fbpx
Wikipedia

Proof (truth)

A proof is sufficient evidence or a sufficient argument for the truth of a proposition.[1][2][3][4]

The concept applies in a variety of disciplines,[5] with both the nature of the evidence or justification and the criteria for sufficiency being area-dependent. In the area of oral and written communication such as conversation, dialog, rhetoric, etc., a proof is a persuasive perlocutionary speech act, which demonstrates the truth of a proposition.[6] In any area of mathematics defined by its assumptions or axioms, a proof is an argument establishing a theorem of that area via accepted rules of inference starting from those axioms and from other previously established theorems.[7] The subject of logic, in particular proof theory, formalizes and studies the notion of formal proof.[8] In some areas of epistemology and theology, the notion of justification plays approximately the role of proof,[9] while in jurisprudence the corresponding term is evidence,[10] with "burden of proof" as a concept common to both philosophy and law.

In most disciplines, evidence is required to prove something. Evidence is drawn from the experience of the world around us, with science obtaining its evidence from nature,[11] law obtaining its evidence from witnesses and forensic investigation,[12] and so on. A notable exception is mathematics, whose proofs are drawn from a mathematical world begun with axioms and further developed and enriched by theorems proved earlier.

Exactly what evidence is sufficient to prove something is also strongly area-dependent, usually with no absolute threshold of sufficiency at which evidence becomes proof.[13][14][15] In law, the same evidence that may convince one jury may not persuade another. Formal proof provides the main exception, where the criteria for proofhood are ironclad and it is impermissible to defend any step in the reasoning as "obvious" (except for the necessary ability of the one proving and the one being proven to, to correctly identify any symbol used in the proof.);[16] for a well-formed formula to qualify as part of a formal proof, it must be the result of applying a rule of the deductive apparatus of some formal system to the previous well-formed formulae in the proof sequence.[17]

Proofs have been presented since antiquity. Aristotle used the observation that patterns of nature never display the machine-like uniformity of determinism as proof that chance is an inherent part of nature.[18] On the other hand, Thomas Aquinas used the observation of the existence of rich patterns in nature as proof that nature is not ruled by chance.[19]

Proofs need not be verbal. Before Copernicus, people took the apparent motion of the Sun across the sky as proof that the Sun went round the Earth.[20] Suitably incriminating evidence left at the scene of a crime may serve as proof of the identity of the perpetrator. Conversely, a verbal entity need not assert a proposition to constitute a proof of that proposition. For example, a signature constitutes direct proof of authorship; less directly, handwriting analysis may be submitted as proof of authorship of a document.[21] Privileged information in a document can serve as proof that the document's author had access to that information; such access might in turn establish the location of the author at certain time, which might then provide the author with an alibi.

Proof vs evidence

18th-century Scottish philosopher David Hume built on Aristotle's separation of belief from knowledge,[22] recognizing that one can be said to "know" something only if one has firsthand experience with it, in a strict sense proof, while one can infer that something is true and therefore "believe" it without knowing, via evidence or supposition. This speaks to one way of separating proof from evidence:

If one cannot find their chocolate bar, and sees chocolate on their napping roommate's face, this evidence can cause one to believe their roommate ate the chocolate bar. But they do not know their roommate ate it. It may turn out that the roommate put the candy away when straightening up, but was thus inspired to go eat their own chocolate. Only if one directly experiences proof of the roommate eating it, perhaps by walking in on them doing so, does one know the roommate did it.

In an absolute sense, one can be argued not to "know" anything, except for the existence of one's own thoughts, as 17th-century philosopher John Locke pointed out.[23] Even earlier, Descartes addressed when saying cogito, ergo sum (I think, therefore I am). While Descartes was attempting to "prove" logically that the world exists, his legacy in doing so is to have shown that one cannot have such proof, because all of one's perceptions could be false (such as under the evil demon or simulated reality hypotheses). But one at least has proof of one's own thoughts existing, and strong evidence that the world exists, enough to be considered "proof" by practical standards, though always indirect and impossible to objectively confirm.

