fbpx
Wikipedia

Reflection principle

In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that, with respect to any given property, resemble the class of all sets. There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending on exactly what is meant by "resemble". Weak forms of the reflection principle are theorems of ZF set theory due to Montague (1961), while stronger forms can be new and very powerful axioms for set theory.

The name "reflection principle" comes from the fact that properties of the universe of all sets are "reflected" down to a smaller set.

Motivation Edit

A naive version of the reflection principle states that "for any property of the universe of all sets we can find a set with the same property". This leads to an immediate contradiction: the universe of all sets contains all sets, but there is no set with the property that it contains all sets. To get useful (and non-contradictory) reflection principles we need to be more careful about what we mean by "property" and what properties we allow.

Reflection principles are associated with attempts to formulate the idea that no one notion, idea, or statement can capture our whole view of the universe of sets.[1] Kurt Gödel described it as follows:[2]

The universe of all sets is structurally indefinable. One possible way to make this statement precise is the following: The universe of sets cannot be uniquely characterized (i.e., distinguished from all its initial segments) by any internal structural property of the membership relation in it which is expressible in any logic of finite or transfinite type, including infinitary logics of any cardinal number. This principle may be considered a generalization of the closure principle.

— 8.7.3, p. 280

All the principles for setting up the axioms of set theory should be reducible to Ackermann's principle: The Absolute is unknowable. The strength of this principle increases as we get stronger and stronger systems of set theory. The other principles are only heuristic principles. Hence, the central principle is the reflection principle, which presumably will be understood better as our experience increases. Meanwhile, it helps to separate out more specific principles which either give some additional information or are not yet seen clearly to be derivable from the reflection principle as we understand it now.

— 8.7.9, p. 283

Generally I believe that, in the last analysis, every axiom of infinity should be derivable from the (extremely plausible) principle that V is indefinable, where definability is to be taken in [a] more and more generalized and idealized sense.

— 8.7.16, p. 285

Georg Cantor expressed similar views on Absolute Infinity: All cardinality properties are satisfied in this number, in which held by a smaller cardinal.

To find non-contradictory reflection principles we might argue informally as follows. Suppose that we have some collection A of methods for forming sets (for example, taking powersets, subsets, the axiom of replacement, and so on). We can imagine taking all sets obtained by repeatedly applying all these methods, and form these sets into a class X, which can be thought of as a model of some set theory. But in light of this view, V is not be exhaustible by a handful of operations, otherwise it would be easily describable from below, this principle is known as inexhaustibility (of V).[3] As a result, V is larger than X. Applying the methods in A to the set X itself would also result in a collection smaller than V, as V is not exhaustible from the image of X under the operations in A. Then we can introduce the following new principle for forming sets: "the collection of all sets obtained from some set by repeatedly applying all methods in the collection A is also a set". After adding this principle to A, V is still not exhaustible by the operations in this new A. This process may be repeated further and further, adding more and more operations to the set A and obtaining larger and larger models X. Each X resembles V in the sense that it shares the property with V of being closed under the operations in A.

We can use this informal argument in two ways. We can try to formalize it in (say) ZF set theory; by doing this we obtain some theorems of ZF set theory, called reflection theorems. Alternatively we can use this argument to motivate introducing new axioms for set theory, such as some axioms asserting existence of large cardinals.[3]

In ZFC Edit

In trying to formalize the argument for the reflection principle of the previous section in ZF set theory, it turns out to be necessary to add some conditions about the collection of properties A (for example, A might be finite). Doing this produces several closely related "reflection theorems" all of which state that we can find a set that is almost a model of ZFC. In contrast to stronger reflection principles, these are provable in ZFC.

