fbpx
Wikipedia

Deterrence theory

Deterrence theory refers to the scholarship and practice of how threats or limited force by one party can convince another party to refrain from initiating some other course of action. The topic gained increased prominence as a military strategy during the Cold War with regard to the use of nuclear weapons and is related to but distinct from the concept of mutual assured destruction, according to which a full-scale nuclear attack on a power with second-strike capability would devastate both parties. The central problem of deterrence revolves around how to credibly threaten military action or nuclear punishment on the adversary despite its costs to the deterrer.[1]

USS Growler, one of two submarines designed to provide a nuclear deterrence using cruise missiles with a 500-mile (800 km) range—placed on patrol by starting to carry the Regulus I missile (shown at Pier 86 in New York, its home as a museum ship)

Deterrence is widely defined as any use of threats (implicit or explicit) or limited force intended to dissuade an actor from taking an action (i.e. maintain the status quo).[2][3] Deterrence is unlike compellence, which is the attempt to get an actor (such as a state) to take an action (i.e. alter the status quo).[4][5][3] Both are forms of coercion. Compellence has been characterized as harder to successfully implement than deterrence.[5][6] Deterrence also tends to be distinguished from defense or the use of full force in wartime.[2]

Deterrence is most likely to be successful when a prospective attacker believes that the probability of success is low and the costs of attack are high.[7] Central problems of deterrence include the credible communication of threats[8][3] and assurance.[9] Deterrence does not necessarily require military superiority.[10][11]

"General deterrence" is considered successful when an actor who might otherwise take an action refrains from doing so due to the consequences that the deterrer is perceived likely to take.[12] "Immediate deterrence" is considered successful when an actor seriously contemplating immediate military force or action refrains from doing so.[12] Scholars distinguish between "extended deterrence" (the protection of allies) and "direct deterrence" (protection of oneself).[11][13] Rational deterrence theory holds that an attacker will be deterred if they believe that[14]:

(Probability of deterrer carrying out deterrent threat × Costs if threat carried out) > (Probability of the attacker accomplishing the action × Benefits of the action)

This model is frequently simplified in game-theoretic terms as:

Costs × P(Costs) > Benefits × P(Benefits)

History edit

By November 1945 general Curtis LeMay, who led American air raids on Japan during World War II, was thinking about how the next war would be fought. He said in a speech that month to the Ohio Society of New York that since "No air attack, once it is launched, can be completely stopped", his country needed an air force that could immediately retaliate: "If we are prepared it may never come. It is not immediately conceivable that any nation will dare to attack us if we are prepared".[15]

Most of the innovative work on deterrence theory occurred from the late 1940s to mid-1960s.[16] Historically, scholarship on deterrence has tended to focus on nuclear deterrence.[17] Since the end of the Cold War, there has been an extension of deterrence scholarship to areas that are not specifically about nuclear weapons.[3]

A distinction is sometimes made between nuclear deterrence and "conventional deterrence."[18][19][20][21]

The two most prominent deterrent strategies are "denial" (denying the attacker the benefits of attack) and "punishment" (inflicting costs on the attacker).[10]

Concept edit

The use of military threats as a means to deter international crises and war has been a central topic of international security research for at least 2000 years.[22]

The concept of deterrence can be defined as the use of threats in limited force by one party to convince another party to refrain from initiating some course of action.[23][2] In Arms and Influence (1966), Schelling offers a broader definition of deterrence, as he defines it as "to prevent from action by fear of consequences."[5] Glenn Snyder also offers a broad definition of deterrence, as he argues that deterrence involves both the threat of sanction and the promise of reward.[24]

A threat serves as a deterrent to the extent that it convinces its target not to carry out the intended action because of the costs and losses that target would incur. In international security, a policy of deterrence generally refers to threats of military retaliation directed by the leaders of one state to the leaders of another in an attempt to prevent the other state from resorting to the use of military force in pursuit of its foreign policy goals.

As outlined by Huth,[23] a policy of deterrence can fit into two broad categories: preventing an armed attack against a state's own territory (known as direct deterrence) or preventing an armed attack against another state (known as extended deterrence). Situations of direct deterrence often occur if there is a territorial dispute between neighboring states in which major powers like the United States do not directly intervene. On the other hand, situations of extended deterrence often occur when a great power becomes involved. The latter case has generated most interest in academic literature. Building on the two broad categories, Huth goes on to outline that deterrence policies may be implemented in response to a pressing short-term threat (known as immediate deterrence) or as strategy to prevent a military conflict or short-term threat from arising (known as general deterrence).

A successful deterrence policy must be considered in military terms but also political terms: International relations, foreign policy and diplomacy. In military terms, deterrence success refers to preventing state leaders from issuing military threats and actions that escalate peacetime diplomatic and military co-operation into a crisis or militarized confrontation that threatens armed conflict and possibly war. The prevention of crises of wars, however, is not the only aim of deterrence. In addition, defending states must be able to resist the political and the military demands of a potential attacking nation. If armed conflict is avoided at the price of diplomatic concessions to the maximum demands of the potential attacking nation under the threat of war, it cannot be claimed that deterrence has succeeded.

Furthermore, as Jentleson et al.[25] argue, two key sets of factors for successful deterrence are important: a defending state strategy that balances credible coercion and deft diplomacy consistent with the three criteria of proportionality, reciprocity, and coercive credibility and minimizes international and domestic constraints and the extent of an attacking state's vulnerability as shaped by its domestic political and economic conditions. In broad terms, a state wishing to implement a strategy of deterrence is most likely to succeed if the costs of noncompliance that it can impose on and the benefits of compliance it can offer to another state are greater than the benefits of noncompliance and the costs of compliance.

Deterrence theory holds that nuclear weapons are intended to deter other states from attacking with their nuclear weapons, through the promise of retaliation and possibly mutually assured destruction. Nuclear deterrence can also be applied to an attack by conventional forces. For example, the doctrine of massive retaliation threatened to launch US nuclear weapons in response to Soviet attacks.

A successful nuclear deterrent requires a country to preserve its ability to retaliate by responding before its own weapons are destroyed or ensuring a second-strike capability. A nuclear deterrent is sometimes composed of a nuclear triad, as in the case of the nuclear weapons owned by the United States, Russia, the China and India. Other countries, such as the United Kingdom and France, have only sea-based and air-based nuclear weapons.

Proportionality edit

Jentleson et al. provides further detail in relation to those factors.[25] Proportionality refers to the relationship between the defending state's scope and nature of the objectives being pursued and the instruments available for use to pursue them. The more the defending state demands of another state, the higher that state's costs of compliance and the greater need for the defending state's strategy to increase the costs of noncompliance and the benefits of compliance. That is a challenge, as deterrence is by definition a strategy of limited means. George (1991) goes on to explain that deterrence sometimes goes beyond threats to the actual use of military force, but if force is actually used, it must be limited and fall short of full-scale use to succeed.[26]

The main source of disproportionality is an objective that goes beyond policy change to regime change, which has been seen in Libya, Iraq, and North Korea. There, defending states have sought to change the leadership of a state and to policy changes relating primarily to their nuclear weapons programs.

Reciprocity edit

Secondly, Jentleson et al.[25] outlines that reciprocity involves an explicit understanding of linkage between the defending state's carrots and the attacking state's concessions. The balance lies in not offering too little, too late or for too much in return and not offering too much, too soon, or for too little return.

Coercive credibility edit

Finally, coercive credibility requires that in addition to calculations about costs and benefits of co-operation, the defending state convincingly conveys to the attacking state that failure to co-operate has consequences. Threats, uses of force, and other coercive instruments such as economic sanctions must be sufficiently credible to raise the attacking state's perceived costs of noncompliance. A defending state having a superior military capability or economic strength in itself is not enough to ensure credibility. Indeed, all three elements of a balanced deterrence strategy are more likely to be achieved if other major international actors like the UN or NATO are supportive, and opposition within the defending state's domestic politics is limited.

The other important considerations outlined by Jentleson et al.[25] that must be taken into consideration is the domestic political and economic conditions in the attacking state affecting its vulnerability to deterrence policies and the attacking state's ability to compensate unfavourable power balances. The first factor is whether internal political support and regime security are better served by defiance, or there are domestic political gains to be made from improving relations with the defending state. The second factor is an economic calculation of the costs that military force, sanctions, and other coercive instruments can impose and the benefits that trade and other economic incentives may carry. That is partly a function of the strength and flexibility of the attacking state's domestic economy and its capacity to absorb or counter the costs being imposed. The third factor is the role of elites and other key domestic political figures within the attacking state. To the extent that such actors' interests are threatened with the defending state's demands, they act to prevent or block the defending state's demands.

Rational deterrence theory edit

One approach to theorizing about deterrence has entailed the use of rational choice and game-theoretic models of decision making (see game theory). Rational deterrence theory entails:[27]

  1. Rationality: actors are rational[11]
  2. Unitary actor assumption: actors are understood as unitary[11]
  3. Dyads: interactions tend to be between dyads (or triads) of states
  4. Strategic interactions: actors consider the choices of other actors[11]
  5. Cost-benefit calculations: outcomes reflect actors' cost-benefit calculations[11][28]

Deterrence theorists have consistently argued that deterrence success is more likely if a defending state's deterrent threat is credible to an attacking state. Huth[23] outlines that a threat is considered credible if the defending state possesses both the military capabilities to inflict substantial costs on an attacking state in an armed conflict, and the attacking state believes that the defending state is resolved to use its available military forces. Huth[23] goes on to explain the four key factors for consideration under rational deterrence theory: the military balance, signaling and bargaining power, reputations for resolve, interests at stake.

The American economist Thomas Schelling brought his background in game theory to the subject of studying international deterrence. Schelling's (1966) classic work on deterrence presents the concept that military strategy can no longer be defined as the science of military victory. Instead, it is argued that military strategy was now equally, if not more, the art of coercion, intimidation and deterrence.[29] Schelling says the capacity to harm another state is now used as a motivating factor for other states to avoid it and influence another state's behavior. To be coercive or deter another state, violence must be anticipated and avoidable by accommodation. It can therefore be summarized that the use of the power to hurt as bargaining power is the foundation of deterrence theory and is most successful when it is held in reserve.[29]

In an article celebrating Schelling's Nobel Memorial Prize for Economics,[30] Michael Kinsley, Washington Post op‑ed columnist and one of Schelling's former students, anecdotally summarizes Schelling's reorientation of game theory thus: "[Y]ou're standing at the edge of a cliff, chained by the ankle to someone else. You'll be released, and one of you will get a large prize, as soon as the other gives in. How do you persuade the other guy to give in, when the only method at your disposal—threatening to push him off the cliff—would doom you both? Answer: You start dancing, closer and closer to the edge. That way, you don't have to convince him that you would do something totally irrational: plunge him and yourself off the cliff. You just have to convince him that you are prepared to take a higher risk than he is of accidentally falling off the cliff. If you can do that, you win."

Military balance edit

Deterrence is often directed against state leaders who have specific territorial goals that they seek to attain either by seizing disputed territory in a limited military attack or by occupying disputed territory after the decisive defeat of the adversary's armed forces. In either case, the strategic orientation of potential attacking states generally is for the short term and is driven by concerns about military cost and effectiveness. For successful deterrence, defending states need the military capacity to respond quickly and strongly to a range of contingencies. Deterrence often fails if either a defending state or an attacking state underestimates or overestimates the other's ability to undertake a particular course of action.

