fbpx
Wikipedia

Academic skepticism

Academic skepticism refers to the skeptical period of the Academy dating from around 266 BCE, when Arcesilaus became scholarch, until around 90 BCE, when Antiochus of Ascalon rejected skepticism, although individual philosophers, such as Favorinus and his teacher Plutarch, continued to defend skepticism after this date. Unlike the existing school of skepticism, the Pyrrhonists, they maintained that knowledge of things is impossible. Ideas or notions are never true; nevertheless, there are degrees of plausibility, and hence degrees of belief, which allow one to act. The school was characterized by its attacks on the Stoics, particularly their dogma that convincing impressions led to true knowledge. The most important Academics were Arcesilaus, Carneades, and Philo of Larissa. The most extensive ancient source of information about Academic skepticism is Academica, written by the Academic skeptic philosopher Cicero.

Skeptics in Raphael's School of Athens painting. 1. Pythodorus 2. Arcesilaus of Pitane 3. Carneades of Cyrene 4. Pyrrho of Elis 5. Timon of Phlius 6. Theodorus the Atheist of Cyrene

Overview edit

Greek philosophical skepticism, as a distinct philosophical movement, began with Pyrrho of Elis (c. 360 – c. 270 BCE), with antecedents in Xenophanes and Democritus. His followers, the Pyrrhonists, pointed out the problem of the criterion: that our theories and our sense impressions are unable to accurately distinguish truth from falsehood; therefore we must suspend judgment (epoche).[1] They were consistent enough to extend their doubt even to their own principle of doubt, making their skepticism universal, thus escaping reproach for basing it upon a fresh dogmatism. Mental imperturbability (ataraxia) was the result to be attained by cultivating such a frame of mind.[1]

Around 266 BCE, Arcesilaus became head of the Platonic Academy. He adopted skepticism as a central tenet of Platonism, making Platonism nearly the same as Pyrrhonism.[2] After Arcesilaus, the Academics diverged from Pyrrhonism.[3] This skeptical period of ancient Platonism, from Arcesilaus to Philo of Larissa, became known as the new Academy, although some ancient authors added further subdivisions, such as a middle Academy. Following the death of the Pyrrhonist Timon of Phlius, the Platonic Academy became the primary advocate of skepticism until the mid-first century BCE.[4] While early Academic skepticism was influenced in part by Pyrrho,[5] it grew more and more dogmatic until Aenesidemus, in the first century BCE, broke with the Academic skeptics and adopted Pyrrhonism, denouncing the Academy as "Stoics fighting against Stoics."[6]

The Academics did not doubt the existence of truth; they just doubted that humans had the capacities for obtaining it.[7] They based this position on Plato's Phaedo,[8] in which Socrates discusses how knowledge is not accessible to mortals.[9]

While the objective of the Pyrrhonists was the attainment of ataraxia, after Arcesilaus the Academics did not hold up ataraxia as the central objective. The Academics focused on criticizing the dogmas of other schools of philosophy, in particular of the dogmatism of the Stoics.[1] They acknowledged some vestiges of a moral law within, at best but a plausible guide, the possession of which, however, formed the real distinction between the sage and the fool.[7] Slight as the difference may appear between the positions of the Academics and the Pyrrhonists, a comparison of their lives leads to the conclusion that a practical philosophical moderation was the characteristic of the Academics[7] whereas the objectives of the Pyrrhonists were more psychological. The second-century Roman historian Aulus Gellius described the distinction between the Academic skeptics and the Pyrrhonists as follows:

"...the Academics apprehend (in some sense) the very fact that nothing can be apprehended, and they determine (in some sense) that nothing can be determined, whereas the Pyrrhonists assert that not even that seems to be true, since nothing seems to be true."[10]

Arcesilaus edit

Up to Arcesilaus, the Platonic Academy accepted the principle of finding a general unity in all things, by the aid of which a principle of certainty might be found.[11] Arcesilaus, however, broke new ground by attacking the very possibility of certainty and denied the possibility of even the Socratic minimum of certainty: "I cannot know even whether I know or not."[11]

The doctrines of Arcesilaus, which must be gathered from the writings of others,[12] represent an attack on the Stoic phantasia kataleptike (criterion) and are based on the skepticism which was latent in the later writings of Plato.[13] Arcesilaus held that strength of intellectual conviction cannot be regarded as valid, inasmuch as it is characteristic equally of contradictory convictions. The uncertainty of sense data applies equally to the conclusions of reason, and therefore man must be content with probability which is sufficient as a practical guide. "We know nothing, not even our ignorance"; therefore the wise man will be content with an agnostic attitude.[13]