One of the most common reflection principles for ZFC is a theorem schema that can be described as follows: for any formula   with parameters, if   is true (in the set-theoretic universe  ), then there is a level   of the cumulative hierarchy such that  . This is known as the Lévy-Montague reflection principle,[4] or the Lévy reflection principle,[5] principally investigated in Lévy (1960) and Montague (1961).[6] Another version of this reflection principle says that for any finite number of formulas of ZFC we can find a set   in the cumulative hierarchy such that all the formulas in the set are absolute for   (which means very roughly that they hold in   if and only if they hold in the universe of all sets). So this says that the set   resembles the universe of all sets, at least as far as the given finite number of formulas is concerned.

Another reflection principle for ZFC is a theorem schema that can be described as follows:[7][8] Let   be a formula with at most free variables  . Then ZFC proves that

 

where   denotes the relativization of   to   (that is, replacing all quantifiers appearing in   of the form   and   by   and  , respectively).

Another form of the reflection principle in ZFC says that for any finite set of axioms of ZFC we can find a countable transitive model satisfying these axioms. (In particular this proves that, unless inconsistent, ZFC is not finitely axiomatizable because if it were it would prove the existence of a model of itself, and hence prove its own consistency, contradicting Gödel's second incompleteness theorem.) This version of the reflection theorem is closely related to the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem.

If   is a strong inaccessible cardinal, then there is a closed unbounded subset   of  , such that for every  , the identity function from   to   is an elementary embedding.

For arithmetic Edit

Reflection principles may be considered for theories of arithmetic which are generally much weaker than ZFC.

For  , a  -model is a model which has the correct truth values of   statements, where   is at the  th level of the analytical hierarchy. A countable  -model of a subsystem of second-order arithmetic consists of a countable set of sets of natural numbers, which may be encoded as a subset of  . The theory   proves the existence of a  -model, also known as a  -model.[9]Theorem VII.2.16

The  -model reflection principle for   formulas states that for any   formula   with   as its only free set variable, for all  , if   holds, then there is a countable coded  -model   where   such that  . An extension   of   by a schema of dependent choice is axiomatized. For any  , the system   is equivalent to  -reflection for   formulas.[9]Theorem VII.7.6

 -model reflection has connections to set-theoretic reflection, for example over the weak set theory KP, adding the schema of reflection of  -formulas to transitive sets (  for all   formulas  ) yields the same  -consequneces as   plus a schema of  -model reflection for   formulas.[10]

As new axioms Edit

Bernays class theory Edit

Paul Bernays used a reflection principle as an axiom for one version of set theory (not Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory, which is a weaker theory). His reflection principle stated roughly that if   is a class with some property, then one can find a transitive set   such that   has the same property when considered as a subset of the "universe"  . This is quite a powerful axiom and implies the existence of several of the smaller large cardinals, such as inaccessible cardinals. (Roughly speaking, the class of all ordinals in ZFC is an inaccessible cardinal apart from the fact that it is not a set, and the reflection principle can then be used to show that there is a set that has the same property, in other words that is an inaccessible cardinal.) Unfortunately, this cannot be axiomatized directly in ZFC, and a class theory like Morse–Kelley set theory normally has to be used. The consistency of Bernays's reflection principle is implied by the existence of an ω-Erdős cardinal.

More precisely, the axioms of Bernays' class theory are:[11]

  1. extensionality
  2. class specification: for any formula   without   free,  
  3. subsets:  
  4. reflection: for any formula  ,  
  5. foundation
  6. choice

where   denotes the powerset.

According to Akihiro Kanamori,[12]: 62  in a 1961 paper, Bernays considered the reflection schema

 

for any formula   without   free, where   asserts that   is transitive. Starting with the observation that set parameters   can appear in   and   can be required to contain them by introducing clauses   into  , Bernays just with this schema established pairing, union, infinity, and replacement, in effect achieving a remarkably economical presentation of ZF.