See also

References

  1. ^ Proof and other dilemmas: mathematics and philosophy by Bonnie Gold, Roger A. Simons 2008 ISBN 0883855674 pages 12–20
  2. ^ Philosophical Papers, Volume 2 by Imre Lakatos, John Worrall, Gregory Currie, ISBN Philosophical Papers, Volume 2 by Imre Lakatos, John Worrall, Gregory Currie 1980 ISBN 0521280303 pages 60–63
  3. ^ Evidence, proof, and facts: a book of sources by Peter Murphy 2003 ISBN 0199261954 pages 1–2
  4. ^ Logic in Theology – And Other Essays by Isaac Taylor 2010 ISBN 1445530139 pages 5–15
  5. ^ Compare 1 Thessalonians 5:21: "Prove all things [...]."
  6. ^ John Langshaw Austin: How to Do Things With Words. Cambridge (Mass.) 1962 – Paperback: Harvard University Press, 2nd edition, 2005, ISBN 0-674-41152-8.
  7. ^ Cupillari, Antonella. The Nuts and Bolts of Proofs. Academic Press, 2001. Page 3.
  8. ^ Alfred Tarski, Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences (ed. Jan Tarski). 4th Edition. Oxford Logic Guides, No. 24. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994, xxiv + 229 pp. ISBN 0-19-504472-X
  9. ^ "Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2018.
  10. ^ "Definition of proof | Dictionary.com". www.dictionary.com.
  11. ^ Reference Manual on Scientific Evidence, 2nd Ed. (2000), p. 71. Accessed May 13, 2007.
  12. ^ John Henry Wigmore, A Treatise on the System of Evidence in Trials at Common Law, 2nd ed., Little, Brown, and Co., Boston, 1915
  13. ^ Simon, Rita James & Mahan, Linda. (1971). "Quantifying Burdens of Proof—A View from the Bench, the Jury, and the Classroom". Law and Society Review. 5 (3): 319–330. doi:10.2307/3052837. JSTOR 3052837.
  14. ^ Katie Evans; David Osthus; Ryan G. Spurrier. (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2013-03-17. Retrieved 2007-01-14.
  15. ^ The Principle of Sufficient Reason: A Reassessment by Alexander R. Pruss
  16. ^ A. S. Troelstra, H. Schwichtenberg (1996). Basic Proof Theory. In series Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0-521-77911-1.
  17. ^ Hunter, Geoffrey, Metalogic: An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First-Order Logic, University of California Press, 1971
  18. ^ Aristotle's Physics: a Guided Study, Joe Sachs, 1995 ISBN 0813521920 p. 70
  19. ^ The treatise on the divine nature: Summa theologiae I, 1–13, by Saint Thomas Aquinas, Brian J. Shanley, 2006 ISBN 0872208052 p. 198
  20. ^ Thomas S. Kuhn, The Copernican Revolution, pp. 5–20
  21. ^ Trial tactics by Stephen A. Saltzburg, 2007 ISBN 159031767X page 47
  22. ^ David Hume
  23. ^ Locke: Knowledge of the External World

