fbpx
Wikipedia

Bhartṛhari

Bhartṛhari (Devanagari: भर्तृहरि; also romanised as Bhartrihari; fl. c. 5th century CE) was a Hindu linguistic philosopher[1] to whom are normally ascribed two influential Sanskrit texts:

  • the Trikāṇḍī (including Vākyapadīya), on Sanskrit grammar and linguistic philosophy, a foundational text in the Indian grammatical tradition, explaining numerous theories on the word and on the sentence, including theories which came to be known under the name of Sphoṭa; in this work Bhartrhari also discussed logical problems such as the liar paradox and a paradox of unnameability or unsignifiability which has become known as Bhartrhari's paradox, and
  • the Śatakatraya, a work of Sanskrit poetry, comprising three collections of about 100 stanzas each; it may or may not be by the same author who composed the two mentioned grammatical works.

In the medieval tradition of Indian scholarship, it was assumed that both texts were written by the same person.[citation needed] Modern philologists were sceptical of this claim, owing to an argument that dated the grammar to a date subsequent to the poetry.[citation needed] Since the 1990s, however, scholars have agreed that both works may indeed have been contemporary, in which case it is plausible that there was only one Bhartrihari who wrote both texts.[citation needed]

Both the grammar and the poetic works had an enormous influence in their respective fields. The grammar in particular, takes a holistic view of language, countering the compositionality position of the Mimamsakas and others.

According to Aithihyamala, he is also credited with some other texts like Harikītika and Amaru Shataka.

The poetry constitute short verses, collected into three centuries of about a hundred poems each. Each century deals with a different rasa or aesthetic mood; on the whole his poetic work has been very highly regarded both within the tradition and by modern scholarship.

The name Bhartrihari is also sometimes associated with Bhartrihari traya Shataka, the legendary king of Ujjaini in the 1st century.

Date and identity

The account of the Chinese traveller Yi-Jing indicates that Bhartrihari's grammar was known by 670 CE, and that he may have been Buddhist, which the poet was not. Based on this, scholarly opinion had formerly attributed the grammar to a separate author of the same name from the 7th century CE.[2] However, other evidence indicates a much earlier date:

Bhartrihari was long believed to have lived in the seventh century CE, but according to the testimony of the Chinese pilgrim Yijing [...] he was known to the Buddhist philosopher Dignaga, and this has pushed his date back to the fifth century CE.

— [3]

A period of c. 450–500[4] "definitely not later than 425–450",[5] or, following Erich Frauwallner, 450–510[6][7] or perhaps 400 CE or even earlier.[8]

Yi-Jing's other claim, that Bhartrihari was a Buddhist, does not seem to hold; his philosophical position is widely held to be an offshoot of the Vyakarana or grammarian school, closely allied to the realism of the Naiyayikas and distinctly opposed to Buddhist positions like Dignaga, who are closer to phenomenalism. It is also opposed to other Mimamsakas like Kumarila Bhatta.[9][10] However, some of his ideas subsequently influenced some Buddhist schools, which may have led Yi-Jing to surmise that he may have been Buddhist.

Thus, on the whole it seems likely that the traditional Sanskritist view, that the poet of the Śatakatraya is the same as the grammarian Bhartṛhari, may be accepted.

The leading Sanskrit scholar Ingalls (1968) submitted that "I see no reason why he should not have written poems as well as grammar and metaphysics", like Dharmakirti, Shankaracharya, and many others.[11] Yi Jing himself appeared to think they were the same person, as he wrote that (the grammarian) Bhartṛhari, author of the Vakyapadiya, was renowned for his vacillation between Buddhist monkhood and a life of pleasure, and for having written verses on the subject.[12][13]

Vākyapadīya

Bhartrihari's views on language build on that of earlier grammarians such as Patanjali, but were quite radical. A key element of his conception of language is the notion of sphoṭa – a term that may be based on an ancient grammarian, Sphoṭāyana, referred by Pāṇini,[14] now lost.

