fbpx
Wikipedia

Sisyphus fragment

The Sisyphus fragment is a fragment from Classical Attic drama which is thought to contain an early argument for atheism, claiming that a clever man invented "the fear of the gods" in order to frighten people into behaving morally.

The fragment was preserved in the works of the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus. In antiquity, its authorship was disputed and is attributed in one tradition to Euripides, in another Critias, but the fragment indicates clear intellectual influences that are less under dispute. This includes the thought of Democritus, as Charles H. Kahn has argued.[1] Like the Sisyphus fragment, Democritus wrote that early humans believed in the gods through fear of natural celestial phenomena:

And there are some who have supposed that we have arrived at the conception of Gods from those events in the world which are marvelous; which opinion seems to have been held by Democritus, who says—“For when the men of old time beheld the disasters in the heavens, such as thunderings and lightnings, and thunderbolts and collisions between stars, and eclipses of sun and moon, they were affrighted, imagining the Gods to be the causes of these things.”[2]

Text

The Greek text is conserved in Sextus Empiricus Against the Physicists Book 1 Section 54[a]

Several English versions exist.[5][6][7] That by R. G. Bury runs:-

A time there was when anarchy did rule
The lives of men, which then were like the beasts,
Enslaved by force; nor was there then reward
For good men, nor for wicked punishment.
Next, as I deem, did men establish laws
For punishment, that Justice might be lord
Of all mankind, and Insolence enchain'd;
And whosoe'r did sin was penalized.
Next, as the laws did hold men back from deeds
Of open violence, but still such deeds
Were done in secret,—then, as I maintain,
Some shrewd man first, a man in counsel wise,
Discovered unto men the fear of Gods,
Thereby to frighten sinners should they sin
E'en secretly in deed, or word, or thought.
Hence was it that he brought in Deity
Telling how God enjoys an endless life,
Hears with his mind and sees, and taketh thought
And heeds things, and his nature is divine,
So that he hearkens to men's every word
And has the power to see men's every act.
E'en if you plan in silence some ill deed,
The Gods will surely mark it; for in them
Wisdom resides. So, speaking words like these
Most cunning doctrine did he introduce,
The truth concealing under speech untrue.
The place he spoke of as the God's abode
Was that whereby he could affright men most,—
The place from which, he knew, both terrors came
And easements unto men of toilsome life—
To wit the vault above, wherein do dwell
The lightnings, he beheld, and awesome claps
Of thunder, and the starry face of heaven,
Fair-spangled by that cunning craftsman Time,—
Whence, too, the meteor's glowing mass doth speed
And liquid rain descends upon the earth.
Such were the fears wherewith he hedged men round,
And so to God he gave a fitting home,
By this his speech, and in a fitting place,
And thus extinguished lawlessness by laws.

And, after proceeding a little further, he adds—

Thus first did some man, as I deem, persuade
Men to suppose the race of Gods exists..[8]

Authorship

The authorship of the fragment, which survives in the writings of Sextus Empiricus, is vigorously debated.[9] Modern classical scholarship accepted the attribution to Critias on the basis of a hypothesis first advanced by Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff in 1875, and thereafter Hermann Diels, Johann August Nauck, and Bruno Snell, endorsed this ascription for which there is but one source in antiquity.[10] In 1977, Albrecht Dihle in a major paper challenged this ascription and assigned the work to Euripides, arguing that the fragment comes from the latter's satyr play of this name, produced in 415 BCE.[11] Since Dihle published his article, the authorship of the fragment has divided modern scholars. Scholars that advocate Euripidean authorship include Charles H. Kahn, Ruth Scodel, Martin Ostwald, Jan Bremmer and Harvey Yunis.[12] However, Critias authorship was argued by Walter Burkert,[b] and other scholars that advocate for the same authorship include Dana Sutton, Marek Winiarczyk, Malcolm Davies, Dirk Obbink, Tim Whitmarsh and Martin Cropp.[14][15][16]

