fbpx
Wikipedia

Philosophical aspects of the abortion debate

The philosophical aspects of the abortion debate are logical arguments that can be made either in support of or in opposition to abortion.

Overview edit

The philosophical arguments in the abortion debate are deontological or rights-based. The view that all or almost all abortion should be illegal generally rests on the claims: (1) that the existence and moral right to life of human beings (human organisms) begins at or near conception-fertilization; (2) that induced abortion is the deliberate and unjust killing of the embryo in violation of its right to life; and (3) that the law should prohibit unjust violations of the right to life. The view that abortion should in most or all circumstances be legal generally rests on the claims: (1) that women have a right to control what happens in and to their own bodies; (2) that abortion is a just exercise of this right; and (3) that the law should not criminalize just exercises of the right to control one's own body and its life-support functions.

Although both sides are likely to see the rights-based considerations as paramount, some popular arguments appeal to consequentialist or utilitarian considerations. For example, anti-abortion groups (see the list below) sometimes claim the existence of post-abortion syndrome or a link between abortion and breast cancer, alleged medical and psychological risks of abortion. On the other side, pro-choice groups (see the list below) say that criminalizing abortion will lead to the deaths of many women through "back-alley abortions"; that unwanted children have a negative social impact (or conversely that abortion lowers the crime rate); and that reproductive rights are necessary to achieve the full and equal participation of women in society and the workforce. Consequentialist arguments on both sides tend to be vigorously disputed, though are not widely discussed in the philosophical literature.

Philosophical argumentation on the moral issue edit

Contemporary philosophical literature contains two kinds of arguments concerning the morality of abortion. One family of arguments (see the following three sections) relates to the moral status of the embryo—whether or not the embryo has a right to life; in other words is the embryo a "person" in a moral sense. An affirmative answer would support claim (1) in the central anti-abortion argument, while a negative answer would support claim (2) in the central pro-choice argument.

Another family of arguments (see the section on Thomson, below) relates to bodily rights—the question of whether the woman's bodily rights justify abortion even if the embryo has a right to life. A negative answer would support claim (2) in the central anti-abortion argument, while an affirmative answer would support claim (2) in the central pro-choice argument.

Arguments based on criteria for personhood edit

Since the zygote is genetically identical to the embryo, the fully formed fetus, and the baby, questioning the beginning of personhood could lead to an instance of the sorites paradox, also known as the paradox of the heap.[1]

Mary Anne Warren, in her article arguing for the permissibility of abortion,[2] holds that moral opposition to abortion is based on the following argument:

  1. It is wrong to kill innocent human beings.
  2. The embryo is an innocent human being.
  3. Hence it is wrong to kill the embryo.

Warren, however, thinks that "human being" is used in different senses in (1) and (2). In (1), "human being" is used in a moral sense to mean a "person", a "full-fledged member of the moral community". In (2), "human being" means "biological human". That the embryo is a biologically human organism or animal is uncontroversial, Warren holds. But it does not follow that the embryo is a person, and it is persons that have rights, such as the right to life.[3]

To help make a distinction between "person" and "biological human", Warren notes that we should respect the lives of highly intelligent aliens, even if they are not biological humans. She thinks there is a cluster of properties that characterize persons:[4]

  1. consciousness (of objects and events external and/or internal to the being), and in particular the capacity to feel pain
  2. reasoning (the developed capacity to solve new and relatively complex problems)
  3. self-motivated activity (activity which is relatively independent of either genetic or direct external control)
  4. the capacity to communicate, by whatever means, messages of an indefinite variety of types, that is, not just with an indefinite number of possible contents, but on indefinitely many possible topics
  5. the presence of self-concepts, and self-awareness, either individual or racial, or both

A person does not have to have each of these, but if something has all five then it definitely is a person whether it is biologically human or not, while if it has none or perhaps only one then it is not a person, again whether it is biologically human or not. The fetus has at most one, consciousness (and this only after it becomes susceptible to pain—the timing of which is disputed), and hence is not a person.[5]

Other writers apply similar criteria, concluding that the embryo lacks a right to life because it lacks self-consciousness,[6] or rationality and self-consciousness,[7][8] or "certain higher psychological capacities" including "autonomy".[9]

Others conclude that personhood should be based on "brain birth" concept, which is in essence the reversal of the brain death used as a modern definition of medical death. Under this proposal, presence of brain waves would be enough to grant personhood, even with other features lacking. Based on whether brain activity in the brain stem, or just in the cerebral cortex, is relevant for personhood, two concepts of "brain birth" emerge:[10]

  • at the first appearance of brain waves in lower brain (brain stem) - 6–8 weeks of gestation (paralleling "whole brain death")
  • at the first appearance of brain waves in higher brain (cerebral cortex) - 19–20 weeks of gestation (paralleling "higher brain death")

These writers disagree on precisely which features confer a right to life,[11] but agree those features must be certain developed psychological or physiological features which the embryo lacks.

Warren's arguments face two main objections. The comatose patient objection claims that as patients in a reversible coma do not satisfy Warren's (or some other) criteria—they are not conscious, do not communicate, and so on—therefore they would lack a right to life on her view.[12] One response is that "although the reversibly comatose lack any conscious mental states, they do retain all their unconscious [or dispositional] mental states, since the appropriate neurological configurations are preserved in the brain."[13] This may allow them to satisfy some of Warren's criteria. The comatose also still possess brain activity (brain waves), so this objection does not apply to "brain birth" theories. Finally, there are some post-natal humans who are unable to feel pain due to genetic disorders and thus do not satisfy all of Warren's criteria.[14]

The infanticide objection points out that infants (indeed up to about one year of age, since it is only around then that they begin to outstrip the abilities of non-human animals) have only one of Warren's characteristics—consciousness—and hence would have to be accounted non-persons on her view; thus her view would permit not only abortion but infanticide. Warren agrees that infants are non-persons (and so killing them is not strictly murder), but denies that infanticide is generally permissible.[15] For, Warren claims, once a human being is born, there is no longer a conflict between it and the woman's rights, since the human being can be given up for adoption. Killing such a human being would be wrong, not because it is a person, but because it would go against the desires of people willing to adopt the infant and to pay to keep the infant alive. Although, this clarification has critics of its own: beef cattle, chickens, or any other livestock raised for meat—or indeed even some plants—have supporters who would pay to keep them alive. However, a response to these supports might be that, while livestock, plants, and infants are all not morally persons, the infant is the only life that can be designated a human being. Thus, Warren's argument does suggest an inherent value for the life of human beings that are not persons over lives that do not have the potential for becoming a person.

Nonetheless, Warren grants that her argument entails that infanticide would be morally acceptable under some circumstances, such as those of a desert island. Philosopher Peter Singer similarly concludes that infanticide, particularly of severely disabled infants, is justifiable under certain conditions.[16] And Jeff McMahan grants that under very limited circumstances it may be permissible to kill one infant to save the lives of several others.[17] Opponents may see these concessions as a reductio ad absurdum of these writers' views; while supporters may see them merely as examples of unpleasant acts being justified in unusual cases.

Since brain waves appear in the lower brain (brain stem) in 6–8 weeks of gestation, and in the higher brain (cerebral cortex) in 19–20 weeks of gestation, both "whole brain" and "higher brain" brain birth personhood concepts based on the presence of brain waves do not permit infanticide.[10]

The natural capacities view edit

Some opponents of Warren's view believe that what matters morally is not that one be actually exhibiting complex mental qualities of the sort she identifies, but rather that one have in oneself a self-directed genetic propensity or natural capacity to develop such qualities. In other words, what is crucial is that one be the kind of entity or substance that, under the right conditions, actively develops itself to the point of exhibiting Warren's qualities at some point in its life, even if it does not actually exhibit them because of not having developed them yet (embryo, infant) or having lost them (severe Alzheimer's). Because human beings do have this natural capacity—and indeed have it essentially—therefore (on this view) they essentially have a right to life: they could not possibly fail to have a right to life.[18] Further, since modern embryology shows that the embryo begins to exist at conception and has a natural capacity for complex mental qualities, therefore the right to life begins at conception.

