fbpx
Wikipedia

Weak ordering

In mathematics, especially order theory, a weak ordering is a mathematical formalization of the intuitive notion of a ranking of a set, some of whose members may be tied with each other. Weak orders are a generalization of totally ordered sets (rankings without ties) and are in turn generalized by (strictly) partially ordered sets and preorders.[1]

A weak order on the set where is ranked below and and are of equal rank, and is ranked above and
I) representation as a strict weak order where is shown as an arrow from to ;
II) representation as a total preorder shown using arrows;
III) representation as an ordered partition, with the sets of the partition as dotted ellipses and the total order on these sets shown with arrows.
The 13 possible strict weak orderings on a set of three elements The only total orders are shown in black. Two orderings are connected by an edge if they differ by a single dichotomy.

There are several common ways of formalizing weak orderings, that are different from each other but cryptomorphic (interconvertable with no loss of information): they may be axiomatized as strict weak orderings (strictly partially ordered sets in which incomparability is a transitive relation), as total preorders (transitive binary relations in which at least one of the two possible relations exists between every pair of elements), or as ordered partitions (partitions of the elements into disjoint subsets, together with a total order on the subsets). In many cases another representation called a preferential arrangement based on a utility function is also possible.

Weak orderings are counted by the ordered Bell numbers. They are used in computer science as part of partition refinement algorithms, and in the C++ Standard Library.[2]

Examples Edit

In horse racing, the use of photo finishes has eliminated some, but not all, ties or (as they are called in this context) dead heats, so the outcome of a horse race may be modeled by a weak ordering.[3] In an example from the Maryland Hunt Cup steeplechase in 2007, The Bruce was the clear winner, but two horses Bug River and Lear Charm tied for second place, with the remaining horses farther back; three horses did not finish.[4] In the weak ordering describing this outcome, The Bruce would be first, Bug River and Lear Charm would be ranked after The Bruce but before all the other horses that finished, and the three horses that did not finish would be placed last in the order but tied with each other.

The points of the Euclidean plane may be ordered by their distance from the origin, giving another example of a weak ordering with infinitely many elements, infinitely many subsets of tied elements (the sets of points that belong to a common circle centered at the origin), and infinitely many points within these subsets. Although this ordering has a smallest element (the origin itself), it does not have any second-smallest elements, nor any largest element.

Opinion polling in political elections provides an example of a type of ordering that resembles weak orderings, but is better modeled mathematically in other ways. In the results of a poll, one candidate may be clearly ahead of another, or the two candidates may be statistically tied, meaning not that their poll results are equal but rather that they are within the margin of error of each other. However, if candidate   is statistically tied with   and   is statistically tied with   it might still be possible for   to be clearly better than   so being tied is not in this case a transitive relation. Because of this possibility, rankings of this type are better modeled as semiorders than as weak orderings.[5]

Axiomatizations Edit

Suppose throughout that   is a homogeneous binary relation on a set   (that is,   is a subset of  ) and as usual, write   and say that   holds or is true if and only if  

Strict weak orderings Edit

Preliminaries on incomparability and transitivity of incomparability

Two elements   and   of   are said to be incomparable with respect to   if neither   nor   is true.[1] Incomparability with respect to   is itself a homogeneous symmetric relation on   that is reflexive if and only if   is irreflexive (meaning that   is always false), which may be assumed so that transitivity is the only property this "incomparability relation" needs in order to be an equivalence relation. Define also an induced homogeneous relation   on   by declaring that

 
where importantly, this definition is not necessarily the same as:   if and only if   Two elements   are incomparable with respect to   if and only if   are equivalent with respect to   (or less verbosely,  -equivalent), which by definition means that both   are true. The relation "are incomparable with respect to  " is thus identical to (that is, equal to) the relation "are  -equivalent" (so in particular, the former is transitive if and only if the latter is). When   is irreflexive then the property known as "transitivity of incomparability" (defined below) is exactly the condition necessary and sufficient to guarantee that the relation "are  -equivalent" does indeed form an equivalence relation on   When this is the case, it allows any two elements   satisfying   to be identified as a single object (specifically, they are identified together in their common equivalence class).

Definition

A strict weak ordering on a set   is a strict partial order   on   for which the incomparability relation induced on   by   is a transitive relation.[1] Explicitly, a strict weak order on   is a homogeneous relation   on   that has all four of the following properties:

  1. Irreflexivity: For all   it is not true that  
    • This condition holds if and only if the induced relation   on   is reflexive, where   is defined by declaring that   is true if and only if   is false.
  2. Transitivity: For all   if   then  
  3. Asymmetry: For all   if   is true then   is false.
  4. Transitivity of incomparability: For all   if   is incomparable with   (meaning that neither   nor   is true) and if   is incomparable with   then   is incomparable with  
    • Two elements   are incomparable with respect to   if and only if they are equivalent with respect to the induced relation   (which by definition means that   are both true), where as before,   is declared to be true if and only if   is false. Thus this condition holds if and only if the symmetric relation on   defined by "  are equivalent with respect to  " is a transitive relation, meaning that whenever   are  -equivalent and also   are  -equivalent then necessarily   are  -equivalent. This can also be restated as: whenever   and also   then necessarily  

Properties (1), (2), and (3) are the defining properties of a strict partial order, although there is some redundancy in this list as asymmetry (3) implies irreflexivity (1), and also because irreflexivity (1) and transitivity (2) together imply asymmetry (3).[6] The incomparability relation is always symmetric and it will be reflexive if and only if   is an irreflexive relation (which is assumed by the above definition). Consequently, a strict partial order   is a strict weak order if and only if its induced incomparability relation is an equivalence relation. In this case, its equivalence classes partition   and moreover, the set   of these equivalence classes can be strictly totally ordered by a binary relation, also denoted by   that is defined for all   by:

  for some (or equivalently, for all) representatives  

Conversely, any strict total order on a partition   of   gives rise to a strict weak ordering   on   defined by   if and only if there exists sets   in this partition such that  

Not every partial order obeys the transitive law for incomparability. For instance, consider the partial order in the set   defined by the relationship   The pairs   are incomparable but   and   are related, so incomparability does not form an equivalence relation and this example is not a strict weak ordering.