Signaling and bargaining power edit

The central problem for a state that seeks to communicate a credible deterrent threat by diplomatic or military actions is that all defending states have an incentive to act as if they are determined to resist an attack in the hope that the attacking state will back away from military conflict with a seemingly resolved adversary. If all defending states have such incentives, potential attacking states may discount statements made by defending states along with any movement of military forces as merely bluffs. In that regard, rational deterrence theorists have argued that costly signals are required to communicate the credibility of a defending state's resolve. Those are actions and statements that clearly increase the risk of a military conflict and also increase the costs of backing down from a deterrent threat. States that bluff are unwilling to cross a certain threshold of threat and military action for fear of committing themselves to an armed conflict.

Reputations for resolve edit

There are three different arguments that have been developed in relation to the role of reputations in influencing deterrence outcomes. The first argument focuses on a defending state's past behavior in international disputes and crises, which creates strong beliefs in a potential attacking state about the defending state's expected behaviour in future conflicts. The credibilities of a defending state's policies are arguably linked over time, and reputations for resolve have a powerful causal impact on an attacking state's decision whether to challenge either general or immediate deterrence. The second approach argues that reputations have a limited impact on deterrence outcomes because the credibility of deterrence is heavily determined by the specific configuration of military capabilities, interests at stake, and political constraints faced by a defending state in a given situation of attempted deterrence. The argument of that school of thought is that potential attacking states are not likely to draw strong inferences about a defending states resolve from prior conflicts because potential attacking states do not believe that a defending state's past behaviour is a reliable predictor of future behavior. The third approach is a middle ground between the first two approaches and argues that potential attacking states are likely to draw reputational inferences about resolve from the past behaviour of defending states only under certain conditions. The insight is the expectation that decisionmakers use only certain types of information when drawing inferences about reputations, and an attacking state updates and revises its beliefs when a defending state's unanticipated behavior cannot be explained by case-specific variables.

An example shows that the problem extends to the perception of the third parties as well as main adversaries and underlies the way in which attempts at deterrence can fail and even backfire if the assumptions about the others' perceptions are incorrect.[31]

Interests at stake edit

Although costly signaling and bargaining power are more well established arguments in rational deterrence theory, the interests of defending states are not as well known. Attacking states may look beyond the short-term bargaining tactics of a defending state and seek to determine what interests are at stake for the defending state that would justify the risks of a military conflict. The argument is that defending states that have greater interests at stake in a dispute are more resolved to use force and more willing to endure military losses to secure those interests. Even less well-established arguments are the specific interests that are more salient to state leaders such as military interests and economic interests.

Furthermore, Huth[23] argues that both supporters and critics of rational deterrence theory agree that an unfavorable assessment of the domestic and international status quo by state leaders can undermine or severely test the success of deterrence. In a rational choice approach, if the expected utility of not using force is reduced by a declining status quo position, deterrence failure is more likely since the alternative option of using force becomes relatively more attractive.

Tripwires edit

International relations scholars Dan Reiter and Paul Poast have argued that so-called "tripwires" do not deter aggression.[32] Tripwires entail that small forces are deployed abroad with the assumption that an attack on them will trigger a greater deployment of forces.[32] Dan Altman has argued that tripwires do work to deter aggression, citing the Western deployment of forces to Berlin in 1948–1949 to deter Soviet aggression as a successful example.[33]

A 2022 study by Brian Blankenship and Erik Lin-Greenberg found that high-resolve, low-capability signals (such as tripwires) were not viewed as more reassuring to allies than low-resolve, high-capability alternatives (such as forces stationed offshore). Their study cast doubt on the reassuring value of tripwires.[34]

Nuclear deterrence theory edit

In 1966, Schelling[29] is prescriptive in outlining the impact of the development of nuclear weapons in the analysis of military power and deterrence. In his analysis, before the widespread use of assured second strike capability, or immediate reprisal, in the form of SSBN submarines, Schelling argues that nuclear weapons give nations the potential to destroy their enemies but also the rest of humanity without drawing immediate reprisal because of the lack of a conceivable defense system and the speed with which nuclear weapons can be deployed. A nation's credible threat of such severe damage empowers their deterrence policies and fuels political coercion and military deadlock, which can produce proxy warfare.

According to Kenneth Waltz, there are three requirements for successful nuclear deterrence:[35]

  1. Part of a state's nuclear arsenal must appear to be able to survive an attack by the adversary and be used for a retaliatory second strike
  2. The state must not respond to false alarms of a strike by the adversary
  3. The state must maintain command and control

The stability–instability paradox is a key concept in rational deterrence theory. It states that when two countries each have nuclear weapons, the probability of a direct war between them greatly decreases, but the probability of minor or indirect conflicts between them increases.[36][37][38] This occurs because rational actors want to avoid nuclear wars, and thus they neither start major conflicts nor allow minor conflicts to escalate into major conflicts—thus making it safe to engage in minor conflicts. For instance, during the Cold War the United States and the Soviet Union never engaged each other in warfare, but fought proxy wars in Korea, Vietnam, Angola, the Middle East, Nicaragua and Afghanistan and spent substantial amounts of money and manpower on gaining relative influence over the third world.[39]

Bernard Brodie wrote in 1959 that a credible nuclear deterrent must be always ready but never used.[40][a]

Scholars have debated whether having a superior nuclear arsenal provides a deterrent against other nuclear-armed states with smaller arsenals. Matthew Kroenig has argued that states with nuclear superiority are more likely to win nuclear crises,[41][42] whereas Todd Sechser, Matthew Fuhrmann and David C. Logan have challenged this assertion.[43][44][45] A 2023 study found that a state with nuclear weapons is less likely to be targeted by non-nuclear states, but that a state with nuclear weapons is not less likely to target other nuclear states in low-level conflict.[46] A 2022 study by Kyungwon Suh suggests that nuclear superiority may not reduce the likelihood that nuclear opponents will initiate nuclear crises.[47]

Proponents of nuclear deterrence theory argue that while newly nuclear-armed states may pose a short- or medium-term risk, but that "nuclear learning" occurs over time as states learn to live with new nuclear-armed states.[48][49] Mark S. Bell and Nicholas L. Miller have however argued that there is a weak theoretical and empirical basis for notions of "nuclear learning."[50]

Stages of US policy of deterrence edit

The US policy of deterrence during the Cold War underwent significant variations.

Containment edit

The early stages of the Cold War were generally characterized by the containment of communism, an aggressive stance on behalf of the US especially on developing nations under its sphere of influence. The period was characterized by numerous proxy wars throughout most of the globe, particularly Africa, Asia, Central America, and South America. One notable conflict was the Korean War. George F. Kennan, who is taken to be the founder of this policy in his Long Telegram, asserted that he never advocated military intervention, merely economic support, and that his ideas were misinterpreted as espoused by the general public.

Détente edit

With the US drawdown from Vietnam, the normalization of US relations with China, and the Sino-Soviet Split, the policy of containment was abandoned and a new policy of détente was established, with peaceful co-existence was sought between the United States and the Soviet Union. Although all of those factors contributed to this shift, the most important factor was probably the rough parity achieved in stockpiling nuclear weapons with the clear capability of mutual assured destruction (MAD). Therefore, the period of détente was characterized by a general reduction in the tension between the Soviet Union and the United States and a thawing of the Cold War, which lasted from the late 1960s until the start of the 1980s. The doctrine of mutual nuclear deterrence then characterized relations between the United States and the Soviet Union and relations with Russia until the onset of the New Cold War in the early 2010s. Since then, relations have been less clear.

Reagan era edit

A third shift occurred with US President Ronald Reagan's arms build-up during the 1980s. Reagan attempted to justify the policy by concerns of growing Soviet influence in Latin America and the post-1979 revolutionary government of Iran. Similar to the old policy of containment, the US funded several proxy wars, including support for Saddam Hussein of Iraq during the Iran–Iraq War, support for the mujahideen in Afghanistan, who were fighting for independence from the Soviet Union, and several anticommunist movements in Latin America such as the overthrow of the Sandinista government in Nicaragua. The funding of the Contras in Nicaragua led to the Iran-Contra Affair, while overt support led to a ruling from the International Court of Justice against the United States in Nicaragua v. United States.

The final expression of the full impact of deterrence during the cold war can be seen in the agreement between Reagan and Mikhail Gorbachev in 1985. They "agreed that a nuclear war cannot be won and must never be fought. Recognizing that any conflict between the USSR and the U.S. could have catastrophic consequences, they emphasized the importance of preventing any war between them, whether nuclear or conventional. They will not seek to achieve military superiority.".

While the army was dealing with the breakup of the Soviet Union and the spread of nuclear technology to other nations beyond the United States and Russia, the concept of deterrence took on a broader multinational dimension. The US policy on deterrence after the Cold War was outlined in 1995 in the document called "Essentials of Post–Cold War Deterrence".[51] It explains that while relations with Russia continue to follow the traditional characteristics of MAD, but the US policy of deterrence towards nations with minor nuclear capabilities should ensure by threats of immense retaliation (or even pre-emptive action) not to threaten the United States, its interests, or allies. The document explains that such threats must also be used to ensure that nations without nuclear technology refrain from developing nuclear weapons and that a universal ban precludes any nation from maintaining chemical or biological weapons. The current tensions with Iran and North Korea over their nuclear programs are caused partly by the continuation of the policy of deterrence.

Post-Cold War period edit

By the beginning of the 2022 Russian invasion of Ukraine, many western hawks expressed the view that deterrence worked in that war but only in one way - in favor of Russia. Former US security advisor, John Bolton, said: Deterrence is working in the Ukraine crisis, just not for the right side. The United States and its allies failed to deter Russia from invading. The purpose of deterrence strategy is to prevent the conflict entirely, and there Washington failed badly. On the other hand, Russian deterrence is enjoying spectacular success. Russia has convinced the West that even a whisper of NATO military action in Ukraine would bring disastrous consequences. Putin threatens, blusters, uses the word “nuclear,” and the West wilts.[52]

When Elon Musk prevented Ukraine from carrying drone attacks on the Russian Black Sea fleet by denying to enable needed Starlink communications in Crimea,[53] Anne Applebaum argued Musk had been deterred by Russia after the country's ambassador warned him an attack on Crimea would be met with a nuclear response.[54] Later Ukrainian attacks on the same fleet using a different communications system also caused deterrence, this time to the Russian Navy.[54]

Timo S. Koster who served at NATO as Director of Defence Policy & Capabilities similarly argued: A massacre is taking place in Europe and the strongest military alliance in the world is staying out of it. We are deterred and Russia is not.[55] Philip Breedlove, a retired four-star U.S. Air Force general and a former SACEUR, said that Western fears about nuclear weapons and World War III have left it "fully deterred" and Putin "completely undeterred." The West have "ceded the initiative to the enemy."[56] No attempt was made by NATO to deter Moscow with the threat of military force, wondered another expert. To the contrary, it was Russia’s deterrence that proved to be successful.[57]

Cyber deterrence edit

Since the early 2000s, there has been an increased focus on cyber deterrence. Cyber deterrence has two meanings:[58]

  1. The use of cyber actions to deter other states
  2. The deterrence of an adversary's cyber operations

Scholars have debated how cyber capabilities alter traditional understandings of deterrence, given that it may be harder to attribute responsibility for cyber attacks, the barriers to entry may be lower, the risks and costs may be lower for actors who conduct cyber attacks, it may be harder to signal and interpret intentions, the advantage of offense over defense, and weak actors and non-state actors can develop considerable cyber capabilities.[58][59][60][61] Scholars have also debated the feasibility of launching highly damaging cyber attacks and engaging in destructive cyber warfare, with most scholars expressing skepticism that cyber capabilities have enhanced the ability of states to launch highly destructive attacks.[62][63][64] The most prominent cyber attack to date is the Stuxnet attack on Iran's nuclear program.[62][63] By 2019, the only publicly acknowledged case of a cyber attack causing a power outage was the 2015 Ukraine power grid hack.[65]