One source in antiquity ascribed the passage to Critias, one of the thirty oligarchs who ruled Athens in the immediate aftermath of the city-state's defeat in the Peloponesian War: two attribute it, or lines in it, to Euripides.[9] Sextus Empiricus assigned these verses to Critias without however indicating which of his works. Both the Stoic logician Chrysippus and the doxographer Aëtius cited Euripides as the author, specifying that it was taken from that author's lost play Sisyphus.[17] In modern times, Wilamowitz came down strongly for the view that it was written by Critias, a disciple of Socrates, and dated it, as forming the coda of a tetralogy, following three tragedies by Critias -Peirithous, Rhadumunthus and Tennes -, which he argued was written sometime after his return from exile in 411.[18][19] The view that it was written by Euripides frequently identifies it as belonging to the Sisyphus, the satyr play capping his 415 trilogy: Alexandros, Palamedes and The Trojan Women,[10] though Jan N. Bremmer suggests another lost play by Euripides; his Autolykos would be a more attractive candidate as the original source.[9]

A major issue in discussing authorship of the passage hinges on the question whether the speaker's views reflect those of a historic atheist, or whether the lines are simply a dramatic mise en scène of an atheistic outlook, and therefore not one entertained by its author. Dihle argued that there was no evidence in the surviving fragments of Kritias that he was an atheist, except for the testimony of Sextus Empiricus and Plutarch,[20] a point Burkert challenged in the revised English version of his book on Greek Religion by citing the testimony of a fragment of Epicurus from Bk.11 of his work On Nature.

Style

The fragment is composed of 42 iambic trimeters. The topic concerns the mythical figure of Sisyphus. Style plays an important function in the authorship question: if we take it as expressing the view of the sophist Critias, the cynical deconstruction of religion would appear to harmonize perfectly with the character of that historical person, – 'that brilliant but sinister figure in the politics and letters of the end of the fifth century'[21] – who gained a reputation for ruthless unscrupulousness. But were it to pertain to the genre of the satyr play, then we would not expect a straightforward exposition of a theory but rather a parody of it, a tone lacking in the surviving fragment.[22]

Interpretations

W. K. C. Guthrie stated that the Sisyphus fragment is 'the first occurrence in history of the theory of religion as a political invention to ensure good behaviour,' an approach which was subsequently adopted by the Hellenistic historian Polybius in his 40 volume history of Rome's emergence as an empire.[23] Karl Popper in his The Open Society and its Enemies noted a 'striking' similarity between the passage ascribed to Critias, and the views Plato, Critias's nephew, developed in his two dialogues, the Republic and the Laws regarding the Noble lie.[24]

Notes

  1. ^ Greek text.

