fbpx
Wikipedia

Completeness of the real numbers

Completeness is a property of the real numbers that, intuitively, implies that there are no "gaps" (in Dedekind's terminology) or "missing points" in the real number line. This contrasts with the rational numbers, whose corresponding number line has a "gap" at each irrational value. In the decimal number system, completeness is equivalent to the statement that any infinite string of decimal digits is actually a decimal representation for some real number.

Depending on the construction of the real numbers used, completeness may take the form of an axiom (the completeness axiom), or may be a theorem proven from the construction. There are many equivalent forms of completeness, the most prominent being Dedekind completeness and Cauchy completeness (completeness as a metric space).

Forms of completeness edit

The real numbers can be defined synthetically as an ordered field satisfying some version of the completeness axiom. Different versions of this axiom are all equivalent in the sense that any ordered field that satisfies one form of completeness satisfies all of them, apart from Cauchy completeness and nested intervals theorem, which are strictly weaker in that there are non Archimedean fields that are ordered and Cauchy complete. When the real numbers are instead constructed using a model, completeness becomes a theorem or collection of theorems.

Least upper bound property edit

The least-upper-bound property states that every nonempty subset of real numbers having an upper bound must have a least upper bound (or supremum) in the set of real numbers.

The rational number line Q does not have the least upper bound property. An example is the subset of rational numbers

 

This set has an upper bound. However, this set has no least upper bound in Q: the least upper bound as a subset of the reals would be √2, but it does not exist in Q. For any upper bound xQ, there is another upper bound yQ with y < x.

For instance, take x = 1.5, then x is certainly an upper bound of S, since x is positive and x2 = 2.25 ≥ 2; that is, no element of S is larger than x. However, we can choose a smaller upper bound, say y = 1.45; this is also an upper bound of S for the same reasons, but it is smaller than x, so x is not a least-upper-bound of S. We can proceed similarly to find an upper bound of S that is smaller than y, say z = 1.42, etc., such that we never find a least-upper-bound of S in Q.

The least upper bound property can be generalized to the setting of partially ordered sets. See completeness (order theory).

Dedekind completeness edit

See Dedekind completeness for more general concepts bearing this name.

Dedekind completeness is the property that every Dedekind cut of the real numbers is generated by a real number. In a synthetic approach to the real numbers, this is the version of completeness that is most often included as an axiom.

The rational number line Q is not Dedekind complete. An example is the Dedekind cut

 
 

L does not have a maximum and R does not have a minimum, so this cut is not generated by a rational number.

There is a construction of the real numbers based on the idea of using Dedekind cuts of rational numbers to name real numbers; e.g. the cut (L,R) described above would name  . If one were to repeat the construction of real numbers with Dedekind cuts (i.e., "close" the set of real numbers by adding all possible Dedekind cuts), one would obtain no additional numbers because the real numbers are already Dedekind complete.

Cauchy completeness edit

Cauchy completeness is the statement that every Cauchy sequence of real numbers converges to a real number.

The rational number line Q is not Cauchy complete. An example is the following sequence of rational numbers:

 

Here the nth term in the sequence is the nth decimal approximation for pi. Though this is a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers, it does not converge to any rational number. (In this real number line, this sequence converges to pi.)

Cauchy completeness is related to the construction of the real numbers using Cauchy sequences. Essentially, this method defines a real number to be the limit of a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers.

In mathematical analysis, Cauchy completeness can be generalized to a notion of completeness for any metric space. See complete metric space.

For an ordered field, Cauchy completeness is weaker than the other forms of completeness on this page. But Cauchy completeness and the Archimedean property taken together are equivalent to the others.

Nested intervals theorem edit

The nested interval theorem is another form of completeness. Let In = [an, bn] be a sequence of closed intervals, and suppose that these intervals are nested in the sense that

 

Moreover, assume that bnan → 0 as n → +∞. The nested interval theorem states that the intersection of all of the intervals In contains exactly one point.

The rational number line does not satisfy the nested interval theorem. For example, the sequence (whose terms are derived from the digits of pi in the suggested way)

 

is a nested sequence of closed intervals in the rational numbers whose intersection is empty. (In the real numbers, the intersection of these intervals contains the number pi.)

Nested intervals theorem shares the same logical status as Cauchy completeness in this spectrum of expressions of completeness. In other words, nested intervals theorem by itself is weaker than other forms of completeness, although taken together with Archimedean property, it is equivalent to the others.

The open induction principle edit

The open induction principle states that a non-empty open subset   of the interval   must be equal to the entire interval, if for any  , we have that   implies  .

