fbpx
Wikipedia

Measurable cardinal

In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure on a cardinal κ, or more generally on any set. For a cardinal κ, it can be described as a subdivision of all of its subsets into large and small sets such that κ itself is large, and all singletons {α}, ακ are small, complements of small sets are large and vice versa. The intersection of fewer than κ large sets is again large.[1]

It turns out that uncountable cardinals endowed with a two-valued measure are large cardinals whose existence cannot be proved from ZFC.[2]

The concept of a measurable cardinal was introduced by Stanislaw Ulam in 1930.[3]

Definition

Formally, a measurable cardinal is an uncountable cardinal number κ such that there exists a κ-additive, non-trivial, 0-1-valued measure on the power set of κ. (Here the term κ-additive means that, for any sequence Aα, α<λ of cardinality λ < κ, Aα being pairwise disjoint sets of ordinals less than κ, the measure of the union of the Aα equals the sum of the measures of the individual Aα.)

Equivalently, κ is measurable means that it is the critical point of a non-trivial elementary embedding of the universe V into a transitive class M. This equivalence is due to Jerome Keisler and Dana Scott, and uses the ultrapower construction from model theory. Since V is a proper class, a technical problem that is not usually present when considering ultrapowers needs to be addressed, by what is now called Scott's trick.

Equivalently, κ is a measurable cardinal if and only if it is an uncountable cardinal with a κ-complete, non-principal ultrafilter. Again, this means that the intersection of any strictly less than κ-many sets in the ultrafilter, is also in the ultrafilter.

Properties

Although it follows from ZFC that every measurable cardinal is inaccessible (and is ineffable, Ramsey, etc.), it is consistent with ZF that a measurable cardinal can be a successor cardinal. It follows from ZF + axiom of determinacy that ω1 is measurable,[4] and that every subset of ω1 contains or is disjoint from a closed and unbounded subset.

Ulam showed that the smallest cardinal κ that admits a non-trivial countably-additive two-valued measure must in fact admit a κ-additive measure. (If there were some collection of fewer than κ measure-0 subsets whose union was κ, then the induced measure on this collection would be a counterexample to the minimality of κ.) From there, one can prove (with the Axiom of Choice) that the least such cardinal must be inaccessible.

It is trivial to note that if κ admits a non-trivial κ-additive measure, then κ must be regular. (By non-triviality and κ-additivity, any subset of cardinality less than κ must have measure 0, and then by κ-additivity again, this means that the entire set must not be a union of fewer than κ sets of cardinality less than κ.) Finally, if λ < κ, then it can't be the case that κ ≤ 2λ. If this were the case, then we could identify κ with some collection of 0-1 sequences of length λ. For each position in the sequence, either the subset of sequences with 1 in that position or the subset with 0 in that position would have to have measure 1. The intersection of these λ-many measure 1 subsets would thus also have to have measure 1, but it would contain exactly one sequence, which would contradict the non-triviality of the measure. Thus, assuming the Axiom of Choice, we can infer that κ is a strong limit cardinal, which completes the proof of its inaccessibility.

If κ is measurable and pVκ and M (the ultrapower of V) satisfies ψ(κ,p), then the set of α < κ such that V satisfies ψ(α,p) is stationary in κ (actually a set of measure 1). In particular if ψ is a Π1 formula and V satisfies ψ(κ,p), then M satisfies it and thus V satisfies ψ(α,p) for a stationary set of α < κ. This property can be used to show that κ is a limit of most types of large cardinals that are weaker than measurable. Notice that the ultrafilter or measure witnessing that κ is measurable cannot be in M since the smallest such measurable cardinal would have to have another such below it, which is impossible.

If one starts with an elementary embedding j1 of V into M1 with critical point κ, then one can define an ultrafilter U on κ as { S⊆κ : κ∈j1(S) }. Then taking an ultrapower of V over U we can get another elementary embedding j2 of V into M2. However, it is important to remember that j2j1. Thus other types of large cardinals such as strong cardinals may also be measurable, but not using the same embedding. It can be shown that a strong cardinal κ is measurable and also has κ-many measurable cardinals below it.