Grounding the right to life in essential natural capacities rather than accidental developed capacities is said to have several advantages.[19] As developed capacities are on a continuum, admitting of greater and lesser degrees—some, for example, are more rational and self-conscious than others—therefore: (1) the "developed capacities" view must arbitrarily select some particular degree of development as the cut-off point for the right to life—whereas the "natural capacities" view is non-arbitrary; (2) those whose capacities are more developed would have more of a right to life on the "developed capacities" view—whereas the "natural capacities" view entails we all have an equal right to life; and (3) the continuum of developed capacities makes the exact point at which personhood ensues vague, and human beings around that point, say between one and two years of age, will have a shadowy or indeterminate moral status—whereas there is no such indeterminacy on the "natural capacities" view.[20]

Some defenders of Warren-style arguments grant that these problems have not yet been fully solved,[21] but reply that the "natural capacities" view fares no better. It is argued, for example, that as human beings vary significantly in their natural cognitive capacities (some are naturally more intelligent than others), and as one can imagine a series or spectrum of species with gradually diminishing natural capacities (for example, a series from humans down to amoebae with only the slightest differences in natural capacities between each successive species), therefore the problems of arbitrariness and inequality will apply equally to the "natural capacities" view.[22] In other words, there is a continuum not only of developed but of natural capacities, and so the "natural capacities" view will inevitably face these problems as well.

Some critics reject the "natural capacities" view on the basis that it takes mere species membership or genetic potential as a basis for respect (in essence a charge of speciesism),[23] or because it entails that anencephalic infants and the irreversibly comatose have a full right to life.[24] Moreover, as with Marquis's argument (see below), some theories of personal identity would support the view that the embryo will never itself develop complex mental qualities (rather, it will simply give rise to a distinct substance or entity that will have these qualities), in which case the "natural capacities" argument would fail. Respondents to this criticism argue that the noted human cases in fact would not be classified as persons as they do not have a natural capacity to develop any psychological features.[25][26][27]

The deprivation argument edit

A seminal essay by Don Marquis argues that abortion is wrong because it deprives the embryo of a valuable future.[28] Marquis begins by arguing that what makes it wrong to kill a normal adult human being is the fact that the killing inflicts a terrible harm on the victim. The harm consists in the fact that "when I die, I am deprived of all of the value of my future":[29] I am deprived of all the valuable "experiences, activities, projects, and enjoyments" that I would otherwise have had.[30] Thus, if a being has a highly valuable future ahead of it—a "future like ours"—then killing that being would be seriously harmful and hence seriously wrong.[31] But then, as a standard embryo does have a highly valuable future, killing it is seriously wrong.[32] And so "the overwhelming majority of deliberate abortions are seriously immoral", "in the same moral category as killing an innocent adult human being".[33]

A consequence of this argument is that abortion is wrong in all the cases where killing a child or adult with the same sort of future as the embryo would be wrong. So for example, if involuntary euthanasia of patients with a future filled with intense physical pain is morally acceptable, aborting embryos whose future is filled with intense physical pain will also be morally acceptable. But it would not do, for example, to invoke the fact that some embryo's future would involve such things as being raised by an unloving family, since we do not take it to be acceptable to kill a five-year-old just because her future involves being raised by an unloving family. Similarly, killing a child or adult may be permissible in exceptional circumstances such as self-defense or (perhaps) capital punishment; but these are irrelevant to standard abortions.

Marquis's argument has prompted several objections. The contraception objection claims that if Marquis's argument is correct, then, since sperm and ova (or perhaps a sperm and ovum jointly) have a future like ours, contraception would be as wrong as murder; but as this conclusion is (it is said) absurd—even those who believe contraception is wrong do not believe it is as wrong as murder—the argument must be unsound. One response[34] is that neither the sperm, nor the egg, nor any particular sperm-egg combination, will ever itself live out a valuable future: what will later have valuable experiences, activities, projects, and enjoyments is a new entity, a new organism, that will come into existence at or near conception; and it is this entity, not the sperm or egg or any sperm-egg combination, that has a future like ours.

As this response makes clear, Marquis's argument requires that what will later have valuable experiences and activities is the same entity, the same biological organism, as the embryo.[35] The identity objection rejects this assumption. On certain theories of personal identity (generally motivated by thought experiments involving brain or cerebrum transplants), each of us is not a biological organism but rather an embodied mind or a person (in John Locke's sense) that comes into existence when the brain gives rise to certain developed psychological capacities.[36] If either of these views is correct, Marquis's argument will fail; for the embryo (even the early fetus, lacking the relevant psychological capacities) would not itself have a future of value, but would merely have the potential to give rise to a different entity, an embodied mind or a person, that would have a future of value. The success of Marquis's argument thus depends on one's favored account of personal identity.

The interests objection claims that what makes murder wrong is not just the deprivation of a valuable future, but the deprivation of a future that one has an interest in. The embryo has no conscious interest in its future, and so (the objection concludes) to kill it is not wrong. The defender of Marquis-style arguments may, however, give the counterexample of the suicidal teenager who takes no interest in their future, but killing whom is nonetheless wrong and murder.[37] If the opponent responds that one can have an interest in one's future without taking an interest in it, then the defender of the Marquis-style argument can claim that this applies to the embryo.[38] Similarly, if an opponent claims that what is crucial is having a valuable future which one would, under ideal conditions, desire to preserve (whether or not one does in fact desire to preserve it),[39] then the defender may ask why the embryo would not, under ideal conditions, desire to preserve its future.

The equality objection claims that Marquis's argument leads to unacceptable inequalities.[40] If, as Marquis claims, killing is wrong because it deprives the victim of a valuable future, then, since some futures appear to contain much more value than others—a 9-year-old has a much longer future than a 90-year-old, a middle class person's future has much less gratuitous pain and suffering than someone in extreme poverty—some killings would turn out to be much more wrong than others. But as this is strongly counterintuitive (most people believe all killings are equally wrong, other things being equal), Marquis's argument must be mistaken. Some writers have concluded that the wrongness of killing arises not from the harm it causes the victim (since this varies greatly among killings), but from the killing's violation of the intrinsic worth or personhood of the victim.[41] However, such accounts may themselves face problems of equality,[42] and so the equality objection may not be decisive against Marquis's argument.

The psychological connectedness objection claims that a being can be seriously harmed by being deprived of a valuable future only if there are sufficient psychological connections—sufficient correlations or continuations of memory, belief, desire and the like—between the being as it is now and the being as it will be when it lives out the valuable future.[43] As there are few psychological connections between the embryo and its later self, it is concluded that depriving it of its future does not seriously harm it (and hence is not seriously wrong). A defense of this objection is likely to rest, as with certain views of personal identity, on thought experiments involving brain or cerebrum swaps; and this may render it implausible to some readers.

The bodily rights argument edit

In her well-known article "A Defense of Abortion",[44] Judith Jarvis Thomson argues that abortion is in some circumstances permissible even if the embryo is a person and has a right to life, because the embryo's right to life is overtrumped by the woman's right to control her body and its life-support functions; in short, Thomson's argument is that the right to life does not include or entail the right to use someone else's body. Her central argument involves a thought experiment. Thomson asks us to imagine that an individual (call Bob) wakes up in bed next to a famous violinist. He is unconscious with a fatal kidney ailment; and because only Bob happens to have the right blood type to help, the Society of Music Lovers has kidnapped Bob and plugged his circulatory system into the violinist's so that Bob's kidneys can filter poisons from his blood as well as his own. If the violinist is disconnected from Bob now, he will die; but in nine months he will recover and can be safely disconnected. Thomson takes it that one may permissibly unplug oneself from the violinist even though this will kill him. The right to life, Thomson says, does not entail the right to use another person's body, and so in disconnecting the violinist one does not violate his right to life but merely deprives him of something—the use of another person's body—to which he has no right. Similarly, even if the fetus has a right to life, it does not have a right to use the pregnant woman's body and life-support functions against her will; and so aborting the pregnancy is permissible in at least some circumstances. However, Thomson notes that the woman's right to abortion does not include the right to directly insist upon the death of the child, should the fetus happen to be viable, that is, capable of surviving outside the womb.[45]

Critics of this argument generally agree that unplugging the violinist is permissible, but claim there are morally relevant disanalogies between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion. The most common objection is that the violinist scenario, involving a kidnapping, is analogous only to abortion after rape. In most cases of abortion, the pregnant woman was not raped but had intercourse voluntarily, and thus has either tacitly consented to allowing the embryo to use her body (the tacit consent objection[46]), or else has a duty to sustain the embryo because the woman herself caused it to stand in need of her body (the responsibility objection[47]). Other common objections turn on the claim that the embryo is the pregnant woman's child whereas the violinist is a stranger (the stranger versus offspring objection[48]); that abortion kills the embryo whereas unplugging the violinist merely lets him die (the killing versus letting die objection[48]); or, similarly, that abortion intentionally causes the embryo's death whereas unplugging the violinist merely causes death as a foreseen but unintended side-effect (the intending versus foreseeing objection;[49] cf the doctrine of double effect).