    ἦν χρόνος ὅτ᾽ ἦν ἄτακτος ἀνθρώπων βίος
    καὶ θηριώδης ἰσχύος θ᾽ ὑπηρέτης,
    ὅτ᾽ οὐδὲν ἆθλον οὔτε τοῖς ἐσθλοῖσιν ἦν
    οὔτ᾽ αὖ κόλασμα τοῖς κακοῖς ἐγίγνετο.
    κἄπειτά μοι δοκοῦσιν ἅνθρωποι νόμους 5
    θέσθαι κολαστάς, ἵνα δίκη τύραννος ᾖ
    <x_ᴗ_x> τήν θ᾽ ὕβριν δούλην ἔχῃ·
    ἐζημιοῦτο δ᾽ εἴ τις ἐξαμαρτάνοι.
    ἔπειτ᾽ ἐπειδὴ τἀμφανῆ μὲν οἱ νόμοι
    ἀπεῖργον αὐτοὺς ἔργα μὴ πράσσειν βίᾳ, 10
    λάθρᾳ δ᾽ ἔπρασσον, τηνικαῦτά μοι δοκεῖ
    <πρῶτον> πυκνός τις καὶ σοφὸς γνώμην ἀνήρ
    <θεῶν> δέος θνητοῖσιν ἐξευρεῖν, ὅπως
    εἴη τι δεῖμα τοῖς κακοῖσι, κἂν λάθρᾳ
    πράσσωσιν ἢ λέγωσιν ἢ φρονῶσί <τι>. 15
    ἐντεῦθεν οὖν τὸ θεῖον εἰσηγήσατο,
    ὡς ἔστι δαίμων ἀφθίτῳ θάλλων βίῳ
    νόῳ τ᾽ ἀκούων καὶ βλέπων, φρονῶν τε καὶ
    προσέχων τε ταῦτα καὶ φύσιν θείαν φορῶν,
    ὃς πᾶν {μὲν} τὸ λεχθὲν ἐν βροτοῖς ἀκού<σ>εται, 20
    <τὸ> δρώμενον δὲ πᾶν ἰδεῖν δυνήσεται.
    ἐὰν δὲ σὺν σιγῇ τι βουλεύῃς κακόν,
    τοῦτ᾽ οὐχὶ λήσει τοὺς θεούς· τὸ γὰρ φρονοῦν
    ἔνεστι. τ<οισύτ>ους δε τοὺς λόγους λέγων
    διδαγμάτων ἥδιστον εἰσηγήσατο 25
    ψευδεῖ καλύψας τὴν ἀλήθειαν λόγῳ.
    <ν>αίει<ν> δ᾽ ἔφασκε τοὺς θεοὺς ἐνταῦθ᾽ ἵνα
    μάλιστ᾽ἂ<ν>1 ἐξέπληξεν ἀνθρώπους ἄγων,
    ὅθεν περ ἔγνω τοὺς φόβους ὄντας βροτοῖς
    καὶ τὰς ὀνήσεις τῷ ταλαιπώρῳ βίῳ, 30
    ἐκ τῆς ὕπερθε περιφορᾶς, ἵν᾽ ἀστραπάς
    κατεῖδον οὔσας, δεινὰ δὲ κτυπήματα
    βροντῆς τό τ᾽ ἀστερωπὸν οὐρανοῦ δέμας,
    Χρόνου καλὸν ποίκιλμα, τέκτονος σοφοῦ,
    ὅθεν τε λαμπρὸς ἀστέρος στείχει μύδρος 35
    ὅ θ᾽ ὑγρὸς εἰς γῆν ὄμβρος ἐκπορεύεται.
    τοίους πέριξ ἔστησεν ἀνθρώποις φόβους,
    δι᾽ οὓς καλῶς τε τῷ λόγῳ κατῴκισεν
    τὸν δαίμον᾽ οὗτος ἐν πρέποντι χωρίῳ,
    τὴν ἀνομίαν τε τοῖς νόμοις κατέσβεσεν 40[3]

    οὕτω δὲ πρῶτον οἴομαι πεῖσαί τινα
    θνητοὺς νομίζειν δαιμόνων εἶναι γένος.[4]

  2. ^ Apropos Dihle's proposal he writes that Dihle 'overlooks the testimony of Epicurus 27.2.8.'[13]

Citations

  1. ^ Kahn 1997, p. 259.
  2. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Against the Physicists Book 1, Section 24
  3. ^ Davies 1989, pp. 16–17.
  4. ^ EF 2009, pp. 670–678.
  5. ^ Davies 1989, p. 18.
  6. ^ Kahn 1997, pp. 247–248.
  7. ^ Guthrie 1969, pp. 243–244.
  8. ^ Bury 1936, pp. 31–32.
  9. ^ a b c Bremmer 2006, p. 16.
  10. ^ a b Kahn 1997, p. 249.
  11. ^ Dihle 1977, pp. 28–30.
  12. ^ Kahn 1997, p. 249 and n.5.
  13. ^ Burkert 1985, p. 467,n.22.
  14. ^ Davies 1989, p. 24-28.
  15. ^ Whitmarsh 2014, p. 112-113.
  16. ^ Cropp 2020.
  17. ^ Davies 1989, p. 17.
  18. ^ Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 1875, pp. 161, 166.
  19. ^ Davies 1989, p. 24.
  20. ^ Dihle 1977, p. 31.
  21. ^ Lovejoy & Boas 1935, p. 211.
  22. ^ Bremmer 2006, p. 8.
  23. ^ Guthrie 1969, p. 244.
  24. ^ Popper 1966, pp. 142–143.

