fbpx
Wikipedia

Impossible world

In philosophical logic, the concept of an impossible world (sometimes called a non-normal world) is used to model certain phenomena that cannot be adequately handled using ordinary possible worlds. An impossible world, , is the same sort of thing as a possible world (whatever that may be), except that it is in some sense "impossible." Depending on the context, this may mean that some contradictions, statements of the form are true at , or that the normal laws of logic, metaphysics, and mathematics, fail to hold at , or both. Impossible worlds are controversial objects in philosophy, logic, and semantics. They have been around since the advent of possible world semantics for modal logic, as well as world based semantics for non-classical logics, but have yet to find the ubiquitous acceptance, that their possible counterparts have found in all walks of philosophy.

Argument from ways Edit

Possible worlds Edit

Possible worlds are often regarded with suspicion, which is why their proponents have struggled to find arguments in their favor.[1] An often-cited argument is called the argument from ways. It defines possible worlds as "ways how things could have been" and relies for its premises and inferences on assumptions from natural language,[2][3][4] for example:

(1) Hillary Clinton could have won the 2016 US election.
(2) So there are other ways how things could have been.
(3) Possible worlds are ways how things could have been.
(4) So there are other possible worlds.

The central step of this argument happens at (2) where the plausible (1) is interpreted in a way that involves quantification over "ways". Many philosophers, following Willard Van Orman Quine,[5] hold that quantification entails ontological commitments, in this case, a commitment to the existence of possible worlds. Quine himself restricted his method to scientific theories, but others have applied it also to natural language, for example, Amie L. Thomasson in her paper entitled Ontology Made Easy.[6] The strength of the argument from ways depends on these assumptions and may be challenged by casting doubt on the quantifier-method of ontology or on the reliability of natural language as a guide to ontology.

Impossible worlds Edit

A similar argument can be used to justify the thesis that there are impossible worlds,[3] for example:

(a) Hillary Clinton couldn't have both won and lost the 2016 US election.
(b) So there are ways how things couldn't have been.
(c) Impossible worlds are ways how things couldn't have been.
(d) So there are impossible worlds.

The problem for the defender of possible worlds is that language is ambiguous concerning the meaning of (a): does it mean that this is a way how things couldn't be or that this is not a way how things could be.[2] It is open to critics of impossible worlds to assert the latter option, which would invalidate the argument.

Applications Edit

Non-normal modal logics Edit

Non-normal worlds were introduced by Saul Kripke in 1965 as a purely technical device to provide semantics for modal logics weaker than the system K — in particular, modal logics that reject the rule of necessitation:

 .

Such logics are typically referred to as "non-normal." Under the standard interpretation of modal vocabulary in Kripke semantics, we have   if and only if in each model,   holds in all worlds. To construct a model in which   holds in all worlds but   does not, we need either to interpret   in a non-standard manner (that is, we do not just consider the truth of   in every accessible world), or we reinterpret the condition for being valid. This latter choice is what Kripke does. We single out a class of worlds as normal, and we take validity to be truth in every normal world in a model. in this way we may construct a model in which   is true in every normal world, but in which   is not. We need only ensure that this world (at which   fails) have an accessible world which is not normal. Here,   can fail, and hence, at our original world,   fails to be necessary, despite being a truth of the logic.

These non-normal worlds are impossible in the sense that they are not constrained by what is true according to the logic. From the fact that  , it does not follow that   holds in a non-normal world.

For more discussion of the interpretation of the language of modal logic in models with worlds, see the entries on modal logic and on Kripke semantics.

Avoiding Curry's paradox Edit

Curry's paradox is a serious problem for logicians who are interested in developing formal languages that are "semantically closed" (i.e. that can express their own semantics). The paradox relies on the seemingly obvious principle of contraction:

 .

There are ways of using non-normal worlds in a semantical system that invalidate contraction. Moreover, these methods can be given a reasonable philosophical justification by construing non-normal worlds as worlds at which "the laws of logic fail."

Counternecessary statements Edit

A counternecessary statement is a counterfactual conditional whose antecedent is not merely false, but necessarily so (or whose consequent is necessarily true).

For the sake of argument, assume that either (or both) of the following are the case:

1. Intuitionism is false.
2. The law of excluded middle is true.

Presumably each of these statements is such that if it is true (false), then it is necessarily true (false).

Thus one (or both) of the following is being assumed:

1′. Intuitionism is false at every possible world.
2′. The law of excluded middle is true at every possible world.