Defenders of Thomson's argument—most notably David Boonin[50]—reply that the alleged disanalogies between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion do not hold, either because the factors that critics appeal to are not genuinely morally relevant, or because those factors are morally relevant but do not apply to abortion in the way that critics have claimed. Critics have in turn responded to Boonin's arguments.[51]

Alternative scenarios have been put forth as more accurate and realistic representations of the moral issues present in abortion. John Noonan proposes the scenario of a family who was found to be liable for frostbite finger loss suffered by a dinner guest whom they refused to allow to stay overnight, although it was very cold outside and the guest showed signs of being sick. It is argued that just as it would not be permissible to refuse temporary accommodation for the guest to protect them from physical harm, it would not be permissible to refuse temporary accommodation of a fetus.[52]

Other critics claim that there is a difference between artificial and extraordinary means of preservation, such as medical treatment, kidney dialysis, and blood transfusions, and normal and natural means of preservation, such as gestation, childbirth, and breastfeeding. They argue that if a baby was born into an environment in which there was no replacement available for her mother's breast milk, and the baby would either breastfeed or starve, the mother would have to allow the baby to breastfeed. But the mother would never have to give the baby a blood transfusion, no matter what the circumstances were. The difference between breastfeeding in that scenario and blood transfusions is the difference between gestation and childbirth on the one hand, and using one's body as a kidney dialysis machine on the other.[53][54][55][56][57][58][59]

Respect for human life edit

One argument against the right to abortion appeals to the (secular) value of a human life. The thought is that all forms of human life, including the fetus, are inherently valuable because they are connected to our thoughts on family and parenthood, among other natural aspects of humanity. Thus, abortion can express the wrong attitudes towards humanity in a way that manifest vicious character. This view is represented by some forms of Humanism and by moral philosopher Rosalind Hursthouse in her widely anthologized article "Virtue Theory and Abortion".[60] Thinking about abortion in this way, according to Hursthouse, shows the unimportance of rights because one can act viciously in exercising a moral right. For example, she says, "Love and friendship do not survive their parties' constantly insisting on their rights, nor do people live well when they think that getting what they have a right to is of preeminent importance; they harm others, and they harm themselves."[60] Hursthouse argues that the ending of a human life is always a serious matter and that abortion, when it is wrong, is wrong because it violates a respect for human life.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Kerckhove, Lee F; Waller, Sara (1998). "Fetal personhood and the sorites paradox". The Journal of Value Inquiry. 32 (2): 175–189. doi:10.1023/a:1004375726894. PMID 15295850. S2CID 37563125.
  2. ^ Warren 1973.
  3. ^ Warren 1973, p. 457. The same point is made in Tooley 1972, pp. 40–43; Singer 2000, pp. 126–28, 155–156; Pojman 1994, p. 280; and elsewhere. "person" can also be used in two senses. In John Locke's sense (often employed in discussions of personal identity), "person" is a descriptive term that tells us about a being's psychological properties. In Warren's sense, "person" is a moral or evaluative term that tells us about a being's moral properties. Warren and others hold, however, that being a person in the moral sense actually requires being a person in the psychological sense.
  4. ^ Warren 1973, p. 458. Glover 1977, p. 127 and English 1975, pp. 316–317 also refer to a "cluster" of properties as constituting personhood.
  5. ^ Warren 1973, pp. 458–459.
  6. ^ Michael Tooley argues that the bearer of a right to life must conceive of itself "as a continuing subject of experiences and other mental states" (Tooley 1972, p. 44), or must at some time possess "the concept of a continuing self or mental substance" (Tooley 1984, p. 218).
  7. ^ Singer 2000, pp. 128, 156–157.
  8. ^ Pojman 1994, pp. 281–2.
  9. ^ McMahan 2002, p. 260.
  10. ^ a b Jones, D. Gareth (1998). "The Problematic Symmetry between Brain Birth and Brain Death". Journal of Medical Ethics. 24 (4): 237–42. doi:10.1136/jme.24.4.237. JSTOR 27718134. PMC 1377672. PMID 9752625.
  11. ^ On the pro-life side (see below), it is similarly unclear which features one must have a natural capacity for, in order to have a right to life (cf Schwarz 1990, pp. 105–109), or which features constitute a "future like ours".
  12. ^ Marquis 1989, pp. 197; Schwarz 1990, p. 89; Rogers 1992; Beckwith 1993, p. 108; Larmer 1995, pp. 245–248; Lee & George 2005, p. 263.
  13. ^ Stretton 2004b, p. 267, original emphasis; see Glover 1977, pp. 98–99; Singer 2000, p. 137; Boonin 2003, pp. 64–70.
  14. ^ "Rare disease makes girl unable to feel pain". Associated Press. 2004-11-07 [n.d.] – via Quad City Times.
  15. ^ Warren 1982.
  16. ^ Singer 2000, pp. 186–193.
  17. ^ McMahan 2002, pp. 359–360.
  18. ^ Grisez 1970, pp. 277–287; Lee 1996, 2004; Lee & George 2005, pp. 16–20; Schwarz 1990, pp. 91–93; Beckwith 1993, pp. 108–10; Reichlin 1997, pp. 22–23; and many others. On Marquis's view (see below), by contrast, one could fail to have a right to life—for example by becoming irreversibly comatose, since one's future would then lack valuable experiences and activities.
  19. ^ See Lee 2004, pp. 254–255; Lee & George 2005, pp. 18–19; Schwarz 1990, pp. 108–109.
  20. ^ This third point is discussed in McMahan 2002, pp. 261–265.
  21. ^ McMahan 2002, pp. 261–265; Stretton 2004b, pp. 281–282.
  22. ^ Stretton 2004b, pp. 270–274 (both responses); McMahan 2002, p. 217 (spectrum argument only).
  23. ^ McMahan 2002, pp. 209–217; Stretton 2004b, pp. 275–276.
  24. ^ Stretton 2004b, p. 276 (both points); Boonin 2003, p. 55 (irreversibly comatose only).
  25. ^ Schwarz 1990, p. 52.
  26. ^ Beckwith, Francis J. (Summer 1991). "When Does a Human Become a Person?". Christian Research Journal: 28. Retrieved 2010-02-18.
  27. ^ Sullivan, Dennis M (2003). "The conception view of personhood: a review". Ethics & Medicine. 19 (1). Retrieved 2022-07-04 – via Cedarville University.
  28. ^ Marquis 1989. For a similar argument (published earlier), see Stone 1987; Stone 1994.
  29. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 190.
  30. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 189.
  31. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 190. The type of wrongness appealed to here is presumptive or prima facie wrongness: as noted below, it may be overridden in exceptional circumstances.
  32. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 192.
  33. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 183. Although Marquis views the killing of an embryo or normal human adult as seriously wrong, he avoids any reference to "rights" or the "right to life", and so is apparently not committed to deontological ethics.
  34. ^ Stone 1987, pp. 816–817; cf Marquis 1989, pp. 201–202.
  35. ^ This view, known as "Animalism" (since it takes you and I to be essentially animals rather than Lockean persons or embodied minds or souls), is defended in Olson 1997.
  36. ^ Supporters of the embodied mind view include Tooley 1984, pp. 218–219 (using the term "subject of consciousness"); McMahan 2002, ch 1; and Hasker 1999, ch 7. Supporters of the personhood view include Warren 1978, p. 18; McInerney 1990 (though there is some ambiguity); Doepke 1996, ch 9; and Baker 2000.
  37. ^ Marquis 1989, p. 198.
  38. ^ Cf Stone 1994, 282 n 4.
  39. ^ Boonin 2003, pp. 70–85.
  40. ^ Paske 1994, p. 365; Stretton 2004b, pp. 250–260; see also McMahan 2002, pp. 234–235, 271.
  41. ^ For example, McMahan 2002, pp. 240–265.
  42. ^ McMahan 2002, pp. 247–248.
  43. ^ McInerney 1990; McMahan 2002, p. 271; Stretton 2004a, pp. 171–179.
  44. ^ Thomson 1971.
  45. ^ "All the same, I agree that the desire for the child's death is not one which anybody may gratify, should it turn out to be possible to detach the child alive." In Thomson 1971[page needed].
  46. ^ e.g. Warren 1973; Steinbock 1992, p. 78.
  47. ^ e.g. Beckwith 1993; McMahan 2002.
  48. ^ a b e.g. Schwarz 1990; Beckwith 1993; McMahan 2002.
  49. ^ e.g. Finnis 1973; Schwarz 1990; Lee 1996; Lee & George 2005.
  50. ^ Boonin 2003, ch 4.
  51. ^ e.g. Beckwith 2006.
  52. ^ Noonan 1970.
  53. ^ Poupard, Richard J (2007). (PDF). Christian Research Journal. 30 (4). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2011-07-16. Retrieved 2009-10-25.
  54. ^ Koukl, G; Klusendorf, S (2001). Making Abortion Unthinkable: The Art of Pro-Life Persuasion. California: STR Press. p. 86.
  55. ^ Nathanson, Bernard; Ostling, Richard (1979). Aborting America. Garden City: Doubleday. ISBN 0-385-14461-X.
  56. ^ Peter Kreeft, David Boonin (2005). Is Abortion Morally Justifiable in a Free Society? – Public debate at Yale University (Audio). Intercollegiate Studies Institute.
  57. ^ Arthur, John (1989). The Unfinished Constitution: Philosophy and Constitutional Practice. Wadsworth. pp. 198–200.
  58. ^ Beckwith, Francis (March 1992). (PDF). International Philosophical Quarterly. 32 (1): 105–118. doi:10.5840/ipq199232156. PMID 11656685. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2010-08-16. Retrieved 2009-10-10.
  59. ^ Parks, Brian D. (2006). "The Natural-Artificial Distinction and Conjoined Twins". The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly. 6 (4): 671–680. doi:10.5840/ncbq2006646. ISSN 1532-5490.
  60. ^ a b Hursthouse, Rosalind (1991). "Virtue Theory and Abortion". Philosophy & Public Affairs. 20 (3): 223–246. JSTOR 2265432. PMID 11659356.