For transitivity of incomparability, each of the following conditions is necessary, and for strict partial orders also sufficient:

  • If   then for all   either   or both.
  • If   is incomparable with   then for all  , either ( ) or ( ) or (  is incomparable with   and   is incomparable with  ).

Total preorders Edit

Strict weak orders are very closely related to total preorders or (non-strict) weak orders, and the same mathematical concepts that can be modeled with strict weak orderings can be modeled equally well with total preorders. A total preorder or weak order is a preorder in which any two elements are comparable.[7] A total preorder   satisfies the following properties:

  • Transitivity: For all   if   then  
  • Strong connectedness: For all    
    • Which implies reflexivity: for all    

A total order is a total preorder which is antisymmetric, in other words, which is also a partial order. Total preorders are sometimes also called preference relations.

The complement of a strict weak order is a total preorder, and vice versa, but it seems more natural to relate strict weak orders and total preorders in a way that preserves rather than reverses the order of the elements. Thus we take the converse of the complement: for a strict weak ordering   define a total preorder   by setting   whenever it is not the case that   In the other direction, to define a strict weak ordering < from a total preorder   set   whenever it is not the case that  [8]

In any preorder there is a corresponding equivalence relation where two elements   and   are defined as equivalent if   In the case of a total preorder the corresponding partial order on the set of equivalence classes is a total order. Two elements are equivalent in a total preorder if and only if they are incomparable in the corresponding strict weak ordering.

Ordered partitions Edit

A partition of a set   is a family of non-empty disjoint subsets of   that have   as their union. A partition, together with a total order on the sets of the partition, gives a structure called by Richard P. Stanley an ordered partition[9] and by Theodore Motzkin a list of sets.[10] An ordered partition of a finite set may be written as a finite sequence of the sets in the partition: for instance, the three ordered partitions of the set   are

 
 
 

In a strict weak ordering, the equivalence classes of incomparability give a set partition, in which the sets inherit a total ordering from their elements, giving rise to an ordered partition. In the other direction, any ordered partition gives rise to a strict weak ordering in which two elements are incomparable when they belong to the same set in the partition, and otherwise inherit the order of the sets that contain them.

Representation by functions Edit

For sets of sufficiently small cardinality, a third axiomatization is possible, based on real-valued functions. If   is any set then a real-valued function   on   induces a strict weak order on   by setting

 
The associated total preorder is given by setting   and the associated equivalence by setting  

The relations do not change when   is replaced by   (composite function), where   is a strictly increasing real-valued function defined on at least the range of   Thus for example, a utility function defines a preference relation. In this context, weak orderings are also known as preferential arrangements.[11]

If   is finite or countable, every weak order on   can be represented by a function in this way.[12] However, there exist strict weak orders that have no corresponding real function. For example, there is no such function for the lexicographic order on   Thus, while in most preference relation models the relation defines a utility function up to order-preserving transformations, there is no such function for lexicographic preferences.

More generally, if   is a set,   is a set with a strict weak ordering   and   is a function, then   induces a strict weak ordering on   by setting

 
As before, the associated total preorder is given by setting   and the associated equivalence by setting   It is not assumed here that   is an injective function, so a class of two equivalent elements on   may induce a larger class of equivalent elements on   Also,   is not assumed to be a surjective function, so a class of equivalent elements on   may induce a smaller or empty class on   However, the function   induces an injective function that maps the partition on   to that on   Thus, in the case of finite partitions, the number of classes in   is less than or equal to the number of classes on  

Related types of ordering Edit

Semiorders generalize strict weak orderings, but do not assume transitivity of incomparability.[13] A strict weak order that is trichotomous is called a strict total order.[14] The total preorder which is the inverse of its complement is in this case a total order.

For a strict weak order   another associated reflexive relation is its reflexive closure, a (non-strict) partial order   The two associated reflexive relations differ with regard to different   and   for which neither   nor  : in the total preorder corresponding to a strict weak order we get   and   while in the partial order given by the reflexive closure we get neither   nor   For strict total orders these two associated reflexive relations are the same: the corresponding (non-strict) total order.[14] The reflexive closure of a strict weak ordering is a type of series-parallel partial order.

All weak orders on a finite set Edit

Combinatorial enumeration Edit

The number of distinct weak orders (represented either as strict weak orders or as total preorders) on an  -element set is given by the following sequence (sequence A000670 in the OEIS):

Number of n-element binary relations of different types
Elem­ents Any Transitive Reflexive Symmetric Preorder Partial order Total preorder Total order Equivalence relation
0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1
1 2 2 1 2 1 1 1 1 1
2 16 13 4 8 4 3 3 2 2
3 512 171 64 64 29 19 13 6 5
4 65,536 3,994 4,096 1,024 355 219 75 24 15
n 2n2 2n(n−1) 2n(n+1)/2 n
k=0
k!S(n, k)
n! n
k=0
S(n, k)
OEIS A002416 A006905 A053763 A006125 A000798 A001035 A000670 A000142 A000110

Note that S(n, k) refers to Stirling numbers of the second kind.

