mid y in L mathrm and mathrm there mathrm exists x in S mathrm such mathrm that P x y mathrm holds mathrm in L nbsp y t h e r e e x i s t s x S s u c h t h a t Q x y displaystyle y mid mathrm there mathrm exists mathrm x in S mathrm such mathrm that Q x y nbsp is a set in V displaystyle V nbsp and a subclass of L displaystyle L nbsp Again using the axiom of replacement in V displaystyle V nbsp we can show that there must be an a displaystyle alpha nbsp such that this set is a subset of L a L a 1 displaystyle L alpha in L alpha 1 nbsp Then one can use the axiom of separation in L displaystyle L nbsp to finish showing that it is an element of L displaystyle L nbsp Axiom of power set For any set x displaystyle x nbsp there exists a set y displaystyle y nbsp such that the elements of y displaystyle y nbsp are precisely the subsets of x displaystyle x nbsp In general some subsets of a set in L displaystyle L nbsp will not be in L displaystyle L nbsp So the whole power set of a set in L displaystyle L nbsp will usually not be in L displaystyle L nbsp What we need here is to show that the intersection of the power set with L displaystyle L nbsp is in L displaystyle L nbsp Use replacement in V displaystyle V nbsp to show that there is an a such that the intersection is a subset of L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp Then the intersection is z z L a a n d z i s a s u b s e t o f x L a 1 displaystyle z mid z in L alpha mathrm and z mathrm is mathrm a mathrm subset mathrm of x in L alpha 1 nbsp Thus the required set is in L displaystyle L nbsp Axiom of choice Given a set x displaystyle x nbsp of mutually disjoint nonempty sets there is a set y displaystyle y nbsp a choice set for x displaystyle x nbsp containing exactly one element from each member of x displaystyle x nbsp One can show that there is a definable well ordering of L in particular based on ordering all sets in L displaystyle L nbsp by their definitions and by the rank they appear at So one chooses the least element of each member of x displaystyle x nbsp to form y displaystyle y nbsp using the axioms of union and separation in L displaystyle L nbsp Notice that the proof that L displaystyle L nbsp is a model of ZFC only requires that V displaystyle V nbsp be a model of ZF i e we do not assume that the axiom of choice holds in V displaystyle V nbsp L is absolute and minimal EditIf W displaystyle W nbsp is any standard model of ZF sharing the same ordinals as V displaystyle V nbsp then the L displaystyle L nbsp defined in W displaystyle W nbsp is the same as the L displaystyle L nbsp defined in V displaystyle V nbsp In particular L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp is the same in W displaystyle W nbsp and V displaystyle V nbsp for any ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp And the same formulas and parameters in D e f L a displaystyle mathrm Def L alpha nbsp produce the same constructible sets in L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp Furthermore since L displaystyle L nbsp is a subclass of V displaystyle V nbsp and similarly L displaystyle L nbsp is a subclass of W displaystyle W nbsp L displaystyle L nbsp is the smallest class containing all the ordinals that is a standard model of ZF Indeed L displaystyle L nbsp is the intersection of all such classes If there is a set W displaystyle W nbsp in V displaystyle V nbsp that is a standard model of ZF and the ordinal k displaystyle kappa nbsp is the set of ordinals that occur in W displaystyle W nbsp then L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp is the L displaystyle L nbsp of W displaystyle W nbsp If there is a set that is a standard model of ZF then the smallest such set is such a L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp This set is called the minimal model of ZFC Using the downward Lowenheim Skolem theorem one can show that the minimal model if it exists is a countable set Of course any consistent theory must have a model so even within the minimal model of set theory there are sets that are models of ZF assuming ZF is consistent However those set models are non standard In particular they do not use the normal element relation and they are not well founded Because both L displaystyle L nbsp constructed within L displaystyle L nbsp and V displaystyle V nbsp constructed within L displaystyle L nbsp result in the real L displaystyle L nbsp and both the L displaystyle L nbsp of L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp and the V displaystyle V nbsp of L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp are the real L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp we get that V L displaystyle V L nbsp is true in L displaystyle L nbsp and in any L k displaystyle