Carneades edit

 
Carneades of Cyrene, the most important of the Academic skeptics

The next stage in Academic skepticism was the moderate skepticism of Carneades, which he said owed its existence to his opposition to Chrysippus.[11]

To the Stoic theory of perception, the phantasia kataleptike, by which they expressed a conviction of certainty arising from impressions so strong as to amount to science, he proposed the doctrine of acatalepsia, which denied any necessary correspondence between perceptions and the objects perceived.[11] All our sensations are relative, and acquaint us, not with things as they are, but only with the impressions that things produce upon us. Experience, he said, clearly shows that there is no true impression. There is no notion that may not deceive us; it is impossible to distinguish between false and true impressions; therefore the Stoic phantasia kataleptike must be given up. There is no phantasia kataleptike ("criterion") of truth. Carneades also assailed Stoic theology and physics. In answer to the doctrine of final cause, of design in nature, he pointed to those things which cause destruction and danger to man, to the evil committed by men endowed with reason, to the miserable condition of humanity, and to the misfortunes that assail the good man. There is, he concluded, no evidence for the doctrine of a divine superintending providence. Even if there were orderly connexion of parts in the universe, this may have resulted quite naturally. No proof can be advanced to show that this world is anything but the product of natural forces.[14]

Knowledge being impossible, a wise man should practice epoche (suspension of judgment).[14] He will not even be sure that he can be sure of nothing. He saved himself, however, from absolute skepticism by the doctrine of plausibility, which may serve as a practical guide in life.[11] Ideas or notions are never true, but only plausible; nevertheless, there are degrees of plausibility, and hence degrees of belief, leading to action. According to Carneades, an impression may be plausible in itself; plausible and uncontradicted (not distracted by synchronous sensations, but shown to be in harmony with them) when compared with others; plausible, uncontradicted, and thoroughly investigated and confirmed. In the first degree there is a strong persuasion of the propriety of the impression made; the second and third degrees are produced by comparisons of the impression with others associated with it, and an analysis of itself.[14] Carneades left no written works; his opinions seem to have been systematized by his pupil Clitomachus, whose works, which included one "on suspension of judgment," were made use of by Cicero.[15]

Philo of Larissa edit

In Philo of Larissa, we find a tendency not only to reconcile the internal divergences of the Academy itself, but also to connect it with parallel systems of thought.[11] In general, his philosophy was a reaction against the skeptic or agnostic position of the middle and new Academy in favor of the dogmatism of Plato.[16] Philo of Larissa endeavored to show that Carneades was not opposed to Plato, and further that the apparent antagonism between Platonism and Stoicism was because they were arguing from different points of view. From this syncretism emerged the eclectic middle Platonism of Antiochus of Ascalon, the last product of Academic development.[11]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Scepticism". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 24 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 306–309.
  2. ^ Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" I.33.232
  3. ^ Sextus Empiricus, "Outlines of Pyrrhonism" I.33.225–231
  4. ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient Scepticism. Stocksfield [U.K.]: Acumen. pp. 120–121. ISBN 978-1844654093. OCLC 715184861. Pyrrhonism, in whatever form it might have taken after Timon's death in 230 BCE, was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention
  5. ^ Thorsrud 2014, p. 45.
  6. ^ Thorsrud 2014, pp. 102–103.
  7. ^ a b c   This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainSmith, William, ed. (1870). "Arcesilaus". Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology.
  8. ^ Phaedo, 64–67
  9. ^ Veres, Máté (2009). "Carlos Lévy, Les Scepticismes; Markus Gabriel, Antike und moderne Skepsis zur Einführung". Rhizai. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science. 6 (1): 107.: 111 
  10. ^ Gellius, Aulus (2008). Noctes Atticae. Josef Feix (3. Dr ed.). Paderborn: Schöningh. ISBN 978-3140107143. OCLC 635311697.
  11. ^ a b c d e f g   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Academy, Greek". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 1 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 105–106.
  12. ^ Cicero, Acad. i. 12, iv. 24; De Orat. iii. 18; Diogenes Laertius iv. 28; Sextus Empiricus, Adv. Math. vii. 150, Pyrrh. Hyp. i. 233
  13. ^ a b   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Arcesilaus". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 2 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 342.
  14. ^ a b c   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Carneades". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 5 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 363–364.
  15. ^   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Clitomachus". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 6 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 531.
  16. ^   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Philo of Larissa". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 21 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 413.