These numbers are also called the Fubini numbers or ordered Bell numbers.

For example, for a set of three labeled items, there is one weak order in which all three items are tied. There are three ways of partitioning the items into one singleton set and one group of two tied items, and each of these partitions gives two weak orders (one in which the singleton is smaller than the group of two, and one in which this ordering is reversed), giving six weak orders of this type. And there is a single way of partitioning the set into three singletons, which can be totally ordered in six different ways. Thus, altogether, there are 13 different weak orders on three items.

Adjacency structure Edit

 
The permutohedron on four elements, a three-dimensional convex polyhedron. It has 24 vertices, 36 edges, and 14 two-dimensional faces, which all together with the whole three-dimensional polyhedron correspond to the 75 weak orderings on four elements.

Unlike for partial orders, the family of weak orderings on a given finite set is not in general connected by moves that add or remove a single order relation to or from a given ordering. For instance, for three elements, the ordering in which all three elements are tied differs by at least two pairs from any other weak ordering on the same set, in either the strict weak ordering or total preorder axiomatizations. However, a different kind of move is possible, in which the weak orderings on a set are more highly connected. Define a dichotomy to be a weak ordering with two equivalence classes, and define a dichotomy to be compatible with a given weak ordering if every two elements that are related in the ordering are either related in the same way or tied in the dichotomy. Alternatively, a dichotomy may be defined as a Dedekind cut for a weak ordering. Then a weak ordering may be characterized by its set of compatible dichotomies. For a finite set of labeled items, every pair of weak orderings may be connected to each other by a sequence of moves that add or remove one dichotomy at a time to or from this set of dichotomies. Moreover, the undirected graph that has the weak orderings as its vertices, and these moves as its edges, forms a partial cube.[15]

Geometrically, the total orderings of a given finite set may be represented as the vertices of a permutohedron, and the dichotomies on this same set as the facets of the permutohedron. In this geometric representation, the weak orderings on the set correspond to the faces of all different dimensions of the permutohedron (including the permutohedron itself, but not the empty set, as a face). The codimension of a face gives the number of equivalence classes in the corresponding weak ordering.[16] In this geometric representation the partial cube of moves on weak orderings is the graph describing the covering relation of the face lattice of the permutohedron.

For instance, for   the permutohedron on three elements is just a regular hexagon. The face lattice of the hexagon (again, including the hexagon itself as a face, but not including the empty set) has thirteen elements: one hexagon, six edges, and six vertices, corresponding to the one completely tied weak ordering, six weak orderings with one tie, and six total orderings. The graph of moves on these 13 weak orderings is shown in the figure.

Applications Edit

As mentioned above, weak orders have applications in utility theory.[12] In linear programming and other types of combinatorial optimization problem, the prioritization of solutions or of bases is often given by a weak order, determined by a real-valued objective function; the phenomenon of ties in these orderings is called "degeneracy", and several types of tie-breaking rule have been used to refine this weak ordering into a total ordering in order to prevent problems caused by degeneracy.[17]

Weak orders have also been used in computer science, in partition refinement based algorithms for lexicographic breadth-first search and lexicographic topological ordering. In these algorithms, a weak ordering on the vertices of a graph (represented as a family of sets that partition the vertices, together with a doubly linked list providing a total order on the sets) is gradually refined over the course of the algorithm, eventually producing a total ordering that is the output of the algorithm.[18]

In the Standard Library for the C++ programming language, the set and multiset data types sort their input by a comparison function that is specified at the time of template instantiation, and that is assumed to implement a strict weak ordering.[2]

See also Edit

  • Comparability – Property of elements related by inequalities
  • Preorder – Reflexive and transitive binary relation
  • Weak component – Partition of vertices of a directed graph − the equivalent subsets in the finest weak ordering consistent with a given relation