There are various ways to engage in cyber deterrence:[58][59][60]

  • Denial: preventing adversaries from achieving military objectives by defending against them[61]
  • Punishment: the imposition of costs on the adversary
  • Norms: the establishment and maintenance of norms that establish appropriate standards of behavior[66][67]
  • Escalation: raising the probability that costs will be imposed on the adversary[68]
  • Entanglement and interdependence: interdependence between actors can have a deterrent effect[59][64]

There is a risk of unintended escalation in cyberspace due to difficulties in discerning the intent of attackers,[69][70] and complexities in state-hacker relationships.[71] According to political scientists Joseph Brown and Tanisha Fazal, states frequently neither confirm nor deny responsibility for cyber operations so that they can avoid the escalatory risks (that come with public credit) while also signaling that they have cyber capabilities and resolve (which can be achieved if intelligence agencies and governments believe they were responsible).[68]

According to Lennart Maschmeyer, cyber weapons have limited coercive effectiveness due to a trilemma "whereby speed, intensity, and control are negatively correlated. These constraints pose a trilemma for actors because a gain in one variable tends to produce losses across the other two variables."[72]

Intrawar deterrence edit

Intrawar deterrence is deterrence within a war context. It means that war has broken out but actors still seek to deter certain forms of behavior. In the words of Caitlin Talmadge, "intra-war deterrence failures... can be thought of as causing wars to get worse in some way."[73] Examples of intrawar deterrence include deterring adversaries from resorting to nuclear, chemical and biological weapons attacks or attacking civilian populations indiscriminately.[74] Broadly, it involves any prevention of escalation.[75]

Criticism edit

Deterrence theory has been criticized by numerous scholars for various reasons, the most basic being skepticism that decision makers are rational. A prominent strain of criticism argues that rational deterrence theory is contradicted by frequent deterrence failures, which may be attributed to misperceptions.[76] Scholars have also argued that leaders do not behave in ways that are consistent with the predictions of nuclear deterrence theory.[77][78][79] Scholars have also argued that rational deterrence theory does not grapple sufficiently with emotions and psychological biases that make accidents, loss of self-control, and loss of control over others likely.[80][81]

Advocates for nuclear disarmament, such as Global Zero, have criticized nuclear deterrence theory. Sam Nunn, William Perry, Henry Kissinger, and George Shultz have all called upon governments to embrace the vision of a world free of nuclear weapons, and created the Nuclear Security Project to advance that agenda.[82] In 2010, the four were featured in a documentary film entitled Nuclear Tipping Point where proposed steps to achieve nuclear disarmament.[83][84] Kissinger has argued, "The classical notion of deterrence was that there was some consequences before which aggressors and evildoers would recoil. In a world of suicide bombers, that calculation doesn't operate in any comparable way."[85] Shultz said, "If you think of the people who are doing suicide attacks, and people like that get a nuclear weapon, they are almost by definition not deterrable."[86]

Paul Nitze argued in 1994 that nuclear weapons were obsolete in the "new world disorder" after the dissolution of the Soviet Union, and he advocated reliance on precision guided munitions to secure a permanent military advantage over future adversaries.[87]

As opposed to the extreme mutually assured destruction form of deterrence, the concept of minimum deterrence in which a state possesses no more nuclear weapons than is necessary to deter an adversary from attacking is presently the most common form of deterrence practiced by nuclear weapon states, such as China, India, Pakistan, Britain, and France.[88] Pursuing minimal deterrence during arms negotiations between the United States and Russia allows each state to make nuclear stockpile reductions without the state becoming vulnerable, but it has been noted that there comes a point that further reductions may be undesirable, once minimal deterrence is reached, as further reductions beyond that point increase a state's vulnerability and provide an incentive for an adversary to expand its nuclear arsenal secretly.[89]

Frank C. Zagare has argued that deterrence theory is logically inconsistent and empirically inaccurate. In place of classical deterrence, rational choice scholars have argued for perfect deterrence, which assumes that states may vary in their internal characteristics and especially in the credibility of their threats of retaliation.[90]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Definition of deterrence from the Dictionary of Modern Strategy and Tactics by Michael Keane: "The prevention or inhibition of action brought about by fear of the consequences. Deterrence is a state of mind brought about by the existence of a credible threat of unacceptable counteraction. It assumes and requires rational decision makers."