In his Mahabhashya, Patanjali (2nd century BCE) uses the term sphoṭa to denote the sound of language, the universal, while the actual sound (dhvani) may be long or short, or vary in other ways. This distinction may be thought to be similar to that of the present notion of phoneme. Bhatrihari however, applies the term sphota to each element of the utterance, varṇa the letter or syllable, pada the word, and vākya the sentence. To create the linguistic invariant, he argues that these must be treated as separate wholes (varṇasphoṭa, padasphoṭa and vākyasphoṭa respectively). For example, the same speech sound or varṇa may have different properties in different word contexts (e.g. assimilation), so that the sound cannot be discerned until the whole word is heard.

Further, Bhartrihari argues for a sentence-holistic view of meaning, saying that the meaning of an utterance is known only after the entire sentence (vākyasphoṭa) has been received, and it is not composed from the individual atomic elements or linguistic units which may change their interpretation based on later elements in the utterance. Further, words are understood only in the context of the sentence whose meaning as a whole is known. His argument for this was based on language acquisition, e.g. consider a child observing the exchange below:

elder adult (uttama-vṛddha "full-grown"): says "bring the horse"
younger adult (madhyama-vṛddha "half-grown"): reacts by bringing the horse

The child observing this may now learn that the unit "horse" refers to the animal. Unless the child knew the sentence meaning a priori, it would be difficult for him to infer the meaning of novel words. Thus, we grasp the sentence meaning as a whole, and reach words as parts of the sentence, and word meanings as parts of the sentence meaning through "analysis, synthesis and abstraction" (apoddhāra).[9]

The sphoṭa theory was influential, but it was opposed by many others. Later Mimamsakas like Kumarila Bhatta (c. 650 CE) strongly rejected the vākyasphoṭa view, and argued for the denotative power of each word, arguing for the composition of meanings (abhihitānvaya). The Prabhakara school (c. 670) among Mimamsakas however took a less atomistic position, arguing that word meanings exist, but are determined by context (anvitābhidhāna).

In a section of the chapter on Relation Bhartrhari discusses the liar paradox and identifies a hidden parameter which turns an unproblematic situation in daily life into a stubborn paradox. In addition, Bhartrhari discusses here a paradox that has been called "Bhartrhari's paradox" by Hans and Radhika Herzberger.[15] This paradox arises from the statement "this is unnameable" or "this is unsignifiable".

The Mahābhāṣya-dīpikā (also Mahābhāṣya-ṭīkā) is an early subcommentary on Patanjali's Vyākaraṇa-Mahābhāṣya, also attributed to Bhartṛhari.[16]

Śatakatraya

Bhartrihari's poetry is aphoristic, and comments on the social mores of the time. The collected work is known as Śatakatraya "the three śatakas or 'hundreds' ('centuries')", consisting of three thematic compilations on shringara, vairagya and niti (loosely: love, dispassion and moral conduct) of hundred verses each.

Unfortunately, the extant manuscript versions of these shatakas vary widely in the verses included. D.D. Kosambi has identified a kernel of two hundred that are common to all the versions.[11]

Here is a sample that comments on social mores:

And here is one dealing with the theme of love:

The clear bright flame of a man's discernment dies
When a girl clouds it with her lamp-black eyes. [Bhartrihari #77, tr. John Brough; poem 167][18]

Bhartrhari's paradox

Bhartrhari's paradox is the title of a 1981 paper by Hans and Radhika Herzberger[15] which drew attention to the discussion of self-referential paradoxes in the work Vākyapadīya attributed to Bhartṛhari.

In the chapter dealing with logical and linguistic relations, the Sambandha-samuddeśa, Bhartrhari discusses several statements of a paradoxical nature, including sarvam mithyā bravīmi "everything I am saying is false" which belongs to the liar paradox family, as well as the paradox arising from the statement that something is unnameable or unsignifiable (in Sanskrit: avācya): this becomes nameable or signifiable precisely by calling it unnameable or unsignifiable. When applied to integers, the latter is known today as Berry paradox.