References Edit

  1. ^ a b c Roberts, Fred; Tesman, Barry (2011), Applied Combinatorics (2nd ed.), CRC Press, Section 4.2.4 Weak Orders, pp. 254–256, ISBN 9781420099836.
  2. ^ a b Josuttis, Nicolai M. (2012), The C++ Standard Library: A Tutorial and Reference, Addison-Wesley, p. 469, ISBN 9780132977739.
  3. ^ de Koninck, J. M. (2009), Those Fascinating Numbers, American Mathematical Society, p. 4, ISBN 9780821886311.
  4. ^ Baker, Kent (April 29, 2007), , The Baltimore Sun, archived from the original on March 29, 2015.
  5. ^ Regenwetter, Michel (2006), Behavioral Social Choice: Probabilistic Models, Statistical Inference, and Applications, Cambridge University Press, pp. 113ff, ISBN 9780521536660.
  6. ^ Flaška, V.; Ježek, J.; Kepka, T.; Kortelainen, J. (2007), (PDF), Prague: School of Mathematics - Physics Charles University, p. 1, S2CID 47676001, archived from the original (PDF) on 2018-04-06, Lemma 1.1 (iv). Note that this source refers to asymmetric relations as "strictly antisymmetric".
  7. ^ Such a relation is also called strongly connected.
  8. ^ Ehrgott, Matthias (2005), Multicriteria Optimization, Springer, Proposition 1.9, p. 10, ISBN 9783540276593.
  9. ^ Stanley, Richard P. (1997), Enumerative Combinatorics, Vol. 2, Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics, vol. 62, Cambridge University Press, p. 297.
  10. ^ Motzkin, Theodore S. (1971), "Sorting numbers for cylinders and other classification numbers", Combinatorics (Proc. Sympos. Pure Math., Vol. XIX, Univ. California, Los Angeles, Calif., 1968), Providence, R.I.: Amer. Math. Soc., pp. 167–176, MR 0332508.
  11. ^ Gross, O. A. (1962), "Preferential arrangements", The American Mathematical Monthly, 69 (1): 4–8, doi:10.2307/2312725, JSTOR 2312725, MR 0130837.
  12. ^ a b Roberts, Fred S. (1979), Measurement Theory, with Applications to Decisionmaking, Utility, and the Social Sciences, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, vol. 7, Addison-Wesley, Theorem 3.1, ISBN 978-0-201-13506-0.
  13. ^ Luce, R. Duncan (1956), "Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination" (PDF), Econometrica, 24 (2): 178–191, doi:10.2307/1905751, JSTOR 1905751, MR 0078632.
  14. ^ a b Velleman, Daniel J. (2006), How to Prove It: A Structured Approach, Cambridge University Press, p. 204, ISBN 9780521675994.
  15. ^ Eppstein, David; Falmagne, Jean-Claude; Ovchinnikov, Sergei (2008), Media Theory: Interdisciplinary Applied Mathematics, Springer, Section 9.4, Weak Orders and Cubical Complexes, pp. 188–196.
  16. ^ Ziegler, Günter M. (1995), Lectures on Polytopes, Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 152, Springer, p. 18.
  17. ^ Chvátal, Vašek (1983), Linear Programming, Macmillan, pp. 29–38, ISBN 9780716715870.
  18. ^ Habib, Michel; Paul, Christophe; Viennot, Laurent (1999), "Partition refinement techniques: an interesting algorithmic tool kit", International Journal of Foundations of Computer Science, 10 (2): 147–170, doi:10.1142/S0129054199000125, MR 1759929.