Now consider the following:

3. If intuitionism is true, then the law of excluded middle holds.

This is intuitively false, as one of the fundamental tenets of intuitionism is precisely that the LEM does not hold. Suppose this statement is cashed out as:

3′. Every possible world at which intuitionism is true is a possible world at which the law of excluded middle holds true.

This holds vacuously, given either (1′) or (2′).

Now suppose impossible worlds are considered in addition to possible ones. It is compatible with (1′) that there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true, and with (2′) that there are impossible worlds at which the LEM is false. This yields the interpretation:

3*. Every (possible or impossible) world at which intuitionism is true is a (possible or impossible) world at which the law of excluded middle holds.

This does not seem to be the case, for intuitively there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true and the law of excluded middle does not hold.

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ Lewis, David K. (1973). "4. Foundations". Counterfactuals. Blackwell.
  2. ^ a b Laan, David A. Vander (1997). "The Ontology of Impossible Worlds". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 38 (4): 597–620. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1039540772.
  3. ^ a b Berto, Francesco; Jago, Mark (2018). Impossible Worlds. Retrieved 14 November 2020. {{cite encyclopedia}}: |website= ignored (help)
  4. ^ Menzel, Christopher (2017). Possible Worlds. Retrieved 14 November 2020. {{cite encyclopedia}}: |website= ignored (help)
  5. ^ Quine, Willard V. (1948). "On What There Is". Review of Metaphysics. 2 (1): 21–38.
  6. ^ Thomasson, Amie L. (2014). Ontology Made Easy. Oup Usa. p. 248.

Bibliography Edit

  • Kripke, Saul. 1965. Semantical analysis of modal logic, II: non-normal modal propositional calculi. In J.W. Addison, L. Henkin, and A. Tarski, eds., The Theory of Models. Amsterdam: North Holland.
  • Priest, Graham (ed.). 1997. Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38, no. 4. (Special issue on impossible worlds.) Table of contents
  • Priest, Graham. 2001. An Introduction to Non-Classical Logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