Others Edit

Some formulations of Ackermann set theory use a reflection principle. Ackermann's axiom states that, for any formula   not mentioning  ,[2]

 

Peter Koellner showed that a general class of reflection principles deemed "intrinsically justified" are either inconsistent or weak, in that they are consistent relative to the Erdös cardinal.[13] However, there are more powerful reflection principles, which are closely related to the various large cardinal axioms. For almost every known large cardinal axiom there is a known reflection principle that implies it, and conversely all but the most powerful known reflection principles are implied by known large cardinal axioms.[11] An example of this is the wholeness axiom,[14] which implies the existence of super-n-huge cardinals for all finite n and its consistency is implied by an I3 rank-into-rank cardinal.

Add an axiom saying that Ord is a Mahlo cardinal — for every closed unbounded class of ordinals C (definable by a formula with parameters), there is a regular ordinal in C. This allows one to derive the existence of strong inaccessible cardinals and much more over any ordinal.

References Edit

  • Jech, Thomas (2002), Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded), Springer, ISBN 3-540-44085-2
  • Kunen, Kenneth (1980), Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs, North-Holland, ISBN 0-444-85401-0
  • Lévy, Azriel (1960), "Axiom schemata of strong infinity in axiomatic set theory", Pacific Journal of Mathematics, 10: 223–238, doi:10.2140/pjm.1960.10.223, ISSN 0030-8730, MR 0124205
  • Montague, Richard (1961), "Fraenkel's addition to the axioms of Zermelo", in Bar-Hillel, Yehoshua; Poznanski, E. I. J.; Rabin, M. O.; Robinson, Abraham (eds.), Essays on the foundations of mathematics, Hebrew Univ., Jerusalem: Magnes Press, pp. 91–114, MR 0163840
  • Reinhardt, W. N. (1974), "Remarks on reflection principles, large cardinals, and elementary embeddings.", Axiomatic set theory, Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., vol. XIII, Part II, Providence, R. I.: Amer. Math. Soc., pp. 189–205, MR 0401475

Citations Edit

  1. ^ Welch, Philip D. (12 November 2019). "Proving Theorems from Reflection". Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics. Synthese Library. Vol. 407. Springer, Cham. pp. 79–97. doi:10.1007/978-3-030-15655-8_4. ISBN 978-3-030-15655-8. S2CID 192577454.
  2. ^ a b Wang, Hao (March 25, 2016). A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy. Bradford Books. pp. 280–285. ISBN 978-0262529167.
  3. ^ a b P. Maddy, "Believing the Axioms. I", pp.501--503. Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 53, no. 2 (1988).
  4. ^ Barton, Neil; Caicedo, Andrés Eduardo; Fuchs, Gunter; Hamkins, Joel David; Reitz, Jonas; Schindler, Ralf (2020). "Inner-Model Reflection Principles". Studia Logica. 108 (3): 573–595. arXiv:1708.06669. doi:10.1007/s11225-019-09860-7. S2CID 255073980.
  5. ^ S. D. Friedman, Evidence for Set-Theoretic Truth and the Hyperuniverse Programme (2016), p.15. Accessed 28 March 2023.
  6. ^ A. Kanamori, The Higher Infinite, p.58. Springer Monographs in Mathematics (2003). ISBN 978-3-540-88866-6.
  7. ^ "Section 3.8 (000F): Reflection principle". The Stacks Project. 2022. Retrieved 7 September 2022.
  8. ^ T. Jech, 'Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, revised and expanded', pp.168--170. Springer Monographs in Mathematics (2006). ISBN 3-540-44085-2
  9. ^ a b S. G. Simpson, Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic (2009)
  10. ^ M. Rathjen, "Proof Theory of Reflection". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, vol. 68, issue 2 (1994), pp.181--224.
  11. ^ a b Marshall R., M. Victoria (1989). "Higher order reflection principles". The Journal of Symbolic Logic. 54 (2): 474–489. doi:10.2307/2274862. JSTOR 2274862. S2CID 250351126. Retrieved 9 September 2022.
  12. ^ Kanamori, Akihiro (March 2009). "Bernays and Set Theory". The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic. 15 (1): 43–69. doi:10.2178/bsl/1231081769. JSTOR 25470304. S2CID 15567244. Retrieved 9 September 2022.
  13. ^ Koellner, Peter (February 2009). "On reflection principles". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 157 (2): 206–219. doi:10.1016/j.apal.2008.09.007.
  14. ^ Corazza, Paul (2000). "The Wholeness Axiom and Laver Sequences". Annals of Pure and Applied Logic. 105 (1–3): 157–260. doi:10.1016/s0168-0072(99)00052-4.