Every measurable cardinal κ is a 0-huge cardinal because κMM, that is, every function from κ to M is in M. Consequently, Vκ+1M.

Implications of existence

If a measurable cardinal exists, every   (with respect to the Borel hierarchy) set of reals has a Lebesgue measure.[4] In particular, any non-measurable set of reals must not be  .

Real-valued measurable

A cardinal κ is called real-valued measurable if there is a κ-additive probability measure on the power set of κ that vanishes on singletons. Real-valued measurable cardinals were introduced by Stefan Banach (1930). Banach & Kuratowski (1929) showed that the continuum hypothesis implies that   is not real-valued measurable. Stanislaw Ulam (1930) showed (see below for parts of Ulam's proof) that real valued measurable cardinals are weakly inaccessible (they are in fact weakly Mahlo). All measurable cardinals are real-valued measurable, and a real-valued measurable cardinal κ is measurable if and only if κ is greater than  . Thus a cardinal is measurable if and only if it is real-valued measurable and strongly inaccessible. A real valued measurable cardinal less than or equal to   exists if and only if there is a countably additive extension of the Lebesgue measure to all sets of real numbers if and only if there is an atomless probability measure on the power set of some non-empty set.

Solovay (1971) showed that existence of measurable cardinals in ZFC, real valued measurable cardinals in ZFC, and measurable cardinals in ZF, are equiconsistent.

Weak inaccessibility of real-valued measurable cardinals

Say that a cardinal number α is an Ulam number if[5][nb 1]

whenever

μ is an outer measure on a set X,

 

 

 

 

(1)

 

 

 

 

 

(2)

 

 

 

 

 

(3)

all   are μ-measurable,

 

 

 

 

(4)

then

 

Equivalently, a cardinal number α is an Ulam number if

whenever

  1. ν is an outer measure on a set Y, and F a disjoint family of subsets of Y,
  2.  
  3.   for  
  4.   is ν-measurable for every  

then

 

The smallest infinite cardinal   is an Ulam number. The class of Ulam numbers is closed under the cardinal successor operation.[6] If an infinite cardinal β has an immediate predecessor α that is an Ulam number, assume μ satisfies properties (1)–(4) with  . In the von Neumann model of ordinals and cardinals, choose injective functions

 

and define the sets

 

Since the   are one-to-one, the sets

 
 

are disjoint. By property (2) of μ, the set

 

is countable, and hence

 

Thus there is a   such that

 

implying, since α is an Ulam number and using the second definition (with   and conditions (1)–(4) fulfilled),

 

If   then   Thus

 

By property (2),   and since  , by (4), (2) and (3),   It follows that   The conclusion is that β is an Ulam number.

There is a similar proof[7] that the supremum of a set S of Ulam numbers with   an Ulam number is again a Ulam number. Together with the previous result, this implies that a cardinal that is not an Ulam number is weakly inaccessible.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ The notion in the article Ulam number is different.

Citations

  1. ^ Maddy 1988
  2. ^ Jech 2002
  3. ^ Ulam 1930
  4. ^ a b T. Jech, "The Brave New World of Determinacy" (PDF download). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 5, number 3, November 1981 (pp.339--349).
  5. ^ Federer 1996, Section 2.1.6
  6. ^ Federer 1996, Second part of theorem in section 2.1.6.
  7. ^ Federer 1996, First part of theorem in section 2.1.6.

