fbpx
Wikipedia

Whitehead's point-free geometry

In mathematics, point-free geometry is a geometry whose primitive ontological notion is region rather than point. Two axiomatic systems are set out below, one grounded in mereology, the other in mereotopology and known as connection theory.

Point-free geometry was first formulated in Whitehead (1919, 1920), not as a theory of geometry or of spacetime, but of "events" and of an "extension relation" between events. Whitehead's purposes were as much philosophical as scientific and mathematical.[a]

Formalizations edit

Whitehead did not set out his theories in a manner that would satisfy present-day canons of formality. The two formal first-order theories described in this entry were devised by others in order to clarify and refine Whitehead's theories. The domain of discourse for both theories consists of "regions." All unquantified variables in this entry should be taken as tacitly universally quantified; hence all axioms should be taken as universal closures. No axiom requires more than three quantified variables; hence a translation of first-order theories into relation algebra is possible. Each set of axioms has but four existential quantifiers.

Inclusion-based point-free geometry (mereology) edit

The fundamental primitive binary relation is inclusion, denoted by the infix operator "≤", which corresponds to the binary Parthood relation that is a standard feature in mereological theories. The intuitive meaning of xy is "x is part of y." Assuming that equality, denoted by the infix operator "=", is part of the background logic, the binary relation Proper Part, denoted by the infix operator "<", is defined as:

 

The axioms are:[b]

G1.   (reflexive)
G2.   (transitive) WP4.
G3.   (antisymmetric)
  • Given any two regions, there exists a region that includes both of them. WP6.
G4.  
G5.  
G6.  
  • Proper Parts Principle. If all the proper parts of x are proper parts of y, then x is included in y. WP3.
G7.  

A model of G1–G7 is an inclusion space.

Definition (Gerla and Miranda 2008: Def. 4.1). Given some inclusion space S, an abstractive class is a class G of regions such that S\G is totally ordered by inclusion. Moreover, there does not exist a region included in all of the regions included in G.

Intuitively, an abstractive class defines a geometrical entity whose dimensionality is less than that of the inclusion space. For example, if the inclusion space is the Euclidean plane, then the corresponding abstractive classes are points and lines.

Inclusion-based point-free geometry (henceforth "point-free geometry") is essentially an axiomatization of Simons's (1987: 83) system W. In turn, W formalizes a theory in Whitehead (1919) whose axioms are not made explicit. Point-free geometry is W with this defect repaired. Simons (1987) did not repair this defect, instead proposing in a footnote that the reader do so as an exercise. The primitive relation of W is Proper Part, a strict partial order. The theory[1] of Whitehead (1919) has a single primitive binary relation K defined as xKyy < x. Hence K is the converse of Proper Part. Simons's WP1 asserts that Proper Part is irreflexive and so corresponds to G1. G3 establishes that inclusion, unlike Proper Part, is antisymmetric.

Point-free geometry is closely related to a dense linear order D, whose axioms are G1-3, G5, and the totality axiom  [2] Hence inclusion-based point-free geometry would be a proper extension of D (namely D ∪ {G4, G6, G7}), were it not that the D relation "≤" is a total order.

Connection theory (mereotopology) edit

A different approach was proposed in Whitehead (1929), one inspired by De Laguna (1922). Whitehead took as primitive the topological notion of "contact" between two regions, resulting in a primitive "connection relation" between events. Connection theory C is a first-order theory that distills the first 12 of the 31 assumptions in chapter 2 of part 4 of Process and Reality into 6 axioms, C1-C6. C is a proper fragment of the theories proposed in Clarke (1981), who noted their mereological character. Theories that, like C, feature both inclusion and topological primitives, are called mereotopologies.

C has one primitive relation, binary "connection," denoted by the prefixed predicate letter C. That x is included in y can now be defined as xy ↔ ∀z[CzxCzy]. Unlike the case with inclusion spaces, connection theory enables defining "non-tangential" inclusion,[c] a total order that enables the construction of abstractive classes. Gerla and Miranda (2008) argue that only thus can mereotopology unambiguously define a point.

The axioms C1-C6 below are, but for numbering, those of Def. 3.1 in Gerla and Miranda (2008):

C1.  
C2.  
C3.  
  • All regions have proper parts, so that C is an atomless theory. P.9.
C4.  
  • Given any two regions, there is a region connected to both of them.
C5.  
  • All regions have at least two unconnected parts. C.14.
C6.  

A model of C is a connection space.