External links Edit

reflection, principle, other, uses, disambiguation, theory, branch, mathematics, reflection, principle, says, that, possible, find, sets, that, with, respect, given, property, resemble, class, sets, there, several, different, forms, reflection, principle, depe. For other uses see Reflection principle disambiguation In set theory a branch of mathematics a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that with respect to any given property resemble the class of all sets There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending on exactly what is meant by resemble Weak forms of the reflection principle are theorems of ZF set theory due to Montague 1961 while stronger forms can be new and very powerful axioms for set theory The name reflection principle comes from the fact that properties of the universe of all sets are reflected down to a smaller set Contents 1 Motivation 2 In ZFC 3 For arithmetic 4 As new axioms 4 1 Bernays class theory 4 2 Others 5 References 5 1 Citations 6 External linksMotivation EditA naive version of the reflection principle states that for any property of the universe of all sets we can find a set with the same property This leads to an immediate contradiction the universe of all sets contains all sets but there is no set with the property that it contains all sets To get useful and non contradictory reflection principles we need to be more careful about what we mean by property and what properties we allow Reflection principles are associated with attempts to formulate the idea that no one notion idea or statement can capture our whole view of the universe of sets 1 Kurt Godel described it as follows 2 The universe of all sets is structurally indefinable One possible way to make this statement precise is the following The universe of sets cannot be uniquely characterized i e distinguished from all its initial segments by any internal structural property of the membership relation in it which is expressible in any logic of finite or transfinite type including infinitary logics of any cardinal number This principle may be considered a generalization of the closure principle 8 7 3 p 280 All the principles for setting up the axioms of set theory should be reducible to Ackermann s principle The Absolute is unknowable The strength of this principle increases as we get stronger and stronger systems of set theory The other principles are only heuristic principles Hence the central principle is the reflection principle which presumably will be understood better as our experience increases Meanwhile it helps to separate out more specific principles which either give some additional information or are not yet seen clearly to be derivable from the reflection principle as we understand it now 8 7 9 p 283 Generally I believe that in the last analysis every axiom of infinity should be derivable from the extremely plausible principle that V is indefinable where definability is to be taken in a more and more generalized and idealized sense 8 7 16 p 285 Georg Cantor expressed similar views on Absolute Infinity All cardinality properties are satisfied in this number in which held by a smaller cardinal To find non contradictory reflection principles we might argue informally as follows Suppose that we have some collection A of methods for forming sets for example taking powersets subsets the axiom of replacement and so on We can imagine taking all sets obtained by repeatedly applying all these methods and form these sets into a class X which can be thought of as a model of some set theory But in light of this view V is not be exhaustible by a handful of operations otherwise it would be easily describable from below this principle is known as inexhaustibility of V 3 As a result V is larger than X Applying the methods in A to the set X itself would also result in a collection smaller than V as V is not exhaustible from the image of X under the operations in A Then we can introduce the following new principle for forming sets the collection of all sets obtained from some set by repeatedly applying all methods in the collection A is also a set After adding this principle to A V is still not exhaustible by the operations in this new A This process may be repeated further and further adding more and more operations to the set A and obtaining larger and larger models X Each X resembles V in