Bhartrhari's interest lies not in strengthening this and other paradoxes by abstracting them from pragmatic context, but rather in exploring how a stubborn paradox may arise from unproblematic situations in daily communication.

An unproblematic situation of communication is turned into a paradox — we have either contradiction (virodha) or infinite regress (anavasthā) — when abstraction is made from the signification and its extension in time, by accepting a simultaneous, opposite function (apara vyāpāra) undoing the previous one.[19]

For Bhartrhari it is important to analyse and solve the unsignifiability paradox because he holds that what cannot be signified may nevertheless be indicated (vyapadiśyate) and it may be understood (pratīyate) to exist.

Works

Works attributed to Bhartr-hari include:[20]

  • Trikāṇḍī ("three books"), sometimes known under the inaccurate title Vakyapadiya
    • The author wrote the commentaries (vṛttis) on the first two books, and probably died before he could do it for the third book. The title Trikāṇḍī was probably not chosen by the author, who originally conceived them as "relatively independent" works, but later thought of unifying them.[21]
  • Tripadi, also known as Mahabhashya-tika or Mahabhashya-dipika
    • The earliest commentators on the text call it Tripadi, and the title Mahabhashya-dipika is known only from one manuscript.[22]
    • The author probably intended to write a commentary on the entire text, but died after completing the work on the three padas of Maha-bhashya. The title Tripadi was probably coined by someone other than the author.[23]
    • The currently surviving version of the work covers only the first seven ahnikas of hte first pada of Mahabhashya. It is known from a fragmentary manuscript.[24]
  • Shabda-dhatu-samiksha, now lost
    • This work is attributed to Bharthari by the Kashmiri Shaivite authors Soma-nanda and Utpalacharya (9th-10th centuries). According to Utpalacharya, in this work, Bharthari described the concept of pashyanti, which he also discusses in the Trikandi.[25]
  • Possibly, a commentary on Jaimini's Mimamsa Sutras

Tradition also attributes several other works to "Bharthari", although the authenticity of such attributions is doubtful.[26] For example, tradition identifies Bharthari the grammarian with the poet who composed Subhashita-tri-shati, a work said to contain 300 stanzas. However, the number of stanzas in the surviving text is much more than 300, which complicates the identification of its actual author.[25]

See also

Regarding Bhartrhari's paradox, see:

  • B. K. Matilal, 1990, The Word and the World: India's Contribution to the Study of Language. Delhi: Oxford University Press. p. 129-130.
  • Hemanta Kumar Ganguli, "Theory of Logical Construction and Solution of some Logical Paradoxes" , appendix to Philosophy of Logical Construction: An Examination of Logical Atomism and Logical Positivism in the light of the Philosophies of Bhartrhari, Dharmakirti and Prajnakaragupta, Calcutta, 1963.
  • Jan E.M. Houben, The Sambandha-samuddeśa (chapter on relation) and Bhartrhari's philosophy of language, Gonda Indological Series, 2. Groningen: Egbert Forsten, 1995, pp. 213–219.