Sources

  • Bremmer, Jan N. (2006). "Atheism in Antiquity". In Martin, Michael (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Atheism. Cambridge University Press. pp. 11–26. ISBN 978-1-139-00118-2.
  • Burkert, Walter (1985). Greek Religion: Archaic and Classical. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-36281-9.
  • Collard, Christopher; Cropp, Martin, eds. (2009). Euripides. Fragments: Oedipus-Chrysippus. Other Fragments. Loeb Classical Library. Vol. 506. Harvard University Press. pp. 670–678.
  • Cropp, Martin (2020). Lamari, A.; Montanari, F. (eds.). Fragmentation in Ancient Greek Drama. De Gruyter. pp. 235–256.
  • Davies, Malcolm (1989). "Sisyphus and the invention of religion ('Critias' TrGF 1 (43) F 19 = B 25 DK)". Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies. 36 (36): 16–32. doi:10.1111/j.2041-5370.1989.tb00560.x. JSTOR 43693889.
  • Dihle, Albrecht (1977). "Das Satyrspiel "Sisyphos"". Hermes. 105 (1): 28–42. JSTOR 4475993.
  • Guthrie, W. K. C. (1969). A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 3. Cambridge University Press.
  • Kahn, Charles H. (1997). "Greek Religion and Philosophy in the Sisyphus Fragment". Phronesis. 42 (3): 247–262. doi:10.1163/15685289760518153. JSTOR 4182561.
  • Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken; Boas, George (1935). Primitivism and Related Ideas in Antiquity. Vol. 1 (2nd ed.). Octagon Books.
  • Miller, James F.; Woodruff, Paul B.. (2000). "Introduction". In Miller, James F.; Woodruff, Paul B. (eds.). Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy. Oxford University Press. pp. 3–11. ISBN 978-0-195-13322-6.
  • Popper, Karl (1966) [First published 1945]. The Open Society and Its Enemies: The Spell of Plato. Vol. 1 (5th ed.). Routledge.
  • Sextus Empiricus (1936). Bury, R. G. (ed.). Sextus Empiricus. Vol. 3. Harvard University Press William Heinemann.
  • Whitmarsh, Tim (2014). "Atheistic Aesthetics: The Sisyphus Fragment, Poetics and the Creativity of Drama". Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society. 60: 109–126.
  • Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von (1875). Analecta Euripidea. Borntraeger.