weak, ordering, confused, with, weak, order, permutations, transitive, binary, relations, vtesymmetricantisymmetricconnectedwell, foundedhas, joinshas, meetsreflexiveirreflexiveasymmetrictotal, semiconnexanti, reflexiveequivalence, relationy, preorder, quasior. Not to be confused with Weak order of permutations Transitive binary relations vteSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricTotal SemiconnexAnti reflexiveEquivalence relationY Y Preorder Quasiorder Y Partial order Y Y Total preorder Y Y Total order YY Y Prewellordering YY Y Well quasi ordering Y Y Well ordering YYY Y Lattice Y YYY Join semilattice Y Y Y Meet semilattice Y YY Strict partial order Y YYStrict weak order Y YYStrict total order YY YYSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricDefinitions for all a b displaystyle a b and S displaystyle S neq varnothing a R b b R a displaystyle begin aligned amp aRb Rightarrow amp bRa end aligned a R b and b R a a b displaystyle begin aligned aRb text and amp bRa Rightarrow a amp b end aligned a b a R b or b R a displaystyle begin aligned a neq amp b Rightarrow aRb text or amp bRa end aligned min S exists displaystyle begin aligned min S text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a vee b text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a wedge b text exists end aligned a R a displaystyle aRa not a R a displaystyle text not aRa a R b not b R a displaystyle begin aligned aRb Rightarrow text not bRa end aligned Y indicates that the column s property is always true the row s term at the very left while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general it might or might not hold For example that every equivalence relation is symmetric but not necessarily antisymmetric is indicated by Y in the Symmetric column and in the Antisymmetric column respectively All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation R displaystyle R be transitive for all a b c displaystyle a b c if a R b displaystyle aRb and b R c displaystyle bRc then a R c displaystyle aRc A term s definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table In mathematics especially order theory a weak ordering is a mathematical formalization of the intuitive notion of a ranking of a set some of whose members may be tied with each other Weak orders are a generalization of totally ordered sets rankings without ties and are in turn generalized by strictly partially ordered sets and preorders 1 A weak order on the set a b c d displaystyle a b c d where a displaystyle a is ranked below b displaystyle b and c b displaystyle c b and c displaystyle c are of equal rank and d displaystyle d is ranked above b displaystyle b and c displaystyle c I representation as a strict weak order lt displaystyle lt where x lt y displaystyle x lt y is shown as an arrow from x displaystyle x to y displaystyle y II representation as a total preorder displaystyle leq shown using arrows III representation as an ordered partition with the sets of the partition as dotted ellipses and the total order on these sets shown with arrows The 13 possible strict weak orderings on a set of three elements a b c displaystyle a b c The only total orders are shown in black Two orderings are connected by an edge if they differ by a single dichotomy There are several common ways of formalizing weak orderings that are different from each other but cryptomorphic interconvertable with no loss of information they may be axiomatized as strict weak orderings strictly partially ordered sets in which incomparability is a transitive relation as total preorders transitive binary relations in which at least one of the two possible relations exists between every pair of elements or as ordered partitions partitions of the elements into disjoint subsets together with a total order on the subsets In many cases another representation called a preferential arrangement based on a utility function is also possible Weak orderings are counted by the ordered Bell numbers They are used in computer science as part of partition refinement algorithms and in the C Standard Library 2 Contents 1 Examples 2 Axiomatizations 2 1 Strict weak orderings 2 2 Total preorders 2 3 Ordered partitions 2 4 Representation by functions 3 Related types of ordering 4 All weak orders on a finite set 4 1 Combinatorial enumeration 4 2 Adjacency structure 5 Applications 6 See also 7 ReferencesExamples EditIn horse racing the use of photo finishes has eliminated some but not all ties or as they are called in this context dead heats so the outcome of a horse race may be modeled by a weak ordering 3 In an example from the Maryland Hunt Cup steeplechase in 2007 The Bruce was the clear winner but two horses Bug River and Lear Charm tied for second place with the remaining horses farther back three horses did not finish 4 In the weak ordering describing this outcome The Bruce would be first Bug River and Lear Charm would be ranked after The Bruce but before all the other horses that finished and the three horses that did not finish would be placed last in the order but tied with each other The points of the Euclidean plane may be ordered by their distance from the origin giving another example of a weak ordering with infinitely many elements infinitely many subsets of tied elements the sets of points that belong to a common circle centered at the origin and infinitely many points within these subsets Although this ordering has a smallest element the origin itself it does not have any second smallest elements nor any largest element Opinion polling in political elections provides an example of a type of ordering that resembles weak orderings but is better modeled mathematically in other ways In the results of a poll one candidate may be clearly ahead of another or the two candidates may be statistically tied meaning not that their poll results are equal but rather that they are within the margin of error of each other However if candidate x displaystyle x nbsp is statistically tied with y displaystyle y nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp is statistically tied with z displaystyle z nbsp it might still be possible for x displaystyle x nbsp to be clearly better than z displaystyle z nbsp so being tied is not in this case a transitive relation Because of this possibility rankings of this type are better modeled as semiorders than as weak orderings 5 Axiomatizations EditSuppose throughout that lt displaystyle lt nbsp is a homogeneous binary relation on a set S displaystyle S nbsp that is lt displaystyle lt nbsp is a subset of S S displaystyle S times S nbsp and as usual write x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp and say that x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp holds or is true if and only if x y lt displaystyle x y in lt nbsp Strict weak orderings Edit Preliminaries on incomparability and transitivity of incomparabilityTwo elements x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp of S displaystyle S nbsp are said to be incomparable with respect to lt displaystyle lt nbsp if neither x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp nor y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp is true 1 Incomparability with respect to lt displaystyle lt nbsp is itself a homogeneous symmetric relation on S displaystyle S nbsp that is reflexive if and only if lt displaystyle lt nbsp is irreflexive meaning that x lt x displaystyle x lt x nbsp is always false which may be assumed so that transitivity is the only property this incomparability relation needs in order to be an equivalence relation Define also an induced homogeneous relation