References edit

  • Baker, L (2000). Persons and Bodies: A Constitution View. Cambridge University Press.
  • Beckwith, F (1993). Politically Correct Death. Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Books. ch 7.
  • Beckwith, F (April 2006). "Defending Abortion Philosophically". Journal of Medicine & Philosophy. 31: 177–203. doi:10.1080/03605310600588723.
  • Boonin, D (2003). A Defense of Abortion. Cambridge University Press. ch 4.
  • Doepke, F (1996). The Kinds of Things. Chicago: Open Court.
  • English, Jane (1975). "Abortion and the Concept of a Person". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 5 (2): 233–243. doi:10.1080/00455091.1975.10716109. PMID 11663579. S2CID 38354546.
  • Finnis, J (Winter 1973). "The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2 (2): 117–145.
  • Glover, J. (1977). Causing Death and Saving Lives. London: Penguin.
  • Grisez, G. (1970). Abortion: the Myths, the Realities, and the Arguments. New York: Corpus Books.
  • Hasker, W. (1999). The Emergent Self. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
  • Larmer, R (1995). "Abortion, Personhood and the Potential for Consciousness". Journal of Applied Philosophy. 12 (3): 241–251. doi:10.1111/j.1468-5930.1995.tb00136.x.
  • Lee, P (1996). Abortion and Unborn Human Life. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press. ch 4.
  • Lee, P (June 2004). "The Pro-Life Argument from Substantial Identity: A Defense". Bioethics. 18 (3): 249–263. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2004.00393.x. PMID 15341038.
  • Lee, P; George, R (2005). "The Wrong of Abortion". In Cohen, A; Wellman, C (eds.). Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell. pp. 13–26, at 20–21.
  • Mappes, T. A.; DeGrazia, D., eds. (2001). Biomedical Ethics (5 ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill. ISBN 0072303654.
  • Marquis, D (April 1989). "Why Abortion Is Immoral". Journal of Philosophy. 86 (4): 183–202. doi:10.2307/2026961. JSTOR 2026961. PMID 11782094.
  • McInerney, Peter K. (May 1990). "Does a Fetus Already Have a Future-Like-Ours?". Journal of Philosophy. 87 (5): 264–268. doi:10.2307/2026834. JSTOR 2026834. PMID 11782096. In Pojman & Beckwith 1998, pp. 357–360.
  • McMahan, J. (2002). The Ethics of Killiing. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Olson, E. (1997). The Human Animal. New York: Oxford University Press.
  • Noonan, John T. (1970). The Morality of abortion: legal and historical perspectives. Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-58725-1.
  • Paske, G. (1994). "Abortion and the Neo-Natal Right to Life: A Critique of Marquis's Futurist Argument". The Abortion Controversy. In Pojman & Beckwith 1998, pp. 361–371.
  • Pojman, L. (1994). "Abortion: A Defense of the Personhood Argument". The Abortion Controversy. In Pojman & Beckwith 1998, pp. 275–290.
  • Pojman, Louis P.; Beckwith, Francis, eds. (1998). The Abortion Controversy: 25 Years After Roe vs. Wade, A Reader (2 ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
  • Reichlin, M (1997). "The Argument from Potential: A Reappraisal". Bioethics. 11 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1111/1467-8519.00041. PMID 11656607.
  • Rogers, K (1992). "Personhood, Potentiality, and the Temporarily Comatose Patient". Public Affairs Quarterly. 6 (2): 245–254. PMID 11652631.
  • Schwarz, S. (1990). The Moral Question of Abortion. Chicago: Loyola University Press. ch. 8.
  • Singer, Peter (2000). Writings on an Ethical Life. Ecco (HarperCollins). ISBN 978-0-06-019838-1.
  • Steinbock, B. (1992). Life Before Birth: The Moral and Legal Status of Embryos and Fetuses. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-510872-9.
  • Stone, J (1987). "Why Potentiality Matters". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 17 (4): 815–30. doi:10.1080/00455091.1987.10715920. S2CID 147106418.
  • Stone, J (1994). "Why Potentiality Still Matters". Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 24 (2): 281–94. doi:10.1080/00455091.1994.10717370. S2CID 170338877.
  • Stretton, D (2004a). "The Deprivation Argument Against Abortion". Bioethics. 18 (2): 144–180. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2004.00386.x. PMID 15148946.
  • Stretton, D (2004b). "Essential Properties and the Right to Life: A Response to Lee". Bioethics. 18 (3): 264–282. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8519.2004.00394.x. PMID 15341039.
  • Thomson, J (1971). "A Defense of Abortion". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 1 (1): 47–66.
  • Tooley, Michael (Autumn 1972). "Abortion and Infanticide". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2 (1). pp. 37–65, at 52–53.
  • Tooley, Michael (1984). "In Defense of Abortion and Infanticide". What is a Person?. pp. 83–114. doi:10.1007/978-1-4612-3950-5_4. ISBN 978-1-4612-8412-3. In Pojman & Beckwith 1998, pp. 209–233.
  • Warren, M. A. (1973). "On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion". Monist. 57 (1): 43–61. doi:10.5840/monist197357133. PMID 11661013. Reprinted in Mappes & DeGrazia 2001, pp. 456–463.
    • Warren, Mary A. "Postscript on Infanticide" (PDF). On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion (4th ed. excerpt excl. notes). Retrieved 2022-07-04. Reprinted in Mappes & DeGrazia 2001, pp. 461–463. (The "postscript" is with regards to Warren 1973 cited above.)
  • Warren, Mary A. (1978). "Do Potential People Have Moral Rights?". In Sikora, R. I.; Barry, Brian (eds.). Obligations to Future Generations. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. pp. 14–30. ISBN 9781874267317. JSTOR j.ctv289dvx3.5.
  • Warren, Mary Anne (July 1982). "Abortion and Moral Theory". Analytic Philosopy. 23 (3): 184–187. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0149.1982.tb00178.x.