References

  1. ^ Cornille, Catherine (8 June 2020). The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Inter-Religious Dialogue. John Wiley & Sons. p. 199. ISBN 978-1-119-57259-6.
  2. ^ Hajime Nakamura (1990), A history of early Vedānta philosophy, Part 1, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., p. 80, ISBN 978-81-208-0651-1
  3. ^ Edward Craig, ed. (1998), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, Taylor & Francis, p. 764, ISBN 978-0-415-16916-5
  4. ^ Harold G. Coward (1976), Bhartṛhari, Twayne Publishers, ISBN 978-0-8057-6243-3
  5. ^ Saroja Bhate; Johannes Bronkhorst, eds. (1994), Bhartṛhari, philosopher and grammarian: Proceedings of the First International Conference on Bhartṛhari (University of Poona, January 6–8, 1992), Motilal Banarsidass Publ., p. 21, ISBN 978-81-208-1198-0
  6. ^ Mulakaluri Srimannarayana Murti (1997), Bhartṛhari, the grammarian, Sahitya Akademi, p. 10, ISBN 978-81-260-0308-2
  7. ^ Harold G. Coward; Karl H. Potter; K. Kunjunni Raja, eds. (1990), Encyclopedia of Indian philosophies: The philosophy of the grammarians, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., p. 121, ISBN 978-81-208-0426-5
  8. ^ George Cardona (1998), Pāṇini: a survey of research, Motilal Banarsidass Publ., p. 298, ISBN 978-81-208-1494-3. Detailed discussion, see also notes on p. 366.
  9. ^ a b Bimal Krishna Matilal (1990). The Word and the World: India's contribution to the study of language. Oxford University Press.
  10. ^ N. V. Isaeva (1995), From early Vedanta to Kashmir Shaivism: Gaudapada, Bhartrhari, and Abhinavagupta, SUNY Press, p. 75, ISBN 978-0-7914-2450-6Bhartrihari may have been "within the fold of Vedānta".
  11. ^ a b Vidyākara (1968), Daniel Henry Holmes Ingalls (ed.), Sanskrit poetry, from Vidyākara's Treasury, Harvard University Press, p. 39, ISBN 978-0-674-78865-7
  12. ^ Miller, Foreword and Introduction
  13. ^ A. K. Warder (1994), Indian kāvya literature: The ways of originality (Bāna to Dāmodaragupta), Motilal Banarsidass Publ., p. 121, ISBN 978-81-208-0449-4
  14. ^ Panini 6.1.123. The 10-century Haradatta assumed that Sphoṭāyana was the author of the sphoṭa theory.
  15. ^ a b Herzberger, Hans and Radhika Herzberger (1981). "Bhartrhari's Paradox" Journal of Indian Philosophy 9: 1-17 (slightly revised version of "Bhartrhari's Paradox" in Studies in Indian Philosophy. A memorial volume in honour of pandit Sukhlalji Sanghvi. (L.D. Series 84.) Gen. ed. Dalsukh Malvania et al. Ahmedabad, 1981).
  16. ^ Extensively used by later grammarians such as Kaiyaṭa, the text is only fragmentarily preserved. An edition based on an incomplete manuscript was published by Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, Pune (1985-1991), in six fascicules (fascicule 6 in two parts).
  17. ^ Bhartrihari: Poems, trans. Barbara Stoller Miller, Columbia 1967
  18. ^ John Brough (trans.) (1977). Poems from the Sanskrit. Penguin. poem 12
  19. ^ Jan E.M. Houben, "Paradoxe et perspectivisme dans la philosophie de langage de Bhartrhari: langage, pensée et réalité", Bulletin d'Études Indiennes 19 (2001):173-199.
  20. ^ Ashok Aklujkar 1994, p. 33.
  21. ^ Ashok Aklujkar 1994, p. 25-26.
  22. ^ Harold G. Coward 1990, pp. 121–122.
  23. ^ Ashok Aklujkar 1994, p. 26.
  24. ^ Ashok Aklujkar 1994, p. 34.
  25. ^ a b Harold G. Coward 1990, p. 122.
  26. ^ Harold G. Coward 1990, p. 121.

Bibliography

  • Ashok Aklujkar (1994). "An introduction to the study of Bhartṛ-hari". In Saroja Bhate; Johannes Bronkhorst (eds.). Bhartr̥hari, Philosopher and Grammarian. Motilal Banarsidass. ISBN 9788120811980.
  • Harold G. Coward; K. Kunjunni Raja, eds. (1990). The Philosophy of the Grammarians. Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies. Vol. 5. Motilal Banarsidass. p. 371. ISBN 9788120804265.