Following the verbal description of each axiom is the identifier of the corresponding axiom in Casati and Varzi (1999). Their system SMT (strong mereotopology) consists of C1-C3, and is essentially due to Clarke (1981).[d] Any mereotopology can be made atomless by invoking C4, without risking paradox or triviality. Hence C extends the atomless variant of SMT by means of the axioms C5 and C6, suggested by chapter 2 of part 4 of Process and Reality. For an advanced and detailed discussion of systems related to C, see Roeper (1997).

Biacino and Gerla (1991) showed that every model of Clarke's theory is a Boolean algebra, and models of such algebras cannot distinguish connection from overlap. It is doubtful whether either fact is faithful to Whitehead's intent.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ See Kneebone (1963), chpt. 13.5, for a gentle introduction to Whitehead's theory. Also see Lucas (2000), chpt. 10.
  2. ^ The axioms G1 to G7 are, but for numbering, those of Def. 2.1 in Gerla and Miranda (2008) (see also Gerla (1995)). The identifiers of the form WPn, included in the verbal description of each axiom, refer to the corresponding axiom in Simons (1987: 83).
  3. ^ Presumably this is Casati and Varzi's (1999) "Internal Part" predicate, IPxy ↔ (x≤y)∧(Czx→∃v[vzvy]. This definition combines their (4.8) and (3.1).
  4. ^ Grzegorczyk (1960) proposed a similar theory, whose motivation was primarily topological.

References edit

  1. ^ Kneebone (1963), p. 346.
  2. ^ Stoll, R. R., 1963. Set Theory and Logic. Dover reprint, 1979. P. 423.

Bibliography edit

  • Biacino L., and Gerla G., 1991, "Connection Structures," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32: 242-47.
  • Casati, R., and Varzi, A. C., 1999. Parts and places: the structures of spatial representation. MIT Press.
  • Clarke, Bowman, 1981, "A calculus of individuals based on 'connection'," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22: 204-18.
  • ------, 1985, "Individuals and Points," Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 26: 61-75.
  • De Laguna, T., 1922, "Point, line and surface as sets of solids," The Journal of Philosophy 19: 449-61.
  • Gerla, G., 1995, "" in Buekenhout, F., Kantor, W. eds., Handbook of incidence geometry: buildings and foundations. North-Holland: 1015-31.
  • --------, and Miranda A., 2008, "Inclusion and Connection in Whitehead's Point-free Geometry," in Michel Weber and Will Desmond, (eds.), Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought, Frankfurt / Lancaster, ontos verlag, Process Thought X1 & X2.
  • Gruszczynski R., and Pietruszczak A., 2008, "Full development of Tarski's geometry of solids," Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14:481-540. The paper contains presentation of point-free system of geometry originating from Whitehead's ideas and based on Lesniewski's mereology. It also briefly discusses the relation between point-free and point-based systems of geometry. Basic properties of mereological structures are given as well.
  • Grzegorczyk, A., 1960, "Axiomatizability of geometry without points," Synthese 12: 228-235.
  • Kneebone, G., 1963. Mathematical Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics. Dover reprint, 2001.
  • Lucas, J. R., 2000. Conceptual Roots of Mathematics. Routledge. Chpt. 10, on "prototopology," discusses Whitehead's systems and is strongly influenced by the unpublished writings of David Bostock.
  • Roeper, P., 1997, "Region-Based Topology," Journal of Philosophical Logic 26: 251-309.
  • Simons, P., 1987. Parts: A Study in Ontology. Oxford Univ. Press.
  • Whitehead, A.N., 1916, "La Theorie Relationiste de l'Espace," Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 23: 423-454. Translated as Hurley, P.J., 1979, "The relational theory of space," Philosophy Research Archives 5: 712-741.
  • --------, 1919. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge. Cambridge Univ. Press. 2nd ed., 1925.
  • --------, 1920. The Concept of Nature. Cambridge Univ. Press. 2004 paperback, Prometheus Books. Being the 1919 Tarner Lectures delivered at Trinity College.
  • --------, 1979 (1929). Process and Reality. Free Press.