Further reading edit

  • Hershenov, D. (January 2001). "Abortions and Distortions". Social Theory and Practice. 27 (1): 129–148. doi:10.5840/soctheorpract200127124.
  • Himma, Kenneth Einar (Fall 1999). "Thomson's Violinist and Conjoined Twins". Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics. 8 (4): 428–435. doi:10.1017/S0963180199004041. PMID 10513300. S2CID 21118754.
  • Kamm, F (1992). Creation and Abortion. Oxford University Press.
  • McElroy, Wendy (2008). "Abortion". In Hamowy, R. (ed.). The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism. Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE; Cato Institute. pp. 2–4. doi:10.4135/9781412965811. ISBN 978-1412965804.
  • Parent, W. (1986). "Editor's introduction". Rights, Restitution, and Risk. By Thomson, J. Harvard University Press. pp. vii–x.
  • Thomson, J (1973). "Rights and Deaths". Philosophy and Public Affairs. 2 (2): 146–159. PMID 11663361.

philosophical, aspects, abortion, debate, philosophical, aspects, abortion, debate, logical, arguments, that, made, either, support, opposition, abortion, contents, overview, philosophical, argumentation, moral, issue, arguments, based, criteria, personhood, n. The philosophical aspects of the abortion debate are logical arguments that can be made either in support of or in opposition to abortion Contents 1 Overview 2 Philosophical argumentation on the moral issue 2 1 Arguments based on criteria for personhood 2 2 The natural capacities view 2 3 The deprivation argument 2 4 The bodily rights argument 2 5 Respect for human life 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 6 Further readingOverview editThe philosophical arguments in the abortion debate are deontological or rights based The view that all or almost all abortion should be illegal generally rests on the claims 1 that the existence and moral right to life of human beings human organisms begins at or near conception fertilization 2 that induced abortion is the deliberate and unjust killing of the embryo in violation of its right to life and 3 that the law should prohibit unjust violations of the right to life The view that abortion should in most or all circumstances be legal generally rests on the claims 1 that women have a right to control what happens in and to their own bodies 2 that abortion is a just exercise of this right and 3 that the law should not criminalize just exercises of the right to control one s own body and its life support functions Although both sides are likely to see the rights based considerations as paramount some popular arguments appeal to consequentialist or utilitarian considerations For example anti abortion groups see the list below sometimes claim the existence of post abortion syndrome or a link between abortion and breast cancer alleged medical and psychological risks of abortion On the other side pro choice groups see the list below say that criminalizing abortion will lead to the deaths of many women through back alley abortions that unwanted children have a negative social impact or conversely that abortion lowers the crime rate and that reproductive rights are necessary to achieve the full and equal participation of women in society and the workforce Consequentialist arguments on both sides tend to be vigorously disputed though are not widely discussed in the philosophical literature Philosophical argumentation on the moral issue editContemporary philosophical literature contains two kinds of arguments concerning the morality of abortion One family of arguments see the following three sections relates to the moral status of the embryo whether or not the embryo has a right to life in other words is the embryo a person in a moral sense An affirmative answer would support claim 1 in the central anti abortion argument while a negative answer would support claim 2 in the central pro choice argument Another family of arguments see the section on Thomson below relates to bodily rights the question of whether the woman s bodily rights justify abortion even if the embryo has a right to life A negative answer would support claim 2 in the central anti abortion argument while an affirmative answer would support claim 2 in the central pro choice argument Arguments based on criteria for personhood edit Further information Beginning of human personhood Since the zygote is genetically identical to the embryo the fully formed fetus and the baby questioning the beginning of personhood could lead to an instance of the sorites paradox also known as the paradox of the heap 1 Mary Anne Warren in her article arguing for the permissibility of abortion 2 holds that moral opposition to abortion is based on the following argument It is wrong to kill innocent human beings The embryo is an innocent human being Hence it is wrong to kill the embryo Warren however thinks that human being is used in different senses in 1 and 2 In 1 human being is used in a moral sense to mean a person a full fledged member of the moral community In 2 human being means biological human That the embryo is a biologically human organism or animal is uncontroversial Warren holds But it does not follow that the embryo is a person and it is persons that have rights such as the right to life 3 To help make a distinction between person and biological human Warren notes that we should respect the lives of highly intelligent aliens even if they are not biological humans She thinks there is a cluster of properties that characterize persons 4 consciousness of objects and events external and or internal to the being and in particular the capacity to feel pain reasoning the developed capacity to solve new and relatively complex problems self motivated activity activity which is relatively independent of either genetic or direct external control the capacity to communicate by whatever means messages of an indefinite variety of types that is not just with an indefinite number of possible contents but on indefinitely many possible topics the presence of self concepts and self awareness either individual or racial or both A person does not have to have each of these but if something has all five then it definitely is a person whether it is biologically human or not while if it has none or perhaps only one then it is not a person again whether it is biologically human or not The fetus has at most one consciousness and this only after it becomes susceptible to pain the timing of which is disputed and hence is not a person 5 Other writers apply similar criteria concluding that the embryo lacks a right to life because it lacks self consciousness 6 or rationality and self consciousness 7 8 or certain higher psychological capacities including autonomy 9 Others conclude that personhood should be based on brain birth concept which is in essence the reversal of the brain death used as a modern definition of medical death Under this proposal presence of brain waves would be enough to grant personhood even with other features lacking Based on whether brain activity in the brain stem or just in the cerebral cortex is relevant for personhood two concepts of brain birth emerge 10 at the first appearance of brain waves in lower brain brain stem 6 8 weeks of gestation paralleling whole brain death at the first appearance of brain waves in higher brain cerebral cortex 19 20 weeks of gestation paralleling higher brain death These writers disagree on precisely which features confer a right to life 11 but agree those features must be certain developed psychological or physiological features which the embryo lacks Warren s arguments face two main objections The comatose patient objection claims that as patients in a reversible coma do not satisfy Warren s or some other criteria they are not conscious do not communicate and so on therefore they would lack a right to life on her view 12 One response is that although the reversibly comatose lack any conscious mental states they do retain all their unconscious or dispositional mental states since the appropriate neurological configurations are preserved in the brain 13 This may allow them to satisfy some of Warren s criteria The comatose also still possess brain activity brain waves so this objection does not apply to brain birth theories Finally there are some post natal humans who are unable to feel pain due to genetic disorders and thus do not satisfy all of Warren s criteria 14 The infanticide objection points out that infants indeed up to about one year of age since it is only around then that they begin to outstrip the abilities of non human animals have only one of Warren s characteristics consciousness and hence would have to be accounted non persons on her view thus her view would permit not only abortion but infanticide Warren agrees that infants are non persons and so killing them is not strictly murder but denies that infanticide is generally permissible 15 For Warren claims once a human being is born there is no longer a conflict between it and the woman s rights since the human being can be given up for adoption Killing such a human being would be wrong not because it is a person but because it would go against the desires of people willing to adopt the infant and to pay to keep the infant alive Although this clarification has critics of its own beef cattle chickens or any other livestock raised for meat or indeed even some plants have supporters who would pay to keep them alive However a response to these supports might be that while livestock plants and infants are all not morally persons the infant is the only life that can be designated a human being Thus Warren s argument does suggest an inherent value for