External links

  • An English translation of the Sisyphus fragment

sisyphus, fragment, fragment, from, classical, attic, drama, which, thought, contain, early, argument, atheism, claiming, that, clever, invented, fear, gods, order, frighten, people, into, behaving, morally, fragment, preserved, works, pyrrhonist, philosopher,. The Sisyphus fragment is a fragment from Classical Attic drama which is thought to contain an early argument for atheism claiming that a clever man invented the fear of the gods in order to frighten people into behaving morally The fragment was preserved in the works of the Pyrrhonist philosopher Sextus Empiricus In antiquity its authorship was disputed and is attributed in one tradition to Euripides in another Critias but the fragment indicates clear intellectual influences that are less under dispute This includes the thought of Democritus as Charles H Kahn has argued 1 Like the Sisyphus fragment Democritus wrote that early humans believed in the gods through fear of natural celestial phenomena And there are some who have supposed that we have arrived at the conception of Gods from those events in the world which are marvelous which opinion seems to have been held by Democritus who says For when the men of old time beheld the disasters in the heavens such as thunderings and lightnings and thunderbolts and collisions between stars and eclipses of sun and moon they were affrighted imagining the Gods to be the causes of these things 2 Contents 1 Text 2 Authorship 3 Style 4 Interpretations 5 Notes 5 1 Citations 6 Sources 7 External linksText EditThe Greek text is conserved in Sextus Empiricus Against the Physicists Book 1 Section 54 a Several English versions exist 5 6 7 That by R G Bury runs A time there was when anarchy did rule The lives of men which then were like the beasts Enslaved by force nor was there then reward For good men nor for wicked punishment Next as I deem did men establish laws For punishment that Justice might be lord Of all mankind and Insolence enchain d And whosoe r did sin was penalized Next as the laws did hold men back from deeds Of open violence but still such deeds Were done in secret then as I maintain Some shrewd man first a man in counsel wise Discovered unto men the fear of Gods Thereby to frighten sinners should they sin E en secretly in deed or word or thought Hence was it that he brought in Deity Telling how God enjoys an endless life Hears with his mind and sees and taketh thought And heeds things and his nature is divine So that he hearkens to men s every word And has the power to see men s every act E en if you plan in silence some ill deed The Gods will surely mark it for in them Wisdom resides So speaking words like these Most cunning doctrine did he introduce The truth concealing under speech untrue The place he spoke of as the God s abode Was that whereby he could affright men most The place from which he knew both terrors came And easements unto men of toilsome life To wit the vault above wherein do dwell The lightnings he beheld and awesome claps Of thunder and the starry face of heaven Fair spangled by that cunning craftsman Time Whence too the meteor s glowing mass doth speed And liquid rain descends upon the earth Such were the fears wherewith he hedged men round And so to God he gave a fitting home By this his speech and in a fitting place And thus extinguished lawlessness by laws And after proceeding a little further he adds Thus first did some man as I deem persuade Men to suppose the race of Gods exists 8 Authorship EditThe authorship of the fragment which survives in the writings of Sextus Empiricus is vigorously debated 9 Modern classical scholarship accepted the attribution to Critias on the basis of a hypothesis first advanced by Ulrich von Wilamowitz Moellendorff in 1875 and thereafter Hermann Diels Johann August Nauck and Bruno Snell endorsed this ascription for which there is but one source in