whitehead, point, free, geometry, this, article, unclear, citation, style, references, used, made, clearer, with, different, consistent, style, citation, footnoting, november, 2022, learn, when, remove, this, template, message, mathematics, point, free, geomet. This article has an unclear citation style The references used may be made clearer with a different or consistent style of citation and footnoting November 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics point free geometry is a geometry whose primitive ontological notion is region rather than point Two axiomatic systems are set out below one grounded in mereology the other in mereotopology and known as connection theory Point free geometry was first formulated in Whitehead 1919 1920 not as a theory of geometry or of spacetime but of events and of an extension relation between events Whitehead s purposes were as much philosophical as scientific and mathematical a Contents 1 Formalizations 2 Inclusion based point free geometry mereology 3 Connection theory mereotopology 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 BibliographyFormalizations editWhitehead did not set out his theories in a manner that would satisfy present day canons of formality The two formal first order theories described in this entry were devised by others in order to clarify and refine Whitehead s theories The domain of discourse for both theories consists of regions All unquantified variables in this entry should be taken as tacitly universally quantified hence all axioms should be taken as universal closures No axiom requires more than three quantified variables hence a translation of first order theories into relation algebra is possible Each set of axioms has but four existential quantifiers Inclusion based point free geometry mereology editThe fundamental primitive binary relation is inclusion denoted by the infix operator which corresponds to the binary Parthood relation that is a standard feature in mereological theories The intuitive meaning of x y is x is part of y Assuming that equality denoted by the infix operator is part of the background logic the binary relation Proper Part denoted by the infix operator lt is defined as x lt y x y x y displaystyle x lt y leftrightarrow x leq y land x not y nbsp The axioms are b Inclusion partially orders the domain G1 x x displaystyle x leq x nbsp reflexive G2 x z z y x y displaystyle x leq z land z leq y rightarrow x leq y nbsp transitive WP4 G3 x y y x x y displaystyle x leq y land y leq x rightarrow x y nbsp antisymmetric Given any two regions there exists a region that includes both of them WP6 G4 z x z y z displaystyle exists z x leq z land y leq z nbsp Proper Part densely orders the domain WP5 G5 x lt y z x lt z lt y displaystyle x lt y rightarrow exists z x lt z lt y nbsp Both atomic regions and a universal region do not exist Hence the domain has neither an upper nor a lower bound WP2 G6 y z y lt x x lt z displaystyle exists y exists z y lt x land x lt z nbsp Proper Parts Principle If all the proper parts of x are proper parts of y then x is included in y WP3 G7 z z lt x z lt y x y displaystyle forall z z lt x rightarrow z lt y rightarrow x leq y nbsp A model of G1 G7 is an inclusion space Definition Gerla and Miranda 2008 Def 4 1 Given some inclusion space S an abstractive class is a class G of regions such that S G is totally ordered by inclusion Moreover there does not exist a region included in all of the regions included in G Intuitively an abstractive class defines a geometrical entity whose dimensionality is less than that of the inclusion space For example if the inclusion space is the Euclidean plane then the corresponding abstractive classes are points and lines Inclusion based point free geometry henceforth point free geometry is essentially an axiomatization of Simons s 1987 83 system W In turn W formalizes a theory in Whitehead 1919 whose axioms are not made explicit Point free geometry is W with this defect repaired Simons 1987 did not repair this defect instead proposing in a footnote that the reader do so as an exercise The primitive relation of W is Proper Part a strict partial order The theory 1 of Whitehead 1919 has a single primitive binary relation K defined as xKy y lt x Hence K is the converse of Proper Part Simons s WP1 asserts that Proper Part is irreflexive and so corresponds to G1 G3 establishes that inclusion unlike Proper Part is antisymmetric Point free geometry is closely related to a dense linear order D whose axioms are G1 3 G5 and the totality axiom x y y x displaystyle x leq y lor y leq x nbsp 2 Hence inclusion based point free geometry would be a proper extension of D namely D G4 G6 G7 were it not that the D relation is a total order Connection theory mereotopology editA different approach was proposed in Whitehead 1929 one inspired by De Laguna 1922 Whitehead took as primitive the topological notion of contact between two regions resulting in a primitive connection relation between events Connection theory C is a first order theory that distills the first 12 of the 31 assumptions in chapter 2 of part 4 of Process and Reality into 6 axioms C1 C6 C is a proper fragment of the theories proposed in Clarke 1981 who