References

  • Banach, Stefan (1930), "Über additive Maßfunktionen in abstrakten Mengen", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 15: 97–101, doi:10.4064/fm-15-1-97-101, ISSN 0016-2736.
  • Banach, Stefan; Kuratowski, Kazimierz (1929), "Sur une généralisation du probleme de la mesure", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 14: 127–131, doi:10.4064/fm-14-1-127-131, ISSN 0016-2736.
  • Drake, F. R. (1974), Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; V. 76), Elsevier Science Ltd, ISBN 978-0-7204-2279-5.
  • Federer, H. (1996) [1969], Geometric Measure Theory, Classics in Mathematics (1st ed reprint ed.), Berlin, Heidelberg, New York: Springer Verlag, ISBN 978-3540606567.
  • Jech, Thomas (2002), Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded), Springer, ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
  • Kanamori, Akihiro (2003), The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings (2nd ed.), Springer, ISBN 3-540-00384-3.
  • Maddy, Penelope (1988), "Believing the Axioms. II", The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 53 (3): 736–764, doi:10.2307/2274569, JSTOR 2274569, S2CID 16544090. A copy of parts I and II of this article with corrections is available at the author's web page.
  • Solovay, Robert M. (1971), "Real-valued measurable cardinals", Axiomatic set theory (Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., Vol. XIII, Part I, Univ. California, Los Angeles, Calif., 1967), Providence, R.I.: Amer. Math. Soc., pp. 397–428, MR 0290961.
  • Ulam, Stanislaw (1930), "Zur Masstheorie in der allgemeinen Mengenlehre", Fundamenta Mathematicae, 16: 140–150, doi:10.4064/fm-16-1-140-150, ISSN 0016-2736.