References edit

External links edit

academic, skepticism, refers, skeptical, period, academy, dating, from, around, when, arcesilaus, became, scholarch, until, around, when, antiochus, ascalon, rejected, skepticism, although, individual, philosophers, such, favorinus, teacher, plutarch, continue. Academic skepticism refers to the skeptical period of the Academy dating from around 266 BCE when Arcesilaus became scholarch until around 90 BCE when Antiochus of Ascalon rejected skepticism although individual philosophers such as Favorinus and his teacher Plutarch continued to defend skepticism after this date Unlike the existing school of skepticism the Pyrrhonists they maintained that knowledge of things is impossible Ideas or notions are never true nevertheless there are degrees of plausibility and hence degrees of belief which allow one to act The school was characterized by its attacks on the Stoics particularly their dogma that convincing impressions led to true knowledge The most important Academics were Arcesilaus Carneades and Philo of Larissa The most extensive ancient source of information about Academic skepticism is Academica written by the Academic skeptic philosopher Cicero Skeptics in Raphael s School of Athens painting 1 Pythodorus 2 Arcesilaus of Pitane 3 Carneades of Cyrene 4 Pyrrho of Elis 5 Timon of Phlius 6 Theodorus the Atheist of Cyrene Contents 1 Overview 2 Arcesilaus 3 Carneades 4 Philo of Larissa 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 External linksOverview editGreek philosophical skepticism as a distinct philosophical movement began with Pyrrho of Elis c 360 c 270 BCE with antecedents in Xenophanes and Democritus His followers the Pyrrhonists pointed out the problem of the criterion that our theories and our sense impressions are unable to accurately distinguish truth from falsehood therefore we must suspend judgment epoche 1 They were consistent enough to extend their doubt even to their own principle of doubt making their skepticism universal thus escaping reproach for basing it upon a fresh dogmatism Mental imperturbability ataraxia was the result to be attained by cultivating such a frame of mind 1 Around 266 BCE Arcesilaus became head of the Platonic Academy He adopted skepticism as a central tenet of Platonism making Platonism nearly the same as Pyrrhonism 2 After Arcesilaus the Academics diverged from Pyrrhonism 3 This skeptical period of ancient Platonism from Arcesilaus to Philo of Larissa became known as the new Academy although some ancient authors added further subdivisions such as a middle Academy Following the death of the Pyrrhonist Timon of Phlius the Platonic Academy became the primary advocate of skepticism until the mid first century BCE 4 While early Academic skepticism was influenced in part by Pyrrho 5 it grew more and more dogmatic until Aenesidemus in the first century BCE broke with the Academic skeptics and adopted Pyrrhonism denouncing the Academy as Stoics fighting against Stoics 6 The Academics did not doubt the existence of truth they just doubted that humans had the capacities for obtaining it 7 They based this position on Plato s Phaedo 8 in which Socrates discusses how knowledge is not accessible to mortals 9 While the objective of the Pyrrhonists was the attainment of ataraxia after Arcesilaus the Academics did not hold up ataraxia as the central objective The Academics focused on criticizing the dogmas of other schools of philosophy in particular of the dogmatism of the Stoics 1 They acknowledged some vestiges of a moral law within at best but a plausible guide the possession of which however formed the real distinction between the sage and the fool 7 Slight as the difference may appear between the positions of the Academics and the Pyrrhonists a comparison of their lives leads to the conclusion that a practical philosophical moderation was the characteristic of the Academics 7 whereas the objectives of the Pyrrhonists were more psychological The second century Roman historian Aulus Gellius described the distinction between the Academic skeptics and the Pyrrhonists as follows the Academics apprehend in some sense the very fact that nothing can be apprehended and they determine in some sense that nothing can be determined whereas the Pyrrhonists assert that not even that seems to be true since nothing seems to be true 10 Arcesilaus editMain article Arcesilaus Up to Arcesilaus the Platonic Academy accepted the principle of finding a general unity in all things by the aid of which a principle of certainty might be found 11 Arcesilaus however broke new ground by attacking the very possibility of certainty and denied the possibility of even the Socratic minimum of certainty I cannot know even whether I know or not 11 The doctrines of Arcesilaus which must be gathered from the writings of others 12 represent an attack on the Stoic phantasia kataleptike criterion and are based on the skepticism which was latent in the later writings of Plato 13 Arcesilaus held that strength of intellectual conviction cannot be regarded as valid inasmuch as it is characteristic equally of contradictory convictions The uncertainty of sense data applies equally to the conclusions of reason and therefore man must be content with probability which is sufficient as a practical guide We know nothing not even our ignorance therefore the wise man will be content with an agnostic attitude 13 Carneades editMain article Carneades nbsp Carneades of Cyrene the most important of the Academic skeptics The next stage in Academic skepticism was the moderate skepticism of Carneades which he said owed its existence to his opposition to Chrysippus 11 To the Stoic theory of perception the phantasia kataleptike by which they expressed a conviction of certainty arising from impressions so strong as to amount to science he proposed the doctrine of acatalepsia which denied any necessary correspondence between perceptions and the objects perceived 11 All our sensations are relative and acquaint us not with things as they are but only with the impressions that things produce upon us Experience he said clearly shows that there is no true impression There is no notion that may not deceive us it is impossible to distinguish between false and true impressions therefore the Stoic phantasia kataleptike must be given up There is no phantasia kataleptike criterion of truth Carneades also assailed Stoic theology and physics In answer to the doctrine of final cause of design in nature he pointed to those things which cause destruction and danger to man to the evil committed by men endowed with reason to the miserable condition of humanity and to the misfortunes that assail the good man There is he concluded no evidence for the doctrine of a divine superintending providence Even if there were orderly connexion of parts in the universe this may have resulted quite naturally No proof can be advanced to show that this world is anything but the product of natural forces 14 Knowledge being impossible a wise man should practice epoche suspension of judgment 14 He will not even be sure that he can be sure of nothing He saved himself however from absolute skepticism by the doctrine of plausibility which may serve as a practical guide in life 11 Ideas or notions are never true but only plausible nevertheless there are degrees of plausibility and hence degrees of belief leading to action According to Carneades an impression may be plausible in itself plausible and uncontradicted not distracted by synchronous sensations but shown to be in harmony with them when compared with others plausible uncontradicted and thoroughly investigated and confirmed In the first degree there is a strong persuasion of the propriety of the impression made the second and third degrees are produced by comparisons of the impression with others associated with it and an analysis of itself 14 Carneades left no written works his opinions seem to have been systematized by his pupil Clitomachus whose works which included one on suspension of judgment were made use of by Cicero 15 Philo of Larissa editMain article Philo of Larissa In Philo of Larissa we find a tendency not only to reconcile the internal divergences of the Academy itself but also to connect it with parallel systems of thought 11 In general his philosophy was a reaction against the skeptic or agnostic position of the middle and new Academy in favor of the dogmatism of Plato 16 Philo of Larissa endeavored to show that Carneades was not opposed to Plato and further that the apparent antagonism between Platonism and Stoicism was because they were arguing from different points of view From this syncretism emerged the eclectic middle Platonism of Antiochus of Ascalon the last product of Academic development 11 See also editProbabilism Scientific skepticismNotes edit a b c nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Scepticism Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 24 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 306 309 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 33 232 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 33 225 231 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient Scepticism Stocksfield U K Acumen pp 120 121 ISBN 978 1844654093 OCLC 715184861 Pyrrhonism in whatever form it might have taken after Timon s death in 230 BCE was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention Thorsrud 2014 p 45 Thorsrud 2014 pp 102 103 a b c nbsp This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Smith William ed 1870 Arcesilaus Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology Phaedo 64 67 Veres Mate 2009 Carlos Levy Les Scepticismes Markus Gabriel Antike und moderne Skepsis zur Einfuhrung Rhizai A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science 6 1 107 111 Gellius Aulus 2008 Noctes Atticae Josef Feix 3 Dr ed Paderborn Schoningh ISBN 978 3140107143 OCLC 635311697 a b c d e f g nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Academy Greek Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 1 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 105 106 Cicero Acad i 12 iv 24 De Orat iii 18 Diogenes Laertius iv 28 Sextus Empiricus Adv Math vii 150 Pyrrh Hyp i 233 a b nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Arcesilaus Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 2 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 342 a b c nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Carneades Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 5 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 363 364 nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Clitomachus Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 6 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 531 nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Philo of Larissa Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 21 11th ed Cambridge University Press p 413 References editThorsrud Harald 2014 Ancient Scepticism Routledge ISBN 978 1 317 49283 2 External links editGroarke Leo Ancient Skepticism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Harold Thorsrud Ancient Greek Skepticism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Academic skepticism amp oldid 1220544308, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.