References edit

  1. ^ Lindsay, Jon R.; Gartzke, Erik (2019). Introduction: Cross-Domain Deterrence, from Practice to Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 2. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190908645.003.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-090960-4.
  2. ^ a b c Morgan, Patrick M. (1977). Deterrence: A Conceptual Analysis. SAGE Publications. pp. 26–30. ISBN 978-0-8039-0819-2.
  3. ^ a b c d Gartzke, Eric; Lindsay, Jon R. (2019). Cross-Domain Deterrence: Strategy in an Era of Complexity. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780190908645.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-090960-4.
  4. ^ Art, Robert J.; Greenhill, Kelly M. (2015). The Use of Force: Military Power and International Politics. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. pp. 3–5. ISBN 978-1-4422-3306-5.
  5. ^ a b c Schelling, Thomas C. (1966). Arms and Influence. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0-300-00221-8. JSTOR j.ctt5vm52s.
  6. ^ Pape, Robert A. (1996). Bombing to Win: Air Power and Coercion in War (1 ed.). Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-3134-0. JSTOR 10.7591/j.ctt1287f6v.
  7. ^ Mearsheimer, John J. (1983). Conventional Deterrence. Cornell University Press. p. 23. ISBN 978-1-5017-1325-5. JSTOR 10.7591/j.ctt1rv61v2.
  8. ^ Shimshoni, Jonathan (1988). Israel and Conventional Deterrence. Cornell University Press. p. 6. doi:10.7591/9781501737831. ISBN 978-1-5017-3783-1. S2CID 243305936.
  9. ^ Glaser, Bonnie S.; Weiss, Jessica Chen; Christensen, Thomas J. (2023-11-30). "Taiwan and the True Sources of Deterrence". Foreign Affairs. ISSN 0015-7120.
  10. ^ a b Heginbotham, Eric; Samuels, Richard J. (2018). "Active Denial: Redesigning Japan's Response to China's Military Challenge". International Security. 42 (4): 128–169. doi:10.1162/isec_a_00313. hdl:1721.1/118651. ISSN 0162-2889. S2CID 57570578.
  11. ^ a b c d e f Huth, Paul; Russett, Bruce (1984). "What Makes Deterrence Work? Cases from 1900 to 1980". World Politics. 36 (4): 496–526. doi:10.2307/2010184. ISSN 0043-8871. JSTOR 2010184. S2CID 153596965.
  12. ^ a b Fearon, James (2002). "Selection Effects and Deterrence". International Interactions. 28 (1): 5–29. doi:10.1080/03050620210390. ISSN 0305-0629. S2CID 35580738.
  13. ^ Lee, Do Young (2021). "Strategies of Extended Deterrence: How States Provide the Security Umbrella". Security Studies. 30 (5): 761–796. doi:10.1080/09636412.2021.2010887. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 246241390.
  14. ^ Glaser, Charles L. (1990). Analyzing Strategic Nuclear Policy. Princeton University Press. p. 20. ISBN 978-1-4008-6202-3.
  15. ^ Rhodes, Richard (1995-06-11). "The General and World War III". The New Yorker. ISSN 0028-792X. Retrieved 2023-11-30.
  16. ^ Art, Robert J.; Greenhill, Kelly M. (2015). The Use of Force: Military Power and International Politics. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. 3. ISBN 978-1-4422-3306-5.
  17. ^ Shimshoni, Jonathan (1988). Israel and Conventional Deterrence. Cornell University Press. p. 1. doi:10.7591/9781501737831. ISBN 978-1-5017-3783-1. S2CID 243305936.
  18. ^ Wirtz, James (2018). "How Does Nuclear Deterrence Differ from Conventional Deterrence?" (PDF). Strategic Studies Quarterly.
  19. ^ Mueller, Karl (2021), Osinga, Frans; Sweijs, Tim (eds.), "The Continuing Relevance of Conventional Deterrence", NL ARMS Netherlands Annual Review of Military Studies 2020: Deterrence in the 21st Century—Insights from Theory and Practice, Nl Arms, T.M.C. Asser Press, pp. 47–63, doi:10.1007/978-94-6265-419-8_4, ISBN 978-94-6265-419-8
  20. ^ Huntington, Samuel P. (1983). "Conventional Deterrence and Conventional Retaliation in Europe". International Security. 8 (3): 32–56. doi:10.2307/2538699. ISSN 0162-2889. JSTOR 2538699. S2CID 154133787.
  21. ^ Mearsheimer, John J. (1982). "Why the Soviets Can't Win Quickly in Central Europe". International Security. 7 (1): 3–39. doi:10.2307/2538686. ISSN 0162-2889. JSTOR 2538686. S2CID 154732192.
  22. ^ See, for example, Carl von Clausewitz, On War, trans. and ed. Michael Howard and Peter Paret (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1989)
  23. ^ a b c d e Huth, P. K. (1999), "Deterrence and International Conflict: Empirical Findings and Theoretical Debate", Annual Review of Political Science, 2: 25–48, doi:10.1146/annurev.polisci.2.1.25
  24. ^ Snyder, Glenn H. (1966). Deterrence and Defense. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-7716-4.
  25. ^ a b c d Jentleson, B.A.; Whytock, C.A. (2005), "Who Won Libya", International Security, 30 (3): 47–86, doi:10.1162/isec.2005.30.3.47, S2CID 57572461
  26. ^ George, A (1991), "The General Theory and Logic of Coercive Diplomacy", Forceful Persuasion: Coercive Diplomacy as an Alternative to War, Washington, D.C: United States Institute of Peace Press, pp. 3–14
  27. ^ Achen, Christopher H.; Snidal, Duncan (1989). "Rational Deterrence Theory and Comparative Case Studies". World Politics. 41 (2): 143–169. doi:10.2307/2010405. ISSN 0043-8871. JSTOR 2010405. S2CID 153591618.
  28. ^ Huth, Paul; Russett, Bruce (1990). "Testing Deterrence Theory: Rigor Makes a Difference". World Politics. 42 (4): 466–501. doi:10.2307/2010511. ISSN 0043-8871. JSTOR 2010511. S2CID 154490426.
  29. ^ a b c Since the consequence of a breakdown of the nuclear deterrence strategy is so catastrophic for human civilisation, it is reasonable to employ the strategy only if the chance of breakdown is zero. Schelling, T. C. (1966), "2", The Diplomacy of Violence, New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 1–34
  30. ^ "A Nobel Laureate Who's Got Game", The Washington Post, October 12, 2005.
  31. ^ Jervis, Robert (1982). "Deterrence and Perception". International Security. 7 (3): 3–30. doi:10.2307/2538549. JSTOR 2538549.
  32. ^ a b "The Truth About Tripwires: Why Small Force Deployments Do Not Deter Aggression". Texas National Security Review. 2021-06-02. Retrieved 2021-06-03.
  33. ^ Altman, Dan (2018). "Advancing without Attacking: The Strategic Game around the Use of Force". Security Studies. 27 (1): 58–88. doi:10.1080/09636412.2017.1360074. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 148987375.
  34. ^ Blankenship, Brian; Lin-Greenberg, Erik (2022). "Trivial Tripwires?: Military Capabilities and Alliance Reassurance". Security Studies. 31: 92–117. doi:10.1080/09636412.2022.2038662. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 247040733.
  35. ^ Sagan, Scott; Waltz, Kenneth (1995). The Spread of Nuclear Weapons: A Debate. W.W. Norton. p. 20. ISBN 978-0-393-03810-1.
  36. ^ Snyder, Glenn Herald (1965). The Balance of Power and the Balance of Terror.
  37. ^ Jervis, Robert (1979). "Why Nuclear Superiority Doesn't Matter". Political Science Quarterly. 94 (4): 617–633. doi:10.2307/2149629. ISSN 0032-3195. JSTOR 2149629.
  38. ^ Jervis, Robert (1989). The Meaning of the Nuclear Revolution: Statecraft and the Prospect of Armageddon. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-9565-6.
  39. ^ Krepon, Michael. (PDF). The Henry Stimson Center. Archived from the original (PDF) on 12 August 2017. Retrieved 12 August 2017.
  40. ^ Brodie, Bernard (1959), "8", "The Anatomy of Deterrence" as found in Strategy in the Missile Age, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp. 264–304
  41. ^ Kroenig, Matthew (2018). The Logic of American Nuclear Strategy: Why Strategic Superiority Matters. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-084918-4.
  42. ^ Kroenig, Matthew (2013). "Nuclear Superiority and the Balance of Resolve: Explaining Nuclear Crisis Outcomes". International Organization. 67 (1): 141–171. doi:10.1017/S0020818312000367. ISSN 0020-8183. JSTOR 43282155. S2CID 155075459.
  43. ^ Sechser, Todd S.; Fuhrmann, Matthew (2013). "Crisis Bargaining and Nuclear Blackmail". International Organization. 67 (1): 173–195. doi:10.1017/S0020818312000392. ISSN 0020-8183. JSTOR 43282156. S2CID 154642193.
  44. ^ Sechser, Todd S.; Fuhrmann, Matthew (2017). Nuclear Weapons and Coercive Diplomacy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781316227305. ISBN 978-1-107-10694-9. S2CID 157599829.
  45. ^ Logan, David C. (2022). "The Nuclear Balance Is What States Make of It". International Security. 46 (4): 172–215. doi:10.1162/isec_a_00434. ISSN 0162-2889. S2CID 248723655. the findings reinforce a key theoretical tenet of the nuclear revolution: Once states have achieved a secure second-strike capability, nuclear superiority does not confer additional political benefits.
  46. ^ Lee, Kyung Suk; Kim, James D.; Jin, Hwalmin; Fuhrmann, Matthew (2023). "Nuclear Weapons and Low-Level Military Conflict". International Studies Quarterly. 66 (5). doi:10.1093/isq/sqac067.
  47. ^ Suh, Kyungwon (2022). "Nuclear balance and the initiation of nuclear crises: Does superiority matter?". Journal of Peace Research. 60 (2): 337–351. doi:10.1177/00223433211067899. S2CID 248609130.
  48. ^ Horowitz, Michael (2009). "The Spread of Nuclear Weapons and International Conflict: Does Experience Matter?". The Journal of Conflict Resolution. 53 (2): 234–257. doi:10.1177/0022002708330388. ISSN 0022-0027. JSTOR 20684583. S2CID 55200649.
  49. ^ Cohen, Michael D. (2017). When Proliferation Causes Peace: The Psychology of Nuclear Crises. Georgetown University Press. ISBN 978-1-62616-495-6.
  50. ^ Bell, Mark S.; Miller, Nicholas L. (2022), Narang, Vipin; Sagan, Scott D. (eds.), "The Limits of Nuclear Learning in the New Nuclear Age", The Fragile Balance of Terror, Deterrence in the New Nuclear Age, Cornell University Press, pp. 209–229, ISBN 978-1-5017-6701-2, JSTOR 10.7591/j.ctv310vm0j.11
  51. ^ . Archived from the original on December 8, 2008.
  52. ^ "How Russia Is Beating the West at Deterrence". Time. 2022-03-09. Retrieved 2023-08-11.
  53. ^ Darcy, Oliver (2023-09-12). "An explosive Elon Musk biography is just hitting shelves. But the book's acclaimed author is already walking back a major claim | CNN Business". CNN. Retrieved 2023-09-15.
  54. ^ a b Applebaum, Anne (2023-09-11). "What Russia Got by Scaring Elon Musk". The Atlantic. Retrieved 2023-09-12.
  55. ^ Koster, Ben Hodges, Timo S. (2022-05-05). "NATO Must Re-Learn Deterrence". CEPA. Retrieved 2023-08-11.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  56. ^ Tavberidze, Vazha, (2022). "Former NATO Commander Says Western Fears Of Nuclear War Are Preventing A Proper Response To Putin," Radio Free Europe, April 07.
  57. ^ Bar, Shmuel, (2022). "Deterrence after Ukraine—a critical analysis," Quillette, March 24.
  58. ^ a b c Schneider, Jacquelyn G. (2019), "Deterrence in and through Cyberspace", Cross-Domain Deterrence, Oxford University Press, pp. 95–120, doi:10.1093/oso/9780190908645.003.0005, ISBN 978-0-19-090864-5
  59. ^ a b c Nye, Joseph S. (2017). "Deterrence and Dissuasion in Cyberspace". International Security. 41 (3): 44–71. doi:10.1162/isec_a_00266. ISSN 0162-2889. S2CID 29361290.
  60. ^ a b Borghard, Erica D.; Lonergan, Shawn W. (2017). "The Logic of Coercion in Cyberspace". Security Studies. 26 (3): 452–481. doi:10.1080/09636412.2017.1306396. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 46356854.
  61. ^ a b Borghard, Erica D.; Lonergan, Shawn W. (2021-08-03). "Deterrence by denial in cyberspace". Journal of Strategic Studies. 46 (3): 534–569. doi:10.1080/01402390.2021.1944856. ISSN 0140-2390. S2CID 238842794.
  62. ^ a b Lindsay, Jon R. (2013). "Stuxnet and the Limits of Cyber Warfare". Security Studies. 22 (3): 365–404. doi:10.1080/09636412.2013.816122. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 154019562.
  63. ^ a b Gartzke, Erik; Lindsay, Jon R. (2015). "Weaving Tangled Webs: Offense, Defense, and Deception in Cyberspace". Security Studies. 24 (2): 316–348. doi:10.1080/09636412.2015.1038188. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 4830861.
  64. ^ a b Farrell, Henry; Glaser, Charles L. (2017). "The role of effects, saliencies and norms in US Cyberwar doctrine". Journal of Cybersecurity. doi:10.1093/cybsec/tyw015. ISSN 2057-2085.
  65. ^ Kostyuk, Nadiya; Zhukov, Yuri M. (2019-02-01). "Invisible Digital Front: Can Cyber Attacks Shape Battlefield Events?". Journal of Conflict Resolution. 63 (2): 317–347. doi:10.1177/0022002717737138. ISSN 0022-0027. S2CID 44364372.
  66. ^ Finnemore, Martha; Hollis, Duncan B. (2016). "Constructing Norms for Global Cybersecurity". The American Journal of International Law. 110 (3): 425–479. doi:10.1017/S0002930000016894. ISSN 0002-9300. JSTOR 10.5305/amerjintelaw.110.3.0425. S2CID 151870657.
  67. ^ Finnemore, Martha; Hollis, Duncan B. (2016). "Constructing Norms for Global Cybersecurity". American Journal of International Law. 110 (3): 425–479. doi:10.1017/S0002930000016894. ISSN 0002-9300. S2CID 151870657.
  68. ^ a b Brown, Joseph M.; Fazal, Tanisha M. (2021). "#SorryNotSorry: Why states neither confirm nor deny responsibility for cyber operations". European Journal of International Security. 6 (4): 401–417. doi:10.1017/eis.2021.18. ISSN 2057-5637. S2CID 238358851.
  69. ^ Lin, Herbert (2012). "Escalation Dynamics and Conflict Termination in Cyberspace". Strategic Studies Quarterly. 6 (3): 46–70. ISSN 1936-1815. JSTOR 26267261.
  70. ^ Borghard, Erica D.; Lonergan, Shawn W. (2017). "The Logic of Coercion in Cyberspace". Security Studies. 26 (3): 452–481. doi:10.1080/09636412.2017.1306396. ISSN 0963-6412. S2CID 46356854.
  71. ^ Maurer, Tim (2018). Cyber Mercenaries: The State, Hackers, and Power. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. doi:10.1017/9781316422724. ISBN 978-1-107-12760-9.
  72. ^ Maschmeyer, Lennart (2021). "The Subversive Trilemma: Why Cyber Operations Fall Short of Expectations". International Security. 46 (2): 51–90. doi:10.1162/isec_a_00418. ISSN 0162-2889. S2CID 239770382.
  73. ^ Talmadge, Caitlin (2019). "Emerging technology and intra-war escalation risks: Evidence from the Cold War, implications for today". Journal of Strategic Studies. 42 (6): 864–887. doi:10.1080/01402390.2019.1631811. ISSN 0140-2390. S2CID 202312573.
  74. ^ Legro, Jeffrey (1995). Cooperation Under Fire: Anglo-German Restraint During World War II. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-8014-2938-5.
  75. ^ Carson, Austin (2018). Secret Wars. Princeton University Press. doi:10.2307/j.ctv346p45. ISBN 978-0-691-18424-1. S2CID 240182441.
  76. ^ Jervis, Robert (1976). Perception and Misperception in International Politics: New Edition. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-1-4008-8511-4.
  77. ^ Green, Brendan Rittenhouse (2020). The Revolution that Failed: Nuclear Competition, Arms Control, and the Cold War. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-1-108-48986-7.
  78. ^ Jervis, Robert (2021), Bartel, Fritz; Monteiro, Nuno P. (eds.), "The Nuclear Age", Before and After the Fall: World Politics and the End of the Cold War, Cambridge University Press, pp. 115–131, doi:10.1017/9781108910194.008, ISBN 978-1-108-90677-7, S2CID 244858515
  79. ^ Sagan, Scott D. (1994). "The Perils of Proliferation: Organization Theory, Deterrence Theory, and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons". International Security. 18 (4): 66–107. doi:10.2307/2539178. ISSN 0162-2889. JSTOR 2539178. S2CID 153925234.
  80. ^ "Don't Be So Confident in Nuclear Decision-Making". Lawfare. 2023-02-26. Retrieved 2023-03-04.
  81. ^ "The Psychology of Nuclear Brinkmanship". International Security. 2023.
  82. ^ "Nuclear endgame: The growing appeal of zero". The Economist. June 16, 2011.
  83. ^ "The Growing Appeal of Zero". The Economist. June 18, 2011. p. 66.
  84. ^ "Documentary Advances Nuclear Free Movement". NPR.org. NPR. Retrieved 2010-06-10.
  85. ^ Ben Goddard (2010-01-27). "Cold Warriors say no nukes". The Hill.
  86. ^ Hugh Gusterson (30 March 2012). . Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists. Archived from the original on 17 February 2014. Retrieved 15 November 2013.
  87. ^ Nitze, Paul. "IS IT TIME TO JUNK OUR NUKES? THE NEW WORLD DISORDER MAKES THEM OBSOLETE". washingtonpost dot com. WP Company LLC. Retrieved July 2, 2019.
  88. ^ Kristensen, Hans M, Robert S Norris, and Ivan Oelrich. "From Counterforce to Minimal Deterrence: A New Nuclear Policy on the Path Toward Eliminating Nuclear Weapons." Federation of American Scientists. April 2009. Accessed July 31, 2010.
  89. ^ Nalebuff, Barry. "Minimal Nuclear Deterrence." Journal of Conflict Resolution 32, no. 3 (September 1988): p. 424.
  90. ^ Zagare, Frank C. (2004), "Reconciling Rationality with Deterrence: A Re-examination of the Logical Foundations of Deterrence Theory", Journal of Theoretical Politics, 16 (2): 107–141, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.335.7353, doi:10.1177/0951629804041117, S2CID 13900591

Further reading edit

  • Schultz, George P. and Goodby, James E. The War that Must Never be Fought, Hoover Press, ISBN 978-0-8179-1845-3, 2015.
  • Freedman, Lawrence. 2004. Deterrence. New York: Polity Press.
  • Jervis, Robert, Richard N. Lebow and Janice G. Stein. 1985. Psychology and Deterrence. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press. 270 pp.
  • Morgan, Patrick. 2003. Deterrence Now. Cambridge University Press.
  • T.V. Paul, Patrick M. Morgan, James J. Wirtz, Complex Deterrence: Strategy In the Global Age (University of Chicago Press, 2009) ISBN 978-0-226-65002-9.
  • Waltz, Kenneth N. "Nuclear Myths and Political Realities". The American Political Science Review. Vol. 84, No. 3 (Sep, 1990), pp. 731–746.