External links

  • Bhartrihari (c. 450—510 C.E.) in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Bibliography on Bhartṛhari, Grammarian and Philosopher
  • Works by Bhartṛhari at LibriVox (public domain audiobooks)  

bhartṛhari, folk, hero, bharthari, king, other, uses, bharthari, devanagari, भर, हर, also, romanised, bhartrihari, century, hindu, linguistic, philosopher, whom, normally, ascribed, influential, sanskrit, texts, trikāṇḍī, including, vākyapadīya, sanskrit, gram. For the folk hero see Bharthari king For other uses see Bharthari Bhartṛhari Devanagari भर त हर also romanised as Bhartrihari fl c 5th century CE was a Hindu linguistic philosopher 1 to whom are normally ascribed two influential Sanskrit texts the Trikaṇḍi including Vakyapadiya on Sanskrit grammar and linguistic philosophy a foundational text in the Indian grammatical tradition explaining numerous theories on the word and on the sentence including theories which came to be known under the name of Sphoṭa in this work Bhartrhari also discussed logical problems such as the liar paradox and a paradox of unnameability or unsignifiability which has become known as Bhartrhari s paradox and the Satakatraya a work of Sanskrit poetry comprising three collections of about 100 stanzas each it may or may not be by the same author who composed the two mentioned grammatical works In the medieval tradition of Indian scholarship it was assumed that both texts were written by the same person citation needed Modern philologists were sceptical of this claim owing to an argument that dated the grammar to a date subsequent to the poetry citation needed Since the 1990s however scholars have agreed that both works may indeed have been contemporary in which case it is plausible that there was only one Bhartrihari who wrote both texts citation needed Both the grammar and the poetic works had an enormous influence in their respective fields The grammar in particular takes a holistic view of language countering the compositionality position of the Mimamsakas and others According to Aithihyamala he is also credited with some other texts like Harikitika and Amaru Shataka The poetry constitute short verses collected into three centuries of about a hundred poems each Each century deals with a different rasa or aesthetic mood on the whole his poetic work has been very highly regarded both within the tradition and by modern scholarship The name Bhartrihari is also sometimes associated with Bhartrihari traya Shataka the legendary king of Ujjaini in the 1st century Contents 1 Date and identity 2 Vakyapadiya 3 Satakatraya 4 Bhartrhari s paradox 5 Works 6 See also 7 References 7 1 Bibliography 8 External linksDate and identity EditThe account of the Chinese traveller Yi Jing indicates that Bhartrihari s grammar was known by 670 CE and that he may have been Buddhist which the poet was not Based on this scholarly opinion had formerly attributed the grammar to a separate author of the same name from the 7th century CE 2 However other evidence indicates a much earlier date Bhartrihari was long believed to have lived in the seventh century CE but according to the testimony of the Chinese pilgrim Yijing he was known to the Buddhist philosopher Dignaga and this has pushed his date back to the fifth century CE 3 A period of c 450 500 4 definitely not later than 425 450 5 or following Erich Frauwallner 450 510 6 7 or perhaps 400 CE or even earlier 8 Yi Jing s other claim that Bhartrihari was a Buddhist does not seem to hold his philosophical position is widely held to be an offshoot of the Vyakarana or grammarian school closely allied to the realism of the Naiyayikas and distinctly opposed to Buddhist positions like Dignaga who are closer to phenomenalism It is also opposed to other Mimamsakas like Kumarila Bhatta 9 10 However some of his ideas subsequently influenced some Buddhist schools which may have led Yi Jing to surmise that he may have been Buddhist Thus on the whole it seems likely that the traditional Sanskritist view that the poet of the Satakatraya is the same