the life of human beings that are not persons over lives that do not have the potential for becoming a person Nonetheless Warren grants that her argument entails that infanticide would be morally acceptable under some circumstances such as those of a desert island Philosopher Peter Singer similarly concludes that infanticide particularly of severely disabled infants is justifiable under certain conditions 16 And Jeff McMahan grants that under very limited circumstances it may be permissible to kill one infant to save the lives of several others 17 Opponents may see these concessions as a reductio ad absurdum of these writers views while supporters may see them merely as examples of unpleasant acts being justified in unusual cases Since brain waves appear in the lower brain brain stem in 6 8 weeks of gestation and in the higher brain cerebral cortex in 19 20 weeks of gestation both whole brain and higher brain brain birth personhood concepts based on the presence of brain waves do not permit infanticide 10 The natural capacities view edit Some opponents of Warren s view believe that what matters morally is not that one be actually exhibiting complex mental qualities of the sort she identifies but rather that one have in oneself a self directed genetic propensity or natural capacity to develop such qualities In other words what is crucial is that one be the kind of entity or substance that under the right conditions actively develops itself to the point of exhibiting Warren s qualities at some point in its life even if it does not actually exhibit them because of not having developed them yet embryo infant or having lost them severe Alzheimer s Because human beings do have this natural capacity and indeed have it essentially therefore on this view they essentially have a right to life they could not possibly fail to have a right to life 18 Further since modern embryology shows that the embryo begins to exist at conception and has a natural capacity for complex mental qualities therefore the right to life begins at conception Grounding the right to life in essential natural capacities rather than accidental developed capacities is said to have several advantages 19 As developed capacities are on a continuum admitting of greater and lesser degrees some for example are more rational and self conscious than others therefore 1 the developed capacities view must arbitrarily select some particular degree of development as the cut off point for the right to life whereas the natural capacities view is non arbitrary 2 those whose capacities are more developed would have more of a right to life on the developed capacities view whereas the natural capacities view entails we all have an equal right to life and 3 the continuum of developed capacities makes the exact point at which personhood ensues vague and human beings around that point say between one and two years of age will have a shadowy or indeterminate moral status whereas there is no such indeterminacy on the natural capacities view 20 Some defenders of Warren style arguments grant that these problems have not yet been fully solved 21 but reply that the natural capacities view fares no better It is argued for example that as human beings vary significantly in their natural cognitive capacities some are naturally more intelligent than others and as one can imagine a series or spectrum of species with gradually diminishing natural capacities for example a series from humans down to amoebae with only the slightest differences in natural capacities between each successive species therefore the problems of arbitrariness and inequality will apply equally to the natural capacities view 22 In other words there is a continuum not only of developed but of natural capacities and so the natural capacities view will inevitably face these problems as well Some critics reject the natural capacities view on the basis that it takes mere species membership or genetic potential as a basis for respect in essence a charge of speciesism 23 or because it entails that anencephalic infants and the irreversibly comatose have a full right to life 24 Moreover as with Marquis s argument see below some theories of personal identity would support the view that the embryo will never itself develop complex mental qualities rather it will simply give rise to a distinct substance or entity that will have these qualities in which case the natural capacities argument would fail Respondents to this criticism argue that the noted human cases in fact would not be classified as persons as they do not have a natural capacity to develop any psychological features 25 26 27 The deprivation argument edit A seminal essay by Don Marquis argues that abortion is wrong because it deprives the embryo of a valuable future 28 Marquis begins by arguing that what makes it wrong to kill a normal adult human being is the fact that the killing inflicts a terrible harm on the victim The harm consists in the fact that when I die I am deprived of all of the value of my future 29 I am deprived of all the valuable experiences activities projects and enjoyments that I would otherwise have had 30 Thus if a being has a highly valuable future ahead of it a future like ours then killing that being would be seriously harmful and hence seriously wrong 31 But then as a standard embryo does have a highly valuable future killing it is seriously wrong 32 And so the overwhelming majority of deliberate abortions are seriously immoral in the same moral category as killing an innocent adult human being 33 A consequence of this argument is that abortion is wrong in all the cases where killing a child or adult with the same sort of future as the embryo would be wrong So for example if involuntary euthanasia of patients with a future filled with intense physical pain is morally acceptable aborting embryos whose future is filled with intense physical pain will also be morally acceptable But it would not do for example to invoke the fact that some embryo s future would involve such things as being raised by an unloving family since we do not take it to be acceptable to kill a five year old just because her future involves being raised by an unloving family Similarly killing a child or adult may be permissible in exceptional circumstances such as self defense or perhaps capital punishment but these are irrelevant to standard abortions Marquis s argument has prompted several objections The contraception objection claims that if Marquis s argument is correct then since sperm and ova or perhaps a sperm and ovum jointly have a future like ours contraception would be as wrong as murder but as this conclusion is it is said absurd even those who believe contraception is wrong do not believe it is as wrong as murder the argument must be unsound One response 34 is that neither the sperm nor the egg nor any particular sperm egg combination will ever itself live out a valuable future what will later have valuable experiences activities projects and enjoyments is a new entity a new organism that will come into existence at or near conception and it is this entity not the sperm or egg or any sperm egg combination that has a future like ours As this response makes clear Marquis s argument requires that what will later have valuable experiences and activities is the same entity the same biological organism as the embryo 35 The identity objection rejects this assumption On certain theories of personal identity generally motivated by thought experiments involving brain or cerebrum transplants each of us is not a biological organism but rather an embodied mind or a person in John Locke s sense that comes into existence when the brain gives rise to certain developed psychological capacities 36 If either of these views is correct Marquis s argument will fail for the embryo even the early fetus lacking the relevant psychological capacities would not itself have a future of value but would merely have the potential to give rise to a different entity an embodied mind or a person that would have a future of value The success of Marquis s argument thus depends on one s favored account of personal identity The interests objection claims that what makes murder wrong is not just the deprivation of a valuable future but the deprivation of a future that one has an interest in The embryo has no conscious interest in its future and so the objection concludes to kill it is not wrong The defender of Marquis style arguments may however give the counterexample of the suicidal teenager who takes no interest in their future but killing whom is nonetheless wrong and murder 37 If the opponent responds that one can have an interest in one s future without taking an interest in it then the defender of the Marquis style argument can claim that this applies to the embryo 38 Similarly if an opponent claims that what is crucial is having a valuable future which one would under ideal conditions desire to preserve whether or not one does in fact desire to preserve it 39 then the defender may ask why the embryo would not under ideal conditions desire to preserve its future The equality objection claims that Marquis s argument leads to unacceptable inequalities 40 If as Marquis claims killing is wrong because it deprives the victim of a valuable future then since some futures appear to contain much more value than others a 9 year old has a much longer future than a 90 year old a middle class person s future has much less gratuitous pain and suffering than someone in extreme poverty some killings would turn out to be much more wrong than others But as this is strongly counterintuitive most people