displaystyle lesssim nbsp on S displaystyle S nbsp by declaring thatx y is true if and only if y lt x is false displaystyle x lesssim y text is true quad text if and only if quad y lt x text is false nbsp where importantly this definition is not necessarily the same as x y displaystyle x lesssim y nbsp if and only if x lt y or x y displaystyle x lt y text or x y nbsp Two elements x y S displaystyle x y in S nbsp are incomparable with respect to lt displaystyle lt nbsp if and only if x and y displaystyle x text and y nbsp are equivalent with respect to displaystyle lesssim nbsp or less verbosely displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent which by definition means that both x y and y x displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim x nbsp are true The relation are incomparable with respect to lt displaystyle lt nbsp is thus identical to that is equal to the relation are displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent so in particular the former is transitive if and only if the latter is When lt displaystyle lt nbsp is irreflexive then the property known as transitivity of incomparability defined below is exactly the condition necessary and sufficient to guarantee that the relation are displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent does indeed form an equivalence relation on S displaystyle S nbsp When this is the case it allows any two elements x y S displaystyle x y in S nbsp satisfying x y and y x displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim x nbsp to be identified as a single object specifically they are identified together in their common equivalence class DefinitionA strict weak ordering on a set S displaystyle S nbsp is a strict partial order lt displaystyle lt nbsp on S displaystyle S nbsp for which the incomparability relation induced on S displaystyle S nbsp by lt displaystyle lt nbsp is a transitive relation 1 Explicitly a strict weak order on S displaystyle S nbsp is a homogeneous relation lt displaystyle lt nbsp on S displaystyle S nbsp that has all four of the following properties Irreflexivity For all x S displaystyle x in S nbsp it is not true that x lt x displaystyle x lt x nbsp This condition holds if and only if the induced relation displaystyle lesssim nbsp on S displaystyle S nbsp is reflexive where displaystyle lesssim nbsp is defined by declaring that x y displaystyle x lesssim y nbsp is true if and only if y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp is false Transitivity For all x y z S displaystyle x y z in S nbsp if x lt y and y lt z displaystyle x lt y text and y lt z nbsp then x lt z displaystyle x lt z nbsp Asymmetry For all x y S displaystyle x y in S nbsp if x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp is true then y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp is false Transitivity of incomparability For all x y z S displaystyle x y z in S nbsp if x displaystyle x nbsp is incomparable with y displaystyle y nbsp meaning that neither x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp nor y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp is true and if y displaystyle y nbsp is incomparable with z displaystyle z nbsp then x displaystyle x nbsp is incomparable with z displaystyle z nbsp Two elements x and y displaystyle x text and y nbsp are incomparable with respect to lt displaystyle lt nbsp if and only if they are equivalent with respect to the induced relation displaystyle lesssim nbsp which by definition means that x y and y x displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim x nbsp are both true where as before x y displaystyle x lesssim y nbsp is declared to be true if and only if y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp is false Thus this condition holds if and only if the symmetric relation on S displaystyle S nbsp defined by x and y displaystyle x text and y nbsp are equivalent with respect to displaystyle lesssim nbsp is a transitive relation meaning that whenever x and y displaystyle x text and y nbsp are displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent and also y and z displaystyle y text and z nbsp are displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent then necessarily x and z displaystyle x text and z nbsp are displaystyle lesssim nbsp equivalent This can also be restated as whenever x y and y x displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim x nbsp and also y z and z y displaystyle y lesssim z text and z lesssim y nbsp then necessarily x z and z x displaystyle x lesssim z text and z lesssim x nbsp Properties 1 2 and 3 are the defining properties of a strict partial order although there is some redundancy in this list as asymmetry 3 implies irreflexivity 1 and also because irreflexivity 1 and transitivity 2 together imply asymmetry 3 6 The incomparability relation is always symmetric and it will be reflexive if and only if lt displaystyle lt nbsp is an irreflexive relation which is assumed by the above definition Consequently a strict partial order lt displaystyle lt nbsp is a strict weak order if and only if its induced incomparability relation is an equivalence relation In this case its equivalence classes partition S displaystyle S nbsp and moreover the set P displaystyle mathcal P nbsp of these equivalence classes can be strictly totally ordered by a binary relation also denoted by lt displaystyle lt nbsp that is defined for all A B P displaystyle A B in mathcal P nbsp by A lt B if and only if a lt b displaystyle A lt B text if and only if a lt b nbsp for some or equivalently for all representatives a A and b B displaystyle a in A text and b in B nbsp Conversely any strict total order on a partition P displaystyle mathcal P nbsp of S displaystyle S nbsp gives rise to a strict weak ordering lt displaystyle lt nbsp on S displaystyle S nbsp defined by a lt b displaystyle a lt b nbsp if and only if there exists sets A B P displaystyle A B in mathcal P nbsp in this partition such that a A b B and A lt B displaystyle a in A b in B text and A lt B nbsp Not every partial order obeys the transitive law for incomparability For instance consider the partial order in the set a b c displaystyle a b c nbsp defined by the relationship b lt c displaystyle b lt c nbsp The pairs a b and a c displaystyle a b text and a c nbsp are incomparable but b displaystyle b nbsp and c displaystyle c nbsp are related so incomparability does not form an equivalence relation and this example is not a strict weak ordering For transitivity of incomparability each of the following conditions is necessary and for strict partial orders also sufficient If x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp then for all z displaystyle z nbsp either x lt z or z lt y displaystyle x lt z text or z lt y nbsp or both If x displaystyle x nbsp is incomparable with y displaystyle y nbsp then for all z displaystyle z nbsp either x lt z and y lt z displaystyle x lt z text and y lt z nbsp or z lt x and z lt y displaystyle z lt x text and z lt y nbsp or z displaystyle z nbsp is incomparable with x displaystyle x nbsp and z displaystyle z nbsp is incomparable with y displaystyle y nbsp Total preorders Edit Strict weak orders are very closely related to total preorders or non strict weak orders and the same mathematical concepts that can be modeled with strict weak orderings can be modeled equally well with total preorders A total preorder or weak order is a preorder in which any two elements are comparable 7 A total preorder displaystyle lesssim nbsp satisfies the following properties Transitivity For all x y and z displaystyle x y text and z nbsp