as the grammarian Bhartṛhari may be accepted The leading Sanskrit scholar Ingalls 1968 submitted that I see no reason why he should not have written poems as well as grammar and metaphysics like Dharmakirti Shankaracharya and many others 11 Yi Jing himself appeared to think they were the same person as he wrote that the grammarian Bhartṛhari author of the Vakyapadiya was renowned for his vacillation between Buddhist monkhood and a life of pleasure and for having written verses on the subject 12 13 Vakyapadiya EditMain articles Trikaṇḍi and Sphoṭa Bhartrihari s views on language build on that of earlier grammarians such as Patanjali but were quite radical A key element of his conception of language is the notion of sphoṭa a term that may be based on an ancient grammarian Sphoṭayana referred by Paṇini 14 now lost In his Mahabhashya Patanjali 2nd century BCE uses the term sphoṭa to denote the sound of language the universal while the actual sound dhvani may be long or short or vary in other ways This distinction may be thought to be similar to that of the present notion of phoneme Bhatrihari however applies the term sphota to each element of the utterance varṇa the letter or syllable pada the word and vakya the sentence To create the linguistic invariant he argues that these must be treated as separate wholes varṇasphoṭa padasphoṭa and vakyasphoṭa respectively For example the same speech sound or varṇa may have different properties in different word contexts e g assimilation so that the sound cannot be discerned until the whole word is heard Further Bhartrihari argues for a sentence holistic view of meaning saying that the meaning of an utterance is known only after the entire sentence vakyasphoṭa has been received and it is not composed from the individual atomic elements or linguistic units which may change their interpretation based on later elements in the utterance Further words are understood only in the context of the sentence whose meaning as a whole is known His argument for this was based on language acquisition e g consider a child observing the exchange below elder adult uttama vṛddha full grown says bring the horse younger adult madhyama vṛddha half grown reacts by bringing the horseThe child observing this may now learn that the unit horse refers to the animal Unless the child knew the sentence meaning a priori it would be difficult for him to infer the meaning of novel words Thus we grasp the sentence meaning as a whole and reach words as parts of the sentence and word meanings as parts of the sentence meaning through analysis synthesis and abstraction apoddhara 9 The sphoṭa theory was influential but it was opposed by many others Later Mimamsakas like Kumarila Bhatta c 650 CE strongly rejected the vakyasphoṭa view and argued for the denotative power of each word arguing for the composition of meanings abhihitanvaya The Prabhakara school c 670 among Mimamsakas however took a less atomistic position arguing that word meanings exist but are determined by context anvitabhidhana In a section of the chapter on Relation Bhartrhari discusses the liar paradox and identifies a hidden parameter which turns an unproblematic situation in daily life into a stubborn paradox In addition Bhartrhari discusses here a paradox that has been called Bhartrhari s paradox by Hans and Radhika Herzberger 15 This paradox arises from the statement this is unnameable or this is unsignifiable The Mahabhaṣya dipika also Mahabhaṣya ṭika is an early subcommentary on Patanjali s Vyakaraṇa Mahabhaṣya also attributed to Bhartṛhari 16 Satakatraya EditMain article Satakatraya Bhartrihari s poetry is aphoristic and comments on the social mores of the time The collected work is known as Satakatraya the three satakas or hundreds centuries consisting of three thematic compilations on shringara vairagya and niti loosely love dispassion and moral conduct of hundred verses each Unfortunately the extant manuscript versions of these shataka s vary widely in the verses included D D Kosambi has identified a kernel of two hundred that are