believe all killings are equally wrong other things being equal Marquis s argument must be mistaken Some writers have concluded that the wrongness of killing arises not from the harm it causes the victim since this varies greatly among killings but from the killing s violation of the intrinsic worth or personhood of the victim 41 However such accounts may themselves face problems of equality 42 and so the equality objection may not be decisive against Marquis s argument The psychological connectedness objection claims that a being can be seriously harmed by being deprived of a valuable future only if there are sufficient psychological connections sufficient correlations or continuations of memory belief desire and the like between the being as it is now and the being as it will be when it lives out the valuable future 43 As there are few psychological connections between the embryo and its later self it is concluded that depriving it of its future does not seriously harm it and hence is not seriously wrong A defense of this objection is likely to rest as with certain views of personal identity on thought experiments involving brain or cerebrum swaps and this may render it implausible to some readers The bodily rights argument edit See also Artificial womb In her well known article A Defense of Abortion 44 Judith Jarvis Thomson argues that abortion is in some circumstances permissible even if the embryo is a person and has a right to life because the embryo s right to life is overtrumped by the woman s right to control her body and its life support functions in short Thomson s argument is that the right to life does not include or entail the right to use someone else s body Her central argument involves a thought experiment Thomson asks us to imagine that an individual call Bob wakes up in bed next to a famous violinist He is unconscious with a fatal kidney ailment and because only Bob happens to have the right blood type to help the Society of Music Lovers has kidnapped Bob and plugged his circulatory system into the violinist s so that Bob s kidneys can filter poisons from his blood as well as his own If the violinist is disconnected from Bob now he will die but in nine months he will recover and can be safely disconnected Thomson takes it that one may permissibly unplug oneself from the violinist even though this will kill him The right to life Thomson says does not entail the right to use another person s body and so in disconnecting the violinist one does not violate his right to life but merely deprives him of something the use of another person s body to which he has no right Similarly even if the fetus has a right to life it does not have a right to use the pregnant woman s body and life support functions against her will and so aborting the pregnancy is permissible in at least some circumstances However Thomson notes that the woman s right to abortion does not include the right to directly insist upon the death of the child should the fetus happen to be viable that is capable of surviving outside the womb 45 Critics of this argument generally agree that unplugging the violinist is permissible but claim there are morally relevant disanalogies between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion The most common objection is that the violinist scenario involving a kidnapping is analogous only to abortion after rape In most cases of abortion the pregnant woman was not raped but had intercourse voluntarily and thus has either tacitly consented to allowing the embryo to use her body the tacit consent objection 46 or else has a duty to sustain the embryo because the woman herself caused it to stand in need of her body the responsibility objection 47 Other common objections turn on the claim that the embryo is the pregnant woman s child whereas the violinist is a stranger the stranger versus offspring objection 48 that abortion kills the embryo whereas unplugging the violinist merely lets him die the killing versus letting die objection 48 or similarly that abortion intentionally causes the embryo s death whereas unplugging the violinist merely causes death as a foreseen but unintended side effect the intending versus foreseeing objection 49 cf the doctrine of double effect Defenders of Thomson s argument most notably David Boonin 50 reply that the alleged disanalogies between the violinist scenario and typical cases of abortion do not hold either because the factors that critics appeal to are not genuinely morally relevant or because those factors are morally relevant but do not apply to abortion in the way that critics have claimed Critics have in turn responded to Boonin s arguments 51 Alternative scenarios have been put forth as more accurate and realistic representations of the moral issues present in abortion John Noonan proposes the scenario of a family who was found to be liable for frostbite finger loss suffered by a dinner guest whom they refused to allow to stay overnight although it was very cold outside and the guest showed signs of being sick It is argued that just as it would not be permissible to refuse temporary accommodation for the guest to protect them from physical harm it would not be permissible to refuse temporary accommodation of a fetus 52 Other critics claim that there is a difference between artificial and extraordinary means of preservation such as medical treatment kidney dialysis and blood transfusions and normal and natural means of preservation such as gestation childbirth and breastfeeding They argue that if a baby was born into an environment in which there was no replacement available for her mother s breast milk and the baby would either breastfeed or starve the mother would have to allow the baby to breastfeed But the mother would never have to give the baby a blood transfusion no matter what the circumstances were The difference between breastfeeding in that scenario and blood transfusions is the difference between gestation and childbirth on the one hand and using one s body as a kidney dialysis machine on the other 53 54 55 56 57 58 59 Respect for human life edit See also Virtue ethics One argument against the right to abortion appeals to the secular value of a human life The thought is that all forms of human life including the fetus are inherently valuable because they are connected to our thoughts on family and parenthood among other natural aspects of humanity Thus abortion can express the wrong attitudes towards humanity in a way that manifest vicious character This view is represented by some forms of Humanism and by moral philosopher Rosalind Hursthouse in her widely anthologized article Virtue Theory and Abortion 60 Thinking about abortion in this way according to Hursthouse shows the unimportance of rights because one can act viciously in exercising a moral right For example she says Love and friendship do not survive their parties constantly insisting on their rights nor do people live well when they think that getting what they have a right to is of preeminent importance they harm others and they harm themselves 60 Hursthouse argues that the ending of a human life is always a serious matter and that abortion when it is wrong is wrong because it violates a respect for human life See also editAbortion debate Beginning of human personhood Human rights Fetal pain Fetal rights Unborn Victims of Violence Act Libertarian perspectives on abortion Paternal rights and abortion Person for a discussion of personhood Religion and abortion Societal attitudes towards abortionNotes edit Kerckhove Lee F Waller Sara 1998 Fetal personhood and the sorites paradox The Journal of Value Inquiry 32 2 175 189 doi 10 1023 a 1004375726894 PMID 15295850 S2CID 37563125 Warren 1973 Warren 1973 p 457 The same point is made in Tooley 1972 pp 40 43 Singer 2000 pp 126 28 155 156 Pojman 1994 p 280 and elsewhere person can also be used in two senses In John Locke s sense often employed in discussions of personal identity person is a descriptive term that tells us about a being s psychological properties In Warren s sense person is a moral or evaluative term that tells us about a being s moral properties Warren and others hold however that being a person in the moral sense actually requires being a person in the psychological sense Warren 1973 p 458 Glover 1977 p 127 and English 1975 pp 316 317 also refer to a cluster of properties as constituting personhood Warren 1973 pp 458 459 Michael Tooley argues that the bearer of a right to life must conceive of itself as a continuing subject of experiences and other mental states Tooley 1972 p 44 or must at some time possess the concept of a continuing self or mental substance Tooley 1984 p 218 Singer 2000 pp 128 156 157 Pojman 1994 pp 281 2 McMahan 2002 p 260 a b Jones D Gareth 1998 The Problematic Symmetry between Brain Birth and Brain Death Journal of Medical Ethics 24 4 237 42 doi 10 1136 jme 24 4 237 JSTOR 27718134 PMC 1377672 PMID 9752625 On the pro life side see below it is similarly unclear which features one must have a natural capacity for in order to have a right to life cf Schwarz 1990 pp 105 109 or which features constitute a future like ours Marquis 1989 pp 197 Schwarz 1990 p 89 Rogers 1992 Beckwith 1993 p 108 Larmer 1995 pp 245 248 Lee amp George 2005 p 263 Stretton 2004b p 267 original emphasis see Glover 1977 pp 98 99 Singer 2000 p 137 Boonin 2003 pp 64 70 Rare disease makes girl unable to feel pain Associated Press 2004 11 07 n d via Quad City Times Warren 1982 Singer 2000 pp 186 193 McMahan 2002 pp 359 360 Grisez 1970 pp 277 287 Lee 1996 2004 Lee amp George 2005 pp 16 20 Schwarz 1990 pp 91 93 Beckwith 1993 pp 108 10 Reichlin 