measurable, cardinal, mathematics, measurable, cardinal, certain, kind, large, cardinal, number, order, define, concept, introduces, valued, measure, cardinal, more, generally, cardinal, described, subdivision, subsets, into, large, small, sets, such, that, it. In mathematics a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number In order to define the concept one introduces a two valued measure on a cardinal k or more generally on any set For a cardinal k it can be described as a subdivision of all of its subsets into large and small sets such that k itself is large and all singletons a a k are small complements of small sets are large and vice versa The intersection of fewer than k large sets is again large 1 It turns out that uncountable cardinals endowed with a two valued measure are large cardinals whose existence cannot be proved from ZFC 2 The concept of a measurable cardinal was introduced by Stanislaw Ulam in 1930 3 Contents 1 Definition 2 Properties 3 Implications of existence 4 Real valued measurable 4 1 Weak inaccessibility of real valued measurable cardinals 5 See also 6 Notes 7 Citations 8 ReferencesDefinition EditFormally a measurable cardinal is an uncountable cardinal number k such that there exists a k additive non trivial 0 1 valued measure on the power set of k Here the term k additive means that for any sequence Aa a lt l of cardinality l lt k Aa being pairwise disjoint sets of ordinals less than k the measure of the union of the Aa equals the sum of the measures of the individual Aa Equivalently k is measurable means that it is the critical point of a non trivial elementary embedding of the universe V into a transitive class M This equivalence is due to Jerome Keisler and Dana Scott and uses the ultrapower construction from model theory Since V is a proper class a technical problem that is not usually present when considering ultrapowers needs to be addressed by what is now called Scott s trick Equivalently k is a measurable cardinal if and only if it is an uncountable cardinal with a k complete non principal ultrafilter Again this means that the intersection of any strictly less than k many sets in the ultrafilter is also in the ultrafilter Properties EditAlthough it follows from ZFC that every measurable cardinal is inaccessible and is ineffable Ramsey etc it is consistent with ZF that a measurable cardinal can be a successor cardinal It follows from ZF axiom of determinacy that w1 is measurable 4 and that every subset of w1 contains or is disjoint from a closed and unbounded subset Ulam showed that the smallest cardinal k that admits a non trivial countably additive two valued measure must in fact admit a k additive measure If there were some collection of fewer than k measure 0 subsets whose union was k then the induced measure on this collection would be a counterexample to the minimality of k From there one can prove with the Axiom of Choice that the least such cardinal must be inaccessible It is trivial to note that if k admits a non trivial k additive measure then k must be regular By non triviality and k additivity any subset of cardinality less than k must have measure 0 and then by k additivity again this means that the entire set must not be a union of fewer than k sets of cardinality less than k Finally if l lt k then it can t be the case that k 2l If this were the case then we could identify k with some collection of 0 1 sequences of length l For each position in the sequence either the subset of sequences with 1 in that position or the subset with 0 in that position would have to have measure 1 The intersection of these l many measure 1 subsets would thus also have to have measure 1 but it would contain exactly one sequence which would contradict the non triviality of the measure Thus assuming the Axiom of Choice we can infer that k is a strong limit cardinal which completes the proof of its inaccessibility If k is measurable and p Vk and M the ultrapower of V satisfies ps k p then the set of a lt k such that V satisfies ps a p is stationary in k actually a set of measure 1 In particular if ps is a P1 formula and V satisfies ps k p then M satisfies it and thus V satisfies ps a p for a stationary set of a lt k This property can be used to show that k is a limit of most types of large cardinals that are weaker than measurable Notice that the ultrafilter or measure witnessing that k is measurable cannot be in M since the smallest such measurable cardinal would have to have another such below it which is impossible If one starts with an elementary embedding j1 of V into M1 with critical point k then one can define an ultrafilter U on k as S k k j1 S Then taking an ultrapower of V over U we can get another elementary embedding j2 of V into M2 However it is important to remember that j2 j1 Thus other types of large cardinals such as strong cardinals may also be measurable but not using the same embedding It can be shown that a strong cardinal k is measurable and also has k many measurable cardinals below it Every measurable cardinal k is a 0 huge cardinal because kM M that is every function from k to M is in M Consequently Vk 1 M Implications of existence EditIf a measurable cardinal exists every S 2 1 displaystyle boldsymbol Sigma 2 1 with respect to the Borel hierarchy set of reals has a Lebesgue measure 4 In particular any non measurable set of reals must not be S 2 1 displaystyle boldsymbol Sigma 2 1 Real valued measurable EditA cardinal k is called real valued measurable if there is a k additive probability measure on the power set of k that vanishes on singletons Real valued measurable cardinals were introduced by Stefan Banach 1930 Banach amp Kuratowski 1929 showed that the continuum hypothesis implies that c displaystyle mathfrak c is not real valued measurable Stanislaw Ulam 1930 showed