noted their mereological character Theories that like C feature both inclusion and topological primitives are called mereotopologies C has one primitive relation binary connection denoted by the prefixed predicate letter C That x is included in y can now be defined as x y z Czx Czy Unlike the case with inclusion spaces connection theory enables defining non tangential inclusion c a total order that enables the construction of abstractive classes Gerla and Miranda 2008 argue that only thus can mereotopology unambiguously define a point The axioms C1 C6 below are but for numbering those of Def 3 1 in Gerla and Miranda 2008 C is reflexive C 1 C1 C x x displaystyle Cxx nbsp C is symmetric C 2 C2 C x y C y x displaystyle Cxy rightarrow Cyx nbsp C is extensional C 11 C3 z C z x C z y x y displaystyle forall z Czx leftrightarrow Czy rightarrow x y nbsp All regions have proper parts so that C is an atomless theory P 9 C4 y y lt x displaystyle exists y y lt x nbsp Given any two regions there is a region connected to both of them C5 z C z x C z y displaystyle exists z Czx land Czy nbsp All regions have at least two unconnected parts C 14 C6 y z y x z x C y z displaystyle exists y exists z y leq x land z leq x land neg Cyz nbsp A model of C is a connection space Following the verbal description of each axiom is the identifier of the corresponding axiom in Casati and Varzi 1999 Their system SMT strong mereotopology consists of C1 C3 and is essentially due to Clarke 1981 d Any mereotopology can be made atomless by invoking C4 without risking paradox or triviality Hence C extends the atomless variant of SMT by means of the axioms C5 and C6 suggested by chapter 2 of part 4 of Process and Reality For an advanced and detailed discussion of systems related to C see Roeper 1997 Biacino and Gerla 1991 showed that every model of Clarke s theory is a Boolean algebra and models of such algebras cannot distinguish connection from overlap It is doubtful whether either fact is faithful to Whitehead s intent See also editMereology Mereotopology Pointless topologyNotes edit See Kneebone 1963 chpt 13 5 for a gentle introduction to Whitehead s theory Also see Lucas 2000 chpt 10 The axioms G1 to G7 are but for numbering those of Def 2 1 in Gerla and Miranda 2008 see also Gerla 1995 The identifiers of the form WPn included in the verbal description of each axiom refer to the corresponding axiom in Simons 1987 83 Presumably this is Casati and Varzi s 1999 Internal Part predicate IPxy x y Czx v v z v y This definition combines their 4 8 and 3 1 Grzegorczyk 1960 proposed a similar theory whose motivation was primarily topological References edit Kneebone 1963 p 346 Stoll R R 1963 Set Theory and Logic Dover reprint 1979 P 423 Bibliography editBiacino L and Gerla G 1991 Connection Structures Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 32 242 47 Casati R and Varzi A C 1999 Parts and places the structures of spatial representation MIT Press Clarke Bowman 1981 A calculus of individuals based on connection Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 204 18 1985 Individuals and Points Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 26 61 75 De Laguna T 1922 Point line and surface as sets of solids The Journal of Philosophy 19 449 61 Gerla G 1995 Pointless Geometries in Buekenhout F Kantor W eds Handbook of incidence geometry buildings and foundations North Holland 1015 31 and Miranda A 2008 Inclusion and Connection in Whitehead s Point free Geometry in Michel Weber and Will Desmond eds Handbook of Whiteheadian Process Thought Frankfurt Lancaster ontos verlag Process Thought X1 amp X2 Gruszczynski R and Pietruszczak A 2008 Full development of Tarski s geometry of solids Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 14 481 540 The paper contains presentation of point free system of geometry originating from Whitehead s ideas and based on Lesniewski s mereology It also briefly discusses the relation between point free and point based systems of geometry Basic properties of mereological structures are given as well Grzegorczyk A 1960 Axiomatizability of geometry without points Synthese 12 228 235 Kneebone G 1963 Mathematical Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics Dover reprint 2001 Lucas J R 2000 Conceptual Roots of Mathematics Routledge Chpt 10 on prototopology discusses Whitehead s systems and is strongly influenced by the unpublished writings of David Bostock Roeper P 1997 Region Based Topology Journal of Philosophical Logic 26 251 309 Simons P 1987 Parts A Study in Ontology Oxford Univ Press Whitehead A N 1916 La Theorie Relationiste de l Espace Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale 23 423 454 Translated as Hurley P J 1979 The relational theory of space Philosophy Research Archives 5 712 741 1919 An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge Cambridge Univ Press 2nd ed 1925 1920 The Concept of Nature Cambridge Univ Press 2004 paperback Prometheus Books Being the 1919 Tarner Lectures delivered at Trinity College 1979 1929 Process and Reality Free Press Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Whitehead 27s point free geometry amp oldid 1152431983, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.