1997 pp 22 23 and many others On Marquis s view see below by contrast one could fail to have a right to life for example by becoming irreversibly comatose since one s future would then lack valuable experiences and activities See Lee 2004 pp 254 255 Lee amp George 2005 pp 18 19 Schwarz 1990 pp 108 109 This third point is discussed in McMahan 2002 pp 261 265 McMahan 2002 pp 261 265 Stretton 2004b pp 281 282 Stretton 2004b pp 270 274 both responses McMahan 2002 p 217 spectrum argument only McMahan 2002 pp 209 217 Stretton 2004b pp 275 276 Stretton 2004b p 276 both points Boonin 2003 p 55 irreversibly comatose only Schwarz 1990 p 52 Beckwith Francis J Summer 1991 When Does a Human Become a Person Christian Research Journal 28 Retrieved 2010 02 18 Sullivan Dennis M 2003 The conception view of personhood a review Ethics amp Medicine 19 1 Retrieved 2022 07 04 via Cedarville University Marquis 1989 For a similar argument published earlier see Stone 1987 Stone 1994 Marquis 1989 p 190 Marquis 1989 p 189 Marquis 1989 p 190 The type of wrongness appealed to here is presumptive or prima facie wrongness as noted below it may be overridden in exceptional circumstances Marquis 1989 p 192 Marquis 1989 p 183 Although Marquis views the killing of an embryo or normal human adult as seriously wrong he avoids any reference to rights or the right to life and so is apparently not committed to deontological ethics Stone 1987 pp 816 817 cf Marquis 1989 pp 201 202 This view known as Animalism since it takes you and I to be essentially animals rather than Lockean persons or embodied minds or souls is defended in Olson 1997 Supporters of the embodied mind view include Tooley 1984 pp 218 219 using the term subject of consciousness McMahan 2002 ch 1 and Hasker 1999 ch 7 Supporters of the personhood view include Warren 1978 p 18 McInerney 1990 though there is some ambiguity Doepke 1996 ch 9 and Baker 2000 Marquis 1989 p 198 Cf Stone 1994 282 n 4 Boonin 2003 pp 70 85 Paske 1994 p 365 Stretton 2004b pp 250 260 see also McMahan 2002 pp 234 235 271 For example McMahan 2002 pp 240 265 McMahan 2002 pp 247 248 McInerney 1990 McMahan 2002 p 271 Stretton 2004a pp 171 179 Thomson 1971 All the same I agree that the desire for the child s death is not one which anybody may gratify should it turn out to be possible to detach the child alive In Thomson 1971 page needed e g Warren 1973 Steinbock 1992 p 78 e g Beckwith 1993 McMahan 2002 a b e g Schwarz 1990 Beckwith 1993 McMahan 2002 e g Finnis 1973 Schwarz 1990 Lee 1996 Lee amp George 2005 Boonin 2003 ch 4 e g Beckwith 2006 Noonan 1970 Poupard Richard J 2007 Suffer the violinist Why the pro abortion argument from bodily autonomy fails PDF Christian Research Journal 30 4 Archived from the original PDF on 2011 07 16 Retrieved 2009 10 25 Koukl G Klusendorf S 2001 Making Abortion Unthinkable The Art of Pro Life Persuasion California STR Press p 86 Nathanson Bernard Ostling Richard 1979 Aborting America Garden City Doubleday ISBN 0 385 14461 X Peter Kreeft David Boonin 2005 Is Abortion Morally Justifiable in a Free Society Public debate at Yale University Audio Intercollegiate Studies Institute Arthur John 1989 The Unfinished Constitution Philosophy and Constitutional Practice Wadsworth pp 198 200 Beckwith Francis March 1992 Personal Bodily Rights Abortion and Unplugging the Violinist PDF International Philosophical Quarterly 32 1 105 118 doi 10 5840 ipq199232156 PMID 11656685 Archived from the original PDF on 2010 08 16 Retrieved 2009 10 10 Parks Brian D 2006 The Natural Artificial Distinction and Conjoined Twins The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 6 4 671 680 doi 10 5840 ncbq2006646 ISSN 1532 5490 a b Hursthouse Rosalind 1991 Virtue Theory and Abortion Philosophy amp Public Affairs 20 3 223 246 JSTOR 2265432 PMID 11659356 References editBaker L 2000 Persons and Bodies A Constitution View Cambridge University Press Beckwith F 1993 Politically Correct Death Grand Rapids MI Baker Books ch 7 Beckwith F April 2006 Defending Abortion Philosophically Journal of Medicine amp Philosophy 31 177 203 doi 10 1080 03605310600588723 Boonin D 2003 A Defense of Abortion Cambridge University Press ch 4 Doepke F 1996 The Kinds of Things Chicago Open Court English Jane 1975 Abortion and the Concept of a Person Canadian Journal of Philosophy 5 2 233 243 doi 10 1080 00455091 1975 10716109 PMID 11663579 S2CID 38354546 Finnis J Winter 1973 The Rights and Wrongs of Abortion Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 2 117 145 Glover J 1977 Causing Death and Saving Lives London Penguin Grisez G 1970 Abortion the Myths the Realities and the Arguments New York Corpus Books Hasker W 1999 The Emergent Self Ithaca NY Cornell University Press Larmer R 1995 Abortion Personhood and the Potential for Consciousness Journal of Applied Philosophy 12 3 241 251 doi 10 1111 j 1468 5930 1995 tb00136 x Lee P 1996 Abortion and Unborn Human Life Washington DC Catholic University of America Press ch 4 Lee P June 2004 The Pro Life Argument from Substantial Identity A Defense Bioethics 18 3 249 263 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8519 2004 00393 x PMID 15341038 Lee P George R 2005 The Wrong of Abortion In Cohen A Wellman C eds Contemporary Debates in Applied Ethics Oxford Blackwell pp 13 26 at 20 21 Mappes T A DeGrazia D eds 2001 Biomedical Ethics 5 ed New York McGraw Hill ISBN 0072303654 Marquis D April 1989 Why Abortion Is Immoral Journal of Philosophy 86 4 183 202 doi 10 2307 2026961 JSTOR 2026961 PMID 11782094 McInerney Peter K May 1990 Does a Fetus Already Have a Future Like Ours Journal of Philosophy 87 5 264 268 doi 10 2307 2026834 JSTOR 2026834 PMID 11782096 In Pojman amp Beckwith 1998 pp 357 360 McMahan J 2002 The Ethics of Killiing New York Oxford University Press Olson E 1997 The Human Animal New York Oxford University Press Noonan John T 1970 The Morality of abortion legal and historical perspectives Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 58725 1 Paske G 1994 Abortion and the Neo Natal Right to Life A Critique of Marquis s Futurist Argument The Abortion Controversy In Pojman amp Beckwith 1998 pp 361 371 Pojman L 1994 Abortion A Defense of the Personhood Argument The Abortion Controversy In Pojman amp Beckwith 1998 pp 275 290 Pojman Louis P Beckwith Francis eds 1998 The Abortion Controversy 25 Years After Roe vs Wade A Reader 2 ed Belmont CA Wadsworth Reichlin M 1997 The Argument from Potential A Reappraisal Bioethics 11 1 1 23 doi 10 1111 1467 8519 00041 PMID 11656607 Rogers K 1992 Personhood Potentiality and the Temporarily Comatose Patient Public Affairs Quarterly 6 2 245 254 PMID 11652631 Schwarz S 1990 The Moral Question of Abortion Chicago Loyola University Press ch 8 Singer Peter 2000 Writings on an Ethical Life Ecco HarperCollins ISBN 978 0 06 019838 1 Steinbock B 1992 Life Before Birth The Moral and Legal Status of Embryos and Fetuses Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 510872 9 Stone J 1987 Why Potentiality Matters Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 4 815 30 doi 10 1080 00455091 1987 10715920 S2CID 147106418 Stone J 1994 Why Potentiality Still Matters Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 2 281 94 doi 10 1080 00455091 1994 10717370 S2CID 170338877 Stretton D 2004a The Deprivation Argument Against Abortion Bioethics 18 2 144 180 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8519 2004 00386 x PMID 15148946 Stretton D 2004b Essential Properties and the Right to Life A Response to Lee Bioethics 18 3 264 282 doi 10 1111 j 1467 8519 2004 00394 x PMID 15341039 Thomson J 1971 A Defense of Abortion Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 1 47 66 Tooley Michael Autumn 1972 Abortion and Infanticide Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 1 pp 37 65 at 52 53 Tooley Michael 1984 In Defense of Abortion and Infanticide What is a Person pp 83 114 doi 10 1007 978 1 4612 3950 5 4 ISBN 978 1 4612 8412 3 In Pojman amp Beckwith 1998 pp 209 233 Warren M A 1973 On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion Monist 57 1 43 61 doi 10 5840 monist197357133 PMID 11661013 Reprinted in Mappes amp DeGrazia 2001 pp 456 463 Warren Mary A Postscript on Infanticide PDF On the Moral and Legal Status of Abortion 4th ed excerpt excl notes Retrieved 2022 07 04 Reprinted in Mappes amp DeGrazia 2001 pp 461 463 The postscript is with regards to Warren 1973 cited above Warren Mary A 1978 Do Potential People Have Moral Rights In Sikora R I Barry Brian eds Obligations to Future Generations Philadelphia PA Temple University Press pp 14 30 ISBN 9781874267317 JSTOR j ctv289dvx3 5 Warren Mary Anne July 1982 Abortion and Moral Theory Analytic Philosopy 23 3 184 187 doi 10 1111 j 1468 0149 1982 tb00178 x Further reading editHershenov D January 2001 Abortions and Distortions Social Theory and Practice 27 1 129 148 doi 10 5840 soctheorpract200127124 Himma Kenneth Einar Fall 1999 Thomson s Violinist and Conjoined Twins Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 8 4 428 435 doi 10 1017 S0963180199004041 PMID 10513300 S2CID 21118754 Kamm F 1992 Creation and Abortion Oxford University Press McElroy Wendy 2008 Abortion In Hamowy R ed The Encyclopedia of Libertarianism Thousand Oaks CA SAGE Cato Institute pp 2 4 doi 10 4135 9781412965811 ISBN 978 1412965804 Parent W 1986 Editor s introduction Rights Restitution and Risk By Thomson J Harvard University Press pp vii x Thomson J 1973 Rights and Deaths Philosophy and Public Affairs 2 2 146 159 PMID 11663361 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Philosophical aspects of the abortion debate amp oldid 1212301379, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.