L kappa nbsp that is a model of ZF However V L displaystyle V L nbsp does not hold in any other standard model of ZF L and large cardinals Edit Since O r d L V displaystyle mathrm Ord subset L subseteq V nbsp properties of ordinals that depend on the absence of a function or other structure i e P 1 Z F displaystyle Pi 1 mathrm ZF nbsp formulas are preserved when going down from V displaystyle V nbsp to L displaystyle L nbsp Hence initial ordinals of cardinals remain initial in L displaystyle L nbsp Regular ordinals remain regular in L displaystyle L nbsp Weak limit cardinals become strong limit cardinals in L displaystyle L nbsp because the generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L displaystyle L nbsp Weakly inaccessible cardinals become strongly inaccessible Weakly Mahlo cardinals become strongly Mahlo And more generally any large cardinal property weaker than 0 see the list of large cardinal properties will be retained in L displaystyle L nbsp However 0 displaystyle 0 sharp nbsp is false in L displaystyle L nbsp even if true in V displaystyle V nbsp So all the large cardinals whose existence implies 0 displaystyle 0 sharp nbsp cease to have those large cardinal properties but retain the properties weaker than 0 displaystyle 0 sharp nbsp which they also possess For example measurable cardinals cease to be measurable but remain Mahlo in L displaystyle L nbsp If 0 displaystyle 0 sharp nbsp holds in V displaystyle V nbsp then there is a closed unbounded class of ordinals that are indiscernible in L displaystyle L nbsp While some of these are not even initial ordinals in V displaystyle V nbsp they have all the large cardinal properties weaker than 0 displaystyle 0 sharp nbsp in L displaystyle L nbsp Furthermore any strictly increasing class function from the class of indiscernibles to itself can be extended in a unique way to an elementary embedding of L displaystyle L nbsp into L displaystyle L nbsp citation needed This gives L displaystyle L nbsp a nice structure of repeating segments L can be well ordered EditThere are various ways of well ordering L displaystyle L nbsp Some of these involve the fine structure of L displaystyle L nbsp which was first described by Ronald Bjorn Jensen in his 1972 paper entitled The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy Instead of explaining the fine structure we will give an outline of how L displaystyle L nbsp could be well ordered using only the definition given above Suppose x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are two different sets in L displaystyle L nbsp and we wish to determine whether x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp or x gt y displaystyle x gt y nbsp If x displaystyle x nbsp first appears in L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp first appears in L b 1 displaystyle L beta 1 nbsp and b displaystyle beta nbsp is different from a displaystyle alpha nbsp then let x displaystyle x nbsp lt y displaystyle y nbsp if and only if a lt b displaystyle alpha lt beta nbsp Henceforth we suppose that b a displaystyle beta alpha nbsp The stage L a 1 D e f L a displaystyle L alpha 1 mathrm Def L alpha nbsp uses formulas with parameters from L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp to define the sets x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp If one discounts for the moment the parameters the formulas can be given a standard Godel numbering by the natural numbers If F displaystyle Phi nbsp is the formula with the smallest Godel number that can be used to define x displaystyle x nbsp and PS displaystyle Psi nbsp is the formula with the smallest Godel number that can be used to define y displaystyle y nbsp and PS displaystyle Psi nbsp is different from F displaystyle Phi nbsp then let x displaystyle x nbsp lt y displaystyle y nbsp if and only if F lt PS displaystyle Phi lt Psi nbsp in the Godel numbering Henceforth we suppose that PS F displaystyle Psi Phi nbsp Suppose that F displaystyle Phi nbsp uses n displaystyle n nbsp parameters from L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp Suppose z 1 z n displaystyle z 1 ldots z n nbsp is the sequence of parameters that can be used with F displaystyle Phi nbsp to define x displaystyle x nbsp and w 1 w n displaystyle w 1 ldots w n nbsp does the same for y displaystyle y nbsp Then let x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp if and only if either z n lt w n displaystyle z n lt w n nbsp or z n w n displaystyle z n w n nbsp and z n 1 lt w n 1 displaystyle z n 1 lt w n 1 nbsp or z n w n displaystyle z n w n nbsp and z n 1 w n 1 displaystyle z n 1 w n 1 nbsp and z n 2 lt w n 2 displaystyle z n 2 lt w n 2 nbsp etc This is called the reverse lexicographic ordering if there are