External links edit

deterrence, theory, this, article, about, deterrent, theories, nuclear, weapons, legal, theory, justice, deterrence, penology, refers, scholarship, practice, threats, limited, force, party, convince, another, party, refrain, from, initiating, some, other, cour. This article is about Deterrent theories of war and nuclear weapons For legal theory of justice see Deterrence penology Deterrence theory refers to the scholarship and practice of how threats or limited force by one party can convince another party to refrain from initiating some other course of action The topic gained increased prominence as a military strategy during the Cold War with regard to the use of nuclear weapons and is related to but distinct from the concept of mutual assured destruction according to which a full scale nuclear attack on a power with second strike capability would devastate both parties The central problem of deterrence revolves around how to credibly threaten military action or nuclear punishment on the adversary despite its costs to the deterrer 1 USS Growler one of two submarines designed to provide a nuclear deterrence using cruise missiles with a 500 mile 800 km range placed on patrol by starting to carry the Regulus I missile shown at Pier 86 in New York its home as a museum ship Deterrence is widely defined as any use of threats implicit or explicit or limited force intended to dissuade an actor from taking an action i e maintain the status quo 2 3 Deterrence is unlike compellence which is the attempt to get an actor such as a state to take an action i e alter the status quo 4 5 3 Both are forms of coercion Compellence has been characterized as harder to successfully implement than deterrence 5 6 Deterrence also tends to be distinguished from defense or the use of full force in wartime 2 Deterrence is most likely to be successful when a prospective attacker believes that the probability of success is low and the costs of attack are high 7 Central problems of deterrence include the credible communication of threats 8 3 and assurance 9 Deterrence does not necessarily require military superiority 10 11 General deterrence is considered successful when an actor who might otherwise take an action refrains from doing so due to the consequences that the deterrer is perceived likely to take 12 Immediate deterrence is considered successful when an actor seriously contemplating immediate military force or action refrains from doing so 12 Scholars distinguish between extended deterrence the protection of allies and direct deterrence protection of oneself 11 13 Rational deterrence theory holds that an attacker will be deterred if they believe that 14 Probability of deterrer carrying out deterrent threat Costs if threat carried out gt Probability of the attacker accomplishing the action Benefits of the action This model is frequently simplified in game theoretic terms as Costs P Costs gt Benefits P Benefits Contents 1 History 2 Concept 2 1 Proportionality 2 2 Reciprocity 2 3 Coercive credibility 3 Rational deterrence theory 3 1 Military balance 3 2 Signaling and bargaining power 3 3 Reputations for resolve 3 4 Interests at stake 3 5 Tripwires 4 Nuclear deterrence theory 4 1 Stages of US policy of deterrence 4 1 1 Containment 4 1 2 Detente 4 1 3 Reagan era 4 2 Post Cold War period 5 Cyber deterrence 6 Intrawar deterrence 7 Criticism 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further reading 12 External linksHistory editBy November 1945 general Curtis LeMay who led American air raids on Japan during World War II was thinking about how the next war would be fought He said in a speech that month to the Ohio Society of New York that since No air attack once it is launched can be completely stopped his country needed an air force that could immediately retaliate If we are prepared it may never come It is not immediately conceivable that any nation will dare to attack us if we are prepared 15 Most of the innovative work on deterrence theory occurred from the late 1940s to mid 1960s 16 Historically scholarship on deterrence has tended to focus on nuclear deterrence 17 Since the end of the Cold War there has been an extension of deterrence scholarship to areas that are not specifically about nuclear weapons 3 A distinction is sometimes made between nuclear deterrence and conventional deterrence 18 19 20 21 The two most prominent deterrent strategies are denial denying the attacker the benefits of attack and punishment inflicting costs on the attacker 10 Concept editThe use of military threats as a means to deter international crises and war has been a central topic of international security research for at least 2000 years 22 The concept of deterrence can be defined as the use of threats in limited force by one party to convince another party to refrain from initiating some course of action 23 2 In Arms and Influence 1966 Schelling offers a broader definition of deterrence as he defines it as to prevent from action by fear of consequences 5 Glenn Snyder also offers a broad definition of deterrence as he argues that deterrence involves both the threat of sanction and the promise of reward 24 A threat serves as a deterrent to the extent that it convinces its target not to carry out the intended action because of the costs and losses that target would incur In international security a policy of deterrence generally refers to threats of military retaliation directed by the leaders of one state to the leaders of another in an attempt to prevent the other state from resorting to the use of military force in pursuit of its foreign policy goals As outlined by Huth 23 a policy of deterrence can fit into two broad categories preventing an armed attack against a state s own territory known as direct deterrence or preventing an armed attack against another state known as extended deterrence Situations of direct deterrence often occur if there is a territorial dispute between neighboring states in which major powers like the United States do not directly intervene On the other hand situations of extended deterrence often occur when a great power becomes involved The latter case has generated most interest in academic literature Building on the two broad categories Huth goes on to outline that deterrence policies may be implemented in response to a pressing short term threat known as immediate deterrence or as strategy to prevent a military conflict or short term threat from arising known as general deterrence A successful deterrence policy must be considered in military terms but also political terms International relations foreign policy and diplomacy In military terms deterrence success refers to preventing state leaders from issuing military threats and actions that escalate peacetime diplomatic and military co operation into a crisis or militarized confrontation that threatens armed conflict and possibly war The prevention of crises of wars however is not the only aim of deterrence In addition defending states must be able to resist the political and the military demands of a potential attacking nation If armed conflict is avoided at the price of diplomatic concessions to the maximum demands of the potential attacking nation under the threat of war it cannot be claimed that deterrence has succeeded Furthermore as Jentleson et al 25 argue two key sets of factors for successful deterrence are important a defending state strategy that balances credible coercion and deft diplomacy consistent with the three criteria of proportionality reciprocity and coercive credibility and minimizes international and domestic constraints and the extent of an attacking state s vulnerability as shaped by its domestic political and economic conditions In broad terms a state wishing to implement a strategy of deterrence is most likely to succeed if the costs of noncompliance that it can impose on and the benefits of compliance it can offer to another state are greater than the benefits of noncompliance and the costs of compliance Deterrence theory holds that nuclear weapons are intended to deter other states from attacking with their nuclear weapons through the promise of retaliation and possibly mutually assured destruction Nuclear deterrence can also be applied to an attack by conventional forces For example the doctrine of massive retaliation threatened to launch US nuclear weapons in response to Soviet attacks A successful nuclear deterrent requires a country to preserve its ability to retaliate by responding before its own weapons are destroyed or ensuring a second strike capability A nuclear deterrent is sometimes composed of a nuclear triad as in the case of the nuclear weapons owned by the United States Russia the China and India Other countries such as the United Kingdom and France have only sea based and air based nuclear weapons Proportionality edit Jentleson et al provides further detail in relation to those factors 25 Proportionality refers to the relationship between the defending state s scope and nature of the objectives being pursued and the instruments available for use to pursue them The more the defending state demands of another state the higher that state s costs of compliance and the greater need for the defending state s strategy to increase the costs of noncompliance and the benefits of compliance That is a challenge as deterrence is by definition a strategy of limited means George 1991 goes on to explain that deterrence sometimes goes beyond threats to the actual use of military force but if force is actually used it must be limited and fall short of full scale use to succeed 26 The main source of disproportionality is an objective that goes beyond policy change to regime change which has been seen in Libya Iraq and North Korea There defending states have sought to change the leadership of a state and to policy changes relating primarily to their nuclear weapons programs Reciprocity edit Secondly Jentleson et al 25 outlines that reciprocity involves an explicit understanding of linkage between the defending state s carrots and the attacking state s concessions The balance lies in not offering too little too late or for too much in return and not offering too much too soon or for too little return Coercive credibility edit Finally coercive credibility requires that in addition to calculations about costs and benefits of co operation the defending state convincingly conveys to the attacking state that failure to co operate has consequences Threats uses of force and other coercive instruments such as economic sanctions must be sufficiently credible to raise the attacking state s perceived costs of noncompliance A defending state having a superior military capability or economic strength in itself is not enough to ensure credibility Indeed all three elements of a balanced deterrence strategy are more likely to be achieved if other major international actors like the UN or NATO are supportive and opposition within the defending state s domestic politics is limited The other important considerations outlined by Jentleson et al 25 that must be taken into consideration is the domestic political and economic conditions in the attacking state affecting its vulnerability to deterrence policies and the attacking state s ability to compensate unfavourable power balances The first factor is whether internal political support and regime security are better served by defiance or there are domestic political gains to be made from improving relations with the defending state The second factor is an economic calculation of the costs that military force sanctions and other coercive instruments can impose and the benefits that trade and other economic incentives may carry That is partly a function of the strength and flexibility of the attacking state s domestic economy and its capacity to absorb or counter the costs being imposed The third factor is the role of elites and other key domestic political figures within the attacking state To the extent that such actors interests are threatened with the defending state s demands they act to prevent or block the defending state s demands Rational deterrence theory editOne approach to theorizing about deterrence has entailed the use of rational choice and game theoretic models of decision making see game theory Rational deterrence theory entails 27 Rationality actors are rational 11 Unitary actor assumption actors are understood as unitary 11 Dyads interactions tend to be between dyads or triads of states Strategic interactions actors consider the choices of other actors 11 Cost benefit calculations outcomes reflect actors cost benefit calculations 11 28 Deterrence theorists have consistently argued that deterrence success is more likely if a defending state s deterrent threat is credible to an attacking state Huth 23 outlines that a threat is considered credible if the defending state possesses both the military capabilities to inflict substantial costs on an attacking state in an armed conflict and the attacking state believes that the defending state is resolved to use its