the sense that it shares the property with V of being closed under the operations in A We can use this informal argument in two ways We can try to formalize it in say ZF set theory by doing this we obtain some theorems of ZF set theory called reflection theorems Alternatively we can use this argument to motivate introducing new axioms for set theory such as some axioms asserting existence of large cardinals 3 In ZFC EditIn trying to formalize the argument for the reflection principle of the previous section in ZF set theory it turns out to be necessary to add some conditions about the collection of properties A for example A might be finite Doing this produces several closely related reflection theorems all of which state that we can find a set that is almost a model of ZFC In contrast to stronger reflection principles these are provable in ZFC One of the most common reflection principles for ZFC is a theorem schema that can be described as follows for any formula ϕ x 1 x n displaystyle phi x 1 ldots x n nbsp with parameters if ϕ x 1 x n displaystyle phi x 1 ldots x n nbsp is true in the set theoretic universe V displaystyle V nbsp then there is a level V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp of the cumulative hierarchy such that V a ϕ x 1 x n displaystyle V alpha vDash phi x 1 ldots x n nbsp This is known as the Levy Montague reflection principle 4 or the Levy reflection principle 5 principally investigated in Levy 1960 and Montague 1961 6 Another version of this reflection principle says that for any finite number of formulas of ZFC we can find a set V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp in the cumulative hierarchy such that all the formulas in the set are absolute for V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp which means very roughly that they hold in V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp if and only if they hold in the universe of all sets So this says that the set V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp resembles the universe of all sets at least as far as the given finite number of formulas is concerned Another reflection principle for ZFC is a theorem schema that can be described as follows 7 8 Let ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp be a formula with at most free variables x 1 x n displaystyle x 1 ldots x n nbsp Then ZFC proves that N M N x 1 x n M ϕ x 1 x n ϕ M displaystyle forall N exists M supseteq N forall x 1 ldots x n in M phi x 1 ldots x n leftrightarrow phi M nbsp where ϕ M displaystyle phi M nbsp denotes the relativization of ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp to M displaystyle M nbsp that is replacing all quantifiers appearing in ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp of the form x displaystyle forall x nbsp and x displaystyle exists x nbsp by x M displaystyle forall x in M nbsp and x M displaystyle exists x in M nbsp respectively Another form of the reflection principle in ZFC says that for any finite set of axioms of ZFC we can find a countable transitive model satisfying these axioms In particular this proves that unless inconsistent ZFC is not finitely axiomatizable because if it were it would prove the existence of a model of itself and hence prove its own consistency contradicting Godel s second incompleteness theorem This version of the reflection theorem is closely related to the Lowenheim Skolem theorem If k displaystyle kappa nbsp is a strong inaccessible cardinal then there is a closed unbounded subset C displaystyle C nbsp of k displaystyle kappa nbsp such that for every a C displaystyle alpha in C nbsp the identity function from V a displaystyle V alpha nbsp to V k displaystyle V kappa nbsp is an elementary embedding For arithmetic EditReflection principles may be considered for theories of arithmetic which are generally much weaker than ZFC For k 1 displaystyle k geq 1 nbsp a b k displaystyle beta k nbsp model is a model which has the correct truth values of P k 1 displaystyle Pi k 1 nbsp statements where P k 1 displaystyle Pi k 1 nbsp is at the k 1 displaystyle k 1 nbsp th level of the analytical hierarchy A countable b k displaystyle beta k nbsp model of a subsystem of second order arithmetic consists of a countable set of sets of natural numbers which may be encoded as a subset of N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp The theory P 1 1 