common to all the versions 11 Here is a sample that comments on social mores yasyasti vittaṃ sa naraḥ kulinaḥsa paṇḍitaḥ sa srutavan guṇajnaḥ sa eva vakta sa ca darsaniyaḥsarve guṇaḥ kancanam asrayanti A man of wealth is held to be high born Wise scholarly and discerning Eloquent and even handsome All virtues are accessories to gold 17 51 Translated by Barbara Stoler MillerAnd here is one dealing with the theme of love The clear bright flame of a man s discernment dies When a girl clouds it with her lamp black eyes Bhartrihari 77 tr John Brough poem 167 18 Bhartrhari s paradox EditBhartrhari s paradox is the title of a 1981 paper by Hans and Radhika Herzberger 15 which drew attention to the discussion of self referential paradoxes in the work Vakyapadiya attributed to Bhartṛhari In the chapter dealing with logical and linguistic relations the Sambandha samuddesa Bhartrhari discusses several statements of a paradoxical nature including sarvam mithya bravimi everything I am saying is false which belongs to the liar paradox family as well as the paradox arising from the statement that something is unnameable or unsignifiable in Sanskrit avacya this becomes nameable or signifiable precisely by calling it unnameable or unsignifiable When applied to integers the latter is known today as Berry paradox Bhartrhari s interest lies not in strengthening this and other paradoxes by abstracting them from pragmatic context but rather in exploring how a stubborn paradox may arise from unproblematic situations in daily communication An unproblematic situation of communication is turned into a paradox we have either contradiction virodha or infinite regress anavastha when abstraction is made from the signification and its extension in time by accepting a simultaneous opposite function apara vyapara undoing the previous one 19 For Bhartrhari it is important to analyse and solve the unsignifiability paradox because he holds that what cannot be signified may nevertheless be indicated vyapadisyate and it may be understood pratiyate to exist Works EditWorks attributed to Bhartr hari include 20 Trikaṇḍi three books sometimes known under the inaccurate title Vakyapadiya The author wrote the commentaries vṛttis on the first two books and probably died before he could do it for the third book The title Trikaṇḍi was probably not chosen by the author who originally conceived them as relatively independent works but later thought of unifying them 21 Tripadi also known as Mahabhashya tika or Mahabhashya dipika The earliest commentators on the text call it Tripadi and the title Mahabhashya dipika is known only from one manuscript 22 The author probably intended to write a commentary on the entire text but died after completing the work on the three padas of Maha bhashya The title Tripadi was probably coined by someone other than the author 23 The currently surviving version of the work covers only the first seven ahnikas of hte first pada of Mahabhashya It is known from a fragmentary manuscript 24 Shabda dhatu samiksha now lost This work is attributed to Bharthari by the Kashmiri Shaivite authors Soma nanda and Utpalacharya 9th 10th centuries According to Utpalacharya in this work Bharthari described the concept of pashyanti which he also discusses in the Trikandi 25 Possibly a commentary on Jaimini s Mimamsa SutrasTradition also attributes several other works to Bharthari although the authenticity of such attributions is doubtful 26 For example tradition identifies Bharthari the grammarian with the poet who composed Subhashita tri shati a work said to contain 300 stanzas However the number of stanzas in the surviving text is much more than 300 which complicates the identification of its actual author 25 See also EditRegarding Bhartrhari s paradox see B K Matilal 1990 The Word and the World India s Contribution to the Study of Language Delhi Oxford University Press p 129 130 Hemanta Kumar Ganguli Theory of Logical Construction and Solution of some Logical Paradoxes appendix to Philosophy of Logical Construction An Examination of Logical