multiple sequences of parameters that define one of the sets we choose the least one under this ordering It being understood that each parameter s possible values are ordered according to the restriction of the ordering of L displaystyle L nbsp to L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp so this definition involves transfinite recursion on a displaystyle alpha nbsp The well ordering of the values of single parameters is provided by the inductive hypothesis of the transfinite induction The values of n displaystyle n nbsp tuples of parameters are well ordered by the product ordering The formulas with parameters are well ordered by the ordered sum by Godel numbers of well orderings And L displaystyle L nbsp is well ordered by the ordered sum indexed by a displaystyle alpha nbsp of the orderings on L a 1 displaystyle L alpha 1 nbsp Notice that this well ordering can be defined within L displaystyle L nbsp itself by a formula of set theory with no parameters only the free variables x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp And this formula gives the same truth value regardless of whether it is evaluated in L displaystyle L nbsp V displaystyle V nbsp or W displaystyle W nbsp some other standard model of ZF with the same ordinals and we will suppose that the formula is false if either x displaystyle x nbsp or y displaystyle y nbsp is not in L displaystyle L nbsp It is well known that the axiom of choice is equivalent to the ability to well order every set Being able to well order the proper class V displaystyle V nbsp as we have done here with L displaystyle L nbsp is equivalent to the axiom of global choice which is more powerful than the ordinary axiom of choice because it also covers proper classes of non empty sets L has a reflection principle EditProving that the axiom of separation axiom of replacement and axiom of choice hold in L displaystyle L nbsp requires at least as shown above the use of a reflection principle for L displaystyle L nbsp Here we describe such a principle By induction on n lt w displaystyle n lt omega nbsp we can use ZF in V displaystyle V nbsp to prove that for any ordinal a displaystyle alpha nbsp there is an ordinal b gt a displaystyle beta gt alpha nbsp such that for any sentence P z 1 z k displaystyle P z 1 ldots z k nbsp with z 1 z k displaystyle z 1 ldots z k nbsp in L b displaystyle L beta nbsp and containing fewer than n displaystyle n nbsp symbols counting a constant symbol for an element of L b displaystyle L beta nbsp as one symbol we get that P z 1 z k displaystyle P z 1 ldots z k nbsp holds in L b displaystyle L beta nbsp if and only if it holds in L displaystyle L nbsp The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L EditLet S L a displaystyle S in L alpha nbsp and let T displaystyle T nbsp be any constructible subset of S displaystyle S nbsp Then there is some b displaystyle beta nbsp with T L b 1 displaystyle T in L beta 1 nbsp so T x L b x S F x z i x S F x z i displaystyle T x in L beta x in S wedge Phi x z i x in S Phi x z i nbsp for some formula F displaystyle Phi nbsp and some z i displaystyle z i nbsp drawn from L b displaystyle L beta nbsp By the downward Lowenheim Skolem theorem and Mostowski collapse there must be some transitive set K displaystyle K nbsp containing L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp and some w i displaystyle w i nbsp and having the same first order theory as L b displaystyle L beta nbsp with the w i displaystyle w i nbsp substituted for the z i displaystyle z i nbsp and this K displaystyle K nbsp will have the same cardinal as L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp Since V L displaystyle V L nbsp is true in L b displaystyle L beta nbsp it is also true in K so K L g displaystyle K L gamma nbsp for some g displaystyle gamma nbsp having the same cardinal as a displaystyle alpha nbsp And T x L b x S F x z i x L g x S F x w i displaystyle T x in L beta x in S wedge Phi x z i x in L gamma x in S wedge Phi x w i nbsp because L b displaystyle L beta nbsp and L g displaystyle L gamma nbsp have the same theory So T displaystyle T nbsp is in fact in L g 1 displaystyle L gamma 1 nbsp So all the constructible subsets of an infinite set S displaystyle S nbsp have ranks with at most the same cardinal k displaystyle kappa nbsp as the rank of S displaystyle S nbsp it follows that if d displaystyle delta nbsp is the initial ordinal for k displaystyle kappa nbsp then L P S L d displaystyle L cap mathcal P S subseteq L delta nbsp serves as the power set of S displaystyle S nbsp within L displaystyle L nbsp Thus this power set L P S L d 1 displaystyle L cap mathcal P S in L delta 1 nbsp And this in turn means that the power set of S displaystyle S nbsp has cardinal