The open induction principle can be shown to be equivalent to Dedekind completeness for arbitrary ordered sets under the order topology, using proofs by contradiction. In weaker foundations such as in constructive analysis where the law of the excluded middle does not hold, the full form of the least upper bound property fails for the Dedekind reals, while the open induction property remains true in most models (following from Brouwer's bar theorem) and is strong enough to give short proofs of key theorems.

Monotone convergence theorem edit

The monotone convergence theorem (described as the fundamental axiom of analysis by Körner[1]) states that every nondecreasing, bounded sequence of real numbers converges. This can be viewed as a special case of the least upper bound property, but it can also be used fairly directly to prove the Cauchy completeness of the real numbers.

Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem edit

The Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem states that every bounded sequence of real numbers has a convergent subsequence. Again, this theorem is equivalent to the other forms of completeness given above.

The intermediate value theorem edit

The intermediate value theorem states that every continuous function that attains both negative and positive values has a root. This is a consequence of the least upper bound property, but it can also be used to prove the least upper bound property if treated as an axiom. (The definition of continuity does not depend on any form of completeness, so there is no circularity: what is meant is that the intermediate value theorem and the least upper bound property are equivalent statements.)

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Körner, Thomas William (2004). A companion to analysis: a second first and first second course in analysis. AMS Chelsea. ISBN 9780821834473.