antiquity 10 In 1977 Albrecht Dihle in a major paper challenged this ascription and assigned the work to Euripides arguing that the fragment comes from the latter s satyr play of this name produced in 415 BCE 11 Since Dihle published his article the authorship of the fragment has divided modern scholars Scholars that advocate Euripidean authorship include Charles H Kahn Ruth Scodel Martin Ostwald Jan Bremmer and Harvey Yunis 12 However Critias authorship was argued by Walter Burkert b and other scholars that advocate for the same authorship include Dana Sutton Marek Winiarczyk Malcolm Davies Dirk Obbink Tim Whitmarsh and Martin Cropp 14 15 16 One source in antiquity ascribed the passage to Critias one of the thirty oligarchs who ruled Athens in the immediate aftermath of the city state s defeat in the Peloponesian War two attribute it or lines in it to Euripides 9 Sextus Empiricus assigned these verses to Critias without however indicating which of his works Both the Stoic logician Chrysippus and the doxographer Aetius cited Euripides as the author specifying that it was taken from that author s lost play Sisyphus 17 In modern times Wilamowitz came down strongly for the view that it was written by Critias a disciple of Socrates and dated it as forming the coda of a tetralogy following three tragedies by Critias Peirithous Rhadumunthus and Tennes which he argued was written sometime after his return from exile in 411 18 19 The view that it was written by Euripides frequently identifies it as belonging to the Sisyphus the satyr play capping his 415 trilogy Alexandros Palamedes and The Trojan Women 10 though Jan N Bremmer suggests another lost play by Euripides his Autolykos would be a more attractive candidate as the original source 9 A major issue in discussing authorship of the passage hinges on the question whether the speaker s views reflect those of a historic atheist or whether the lines are simply a dramatic mise en scene of an atheistic outlook and therefore not one entertained by its author Dihle argued that there was no evidence in the surviving fragments of Kritias that he was an atheist except for the testimony of Sextus Empiricus and Plutarch 20 a point Burkert challenged in the revised English version of his book on Greek Religion by citing the testimony of a fragment of Epicurus from Bk 11 of his work On Nature Style EditThe fragment is composed of 42 iambic trimeters The topic concerns the mythical figure of Sisyphus Style plays an important function in the authorship question if we take it as expressing the view of the sophist Critias the cynical deconstruction of religion would appear to harmonize perfectly with the character of that historical person that brilliant but sinister figure in the politics and letters of the end of the fifth century 21 who gained a reputation for ruthless unscrupulousness But were it to pertain to the genre of the satyr play then we would not expect a straightforward exposition of a theory but rather a parody of it a tone lacking in the surviving fragment 22 Interpretations EditW K C Guthrie stated that the Sisyphus fragment is the first occurrence in history of the theory of religion as a political invention to ensure good behaviour an approach which was subsequently adopted by the Hellenistic historian Polybius in his 40 volume history of Rome s emergence as an empire 23 Karl Popper in his The Open Society and its Enemies noted a striking similarity between the passage ascribed to Critias and the views Plato Critias s nephew developed in his two dialogues the Republic and the Laws regarding the Noble lie 24 Notes Edit Greek text ἦn xronos ὅt ἦn ἄtaktos ἀn8rwpwn bios kaὶ 8hriwdhs ἰsxyos 8 ὑphreths ὅt oὐdὲn ἆ8lon oὔte toῖs ἐs8loῖsin ἦn oὔt aὖ kolasma toῖs kakoῖs ἐgigneto kἄpeita moi dokoῦsin ἅn8rwpoi nomoys 5 8es8ai kolastas ἵna dikh tyrannos ᾖ lt x ᴗ x gt thn 8 ὕbrin doylhn ἔxῃ ἐzhmioῦto d eἴ tis ἐ3amartanoi ἔpeit ἐpeidὴ tἀmfanῆ mὲn oἱ nomoi ἀpeῖrgon aὐtoὺs ἔrga mὴ prassein biᾳ 10 la8rᾳ d ἔprasson thnikaῦta moi dokeῖ lt prῶton gt pyknos tis kaὶ sofὸs gnwmhn ἀnhr lt 8eῶn gt deos 8nhtoῖsin ἐ3eyreῖn ὅpws eἴh ti deῖma toῖs kakoῖsi kἂn la8rᾳ prasswsin ἢ legwsin ἢ fronῶsi lt ti gt 15 ἐnteῦ8en oὖn tὸ 8eῖon eἰshghsato ὡs ἔsti daimwn ἀf8itῳ 8allwn biῳ noῳ t ἀkoywn kaὶ blepwn fronῶn te kaὶ prosexwn te taῦta kaὶ fysin 8eian forῶn ὃs pᾶn mὲn tὸ lex8ὲn ἐn brotoῖs ἀkoy lt s gt etai 20 lt tὸ gt drwmenon dὲ pᾶn ἰdeῖn dynhsetai ἐὰn dὲ sὺn sigῇ ti boyleyῃs kakon toῦt oὐxὶ lhsei toὺs 8eoys tὸ gὰr fronoῦn ἔnesti t lt oisyt gt oys de toὺs logoys legwn didagmatwn ἥdiston eἰshghsato 25 pseydeῖ kalypsas tὴn ἀlh8eian logῳ lt n gt aiei lt n gt d ἔfaske toὺs 8eoὺs ἐntaῦ8 ἵna malist ἂ lt n gt 1 ἐ3eplh3en ἀn8rwpoys ἄgwn ὅ8en per ἔgnw toὺs foboys ὄntas brotoῖs kaὶ tὰs ὀnhseis tῷ talaipwrῳ biῳ 30 ἐk tῆs ὕper8e periforᾶs ἵn ἀstrapas kateῖdon oὔsas deinὰ dὲ ktyphmata brontῆs to t ἀsterwpὸn oὐranoῦ demas Xronoy kalὸn poikilma tektonos sofoῦ ὅ8en te lamprὸs ἀsteros steixei mydros 35 ὅ 8 ὑgrὸs eἰs gῆn ὄmbros ἐkporeyetai toioys peri3 ἔsthsen ἀn8rwpois foboys di oὓs kalῶs te tῷ logῳ katῴkisen tὸn daimon oὗtos ἐn preponti xwriῳ tὴn ἀnomian te toῖs nomois katesbesen 40 3 oὕtw dὲ prῶton oἴomai peῖsai tina 8nhtoὺs nomizein daimonwn eἶnai genos 4 Apropos Dihle s proposal he writes that Dihle overlooks the testimony of Epicurus 27 2 8 13 Citations Edit Kahn 1997 p 259 Sextus Empiricus Against the Physicists Book 1 Section 24 Davies 1989 pp 16 17 EF 2009 pp 670 678 Davies 1989 p 18 Kahn 1997 pp 247 248 Guthrie 1969 pp 243 244 Bury 1936 pp 31 32 a b c Bremmer 2006 p 16 a b Kahn 1997 p 249 Dihle 1977 pp 28 30 Kahn 1997 p 249 and n 5 Burkert 1985 p 467 n 22 Davies 1989 p 24 28 Whitmarsh 2014 p 112 113 Cropp 2020 Davies 1989 p 17 Wilamowitz Moellendorff 1875 pp 161 166 Davies 1989 p 24 Dihle 1977 p 31 Lovejoy amp Boas 1935 p 211 Bremmer 2006 p 8 Guthrie 1969 p 244 Popper 1966 pp 142 143 Sources EditBremmer Jan N 2006 Atheism in Antiquity In Martin Michael ed The Cambridge Companion to Atheism Cambridge University Press pp 11 26 ISBN 978 1 139 00118 2 Burkert Walter 1985 Greek Religion Archaic and Classical Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 36281 9 Collard Christopher Cropp Martin eds 2009 Euripides Fragments Oedipus Chrysippus Other Fragments Loeb Classical Library Vol 506 Harvard University Press pp 670 678 Cropp Martin 2020 Lamari A Montanari F eds Fragmentation in Ancient Greek Drama De Gruyter pp 235 256 Davies Malcolm 1989 Sisyphus and the invention of religion Critias TrGF 1 43 F 19 B 25 DK Bulletin of the Institute of Classical Studies 36 36 16 32 doi 10 1111 j 2041 5370 1989 tb00560 x JSTOR 43693889 Dihle Albrecht 1977 Das Satyrspiel Sisyphos Hermes 105 1 28 42 JSTOR 4475993 Guthrie W K C 1969 A History of Greek Philosophy Vol 3 Cambridge University Press Kahn Charles H 1997 Greek Religion and Philosophy in the Sisyphus Fragment Phronesis 42 3 247 262 doi 10 1163 15685289760518153 JSTOR 4182561 Lovejoy Arthur Oncken Boas George 1935 Primitivism and Related Ideas in Antiquity Vol 1 2nd ed Octagon Books Miller James F Woodruff Paul B 2000 Introduction In Miller James F Woodruff Paul B eds Reason and Religion in Socratic Philosophy Oxford University Press pp 3 11 ISBN 978 0 195 13322 6 Popper Karl 1966 First published 1945 The Open Society and Its Enemies The Spell of Plato Vol 1 5th ed Routledge Sextus Empiricus 1936 Bury R G ed Sextus Empiricus Vol 3 Harvard University Press William Heinemann Whitmarsh Tim 2014 Atheistic Aesthetics The Sisyphus Fragment Poetics and the Creativity of Drama Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society 60 109 126 Wilamowitz Moellendorff Ulrich von 1875 Analecta Euripidea Borntraeger External links EditAn English translation of the Sisyphus fragment Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Sisyphus fragment amp oldid 1090556323, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.