at most d displaystyle vert delta vert nbsp Assuming S displaystyle S nbsp itself has cardinal k displaystyle kappa nbsp the power set must then have cardinal exactly k displaystyle kappa nbsp But this is precisely the generalized continuum hypothesis relativized to L displaystyle L nbsp Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals EditThere is a formula of set theory that expresses the idea that X L a displaystyle X L alpha nbsp It has only free variables for X displaystyle X nbsp and a displaystyle alpha nbsp Using this we can expand the definition of each constructible set If S L a 1 displaystyle S in L alpha 1 nbsp then S y y L a a n d F y z 1 z n h o l d s i n L a displaystyle S y mid y in L alpha mathrm and Phi y z 1 ldots z n mathrm holds mathrm in L alpha in nbsp for some formula F displaystyle Phi nbsp and some z 1 z n displaystyle z 1 ldots z n nbsp in L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp This is equivalent to saying that for all y displaystyle y nbsp y S displaystyle y in S nbsp if and only if there exists X displaystyle X nbsp such that X L a displaystyle X L alpha nbsp and y X displaystyle y in X nbsp and PS X y z 1 z n displaystyle Psi X y z 1 ldots z n nbsp where PS X displaystyle Psi X ldots nbsp is the result of restricting each quantifier in F displaystyle Phi ldots nbsp to X displaystyle X nbsp Notice that each z k L b 1 displaystyle z k in L beta 1 nbsp for some b lt a displaystyle beta lt alpha nbsp Combine formulas for the z displaystyle z nbsp s with the formula for S displaystyle S nbsp and apply existential quantifiers over the z displaystyle z nbsp s outside and one gets a formula that defines the constructible set S displaystyle S nbsp using only the ordinals a displaystyle alpha nbsp that appear in expressions like x L a displaystyle x L alpha nbsp as parameters Example The set 5 w displaystyle 5 omega nbsp is constructible It is the unique set s displaystyle s nbsp that satisfies the formula y y s y L w 1 a a y a L 5 O r d a b b y b L w O r d b displaystyle forall y y in s iff y in L omega 1 land forall a a in y iff a in L 5 land Ord a lor forall b b in y iff b in L omega land Ord b nbsp where O r d a displaystyle Ord a nbsp is short for c a d c d a e d e c displaystyle forall c in a forall d in c d in a land forall e in d e in c nbsp Actually even this complex formula has been simplified from what the instructions given in the first paragraph would yield But the point remains there is a formula of set theory that is true only for the desired constructible set S displaystyle S nbsp and that contains parameters only for ordinals Relative constructibility EditSometimes it is desirable to find a model of set theory that is narrow like L displaystyle L nbsp but that includes or is influenced by a set that is not constructible This gives rise to the concept of relative constructibility of which there are two flavors denoted by L A displaystyle L A nbsp and L A displaystyle L A nbsp The class L A displaystyle L A nbsp for a non constructible set A displaystyle A nbsp is the intersection of all classes that are standard models of set theory and contain A displaystyle A nbsp and all the ordinals L A displaystyle L A nbsp is defined by transfinite recursion as follows L 0 A displaystyle L 0 A nbsp the smallest transitive set containing A displaystyle A nbsp as an element i e the transitive closure of A displaystyle A nbsp L a 1 A displaystyle L alpha 1 A nbsp D e f L a A displaystyle mathrm Def L alpha A nbsp If l displaystyle lambda nbsp is a limit ordinal then L l A a lt l L a A displaystyle L lambda A bigcup alpha lt lambda L alpha A nbsp L A a L a A displaystyle L A bigcup alpha L alpha A nbsp If L A displaystyle L A nbsp contains a well ordering of the transitive closure of A displaystyle A nbsp then this can be extended to a well ordering of L A displaystyle L A nbsp Otherwise the axiom of choice will fail in L A displaystyle L A nbsp A common example is L R displaystyle L mathbb R nbsp the smallest model that contains all the real numbers which is used extensively in modern descriptive set theory The class L A displaystyle L A nbsp is the class of sets whose construction is influenced by A displaystyle A nbsp where A displaystyle A nbsp may be a presumably non constructible set or a proper class The definition of this class uses D e f A X displaystyle mathrm Def A X nbsp which is the same as D e f X displaystyle mathrm Def X nbsp except instead of evaluating the truth of formulas F displaystyle Phi nbsp in the model X displaystyle X in nbsp one uses the model X A displaystyle X in A nbsp where A displaystyle A nbsp is a unary predicate The intended interpretation of span, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.