Further reading edit

completeness, real, numbers, confused, with, completeness, logic, completeness, property, real, numbers, that, intuitively, implies, that, there, gaps, dedekind, terminology, missing, points, real, number, line, this, contrasts, with, rational, numbers, whose,. Not to be confused with Completeness logic Completeness is a property of the real numbers that intuitively implies that there are no gaps in Dedekind s terminology or missing points in the real number line This contrasts with the rational numbers whose corresponding number line has a gap at each irrational value In the decimal number system completeness is equivalent to the statement that any infinite string of decimal digits is actually a decimal representation for some real number Depending on the construction of the real numbers used completeness may take the form of an axiom the completeness axiom or may be a theorem proven from the construction There are many equivalent forms of completeness the most prominent being Dedekind completeness and Cauchy completeness completeness as a metric space Contents 1 Forms of completeness 1 1 Least upper bound property 1 2 Dedekind completeness 1 3 Cauchy completeness 1 4 Nested intervals theorem 1 5 The open induction principle 1 6 Monotone convergence theorem 1 7 Bolzano Weierstrass theorem 1 8 The intermediate value theorem 2 See also 3 References 4 Further readingForms of completeness editThe real numbers can be defined synthetically as an ordered field satisfying some version of the completeness axiom Different versions of this axiom are all equivalent in the sense that any ordered field that satisfies one form of completeness satisfies all of them apart from Cauchy completeness and nested intervals theorem which are strictly weaker in that there are non Archimedean fields that are ordered and Cauchy complete When the real numbers are instead constructed using a model completeness becomes a theorem or collection of theorems Least upper bound property edit Main article Least upper bound property The least upper bound property states that every nonempty subset of real numbers having an upper bound must have a least upper bound or supremum in the set of real numbers The rational number line Q does not have the least upper bound property An example is the subset of rational numbers S x Q x 2 lt 2 displaystyle S x in mathbb Q mid x 2 lt 2 nbsp This set has an upper bound However this set has no least upper bound in Q the least upper bound as a subset of the reals would be 2 but it does not exist in Q For any upper bound x Q there is another upper bound y Q with y lt x For instance take x 1 5 then x is certainly an upper bound of S since x is positive and x2 2 25 2 that is no element of S is larger than x However we can choose a smaller upper bound say y 1 45 this is also an upper bound of S for the same reasons but it is smaller than x so x is not a least upper bound of S We can proceed similarly to find an upper bound of S that is smaller than y say z 1 42 etc such that we never find a least upper bound of S in Q The least upper bound property can be generalized to the setting of partially ordered sets See completeness order theory Dedekind completeness edit See Dedekind completeness for more general concepts bearing this name Dedekind completeness is the property that every Dedekind cut of the real numbers is generated by a real number In a synthetic approach to the real numbers this is the version of completeness that is most often included as an axiom The rational number line Q is not Dedekind complete An example is the Dedekind cut L x Q x 2 2 x lt 0 displaystyle L x in mathbb Q mid x 2 leq 2 vee x lt 0 nbsp R x Q x 2 2 x gt 0 displaystyle R x in mathbb Q mid x 2 geq 2 wedge x gt 0 nbsp L does not have a maximum and R does not have a minimum so this cut is not generated by a rational number There is a construction of the real numbers based on the idea of using Dedekind cuts of rational numbers to name real numbers e g the cut L R described above would name 2 displaystyle sqrt 2 nbsp If one were to repeat the construction of real numbers with Dedekind cuts i e close the set of real numbers by adding all possible Dedekind cuts one would obtain no additional numbers because the real numbers are already Dedekind complete Cauchy completeness edit Cauchy completeness is the statement that every Cauchy sequence of real numbers converges to a real number The rational number line Q is not Cauchy complete An example is the following sequence of rational numbers 3 3 1 3 14 3 142 3 1416 displaystyle 3 quad 3 1 quad 3 14 quad 3 142 quad 3 1416 quad ldots nbsp Here the nth term in the sequence is the nth decimal approximation for pi Though this is a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers it does not converge to any rational number In this real number line this sequence converges to pi Cauchy completeness is related to the construction of the real numbers using Cauchy sequences Essentially this method defines a real number to be the limit of a Cauchy sequence of rational numbers In mathematical analysis Cauchy completeness can be generalized to a notion of completeness for any metric space See complete metric space For an ordered field Cauchy completeness is weaker than the other forms of completeness on this page But Cauchy completeness and the Archimedean property taken together are equivalent to the others Nested intervals theorem edit Main article Nested intervals The nested interval theorem is another form of completeness Let In an bn be a sequence of closed intervals and suppose that these intervals are nested in the sense that I 1 I 2 I 3 displaystyle I 1 supset I 2 supset I 3 supset cdots nbsp Moreover assume that bn an 0 as n The nested interval theorem states that the intersection of all of the intervals In contains exactly one point The rational number line does not satisfy the nested interval theorem For example the sequence whose terms are derived from the digits of pi in the suggested way 3 4 3 1 3 2 3 14 3 15 3 141 3 142 displaystyle 3 4 supset 3 1 3 2 supset 3 14 3 15 supset 3 141 3 142 supset cdots nbsp is a nested sequence of closed intervals in the rational numbers whose intersection is empty In the real numbers the intersection of these intervals contains the number pi Nested intervals theorem shares the same logical status as Cauchy completeness in this spectrum of expressions of completeness In other words nested intervals theorem by itself is weaker than other forms of completeness although taken together with Archimedean property it is equivalent to the others The open induction principle edit The open induction principle states that a non empty open subset S displaystyle S nbsp of the interval a b displaystyle a b nbsp must be equal to the entire interval if for any r a b displaystyle r in a b nbsp we have that a r S displaystyle a r subset S nbsp implies a r S displaystyle a r subset S nbsp The open induction principle can be shown to be equivalent to Dedekind completeness for arbitrary ordered sets under the order topology using proofs by contradiction In weaker foundations such as in constructive analysis where the law of the excluded middle does not hold the full form of the least upper bound property fails for the Dedekind reals while the open induction property remains true in most models following from Brouwer s bar theorem and is strong enough to give short proofs of key theorems Monotone convergence theorem edit The monotone convergence theorem described as the fundamental axiom of analysis by Korner 1 states that every nondecreasing bounded sequence of real numbers converges This can be viewed as a special case of the least upper bound property but it can also be used fairly directly to prove the Cauchy completeness of the real numbers Bolzano Weierstrass theorem edit The Bolzano Weierstrass theorem states that every bounded sequence of real numbers has a convergent subsequence Again this theorem is equivalent to the other forms of completeness given above The intermediate value theorem edit The intermediate value theorem states that every continuous function that attains both negative and positive values has a root This is a consequence of the least upper bound property but it can also be used to prove the least upper bound property if treated as an axiom The definition of continuity does not depend on any form of completeness so there is no circularity what is meant is that the intermediate value theorem and the least upper bound property are equivalent statements See also editList of real analysis topicsReferences edit Korner Thomas William 2004 A companion to analysis a second first and first second course in analysis AMS Chelsea ISBN 9780821834473 Further reading editAliprantis Charalambos D Burkinshaw Owen 1998 Principles of real analysis 3rd ed Academic ISBN 0 12 050257 7 Browder Andrew 1996 Mathematical Analysis An Introduction Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics New York City Springer Verlag ISBN 0 387 94614 4 Bartle Robert G Sherbert Donald R 2000 Introduction to Real Analysis 3rd ed New York City John Wiley and Sons ISBN 0 471 32148 6 Abbott Stephen 2001 Understanding Analysis Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics New York Springer Verlag ISBN 0 387 95060 5 Rudin Walter 1976 Principles of Mathematical Analysis Walter Rudin Student Series in Advanced Mathematics 3rd ed McGraw Hill ISBN 9780070542358 Dangello Frank Seyfried Michael 1999 Introductory Real Analysis Brooks Cole ISBN 9780395959336 Bressoud David 2007 A Radical Approach to Real Analysis MAA ISBN 978 0 88385 747 2 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Completeness of the real numbers amp oldid 1176349291, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.