see below for parts of Ulam s proof that real valued measurable cardinals are weakly inaccessible they are in fact weakly Mahlo All measurable cardinals are real valued measurable and a real valued measurable cardinal k is measurable if and only if k is greater than c displaystyle mathfrak c Thus a cardinal is measurable if and only if it is real valued measurable and strongly inaccessible A real valued measurable cardinal less than or equal to c displaystyle mathfrak c exists if and only if there is a countably additive extension of the Lebesgue measure to all sets of real numbers if and only if there is an atomless probability measure on the power set of some non empty set Solovay 1971 showed that existence of measurable cardinals in ZFC real valued measurable cardinals in ZFC and measurable cardinals in ZF are equiconsistent Weak inaccessibility of real valued measurable cardinals Edit Say that a cardinal number a is an Ulam number if 5 nb 1 whenever m is an outer measure on a set X 1 m X lt displaystyle mu X lt infty 2 m x 0 x X displaystyle mu x 0 x in X 3 all A X displaystyle A subset X are m measurable 4 then card X a m X 0 displaystyle operatorname card X leq alpha Rightarrow mu X 0 dd Equivalently a cardinal number a is an Ulam number ifwhenever n is an outer measure on a set Y and F a disjoint family of subsets of Y n F lt displaystyle nu left bigcup F right lt infty n A 0 displaystyle nu A 0 for A F displaystyle A in F G displaystyle bigcup G is n measurable for every G F displaystyle G subset F then card F a n F 0 displaystyle operatorname card F leq alpha Rightarrow nu left bigcup F right 0 dd The smallest infinite cardinal ℵ 0 displaystyle aleph 0 is an Ulam number The class of Ulam numbers is closed under the cardinal successor operation 6 If an infinite cardinal b has an immediate predecessor a that is an Ulam number assume m satisfies properties 1 4 with X b displaystyle X beta In the von Neumann model of ordinals and cardinals choose injective functions f x x a x b displaystyle f x x rightarrow alpha quad forall x in beta and define the sets U b a x b f x b a a a b b displaystyle U b a x in beta f x b a quad a in alpha b in beta Since the f x displaystyle f x are one to one the sets U b a b b a fixed displaystyle left U b a b in beta right text a text fixed U b a a a b fixed displaystyle left U b a a in alpha right text b text fixed are disjoint By property 2 of m the set b b m U b a gt 0 displaystyle left b in beta mu U b a gt 0 right is countable and hence card b a b a m U b a gt 0 ℵ 0 a a displaystyle operatorname card left b a in beta times alpha mu U b a gt 0 right leq aleph 0 cdot alpha alpha Thus there is a b 0 displaystyle b 0 such that m U b 0 a 0 a a displaystyle mu U b 0 a 0 quad forall a in alpha implying since a is an Ulam number and using the second definition with n m displaystyle nu mu and conditions 1 4 fulfilled m a a U b 0 a 0 displaystyle mu left bigcup a in alpha U b 0 a right 0 If b 0 lt x lt b displaystyle b 0 lt x lt beta then f x b 0 a x x U b 0 a x displaystyle f x b 0 a x Rightarrow x in U b 0 a x Thus b b 0 b 0 a a U b 0 a displaystyle beta b 0 cup b 0 cup bigcup a in alpha U b 0 a By property 2 m b 0 0 displaystyle mu b 0 0 and since card b 0 a displaystyle operatorname card b 0 leq alpha by 4 2 and 3 m b 0 0 displaystyle mu b 0 0 It follows that m b 0 displaystyle mu beta 0 The conclusion is that b is an Ulam number There is a similar proof 7 that the supremum of a set S of Ulam numbers with card S displaystyle operatorname card S an Ulam number is again a Ulam number Together with the previous result this implies that a cardinal that is not an Ulam number is weakly inaccessible See also EditNormal measure Mitchell order List of large cardinal propertiesNotes Edit The notion in the article Ulam number is different Citations Edit Maddy 1988 Jech 2002harvnb error no target CITEREFJech2002 help Ulam 1930 a b T Jech The Brave New World of Determinacy PDF download Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society vol 5 number 3 November 1981 pp 339 349 Federer 1996 Section 2 1 6 Federer 1996 Second part of theorem in section 2 1 6 Federer 1996 First part of theorem in section 2 1 6 References EditBanach Stefan 1930 Uber additive Massfunktionen in abstrakten Mengen Fundamenta Mathematicae 15 97 101 doi 10 4064 fm 15 1 97 101 ISSN 0016 2736 Banach Stefan Kuratowski Kazimierz 1929 Sur une generalisation du probleme de la mesure Fundamenta Mathematicae 14 127 131 doi 10 4064 fm 14 1 127 131 ISSN 0016 2736 Drake F R 1974 Set Theory An Introduction to Large Cardinals Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics V 76 Elsevier Science Ltd ISBN 978 0 7204 2279 5 Federer H 1996 1969 Geometric Measure Theory Classics in Mathematics 1st ed reprint ed Berlin Heidelberg New York Springer Verlag ISBN 978 3540606567 Jech Thomas 2002 Set theory third millennium edition revised and expanded Springer ISBN 3 540 44085 2 Kanamori Akihiro 2003 The Higher Infinite Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings 2nd ed Springer ISBN 3 540 00384 3 Maddy Penelope 1988 Believing the Axioms II The Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 3 736 764 doi 10 2307 2274569 JSTOR 2274569 S2CID 16544090 A copy of parts I and II of this article with corrections is available at the author s web page Solovay Robert M 1971 Real valued measurable cardinals Axiomatic set theory Proc Sympos Pure Math Vol XIII Part I Univ California Los Angeles Calif 1967 Providence R I Amer Math Soc pp 397 428 MR 0290961 Ulam Stanislaw 1930 Zur Masstheorie in der allgemeinen Mengenlehre Fundamenta Mathematicae 16 140 150 doi 10 4064 fm 16 1 140 150 ISSN 0016 2736 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Measurable cardinal amp oldid 1133916725, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.