available military forces Huth 23 goes on to explain the four key factors for consideration under rational deterrence theory the military balance signaling and bargaining power reputations for resolve interests at stake The American economist Thomas Schelling brought his background in game theory to the subject of studying international deterrence Schelling s 1966 classic work on deterrence presents the concept that military strategy can no longer be defined as the science of military victory Instead it is argued that military strategy was now equally if not more the art of coercion intimidation and deterrence 29 Schelling says the capacity to harm another state is now used as a motivating factor for other states to avoid it and influence another state s behavior To be coercive or deter another state violence must be anticipated and avoidable by accommodation It can therefore be summarized that the use of the power to hurt as bargaining power is the foundation of deterrence theory and is most successful when it is held in reserve 29 In an article celebrating Schelling s Nobel Memorial Prize for Economics 30 Michael Kinsley Washington Post op ed columnist and one of Schelling s former students anecdotally summarizes Schelling s reorientation of game theory thus Y ou re standing at the edge of a cliff chained by the ankle to someone else You ll be released and one of you will get a large prize as soon as the other gives in How do you persuade the other guy to give in when the only method at your disposal threatening to push him off the cliff would doom you both Answer You start dancing closer and closer to the edge That way you don t have to convince him that you would do something totally irrational plunge him and yourself off the cliff You just have to convince him that you are prepared to take a higher risk than he is of accidentally falling off the cliff If you can do that you win Military balance edit Deterrence is often directed against state leaders who have specific territorial goals that they seek to attain either by seizing disputed territory in a limited military attack or by occupying disputed territory after the decisive defeat of the adversary s armed forces In either case the strategic orientation of potential attacking states generally is for the short term and is driven by concerns about military cost and effectiveness For successful deterrence defending states need the military capacity to respond quickly and strongly to a range of contingencies Deterrence often fails if either a defending state or an attacking state underestimates or overestimates the other s ability to undertake a particular course of action Signaling and bargaining power edit The central problem for a state that seeks to communicate a credible deterrent threat by diplomatic or military actions is that all defending states have an incentive to act as if they are determined to resist an attack in the hope that the attacking state will back away from military conflict with a seemingly resolved adversary If all defending states have such incentives potential attacking states may discount statements made by defending states along with any movement of military forces as merely bluffs In that regard rational deterrence theorists have argued that costly signals are required to communicate the credibility of a defending state s resolve Those are actions and statements that clearly increase the risk of a military conflict and also increase the costs of backing down from a deterrent threat States that bluff are unwilling to cross a certain threshold of threat and military action for fear of committing themselves to an armed conflict Reputations for resolve edit Main article Credibility international relations There are three different arguments that have been developed in relation to the role of reputations in influencing deterrence outcomes The first argument focuses on a defending state s past behavior in international disputes and crises which creates strong beliefs in a potential attacking state about the defending state s expected behaviour in future conflicts The credibilities of a defending state s policies are arguably linked over time and reputations for resolve have a powerful causal impact on an attacking state s decision whether to challenge either general or immediate deterrence The second approach argues that reputations have a limited impact on deterrence outcomes because the credibility of deterrence is heavily determined by the specific configuration of military capabilities interests at stake and political constraints faced by a defending state in a given situation of attempted deterrence The argument of that school of thought is that potential attacking states are not likely to draw strong inferences about a defending states resolve from prior conflicts because potential attacking states do not believe that a defending state s past behaviour is a reliable predictor of future behavior The third approach is a middle ground between the first two approaches and argues that potential attacking states are likely to draw reputational inferences about resolve from the past behaviour of defending states only under certain conditions The insight is the expectation that decisionmakers use only certain types of information when drawing inferences about reputations and an attacking state updates and revises its beliefs when a defending state s unanticipated behavior cannot be explained by case specific variables An example shows that the problem extends to the perception of the third parties as well as main adversaries and underlies the way in which attempts at deterrence can fail and even backfire if the assumptions about the others perceptions are incorrect 31 Interests at stake edit Although costly signaling and bargaining power are more well established arguments in rational deterrence theory the interests of defending states are not as well known Attacking states may look beyond the short term bargaining tactics of a defending state and seek to determine what interests are at stake for the defending state that would justify the risks of a military conflict The argument is that defending states that have greater interests at stake in a dispute are more resolved to use force and more willing to endure military losses to secure those interests Even less well established arguments are the specific interests that are more salient to state leaders such as military interests and economic interests Furthermore Huth 23 argues that both supporters and critics of rational deterrence theory agree that an unfavorable assessment of the domestic and international status quo by state leaders can undermine or severely test the success of deterrence In a rational choice approach if the expected utility of not using force is reduced by a declining status quo position deterrence failure is more likely since the alternative option of using force becomes relatively more attractive Tripwires edit International relations scholars Dan Reiter and Paul Poast have argued that so called tripwires do not deter aggression 32 Tripwires entail that small forces are deployed abroad with the assumption that an attack on them will trigger a greater deployment of forces 32 Dan Altman has argued that tripwires do work to deter aggression citing the Western deployment of forces to Berlin in 1948 1949 to deter Soviet aggression as a successful example 33 A 2022 study by Brian Blankenship and Erik Lin Greenberg found that high resolve low capability signals such as tripwires were not viewed as more reassuring to allies than low resolve high capability alternatives such as forces stationed offshore Their study cast doubt on the reassuring value of tripwires 34 Nuclear deterrence theory editMain articles Nuclear strategy Massive retaliation Mutual assured destruction and Flexible response In 1966 Schelling 29 is prescriptive in outlining the impact of the development of nuclear weapons in the analysis of military power and deterrence In his analysis before the widespread use of assured second strike capability or immediate reprisal in the form of SSBN submarines Schelling argues that nuclear weapons give nations the potential to destroy their enemies but also the rest of humanity without drawing immediate reprisal because of the lack of a conceivable defense system and the speed with which nuclear weapons can be deployed A nation s credible threat of such severe damage empowers their deterrence policies and fuels political coercion and military deadlock which can produce proxy warfare According to Kenneth Waltz there are three requirements for successful nuclear deterrence 35 Part of a state s nuclear arsenal must appear to be able to survive an attack by the adversary and be used for a retaliatory second strike The state must not respond to false alarms of a strike by the adversary The state must maintain command and controlThe stability instability paradox is a key concept in rational deterrence theory It states that when two countries each have nuclear weapons the probability of a direct war between them greatly decreases but the probability of minor or indirect conflicts between them increases 36 37 38 This occurs because rational actors want to avoid nuclear wars and thus they neither start major conflicts nor allow minor conflicts to escalate into major conflicts thus making it safe to engage in minor conflicts For instance during the Cold War the United States and the Soviet Union never engaged each other in warfare but fought proxy wars in Korea Vietnam Angola the Middle East Nicaragua and Afghanistan and spent substantial amounts of money and manpower on gaining relative influence over the third world 39 Bernard Brodie wrote in 1959 that a credible nuclear deterrent must be always ready but never used 40 a Scholars have debated whether having a superior nuclear arsenal provides a deterrent against other nuclear armed states with smaller arsenals Matthew Kroenig has argued that states with nuclear superiority are more likely to win nuclear crises 41 42 whereas Todd Sechser Matthew Fuhrmann and David C Logan have challenged this assertion 43 44 45 A 2023 study found that a state with nuclear weapons is less likely to be targeted by non nuclear states but that a state with nuclear weapons is not less likely to target other nuclear states in low level conflict 46 A 2022 study by Kyungwon Suh suggests that nuclear superiority may not reduce the likelihood that nuclear opponents will initiate nuclear crises 47 Proponents of nuclear deterrence theory argue that while newly nuclear armed states may pose a short or medium term risk but that nuclear learning occurs over time as states learn to live with new nuclear armed states 48 49 Mark S Bell and Nicholas L Miller have however argued that there is a weak theoretical and empirical basis for notions of nuclear learning 50 Stages of US policy of deterrence edit The US policy of deterrence during the Cold War underwent significant variations Containment edit The early stages of the Cold War were generally characterized by the containment of communism an aggressive stance on behalf of the US especially on developing nations under its sphere of influence The period was characterized by numerous proxy wars throughout most of the globe particularly Africa Asia Central America and South America One notable conflict was the Korean War George F Kennan who is taken to be the founder of this policy in his Long Telegram asserted that he never advocated military intervention merely economic support and that his ideas were misinterpreted as espoused by the general public Detente edit With the US drawdown from Vietnam the normalization of US relations with China and the Sino Soviet Split the policy of containment was abandoned and a new policy of detente was established with peaceful co existence was sought between the United States and the Soviet Union Although all of those factors contributed to this shift the most important factor was probably the rough parity achieved in stockpiling nuclear weapons with the clear capability of mutual assured destruction MAD Therefore the period of detente was characterized by a general reduction in the tension between the Soviet Union and the United States and a thawing of the Cold War which lasted from the late 1960s until the start of the 1980s The doctrine of mutual nuclear deterrence then characterized relations between the United States and the Soviet Union and relations with Russia until the onset of the New Cold War in the early 2010s Since then relations have been less clear Reagan era edit A third shift occurred with US President Ronald Reagan s arms build up during the 1980s Reagan attempted to justify the policy by concerns of growing Soviet influence in Latin America and the post 1979 revolutionary government of Iran Similar to the old policy of containment the US funded several proxy wars including support for Saddam Hussein of Iraq during the Iran Iraq War support for the mujahideen in Afghanistan who were fighting for independence from the Soviet Union and several