fbpx
Wikipedia

Normal function

In axiomatic set theory, a function f : Ord → Ord is called normal (or a normal function) if it is continuous (with respect to the order topology) and strictly monotonically increasing. This is equivalent to the following two conditions:

  1. For every limit ordinal γ (i.e. γ is neither zero nor a successor), it is the case that f (γ) = sup{f (ν) : ν < γ}.
  2. For all ordinals α < β, it is the case that f (α) < f (β).

Examples edit

A simple normal function is given by f (α) = 1 + α (see ordinal arithmetic). But f (α) = α + 1 is not normal because it is not continuous at any limit ordinal; that is, the inverse image of the one-point open set {λ + 1} is the set {λ}, which is not open when λ is a limit ordinal. If β is a fixed ordinal, then the functions f (α) = β + α, f (α) = β × α (for β ≥ 1), and f (α) = βα (for β ≥ 2) are all normal.

More important examples of normal functions are given by the aleph numbers  , which connect ordinal and cardinal numbers, and by the beth numbers  .

Properties edit

If f is normal, then for any ordinal α,

f (α) ≥ α.[1]

Proof: If not, choose γ minimal such that f (γ) < γ. Since f is strictly monotonically increasing, f (f (γ)) < f (γ), contradicting minimality of γ.

Furthermore, for any non-empty set S of ordinals, we have

f (sup S) = sup f (S).

Proof: "≥" follows from the monotonicity of f and the definition of the supremum. For "", set δ = sup S and consider three cases:

  • if δ = 0, then S = {0} and sup f (S) = f (0);
  • if δ = ν + 1 is a successor, then there exists s in S with ν < s, so that δs. Therefore, f (δ) ≤ f (s), which implies f (δ) ≤ sup f (S);
  • if δ is a nonzero limit, pick any ν < δ, and an s in S such that ν < s (possible since δ = sup S). Therefore, f (ν) < f (s) so that f (ν) < sup f (S), yielding f (δ) = sup {f (ν) : ν < δ} ≤ sup f (S), as desired.

Every normal function f has arbitrarily large fixed points; see the fixed-point lemma for normal functions for a proof. One can create a normal function f ′ : Ord → Ord, called the derivative of f, such that f ′(α) is the α-th fixed point of f.[2] For a hierarchy of normal functions, see Veblen functions.

Notes edit

  1. ^ Johnstone 1987, Exercise 6.9, p. 77
  2. ^ Johnstone 1987, Exercise 6.9, p. 77

References edit

  • Johnstone, Peter (1987), Notes on Logic and Set Theory, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 978-0-521-33692-5

normal, function, this, article, relies, largely, entirely, single, source, relevant, discussion, found, talk, page, please, help, improve, this, article, introducing, citations, additional, sources, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar, jstor, marc. This article relies largely or entirely on a single source Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page Please help improve this article by introducing citations to additional sources Find sources Normal function news newspapers books scholar JSTOR March 2024 In axiomatic set theory a function f Ord Ord is called normal or a normal function if it is continuous with respect to the order topology and strictly monotonically increasing This is equivalent to the following two conditions For every limit ordinal g i e g is neither zero nor a successor it is the case that f g sup f n n lt g For all ordinals a lt b it is the case that f a lt f b Contents 1 Examples 2 Properties 3 Notes 4 ReferencesExamples editA simple normal function is given by f a 1 a see ordinal arithmetic But f a a 1 is not normal because it is not continuous at any limit ordinal that is the inverse image of the one point open set l 1 is the set l which is not open when l is a limit ordinal If b is a fixed ordinal then the functions f a b a f a b a for b 1 and f a ba for b 2 are all normal More important examples of normal functions are given by the aleph numbers f a ℵ a displaystyle f alpha aleph alpha nbsp which connect ordinal and cardinal numbers and by the beth numbers f a ℶ a displaystyle f alpha beth alpha nbsp Properties editIf f is normal then for any ordinal a f a a 1 Proof If not choose g minimal such that f g lt g Since f is strictly monotonically increasing f f g lt f g contradicting minimality of g Furthermore for any non empty set S of ordinals we have f sup S sup f S Proof follows from the monotonicity of f and the definition of the supremum For set d sup S and consider three cases if d 0 then S 0 and sup f S f 0 if d n 1 is a successor then there exists s in S with n lt s so that d s Therefore f d f s which implies f d sup f S if d is a nonzero limit pick any n lt d and an s in S such that n lt s possible since d sup S Therefore f n lt f s so that f n lt sup f S yielding f d sup f n n lt d sup f S as desired Every normal function f has arbitrarily large fixed points see the fixed point lemma for normal functions for a proof One can create a normal function f Ord Ord called the derivative of f such that f a is the a th fixed point of f 2 For a hierarchy of normal functions see Veblen functions Notes edit Johnstone 1987 Exercise 6 9 p 77 Johnstone 1987 Exercise 6 9 p 77References editJohnstone Peter 1987 Notes on Logic and Set Theory Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 33692 5 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Normal function amp oldid 1220430750, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.