C A 0 displaystyle Pi 1 1 mathsf CA 0 nbsp proves the existence of a b 1 displaystyle beta 1 nbsp model also known as a b displaystyle beta nbsp model 9 Theorem VII 2 16The b k displaystyle beta k nbsp model reflection principle for S n 1 displaystyle Sigma n 1 nbsp formulas states that for any S n 1 displaystyle Sigma n 1 nbsp formula 8 X displaystyle theta X nbsp with X displaystyle X nbsp as its only free set variable for all X N displaystyle X subseteq mathbb N nbsp if 8 X displaystyle theta X nbsp holds then there is a countable coded b k displaystyle beta k nbsp model M displaystyle M nbsp where X M displaystyle X in M nbsp such that M 8 X displaystyle M vDash theta X nbsp An extension S k 1 D C 0 displaystyle Sigma k 1 mathsf DC 0 nbsp of A C A 0 displaystyle mathsf ACA 0 nbsp by a schema of dependent choice is axiomatized For any 0 k displaystyle 0 leq k nbsp the system S k 2 1 D C 0 displaystyle Sigma k 2 1 mathsf DC 0 nbsp is equivalent to b k 1 displaystyle beta k 1 nbsp reflection for S k 4 1 displaystyle Sigma k 4 1 nbsp formulas 9 Theorem VII 7 6b displaystyle beta nbsp model reflection has connections to set theoretic reflection for example over the weak set theory KP adding the schema of reflection of P n displaystyle Pi n nbsp formulas to transitive sets ϕ z transitive z ϕ z displaystyle phi implies exists z textrm transitive z land phi z nbsp for all P n displaystyle Pi n nbsp formulas ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp yields the same P 4 1 displaystyle Pi 4 1 nbsp consequneces as A C A B I displaystyle mathsf ACA BI nbsp plus a schema of b displaystyle beta nbsp model reflection for P n 1 1 displaystyle Pi n 1 1 nbsp formulas 10 As new axioms EditBernays class theory Edit Paul Bernays used a reflection principle as an axiom for one version of set theory not Von Neumann Bernays Godel set theory which is a weaker theory His reflection principle stated roughly that if A displaystyle A nbsp is a class with some property then one can find a transitive set u displaystyle u nbsp such that A u displaystyle A cap u nbsp has the same property when considered as a subset of the universe u displaystyle u nbsp This is quite a powerful axiom and implies the existence of several of the smaller large cardinals such as inaccessible cardinals Roughly speaking the class of all ordinals in ZFC is an inaccessible cardinal apart from the fact that it is not a set and the reflection principle can then be used to show that there is a set that has the same property in other words that is an inaccessible cardinal Unfortunately this cannot be axiomatized directly in ZFC and a class theory like Morse Kelley set theory normally has to be used The consistency of Bernays s reflection principle is implied by the existence of an w Erdos cardinal More precisely the axioms of Bernays class theory are 11 extensionality class specification for any formula ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp without a displaystyle a nbsp free a b b a ϕ b is a set displaystyle exists a forall b b in a leftrightarrow phi land b text is a set nbsp subsets b a a is a set b is a set displaystyle b subseteq a land a text is a set to b text is a set nbsp reflection for any formula ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp ϕ A u u is a transitive set ϕ P u A u displaystyle phi A to exists u u text is a transitive set land phi mathcal P u A cap u nbsp foundation choicewhere P displaystyle mathcal P nbsp denotes the powerset According to Akihiro Kanamori 12 62 in a 1961 paper Bernays considered the reflection schema ϕ x transitive x ϕ x displaystyle phi to exists x text transitive x land phi x nbsp for any formula ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp without x displaystyle x nbsp free where transitive x displaystyle text transitive x nbsp asserts that x displaystyle x nbsp is transitive Starting with the observation that set parameters a 1 a n displaystyle a 1 ldots a n nbsp can appear in ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp and x displaystyle x nbsp can be required to contain them by introducing clauses y a i y displaystyle exists y a i in y nbsp into ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp Bernays just with this schema established pairing union infinity and replacement in effect achieving a remarkably economical presentation of ZF Others Edit Some formulations of