anticommunist movements in Latin America such as the overthrow of the Sandinista government in Nicaragua The funding of the Contras in Nicaragua led to the Iran Contra Affair while overt support led to a ruling from the International Court of Justice against the United States in Nicaragua v United States The final expression of the full impact of deterrence during the cold war can be seen in the agreement between Reagan and Mikhail Gorbachev in 1985 They agreed that a nuclear war cannot be won and must never be fought Recognizing that any conflict between the USSR and the U S could have catastrophic consequences they emphasized the importance of preventing any war between them whether nuclear or conventional They will not seek to achieve military superiority While the army was dealing with the breakup of the Soviet Union and the spread of nuclear technology to other nations beyond the United States and Russia the concept of deterrence took on a broader multinational dimension The US policy on deterrence after the Cold War was outlined in 1995 in the document called Essentials of Post Cold War Deterrence 51 It explains that while relations with Russia continue to follow the traditional characteristics of MAD but the US policy of deterrence towards nations with minor nuclear capabilities should ensure by threats of immense retaliation or even pre emptive action not to threaten the United States its interests or allies The document explains that such threats must also be used to ensure that nations without nuclear technology refrain from developing nuclear weapons and that a universal ban precludes any nation from maintaining chemical or biological weapons The current tensions with Iran and North Korea over their nuclear programs are caused partly by the continuation of the policy of deterrence Post Cold War period edit By the beginning of the 2022 Russian invasion of Ukraine many western hawks expressed the view that deterrence worked in that war but only in one way in favor of Russia Former US security advisor John Bolton said Deterrence is working in the Ukraine crisis just not for the right side The United States and its allies failed to deter Russia from invading The purpose of deterrence strategy is to prevent the conflict entirely and there Washington failed badly On the other hand Russian deterrence is enjoying spectacular success Russia has convinced the West that even a whisper of NATO military action in Ukraine would bring disastrous consequences Putin threatens blusters uses the word nuclear and the West wilts 52 When Elon Musk prevented Ukraine from carrying drone attacks on the Russian Black Sea fleet by denying to enable needed Starlink communications in Crimea 53 Anne Applebaum argued Musk had been deterred by Russia after the country s ambassador warned him an attack on Crimea would be met with a nuclear response 54 Later Ukrainian attacks on the same fleet using a different communications system also caused deterrence this time to the Russian Navy 54 Timo S Koster who served at NATO as Director of Defence Policy amp Capabilities similarly argued A massacre is taking place in Europe and the strongest military alliance in the world is staying out of it We are deterred and Russia is not 55 Philip Breedlove a retired four star U S Air Force general and a former SACEUR said that Western fears about nuclear weapons and World War III have left it fully deterred and Putin completely undeterred The West have ceded the initiative to the enemy 56 No attempt was made by NATO to deter Moscow with the threat of military force wondered another expert To the contrary it was Russia s deterrence that proved to be successful 57 Cyber deterrence editMain articles Cyberwarfare and Cyberweapon Since the early 2000s there has been an increased focus on cyber deterrence Cyber deterrence has two meanings 58 The use of cyber actions to deter other states The deterrence of an adversary s cyber operationsScholars have debated how cyber capabilities alter traditional understandings of deterrence given that it may be harder to attribute responsibility for cyber attacks the barriers to entry may be lower the risks and costs may be lower for actors who conduct cyber attacks it may be harder to signal and interpret intentions the advantage of offense over defense and weak actors and non state actors can develop considerable cyber capabilities 58 59 60 61 Scholars have also debated the feasibility of launching highly damaging cyber attacks and engaging in destructive cyber warfare with most scholars expressing skepticism that cyber capabilities have enhanced the ability of states to launch highly destructive attacks 62 63 64 The most prominent cyber attack to date is the Stuxnet attack on Iran s nuclear program 62 63 By 2019 the only publicly acknowledged case of a cyber attack causing a power outage was the 2015 Ukraine power grid hack 65 There are various ways to engage in cyber deterrence 58 59 60 Denial preventing adversaries from achieving military objectives by defending against them 61 Punishment the imposition of costs on the adversary Norms the establishment and maintenance of norms that establish appropriate standards of behavior 66 67 Escalation raising the probability that costs will be imposed on the adversary 68 Entanglement and interdependence interdependence between actors can have a deterrent effect 59 64 There is a risk of unintended escalation in cyberspace due to difficulties in discerning the intent of attackers 69 70 and complexities in state hacker relationships 71 According to political scientists Joseph Brown and Tanisha Fazal states frequently neither confirm nor deny responsibility for cyber operations so that they can avoid the escalatory risks that come with public credit while also signaling that they have cyber capabilities and resolve which can be achieved if intelligence agencies and governments believe they were responsible 68 According to Lennart Maschmeyer cyber weapons have limited coercive effectiveness due to a trilemma whereby speed intensity and control are negatively correlated These constraints pose a trilemma for actors because a gain in one variable tends to produce losses across the other two variables 72 Intrawar deterrence editIntrawar deterrence is deterrence within a war context It means that war has broken out but actors still seek to deter certain forms of behavior In the words of Caitlin Talmadge intra war deterrence failures can be thought of as causing wars to get worse in some way 73 Examples of intrawar deterrence include deterring adversaries from resorting to nuclear chemical and biological weapons attacks or attacking civilian populations indiscriminately 74 Broadly it involves any prevention of escalation 75 Criticism editDeterrence theory has been criticized by numerous scholars for various reasons the most basic being skepticism that decision makers are rational A prominent strain of criticism argues that rational deterrence theory is contradicted by frequent deterrence failures which may be attributed to misperceptions 76 Scholars have also argued that leaders do not behave in ways that are consistent with the predictions of nuclear deterrence theory 77 78 79 Scholars have also argued that rational deterrence theory does not grapple sufficiently with emotions and psychological biases that make accidents loss of self control and loss of control over others likely 80 81 Advocates for nuclear disarmament such as Global Zero have criticized nuclear deterrence theory Sam Nunn William Perry Henry Kissinger and George Shultz have all called upon governments to embrace the vision of a world free of nuclear weapons and created the Nuclear Security Project to advance that agenda 82 In 2010 the four were featured in a documentary film entitled Nuclear Tipping Point where proposed steps to achieve nuclear disarmament 83 84 Kissinger has argued The classical notion of deterrence was that there was some consequences before which aggressors and evildoers would recoil In a world of suicide bombers that calculation doesn t operate in any comparable way 85 Shultz said If you think of the people who are doing suicide attacks and people like that get a nuclear weapon they are almost by definition not deterrable 86 Paul Nitze argued in 1994 that nuclear weapons were obsolete in the new world disorder after the dissolution of the Soviet Union and he advocated reliance on precision guided munitions to secure a permanent military advantage over future adversaries 87 As opposed to the extreme mutually assured destruction form of deterrence the concept of minimum deterrence in which a state possesses no more nuclear weapons than is necessary to deter an adversary from attacking is presently the most common form of deterrence practiced by nuclear weapon states such as China India Pakistan Britain and France 88 Pursuing minimal deterrence during arms negotiations between the United States and Russia allows each state to make nuclear stockpile reductions without the state becoming vulnerable but it has been noted that there comes a point that further reductions may be undesirable once minimal deterrence is reached as further reductions beyond that point increase a state s vulnerability and provide an incentive for an adversary to expand its nuclear arsenal secretly 89 Frank C Zagare has argued that deterrence theory is logically inconsistent and empirically inaccurate In place of classical deterrence rational choice scholars have argued for perfect deterrence which assumes that states may vary in their internal characteristics and especially in the credibility of their threats of retaliation 90 See also editBalance of terror Chainstore paradox Confidence building measures Decapitation strike International relations Launch on warning Long Peace N deterrence Nuclear blackmail Nuclear ethics Nuclear peace Nuclear strategy Nuclear terrorism Nuclear warfare Peace through strength Prisoner s dilemma Reagan Doctrine Security dilemma Tripwire force WargamingNotes edit Definition of deterrence from the Dictionary of Modern Strategy and Tactics by Michael Keane The prevention or inhibition of action brought about by fear of the consequences Deterrence is a state of mind brought about by the existence of a credible threat of unacceptable counteraction It assumes and requires rational decision makers References edit Lindsay Jon R Gartzke Erik 2019 Introduction Cross Domain Deterrence from Practice to Theory Oxford University Press p 2 doi 10 1093 oso 9780190908645 003 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 090960 4 a b c Morgan Patrick M 1977 Deterrence A Conceptual Analysis SAGE Publications pp 26 30 ISBN 978 0 8039 0819 2 a b c d Gartzke Eric Lindsay Jon R 2019 Cross Domain Deterrence Strategy in an Era of Complexity Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oso 9780190908645 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 090960 4 Art Robert J Greenhill Kelly M 2015 The Use of Force Military Power and International Politics Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers pp 3 5 ISBN 978 1 4422 3306 5 a b c Schelling Thomas C 1966 Arms and Influence Yale University Press ISBN 978 0 300 00221 8 JSTOR j ctt5vm52s Pape Robert A 1996 Bombing to Win Air Power and Coercion in War 1 ed Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 3134 0 JSTOR 10 7591 j ctt1287f6v Mearsheimer John J 1983 Conventional Deterrence Cornell University Press p 23 ISBN 978 1 5017 1325 5 JSTOR 10 7591 j ctt1rv61v2 Shimshoni Jonathan 1988 Israel and Conventional Deterrence Cornell University Press p 6 doi 10 7591 9781501737831 ISBN 978 1 5017 3783 1 S2CID 243305936 Glaser Bonnie S Weiss Jessica Chen Christensen Thomas J 2023 11 30 Taiwan and the True Sources of Deterrence Foreign Affairs ISSN 0015 7120 a b Heginbotham Eric Samuels Richard J 2018 Active Denial Redesigning Japan s Response to China s Military Challenge International Security 42 4 128 169 doi 10 1162 isec a 00313 hdl 1721 1 118651 ISSN 0162 2889 S2CID 57570578 a b c d e f Huth Paul Russett Bruce 1984 What Makes Deterrence Work Cases from 1900 to 1980 World Politics 36 4 496 526 doi 10 2307 2010184 ISSN 0043 8871 JSTOR 2010184 S2CID 153596965 a b Fearon James 2002 Selection Effects and Deterrence International Interactions 28 1 5 29 doi 10 1080 03050620210390 ISSN 0305 0629 S2CID 35580738 Lee Do Young 2021 Strategies of Extended Deterrence How States Provide the Security Umbrella Security Studies 30 5 761 796 doi 10 1080 09636412 2021 2010887 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 246241390 Glaser Charles L 1990 Analyzing Strategic Nuclear Policy Princeton University Press p 20 ISBN 978 1 4008 6202 3 Rhodes Richard 1995 06 11 The General and World War III The New Yorker ISSN 0028 792X Retrieved 2023 11 30 Art Robert J Greenhill Kelly M 2015 The Use of Force Military Power and International Politics Rowman amp Littlefield Publishers p 3 ISBN 978 1 4422 3306 5 Shimshoni Jonathan 1988 Israel and Conventional Deterrence Cornell University Press p 1 doi 10 7591 9781501737831 ISBN 978 1 5017 3783 1 S2CID 243305936 