External links Edit

impossible, world, philosophical, logic, concept, impossible, world, sometimes, called, normal, world, used, model, certain, phenomena, that, cannot, adequately, handled, using, ordinary, possible, worlds, impossible, world, displaystyle, same, sort, thing, po. In philosophical logic the concept of an impossible world sometimes called a non normal world is used to model certain phenomena that cannot be adequately handled using ordinary possible worlds An impossible world i displaystyle i is the same sort of thing as a possible world w displaystyle w whatever that may be except that it is in some sense impossible Depending on the context this may mean that some contradictions statements of the form p amp p displaystyle p amp lnot p are true at i displaystyle i or that the normal laws of logic metaphysics and mathematics fail to hold at i displaystyle i or both Impossible worlds are controversial objects in philosophy logic and semantics They have been around since the advent of possible world semantics for modal logic as well as world based semantics for non classical logics but have yet to find the ubiquitous acceptance that their possible counterparts have found in all walks of philosophy Contents 1 Argument from ways 1 1 Possible worlds 1 2 Impossible worlds 2 Applications 2 1 Non normal modal logics 2 2 Avoiding Curry s paradox 2 3 Counternecessary statements 3 See also 4 References 5 Bibliography 6 External linksArgument from ways EditPossible worlds Edit Possible worlds are often regarded with suspicion which is why their proponents have struggled to find arguments in their favor 1 An often cited argument is called the argument from ways It defines possible worlds as ways how things could have been and relies for its premises and inferences on assumptions from natural language 2 3 4 for example 1 Hillary Clinton could have won the 2016 US election 2 So there are other ways how things could have been 3 Possible worlds are ways how things could have been 4 So there are other possible worlds The central step of this argument happens at 2 where the plausible 1 is interpreted in a way that involves quantification over ways Many philosophers following Willard Van Orman Quine 5 hold that quantification entails ontological commitments in this case a commitment to the existence of possible worlds Quine himself restricted his method to scientific theories but others have applied it also to natural language for example Amie L Thomasson in her paper entitled Ontology Made Easy 6 The strength of the argument from ways depends on these assumptions and may be challenged by casting doubt on the quantifier method of ontology or on the reliability of natural language as a guide to ontology Impossible worlds Edit A similar argument can be used to justify the thesis that there are impossible worlds 3 for example a Hillary Clinton couldn t have both won and lost the 2016 US election b So there are ways how things couldn t have been c Impossible worlds are ways how things couldn t have been d So there are impossible worlds The problem for the defender of possible worlds is that language is ambiguous concerning the meaning of a does it mean that this is a way how things couldn t be or that this is not a way how things could be 2 It is open to critics of impossible worlds to assert the latter option which would invalidate the argument Applications EditNon normal modal logics Edit Non normal worlds were introduced by Saul Kripke in 1965 as a purely technical device to provide semantics for modal logics weaker than the system K in particular modal logics that reject the rule of necessitation A A displaystyle vdash A Rightarrow vdash Box A Such logics are typically referred to as non normal Under the standard interpretation of modal vocabulary in Kripke semantics we have A displaystyle vdash A if and only if in each model A displaystyle A holds in all worlds To construct a model in which A displaystyle A holds in all worlds but A displaystyle Box A does not we need either to interpret displaystyle Box in a non standard manner that is we do not just consider the truth of A displaystyle A in every accessible world or we reinterpret the condition for being valid This latter choice is what Kripke does We single out a class of worlds as normal and we take validity to be truth in every normal world in a model in this way we may construct a model in which A displaystyle A is true in every normal world but in which A displaystyle Box A is not We need only ensure that this world at which A displaystyle Box A fails have an accessible world which is not normal Here A displaystyle A can fail and hence at our original world A displaystyle Box A fails to be necessary despite being a truth of the logic These non normal worlds are impossible in the sense that they are not constrained by what is true according to the logic From the fact that A displaystyle vdash A it does not follow that A displaystyle A holds in a non normal world For more discussion of the interpretation of the language of modal logic in models with worlds see the entries on modal logic and on Kripke semantics Avoiding Curry s paradox Edit Curry s paradox is a serious problem for logicians who are interested in developing formal languages that are semantically closed i e that can express their own semantics The paradox relies on the seemingly obvious principle of contraction A A B A B displaystyle A rightarrow A rightarrow B rightarrow A rightarrow B There are ways of using non normal worlds in a semantical system that invalidate contraction Moreover these methods can be given a reasonable philosophical justification by construing non normal worlds as worlds at which the laws of logic fail Counternecessary statements Edit A counternecessary statement is a counterfactual conditional whose antecedent is not merely false but necessarily so or whose consequent is necessarily true For the sake of argument assume that either or both of the following are the case 1 Intuitionism is false 2 The law of excluded middle is true Presumably each of these statements is such that if it is true false then it is necessarily true false Thus one or both of the following is being assumed 1 Intuitionism is false at every possible world 2 The law of excluded middle is true at every possible world Now consider the following 3 If intuitionism is true then the law of excluded middle holds This is intuitively false as one of the fundamental tenets of intuitionism is precisely that the LEM does not hold Suppose this statement is cashed out as 3 Every possible world at which intuitionism is true is a possible world at which the law of excluded middle holds true This holds vacuously given either 1 or 2 Now suppose impossible worlds are considered in addition to possible ones It is compatible with 1 that there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true and with 2 that there are impossible worlds at which the LEM is false This yields the interpretation 3 Every possible or impossible world at which intuitionism is true is a possible or impossible world at which the law of excluded middle holds This does not seem to be the case for intuitively there are impossible worlds at which intuitionism is true and the law of excluded middle does not hold See also EditPossible world Modal realism Extended modal realismReferences Edit Lewis David K 1973 4 Foundations Counterfactuals Blackwell a b Laan David A Vander 1997 The Ontology of Impossible Worlds Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 4 597 620 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1039540772 a b Berto Francesco Jago Mark 2018 Impossible Worlds Retrieved 14 November 2020 a href Template Cite encyclopedia html title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a website ignored help Menzel Christopher 2017 Possible Worlds Retrieved 14 November 2020 a href Template Cite encyclopedia html title Template Cite encyclopedia cite encyclopedia a website ignored help Quine Willard V 1948 On What There Is Review of Metaphysics 2 1 21 38 Thomasson Amie L 2014 Ontology Made Easy Oup Usa p 248 Bibliography EditKripke Saul 1965 Semantical analysis of modal logic II non normal modal propositional calculi In J W Addison L Henkin and A Tarski eds The Theory of Models Amsterdam North Holland Priest Graham ed 1997 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 no 4 Special issue on impossible worlds Table of contents Priest Graham 2001 An Introduction to Non Classical Logic Cambridge Cambridge University Press External links EditBerto Francesco Impossible Worlds In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward N Zalta A classically based theory of impossible worlds PDF Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Impossible world amp oldid 1158079283, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.