Ackermann set theory use a reflection principle Ackermann s axiom states that for any formula ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp not mentioning V displaystyle V nbsp 2 a V b V x ϕ x V u V x x u ϕ displaystyle a in V land b in V to forall x phi to x in V to exists u in V forall x x in u leftrightarrow phi nbsp Peter Koellner showed that a general class of reflection principles deemed intrinsically justified are either inconsistent or weak in that they are consistent relative to the Erdos cardinal 13 However there are more powerful reflection principles which are closely related to the various large cardinal axioms For almost every known large cardinal axiom there is a known reflection principle that implies it and conversely all but the most powerful known reflection principles are implied by known large cardinal axioms 11 An example of this is the wholeness axiom 14 which implies the existence of super n huge cardinals for all finite n and its consistency is implied by an I3 rank into rank cardinal Add an axiom saying that Ord is a Mahlo cardinal for every closed unbounded class of ordinals C definable by a formula with parameters there is a regular ordinal in C This allows one to derive the existence of strong inaccessible cardinals and much more over any ordinal References EditJech Thomas 2002 Set theory third millennium edition revised and expanded Springer ISBN 3 540 44085 2 Kunen Kenneth 1980 Set Theory An Introduction to Independence Proofs North Holland ISBN 0 444 85401 0 Levy Azriel 1960 Axiom schemata of strong infinity in axiomatic set theory Pacific Journal of Mathematics 10 223 238 doi 10 2140 pjm 1960 10 223 ISSN 0030 8730 MR 0124205 Montague Richard 1961 Fraenkel s addition to the axioms of Zermelo in Bar Hillel Yehoshua Poznanski E I J Rabin M O Robinson Abraham eds Essays on the foundations of mathematics Hebrew Univ Jerusalem Magnes Press pp 91 114 MR 0163840 Reinhardt W N 1974 Remarks on reflection principles large cardinals and elementary embeddings Axiomatic set theory Proc Sympos Pure Math vol XIII Part II Providence R I Amer Math Soc pp 189 205 MR 0401475Citations Edit Welch Philip D 12 November 2019 Proving Theorems from Reflection Reflections on the Foundations of Mathematics Synthese Library Vol 407 Springer Cham pp 79 97 doi 10 1007 978 3 030 15655 8 4 ISBN 978 3 030 15655 8 S2CID 192577454 a b Wang Hao March 25 2016 A Logical Journey From Godel to Philosophy Bradford Books pp 280 285 ISBN 978 0262529167 a b P Maddy Believing the Axioms I pp 501 503 Journal of Symbolic Logic vol 53 no 2 1988 Barton Neil Caicedo Andres Eduardo Fuchs Gunter Hamkins Joel David Reitz Jonas Schindler Ralf 2020 Inner Model Reflection Principles Studia Logica 108 3 573 595 arXiv 1708 06669 doi 10 1007 s11225 019 09860 7 S2CID 255073980 S D Friedman Evidence for Set Theoretic Truth and the Hyperuniverse Programme 2016 p 15 Accessed 28 March 2023 A Kanamori The Higher Infinite p 58 Springer Monographs in Mathematics 2003 ISBN 978 3 540 88866 6 Section 3 8 000F Reflection principle The Stacks Project 2022 Retrieved 7 September 2022 T Jech Set Theory The Third Millennium Edition revised and expanded pp 168 170 Springer Monographs in Mathematics 2006 ISBN 3 540 44085 2 a b S G Simpson Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic 2009 M Rathjen Proof Theory of Reflection Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol 68 issue 2 1994 pp 181 224 a b Marshall R M Victoria 1989 Higher order reflection principles The Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 2 474 489 doi 10 2307 2274862 JSTOR 2274862 S2CID 250351126 Retrieved 9 September 2022 Kanamori Akihiro March 2009 Bernays and Set Theory The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 15 1 43 69 doi 10 2178 bsl 1231081769 JSTOR 25470304 S2CID 15567244 Retrieved 9 September 2022 Koellner Peter February 2009 On reflection principles Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 157 2 206 219 doi 10 1016 j apal 2008 09 007 Corazza Paul 2000 The Wholeness Axiom and Laver Sequences Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 105 1 3 157 260 doi 10 1016 s0168 0072 99 00052 4 External links EditMizar system proof http mizar org version current html zf refle html Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Reflection principle amp oldid 1177680071, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.