Wirtz James 2018 How Does Nuclear Deterrence Differ from Conventional Deterrence PDF Strategic Studies Quarterly Mueller Karl 2021 Osinga Frans Sweijs Tim eds The Continuing Relevance of Conventional Deterrence NL ARMS Netherlands Annual Review of Military Studies 2020 Deterrence in the 21st Century Insights from Theory and Practice Nl Arms T M C Asser Press pp 47 63 doi 10 1007 978 94 6265 419 8 4 ISBN 978 94 6265 419 8 Huntington Samuel P 1983 Conventional Deterrence and Conventional Retaliation in Europe International Security 8 3 32 56 doi 10 2307 2538699 ISSN 0162 2889 JSTOR 2538699 S2CID 154133787 Mearsheimer John J 1982 Why the Soviets Can t Win Quickly in Central Europe International Security 7 1 3 39 doi 10 2307 2538686 ISSN 0162 2889 JSTOR 2538686 S2CID 154732192 See for example Carl von Clausewitz On War trans and ed Michael Howard and Peter Paret Princeton Princeton University Press 1989 a b c d e Huth P K 1999 Deterrence and International Conflict Empirical Findings and Theoretical Debate Annual Review of Political Science 2 25 48 doi 10 1146 annurev polisci 2 1 25 Snyder Glenn H 1966 Deterrence and Defense Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 7716 4 a b c d Jentleson B A Whytock C A 2005 Who Won Libya International Security 30 3 47 86 doi 10 1162 isec 2005 30 3 47 S2CID 57572461 George A 1991 The General Theory and Logic of Coercive Diplomacy Forceful Persuasion Coercive Diplomacy as an Alternative to War Washington D C United States Institute of Peace Press pp 3 14 Achen Christopher H Snidal Duncan 1989 Rational Deterrence Theory and Comparative Case Studies World Politics 41 2 143 169 doi 10 2307 2010405 ISSN 0043 8871 JSTOR 2010405 S2CID 153591618 Huth Paul Russett Bruce 1990 Testing Deterrence Theory Rigor Makes a Difference World Politics 42 4 466 501 doi 10 2307 2010511 ISSN 0043 8871 JSTOR 2010511 S2CID 154490426 a b c Since the consequence of a breakdown of the nuclear deterrence strategy is so catastrophic for human civilisation it is reasonable to employ the strategy only if the chance of breakdown is zero Schelling T C 1966 2 The Diplomacy of Violence New Haven Yale University Press pp 1 34 A Nobel Laureate Who s Got Game The Washington Post October 12 2005 Jervis Robert 1982 Deterrence and Perception International Security 7 3 3 30 doi 10 2307 2538549 JSTOR 2538549 a b The Truth About Tripwires Why Small Force Deployments Do Not Deter Aggression Texas National Security Review 2021 06 02 Retrieved 2021 06 03 Altman Dan 2018 Advancing without Attacking The Strategic Game around the Use of Force Security Studies 27 1 58 88 doi 10 1080 09636412 2017 1360074 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 148987375 Blankenship Brian Lin Greenberg Erik 2022 Trivial Tripwires Military Capabilities and Alliance Reassurance Security Studies 31 92 117 doi 10 1080 09636412 2022 2038662 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 247040733 Sagan Scott Waltz Kenneth 1995 The Spread of Nuclear Weapons A Debate W W Norton p 20 ISBN 978 0 393 03810 1 Snyder Glenn Herald 1965 The Balance of Power and the Balance of Terror Jervis Robert 1979 Why Nuclear Superiority Doesn t Matter Political Science Quarterly 94 4 617 633 doi 10 2307 2149629 ISSN 0032 3195 JSTOR 2149629 Jervis Robert 1989 The Meaning of the Nuclear Revolution Statecraft and the Prospect of Armageddon Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 9565 6 Krepon Michael The Stability Instability Paradox Misperception and Escalation Control in South Asia essay PDF The Henry Stimson Center Archived from the original PDF on 12 August 2017 Retrieved 12 August 2017 Brodie Bernard 1959 8 The Anatomy of Deterrence as found in Strategy in the Missile Age Princeton Princeton University Press pp 264 304 Kroenig Matthew 2018 The Logic of American Nuclear Strategy Why Strategic Superiority Matters Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 084918 4 Kroenig Matthew 2013 Nuclear Superiority and the Balance of Resolve Explaining Nuclear Crisis Outcomes International Organization 67 1 141 171 doi 10 1017 S0020818312000367 ISSN 0020 8183 JSTOR 43282155 S2CID 155075459 Sechser Todd S Fuhrmann Matthew 2013 Crisis Bargaining and Nuclear Blackmail International Organization 67 1 173 195 doi 10 1017 S0020818312000392 ISSN 0020 8183 JSTOR 43282156 S2CID 154642193 Sechser Todd S Fuhrmann Matthew 2017 Nuclear Weapons and Coercive Diplomacy Cambridge Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 9781316227305 ISBN 978 1 107 10694 9 S2CID 157599829 Logan David C 2022 The Nuclear Balance Is What States Make of It International Security 46 4 172 215 doi 10 1162 isec a 00434 ISSN 0162 2889 S2CID 248723655 the findings reinforce a key theoretical tenet of the nuclear revolution Once states have achieved a secure second strike capability nuclear superiority does not confer additional political benefits Lee Kyung Suk Kim James D Jin Hwalmin Fuhrmann Matthew 2023 Nuclear Weapons and Low Level Military Conflict International Studies Quarterly 66 5 doi 10 1093 isq sqac067 Suh Kyungwon 2022 Nuclear balance and the initiation of nuclear crises Does superiority matter Journal of Peace Research 60 2 337 351 doi 10 1177 00223433211067899 S2CID 248609130 Horowitz Michael 2009 The Spread of Nuclear Weapons and International Conflict Does Experience Matter The Journal of Conflict Resolution 53 2 234 257 doi 10 1177 0022002708330388 ISSN 0022 0027 JSTOR 20684583 S2CID 55200649 Cohen Michael D 2017 When Proliferation Causes Peace The Psychology of Nuclear Crises Georgetown University Press ISBN 978 1 62616 495 6 Bell Mark S Miller Nicholas L 2022 Narang Vipin Sagan Scott D eds The Limits of Nuclear Learning in the New Nuclear Age The Fragile Balance of Terror Deterrence in the New Nuclear Age Cornell University Press pp 209 229 ISBN 978 1 5017 6701 2 JSTOR 10 7591 j ctv310vm0j 11 The Nautilus Institute Nuclear Strategy Project US FOIA Documents Archived from the original on December 8 2008 How Russia Is Beating the West at Deterrence Time 2022 03 09 Retrieved 2023 08 11 Darcy Oliver 2023 09 12 An explosive Elon Musk biography is just hitting shelves But the book s acclaimed author is already walking back a major claim CNN Business CNN Retrieved 2023 09 15 a b Applebaum Anne 2023 09 11 What Russia Got by Scaring Elon Musk The Atlantic Retrieved 2023 09 12 Koster Ben Hodges Timo S 2022 05 05 NATO Must Re Learn Deterrence CEPA Retrieved 2023 08 11 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Tavberidze Vazha 2022 Former NATO Commander Says Western Fears Of Nuclear War Are Preventing A Proper Response To Putin Radio Free Europe April 07 Bar Shmuel 2022 Deterrence after Ukraine a critical analysis Quillette March 24 a b c Schneider Jacquelyn G 2019 Deterrence in and through Cyberspace Cross Domain Deterrence Oxford University Press pp 95 120 doi 10 1093 oso 9780190908645 003 0005 ISBN 978 0 19 090864 5 a b c Nye Joseph S 2017 Deterrence and Dissuasion in Cyberspace International Security 41 3 44 71 doi 10 1162 isec a 00266 ISSN 0162 2889 S2CID 29361290 a b Borghard Erica D Lonergan Shawn W 2017 The Logic of Coercion in Cyberspace Security Studies 26 3 452 481 doi 10 1080 09636412 2017 1306396 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 46356854 a b Borghard Erica D Lonergan Shawn W 2021 08 03 Deterrence by denial in cyberspace Journal of Strategic Studies 46 3 534 569 doi 10 1080 01402390 2021 1944856 ISSN 0140 2390 S2CID 238842794 a b Lindsay Jon R 2013 Stuxnet and the Limits of Cyber Warfare Security Studies 22 3 365 404 doi 10 1080 09636412 2013 816122 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 154019562 a b Gartzke Erik Lindsay Jon R 2015 Weaving Tangled Webs Offense Defense and Deception in Cyberspace Security Studies 24 2 316 348 doi 10 1080 09636412 2015 1038188 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 4830861 a b Farrell Henry Glaser Charles L 2017 The role of effects saliencies and norms in US Cyberwar doctrine Journal of Cybersecurity doi 10 1093 cybsec tyw015 ISSN 2057 2085 Kostyuk Nadiya Zhukov Yuri M 2019 02 01 Invisible Digital Front Can Cyber Attacks Shape Battlefield Events Journal of Conflict Resolution 63 2 317 347 doi 10 1177 0022002717737138 ISSN 0022 0027 S2CID 44364372 Finnemore Martha Hollis Duncan B 2016 Constructing Norms for Global Cybersecurity The American Journal of International Law 110 3 425 479 doi 10 1017 S0002930000016894 ISSN 0002 9300 JSTOR 10 5305 amerjintelaw 110 3 0425 S2CID 151870657 Finnemore Martha Hollis Duncan B 2016 Constructing Norms for Global Cybersecurity American Journal of International Law 110 3 425 479 doi 10 1017 S0002930000016894 ISSN 0002 9300 S2CID 151870657 a b Brown Joseph M Fazal Tanisha M 2021 SorryNotSorry Why states neither confirm nor deny responsibility for cyber operations European Journal of International Security 6 4 401 417 doi 10 1017 eis 2021 18 ISSN 2057 5637 S2CID 238358851 Lin Herbert 2012 Escalation Dynamics and Conflict Termination in Cyberspace Strategic Studies Quarterly 6 3 46 70 ISSN 1936 1815 JSTOR 26267261 Borghard Erica D Lonergan Shawn W 2017 The Logic of Coercion in Cyberspace Security Studies 26 3 452 481 doi 10 1080 09636412 2017 1306396 ISSN 0963 6412 S2CID 46356854 Maurer Tim 2018 Cyber Mercenaries The State Hackers and Power Cambridge Cambridge University Press doi 10 1017 9781316422724 ISBN 978 1 107 12760 9 Maschmeyer Lennart 2021 The Subversive Trilemma Why Cyber Operations Fall Short of Expectations International Security 46 2 51 90 doi 10 1162 isec a 00418 ISSN 0162 2889 S2CID 239770382 Talmadge Caitlin 2019 Emerging technology and intra war escalation risks Evidence from the Cold War implications for today Journal of Strategic Studies 42 6 864 887 doi 10 1080 01402390 2019 1631811 ISSN 0140 2390 S2CID 202312573 Legro Jeffrey 1995 Cooperation Under Fire Anglo German Restraint During World War II Cornell University Press ISBN 978 0 8014 2938 5 Carson Austin 2018 Secret Wars Princeton University Press doi 10 2307 j ctv346p45 ISBN 978 0 691 18424 1 S2CID 240182441 Jervis Robert 1976 Perception and Misperception in International Politics New Edition Princeton University Press ISBN 978 1 4008 8511 4 Green Brendan Rittenhouse 2020 The Revolution that Failed Nuclear Competition Arms Control and the Cold War Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 1 108 48986 7 Jervis Robert 2021 Bartel Fritz Monteiro Nuno P eds The Nuclear Age Before and After the Fall World Politics and the End of the Cold War Cambridge University Press pp 115 131 doi 10 1017 9781108910194 008 ISBN 978 1 108 90677 7 S2CID 244858515 Sagan Scott D 1994 The Perils of Proliferation Organization Theory Deterrence Theory and the Spread of Nuclear Weapons International Security 18 4 66 107 doi 10 2307 2539178 ISSN 0162 2889 JSTOR 2539178 S2CID 153925234 Don t Be So Confident in Nuclear Decision Making Lawfare 2023 02 26 Retrieved 2023 03 04 The Psychology of Nuclear Brinkmanship International Security 2023 Nuclear endgame The growing appeal of zero The Economist June 16 2011 The Growing Appeal of Zero The Economist June 18 2011 p 66 Documentary Advances Nuclear Free Movement NPR org NPR Retrieved 2010 06 10 Ben Goddard 2010 01 27 Cold Warriors say no nukes The Hill Hugh Gusterson 30 March 2012 The new abolitionists Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists Archived from the original on 17 February 2014 Retrieved 15 November 2013 Nitze Paul IS IT TIME TO JUNK OUR NUKES THE NEW WORLD DISORDER MAKES THEM OBSOLETE washingtonpost dot com WP Company LLC Retrieved July 2 2019 Kristensen Hans M Robert S Norris and Ivan Oelrich From Counterforce to Minimal Deterrence A New Nuclear Policy on the Path Toward Eliminating Nuclear Weapons Federation of American Scientists April 2009 Accessed July 31 2010 Nalebuff Barry Minimal Nuclear Deterrence Journal of Conflict Resolution 32 no 3 September 1988 p 424 Zagare Frank C 2004 Reconciling Rationality with Deterrence A Re examination of the Logical Foundations of Deterrence Theory Journal of Theoretical Politics 16 2 107 141 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 335 7353 doi 10 1177 0951629804041117 S2CID 13900591Further reading editSchultz George P and Goodby James E The War that Must Never be Fought Hoover Press ISBN 978 0 8179 1845 3 2015 Freedman Lawrence 2004 Deterrence New York Polity Press Jervis Robert Richard N Lebow and Janice G Stein 1985 Psychology and Deterrence Baltimore Johns Hopkins University Press 270 pp Morgan Patrick 2003 Deterrence Now Cambridge University Press T V Paul Patrick M Morgan James J Wirtz Complex Deterrence Strategy In the Global Age University of Chicago Press 2009 ISBN 978 0 226 65002 9 Waltz Kenneth N Nuclear Myths and Political Realities The American Political Science Review Vol 84 No 3 Sep 1990 pp 731 746 External links edit nbsp Wikiversity has learning resources about Survey research and design in psychology Tutorials Multiple linear regression Exercises Deterrence theory Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Deterrence theory amp oldid 1196045247, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.