if x y and y z displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim z nbsp then x z displaystyle x lesssim z nbsp Strong connectedness For all x and y displaystyle x text and y nbsp x y or y x displaystyle x lesssim y text or y lesssim x nbsp Which implies reflexivity for all x displaystyle x nbsp x x displaystyle x lesssim x nbsp A total order is a total preorder which is antisymmetric in other words which is also a partial order Total preorders are sometimes also called preference relations The complement of a strict weak order is a total preorder and vice versa but it seems more natural to relate strict weak orders and total preorders in a way that preserves rather than reverses the order of the elements Thus we take the converse of the complement for a strict weak ordering lt displaystyle lt nbsp define a total preorder displaystyle lesssim nbsp by setting x y displaystyle x lesssim y nbsp whenever it is not the case that y lt x displaystyle y lt x nbsp In the other direction to define a strict weak ordering lt from a total preorder displaystyle lesssim nbsp set x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp whenever it is not the case that y x displaystyle y lesssim x nbsp 8 In any preorder there is a corresponding equivalence relation where two elements x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp are defined as equivalent if x y and y x displaystyle x lesssim y text and y lesssim x nbsp In the case of a total preorder the corresponding partial order on the set of equivalence classes is a total order Two elements are equivalent in a total preorder if and only if they are incomparable in the corresponding strict weak ordering Ordered partitions Edit A partition of a set S displaystyle S nbsp is a family of non empty disjoint subsets of S displaystyle S nbsp that have S displaystyle S nbsp as their union A partition together with a total order on the sets of the partition gives a structure called by Richard P Stanley an ordered partition 9 and by Theodore Motzkin a list of sets 10 An ordered partition of a finite set may be written as a finite sequence of the sets in the partition for instance the three ordered partitions of the set a b displaystyle a b nbsp are a b displaystyle a b nbsp b a and displaystyle b a text and nbsp a b displaystyle a b nbsp In a strict weak ordering the equivalence classes of incomparability give a set partition in which the sets inherit a total ordering from their elements giving rise to an ordered partition In the other direction any ordered partition gives rise to a strict weak ordering in which two elements are incomparable when they belong to the same set in the partition and otherwise inherit the order of the sets that contain them Representation by functions Edit For sets of sufficiently small cardinality a third axiomatization is possible based on real valued functions If X displaystyle X nbsp is any set then a real valued function f X R displaystyle f X to mathbb R nbsp on X displaystyle X nbsp induces a strict weak order on X displaystyle X nbsp by settinga lt b if and only if f a lt f b displaystyle a lt b text if and only if f a lt f b nbsp The associated total preorder is given by setting a b if and only if f a f b displaystyle a lesssim b text if and only if f a leq f b nbsp and the associated equivalence by setting a b if and only if f a f b displaystyle a sim b text if and only if f a f b nbsp The relations do not change when f displaystyle f nbsp is replaced by g f displaystyle g circ f nbsp composite function where g displaystyle g nbsp is a strictly increasing real valued function defined on at least the range of f displaystyle f nbsp Thus for example a utility function defines a preference relation In this context weak orderings are also known as preferential arrangements 11 If X displaystyle X nbsp is finite or countable every weak order on X displaystyle X nbsp can be represented by a function in this way 12 However there exist strict weak orders that have no corresponding real function For example there is no such function for the lexicographic order on R n displaystyle mathbb R n nbsp Thus while in most preference relation models the relation defines a utility function up to order preserving transformations there is no such function for lexicographic preferences More generally if X displaystyle X nbsp is a set Y displaystyle Y nbsp is a set with a strict weak ordering lt displaystyle lt nbsp and f X Y displaystyle f X to Y nbsp is a function then f displaystyle f nbsp induces a strict weak ordering on X displaystyle X nbsp by settinga lt b if and only if f a lt f b displaystyle a lt b text if and only if f a lt f b nbsp As before the associated total preorder is given by setting a b if and only if f a f b displaystyle a lesssim b text if and only if f a lesssim f b nbsp and the associated equivalence by setting a b if and only if f a f b displaystyle a sim b text if and only if f a sim f b nbsp It is not assumed here that f displaystyle f nbsp is an injective function so a class of two equivalent elements on Y displaystyle Y nbsp may induce a larger class of equivalent elements on X displaystyle X nbsp Also f displaystyle f nbsp is not assumed to be a surjective function so a class of equivalent elements on Y displaystyle Y nbsp may induce a smaller or empty class on X displaystyle X nbsp However the function f displaystyle f nbsp induces an injective function that maps the partition on X displaystyle X nbsp to that on Y displaystyle Y nbsp Thus in the case of finite partitions the number of classes in X displaystyle X nbsp is less than or equal to the number of classes on Y displaystyle Y nbsp Related types of ordering EditSemiorders generalize strict weak orderings but do not assume transitivity of incomparability 13 A strict weak order that is trichotomous is called a strict total order 14 The total preorder which is the inverse of its complement is in this case a total order For a strict weak order lt displaystyle lt nbsp another associated reflexive relation is its reflexive closure a non strict partial order displaystyle leq nbsp The two associated reflexive relations differ with regard to different a displaystyle a nbsp and b displaystyle b nbsp for which neither a lt b displaystyle a lt b nbsp nor b lt a displaystyle b lt a nbsp in the total preorder corresponding to a strict weak order we get a b displaystyle a lesssim b nbsp and b a displaystyle b lesssim a nbsp while in the partial order given by the reflexive closure we get neither a b displaystyle a leq b nbsp nor b a displaystyle b leq a nbsp For strict total orders these two associated reflexive relations are the same the corresponding non strict total order 14 The reflexive closure of a strict weak ordering is a type of series parallel partial order All weak orders on a finite set EditCombinatorial enumeration Edit Main article ordered Bell number The number of distinct weak orders represented either as strict weak orders or as total preorders on an n displaystyle n nbsp element set is given by the following sequence sequence A000670 in the OEIS Number of n element binary relations of different types Elem ents Any Transitive Reflexive Symmetric Preorder Partial order Total preorder Total order Equivalence relation0 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 11 2 2 1 2 1 1 1 1 12 16 13 4 8 4 3 3 2 23 512 171 64 64 29 19 13 6 54 65 536 3 994 4 096 1 024 355 219 75 24 15n 2n2 2n n 1 2n n 1 2 nk 0 k S n k n nk 0 S n k OEIS A002416 A006905 A053763 A006125 A000798 A001035 A000670 A000142 A000110Note that S n k refers to Stirling numbers of the second kind These numbers