Atomism and Logical Positivism in the light of the Philosophies of Bhartrhari Dharmakirti and Prajnakaragupta Calcutta 1963 Jan E M Houben The Sambandha samuddesa chapter on relation and Bhartrhari s philosophy of language Gonda Indological Series 2 Groningen Egbert Forsten 1995 pp 213 219 References Edit Cornille Catherine 8 June 2020 The Wiley Blackwell Companion to Inter Religious Dialogue John Wiley amp Sons p 199 ISBN 978 1 119 57259 6 Hajime Nakamura 1990 A history of early Vedanta philosophy Part 1 Motilal Banarsidass Publ p 80 ISBN 978 81 208 0651 1 Edward Craig ed 1998 Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy Taylor amp Francis p 764 ISBN 978 0 415 16916 5 Harold G Coward 1976 Bhartṛhari Twayne Publishers ISBN 978 0 8057 6243 3 Saroja Bhate Johannes Bronkhorst eds 1994 Bhartṛhari philosopher and grammarian Proceedings of the First International Conference on Bhartṛhari University of Poona January 6 8 1992 Motilal Banarsidass Publ p 21 ISBN 978 81 208 1198 0 Mulakaluri Srimannarayana Murti 1997 Bhartṛhari the grammarian Sahitya Akademi p 10 ISBN 978 81 260 0308 2 Harold G Coward Karl H Potter K Kunjunni Raja eds 1990 Encyclopedia of Indian philosophies The philosophy of the grammarians Motilal Banarsidass Publ p 121 ISBN 978 81 208 0426 5 George Cardona 1998 Paṇini a survey of research Motilal Banarsidass Publ p 298 ISBN 978 81 208 1494 3 Detailed discussion see also notes on p 366 a b Bimal Krishna Matilal 1990 The Word and the World India s contribution to the study of language Oxford University Press N V Isaeva 1995 From early Vedanta to Kashmir Shaivism Gaudapada Bhartrhari and Abhinavagupta SUNY Press p 75 ISBN 978 0 7914 2450 6 Bhartrihari may have been within the fold of Vedanta a b Vidyakara 1968 Daniel Henry Holmes Ingalls ed Sanskrit poetry from Vidyakara s Treasury Harvard University Press p 39 ISBN 978 0 674 78865 7 Miller Foreword and Introduction A K Warder 1994 Indian kavya literature The ways of originality Bana to Damodaragupta Motilal Banarsidass Publ p 121 ISBN 978 81 208 0449 4 Panini 6 1 123 The 10 century Haradatta assumed that Sphoṭayana was the author of the sphoṭa theory a b Herzberger Hans and Radhika Herzberger 1981 Bhartrhari s Paradox Journal of Indian Philosophy 9 1 17 slightly revised version of Bhartrhari s Paradox in Studies in Indian Philosophy A memorial volume in honour of pandit Sukhlalji Sanghvi L D Series 84 Gen ed Dalsukh Malvania et al Ahmedabad 1981 Extensively used by later grammarians such as Kaiyaṭa the text is only fragmentarily preserved An edition based on an incomplete manuscript was published by Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute Pune 1985 1991 in six fascicules fascicule 6 in two parts Bhartrihari Poems trans Barbara Stoller Miller Columbia 1967 John Brough trans 1977 Poems from the Sanskrit Penguin poem 12 Jan E M Houben Paradoxe et perspectivisme dans la philosophie de langage de Bhartrhari langage pensee et realite Bulletin d Etudes Indiennes 19 2001 173 199 Ashok Aklujkar 1994 p 33 Ashok Aklujkar 1994 p 25 26 Harold G Coward 1990 pp 121 122 Ashok Aklujkar 1994 p 26 Ashok Aklujkar 1994 p 34 a b Harold G Coward 1990 p 122 Harold G Coward 1990 p 121 Bibliography Edit Ashok Aklujkar 1994 An introduction to the study of Bhartṛ hari In Saroja Bhate Johannes Bronkhorst eds Bhartr hari Philosopher and Grammarian Motilal Banarsidass ISBN 9788120811980 Harold G Coward K Kunjunni Raja eds 1990 The Philosophy of the Grammarians Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies Vol 5 Motilal Banarsidass p 371 ISBN 9788120804265 External links Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Bhartṛhari Bhartrihari c 450 510 C E in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Bibliography on Bhartṛhari Grammarian and Philosopher Works by Bhartṛhari at LibriVox public domain audiobooks Tracking the Hermit s Soul A Jungian Reading Of Bhartrihari s Satakatraya by Mathew V Spano Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Bhartṛhari amp oldid 1151779381, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.