proof, truth, other, uses, proof, proof, sufficient, evidence, sufficient, argument, truth, proposition, concept, applies, variety, disciplines, with, both, nature, evidence, justification, criteria, sufficiency, being, area, dependent, area, oral, written, co. For other uses see Proof A proof is sufficient evidence or a sufficient argument for the truth of a proposition 1 2 3 4 The concept applies in a variety of disciplines 5 with both the nature of the evidence or justification and the criteria for sufficiency being area dependent In the area of oral and written communication such as conversation dialog rhetoric etc a proof is a persuasive perlocutionary speech act which demonstrates the truth of a proposition 6 In any area of mathematics defined by its assumptions or axioms a proof is an argument establishing a theorem of that area via accepted rules of inference starting from those axioms and from other previously established theorems 7 The subject of logic in particular proof theory formalizes and studies the notion of formal proof 8 In some areas of epistemology and theology the notion of justification plays approximately the role of proof 9 while in jurisprudence the corresponding term is evidence 10 with burden of proof as a concept common to both philosophy and law In most disciplines evidence is required to prove something Evidence is drawn from the experience of the world around us with science obtaining its evidence from nature 11 law obtaining its evidence from witnesses and forensic investigation 12 and so on A notable exception is mathematics whose proofs are drawn from a mathematical world begun with axioms and further developed and enriched by theorems proved earlier Exactly what evidence is sufficient to prove something is also strongly area dependent usually with no absolute threshold of sufficiency at which evidence becomes proof 13 14 15 In law the same evidence that may convince one jury may not persuade another Formal proof provides the main exception where the criteria for proofhood are ironclad and it is impermissible to defend any step in the reasoning as obvious except for the necessary ability of the one proving and the one being proven to to correctly identify any symbol used in the proof 16 for a well formed formula to qualify as part of a formal proof it must be the result of applying a rule of the deductive apparatus of some formal system to the previous well formed formulae in the proof sequence 17 Proofs have been presented since antiquity Aristotle used the observation that patterns of nature never display the machine like uniformity of determinism as proof that chance is an inherent part of nature 18 On the other hand Thomas Aquinas used the observation of the existence of rich patterns in nature as proof that nature is not ruled by chance 19 Proofs need not be verbal Before Copernicus people took the apparent motion of the Sun across the sky as proof that the Sun went round the Earth 20 Suitably incriminating evidence left at the scene of a crime may serve as proof of the identity of the perpetrator Conversely a verbal entity need not assert a proposition to constitute a proof of that proposition For example a signature constitutes direct proof of authorship less directly handwriting analysis may be submitted as proof of authorship of a document 21 Privileged information in a document can serve as proof that the document s author had access to that information such access might in turn establish the location of the author at certain time which might then provide the author with an alibi Proof vs evidence Edit18th century Scottish philosopher David Hume built on Aristotle s separation of belief from knowledge 22 recognizing that one can be said to know something only if one has firsthand experience with it in a strict sense proof while one can infer that something is true and therefore believe it without knowing via evidence or supposition This speaks to one way of separating proof from evidence If one cannot find their chocolate bar and sees chocolate on their napping roommate s face this evidence can cause one to believe their roommate ate the chocolate bar But they do not know their roommate ate it It may turn out that the roommate put the candy away when straightening up but was thus inspired to go eat their own chocolate Only if one directly experiences proof of the roommate eating it perhaps by walking in on them doing so does one know the roommate did it In an absolute sense one can be argued not to know anything except for the existence of one s own thoughts as 17th century philosopher John Locke pointed out 23 Even earlier Descartes addressed when saying cogito ergo sum I think therefore I am While Descartes was attempting to prove logically that the world exists his legacy in doing so is to have shown that one cannot have such proof because all of one s perceptions could be false such as under the evil demon or simulated reality hypotheses But one at least has proof of one s own thoughts existing and strong evidence that the world exists enough to be considered proof by practical standards though always indirect and impossible to objectively confirm See also Edit Wikiquote has quotations related to Proof Mathematical proof Proof theory Proof of concept Provability logic Evidence information which tends to determine or demonstrate the truth of a proposition Proof procedure Proof complexity Standard of proofReferences Edit Proof and other dilemmas mathematics and philosophy by Bonnie Gold Roger A Simons 2008 ISBN 0883855674 pages 12 20 Philosophical Papers Volume 2 by Imre Lakatos John Worrall Gregory Currie ISBN Philosophical Papers Volume 2 by Imre Lakatos John Worrall Gregory Currie 1980 ISBN 0521280303 pages 60 63 Evidence proof and facts a book of sources by Peter Murphy 2003 ISBN 0199261954 pages 1 2 Logic in Theology And Other Essays by Isaac Taylor 2010 ISBN 1445530139 pages 5 15 Compare 1 Thessalonians 5 21 Prove all things John Langshaw Austin How to Do Things With Words Cambridge Mass 1962 Paperback Harvard University Press 2nd edition 2005 ISBN 0 674 41152 8 Cupillari Antonella The Nuts and Bolts of Proofs Academic Press 2001 Page 3 Alfred Tarski Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences ed Jan Tarski 4th Edition Oxford Logic Guides No 24 New York and Oxford Oxford University Press 1994 xxiv 229 pp ISBN 0 19 504472 X Foundationalist Theories of Epistemic Justification The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2018 Definition of proof Dictionary com www dictionary com Reference Manual on Scientific Evidence 2nd Ed 2000 p 71 Accessed May 13 2007 John Henry Wigmore A Treatise on the System of Evidence in Trials at Common Law 2nd ed Little Brown and Co Boston 1915 Simon Rita James amp Mahan Linda 1971 Quantifying Burdens of Proof A View from the Bench the Jury and the Classroom Law and Society Review 5 3 319 330 doi 10 2307 3052837 JSTOR 3052837 Katie Evans David Osthus Ryan G Spurrier Distributions of Interest for Quantifying Reasonable Doubt and Their Applications PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2013 03 17 Retrieved 2007 01 14 The Principle of Sufficient Reason A Reassessment by Alexander R Pruss A S Troelstra H Schwichtenberg 1996 Basic Proof Theory In series Cambridge Tracts in Theoretical Computer Science Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 77911 1 Hunter Geoffrey Metalogic An Introduction to the Metatheory of Standard First Order Logic University of California Press 1971 Aristotle s Physics a Guided Study Joe Sachs 1995 ISBN 0813521920 p 70 The treatise on the divine nature Summa theologiae I 1 13 by Saint Thomas Aquinas Brian J Shanley 2006 ISBN 0872208052 p 198 Thomas S Kuhn The Copernican Revolution pp 5 20 Trial tactics by Stephen A Saltzburg 2007 ISBN 159031767X page 47 David Hume Locke Knowledge of the External World Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Proof truth amp oldid 1118569915, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.