are also called the Fubini numbers or ordered Bell numbers For example for a set of three labeled items there is one weak order in which all three items are tied There are three ways of partitioning the items into one singleton set and one group of two tied items and each of these partitions gives two weak orders one in which the singleton is smaller than the group of two and one in which this ordering is reversed giving six weak orders of this type And there is a single way of partitioning the set into three singletons which can be totally ordered in six different ways Thus altogether there are 13 different weak orders on three items Adjacency structure Edit nbsp The permutohedron on four elements a three dimensional convex polyhedron It has 24 vertices 36 edges and 14 two dimensional faces which all together with the whole three dimensional polyhedron correspond to the 75 weak orderings on four elements Unlike for partial orders the family of weak orderings on a given finite set is not in general connected by moves that add or remove a single order relation to or from a given ordering For instance for three elements the ordering in which all three elements are tied differs by at least two pairs from any other weak ordering on the same set in either the strict weak ordering or total preorder axiomatizations However a different kind of move is possible in which the weak orderings on a set are more highly connected Define a dichotomy to be a weak ordering with two equivalence classes and define a dichotomy to be compatible with a given weak ordering if every two elements that are related in the ordering are either related in the same way or tied in the dichotomy Alternatively a dichotomy may be defined as a Dedekind cut for a weak ordering Then a weak ordering may be characterized by its set of compatible dichotomies For a finite set of labeled items every pair of weak orderings may be connected to each other by a sequence of moves that add or remove one dichotomy at a time to or from this set of dichotomies Moreover the undirected graph that has the weak orderings as its vertices and these moves as its edges forms a partial cube 15 Geometrically the total orderings of a given finite set may be represented as the vertices of a permutohedron and the dichotomies on this same set as the facets of the permutohedron In this geometric representation the weak orderings on the set correspond to the faces of all different dimensions of the permutohedron including the permutohedron itself but not the empty set as a face The codimension of a face gives the number of equivalence classes in the corresponding weak ordering 16 In this geometric representation the partial cube of moves on weak orderings is the graph describing the covering relation of the face lattice of the permutohedron For instance for n 3 displaystyle n 3 nbsp the permutohedron on three elements is just a regular hexagon The face lattice of the hexagon again including the hexagon itself as a face but not including the empty set has thirteen elements one hexagon six edges and six vertices corresponding to the one completely tied weak ordering six weak orderings with one tie and six total orderings The graph of moves on these 13 weak orderings is shown in the figure Applications EditAs mentioned above weak orders have applications in utility theory 12 In linear programming and other types of combinatorial optimization problem the prioritization of solutions or of bases is often given by a weak order determined by a real valued objective function the phenomenon of ties in these orderings is called degeneracy and several types of tie breaking rule have been used to refine this weak ordering into a total ordering in order to prevent problems caused by degeneracy 17 Weak orders have also been used in computer science in partition refinement based algorithms for lexicographic breadth first search and lexicographic topological ordering In these algorithms a weak ordering on the vertices of a graph represented as a family of sets that partition the vertices together with a doubly linked list providing a total order on the sets is gradually refined over the course of the algorithm eventually producing a total ordering that is the output of the algorithm 18 In the Standard Library for the C programming language the set and multiset data types sort their input by a comparison function that is specified at the time of template instantiation and that is assumed to implement a strict weak ordering 2 See also EditComparability Property of elements related by inequalities Preorder Reflexive and transitive binary relation Weak component Partition of vertices of a directed graph the equivalent subsets in the finest weak ordering consistent with a given relationReferences Edit a b c Roberts Fred Tesman Barry 2011 Applied Combinatorics 2nd ed CRC Press Section 4 2 4 Weak Orders pp 254 256 ISBN 9781420099836 a b Josuttis Nicolai M 2012 The C Standard Library A Tutorial and Reference Addison Wesley p 469 ISBN 9780132977739 de Koninck J M 2009 Those Fascinating Numbers American Mathematical Society p 4 ISBN 9780821886311 Baker Kent April 29 2007 The Bruce hangs on for Hunt Cup victory Bug River Lear Charm finish in dead heat for second The Baltimore Sun archived from the original on March 29 2015 Regenwetter Michel 2006 Behavioral Social Choice Probabilistic Models Statistical Inference and Applications Cambridge University Press pp 113ff ISBN 9780521536660 Flaska V Jezek J Kepka T Kortelainen J 2007 Transitive Closures of Binary Relations I PDF Prague School of Mathematics Physics Charles University p 1 S2CID 47676001 archived from the original PDF on 2018 04 06 Lemma 1 1 iv Note that this source refers to asymmetric relations as strictly antisymmetric Such a relation is also called strongly connected Ehrgott Matthias 2005 Multicriteria Optimization Springer Proposition 1 9 p 10 ISBN 9783540276593 Stanley Richard P 1997 Enumerative Combinatorics Vol 2 Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics vol 62 Cambridge University Press p 297 Motzkin Theodore S 1971 Sorting numbers for cylinders and other classification numbers Combinatorics Proc Sympos Pure Math Vol XIX Univ California Los Angeles Calif 1968 Providence R I Amer Math Soc pp 167 176 MR 0332508 Gross O A 1962 Preferential arrangements The American Mathematical Monthly 69 1 4 8 doi 10 2307 2312725 JSTOR 2312725 MR 0130837 a b Roberts Fred S 1979 Measurement Theory with Applications to Decisionmaking Utility and the Social Sciences Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications vol 7 Addison Wesley Theorem 3 1 ISBN 978 0 201 13506 0 Luce R Duncan 1956 Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination PDF Econometrica 24 2 178 191 doi 10 2307 1905751 JSTOR 1905751 MR 0078632 a b Velleman Daniel J 2006 How to Prove It A Structured Approach Cambridge University Press p 204 ISBN 9780521675994 Eppstein David Falmagne Jean Claude Ovchinnikov Sergei 2008 Media Theory Interdisciplinary Applied Mathematics Springer Section 9 4 Weak Orders and Cubical Complexes pp 188 196 Ziegler Gunter M 1995 Lectures on Polytopes Graduate Texts in Mathematics vol 152 Springer p 18 Chvatal Vasek 1983 Linear Programming Macmillan pp 29 38 ISBN 9780716715870 Habib Michel Paul Christophe Viennot Laurent 1999 Partition refinement techniques an interesting algorithmic tool kit International Journal of Foundations of Computer Science 10 2 147 170 doi 10 1142 S0129054199000125 MR 1759929 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Weak ordering amp oldid 1163594809, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.