fbpx
Wikipedia

Heideggerian terminology

Martin Heidegger, the 20th-century German philosopher, produced a large body of work that intended a profound change of direction for philosophy. Such was the depth of change that he found it necessary to introduce many neologisms, often connected to idiomatic words and phrases in the German language.

Terms edit

Aletheia edit

(Ancient Greek: ἀλήθεια)

Heidegger's idea of aletheia, or disclosure (Erschlossenheit), was an attempt to make sense of how things in the world appear to human beings as part of an opening in intelligibility, as "unclosedness" or "unconcealedness". (This is Heidegger's usual reading of aletheia as Unverborgenheit, "unconcealment".)[1] It is closely related to the notion of world disclosure, the way in which things get their sense as part of a holistically structured, pre-interpreted background of meaning. Initially, Heidegger wanted aletheia to stand for a re-interpreted definition of truth. However, he later corrected the association of aletheia with truth.

Apophantic edit

(German: apophantisch)

An assertion (as opposed to a question, a doubt or a more expressive sense) is apophantic. It is a statement that covers up meaning and instead gives something present-at-hand. For instance, "The President is on vacation", and, "Salt is Sodium Chloride" are sentences that, because of their apophantic character, can easily be picked up and repeated in news and gossip by 'The They.' However, the real ready-to-hand meaning and context may be lost.

Being-in-the-world edit

(German: In-der-Welt-sein)

Being-in-the-world is Heidegger's replacement for terms such as subject, object, consciousness, and world. For him, the split of things into subject/object, as is found in the Western tradition and even in language, must be overcome, as is indicated by the root structure of Husserl and Brentano's concept of intentionality, i.e., that all consciousness is consciousness of something, that there is no consciousness, as such, cut off from an object (be it the matter of a thought or of a perception). Nor are there objects without some consciousness beholding or being involved with them.

At the most basic level of being-in-the-world, Heidegger notes that there is always a mood, a mood that "assails us" in humanity's unreflecting devotion to the world. A mood comes neither from the "outside" nor from the "inside", but arises from being-in-the-world. A person may turn away from a mood but that is only to another mood, as part of facticity. Only with a mood is someone permitted to encounter things in the world. Dasein (a co-term for being-in-the-world) has an openness to the world that is constituted by the attunement of a mood or state of mind. As such, Dasein is a "thrown" "projection" (geworfener Entwurf), projecting itself onto the possibilities that lie before it or may be hidden, and interpreting and understanding the world in terms of possibilities. Such projecting has nothing to do with comporting oneself toward a plan that has been thought out. It is not a plan, since Dasein has, as Dasein, already projected itself. Dasein always understands itself in terms of possibilities. As projecting, the understanding of Dasein is its possibilities as possibilities. One can take up the possibilities of "The They" self and merely follow along or make some more authentic understanding.[2]

Being-toward-death edit

(German: Sein-zum-Tode)

Being-toward-death is not an orientation that brings Dasein closer to its end, in terms of clinical death, but is rather a way of being.[3] Being-toward-death refers to a process of growing through the world where a certain foresight guides the Dasein towards gaining an authentic perspective. It is provided by dread of death. In the analysis of time, it is revealed as a threefold condition of Being. Time, the present, and the notion of the "eternal", are modes of temporality, which is the way humanity views time. For Heidegger, it is very different from the mistaken view of time as being a linear series of past, present and future. Instead he sees it as being an ecstasy, an outside-of-itself, of futural projections (possibilities) and one's place in history as a part of one's generation. Possibilities, then, are integral to understanding of time; projects, or thrown projection in-the-world, are what absorb and direct people. Futurity, as a direction toward the future that always contains the past—the has-been—is a primary mode of Dasein's temporality.

Death is that possibility which is the absolute impossibility of Dasein. As such, it cannot be compared to any other kind of ending or "running out" of something. For example, one's death is not an empirical event. For Heidegger, death is Dasein's ownmost (it is what illuminates Dasein in its individuality), it is non-relational (nobody can take one's death away from one, or die in one's place, and we can not understand our own death through the death of other Dasein), and it is not to be outstripped. The "not-yet" of life is always already a part of Dasein: "as soon as man comes to life, he is at once old enough to die." The threefold condition of death is thus simultaneously one's "ownmost potentiality-for-being, non-relational, and not to be out-stripped". Death is determinate in its inevitability, but an authentic Being-toward-death understands the indeterminate nature of one's own inevitable death—one never knows when or how it is going to come. However, this indeterminacy does not put death in some distant, futural "not-yet"; authentic Being-toward-death understands one's individual death as always already a part of one.[4]

With average, everyday (normal) discussion of death, all this is concealed. The "they-self" talks about it in a fugitive manner, passes it off as something that occurs at some time but is not yet "present-at-hand" as an actuality, and hides its character as one's ownmost possibility, presenting it as belonging to no one in particular. It becomes devalued—redefined as a neutral and mundane aspect of existence that merits no authentic consideration. "One dies" is interpreted as a fact, and comes to mean "nobody dies".[5]

On the other hand, authenticity takes Dasein out of the "They", in part by revealing its place as a part of the They. Heidegger states that Authentic being-toward-death calls Dasein's individual self out of its "they-self", and frees it to re-evaluate life from the standpoint of finitude. In so doing, Dasein opens itself up for "angst", translated alternately as "dread" or as "anxiety". Angst, as opposed to fear, does not have any distinct object for its dread; it is rather anxious in the face of Being-in-the-world in general—that is, it is anxious in the face of Dasein's own self. Angst is a shocking individuation of Dasein, when it realizes that it is not at home in the world, or when it comes face to face with its own "uncanny" (German Unheimlich, "not homelike"). In Dasein's individuation, it is open to hearing the "call of conscience" (German Gewissensruf), which comes from Dasein's own Self when it wants to be its Self. This Self is then open to truth, understood as unconcealment (Greek aletheia). In this moment of vision, Dasein understands what is hidden as well as hiddenness itself, indicating Heidegger's regular uniting of opposites; in this case, truth and untruth.[6]

Being-with edit

(German: Mitsein)

The term "Being-with" refers to an ontological characteristic of the human being, that it is always already[a] with others of its kind. This assertion is to be understood not as a factual statement about an individual, that they are at the moment in spatial proximity to one or more other individuals, but rather a statement about the being of every human, that in the structures of its being-in-the-world one finds an implicit reference to other humans, as one could not live without others. Humans have been called (by others, not by Heidegger) "ultrasocial"[7] and "obligatorily gregarious".[8] Heidegger, from his phenomenological perspective, calls this feature of human life "Being-with" (Mitsein), and says it is essential to being human,[9] classifying it as inauthentic when a person fails to recognize how much, and in what ways, someone thinks of themself, and how they habitually behave as influenced by our social surroundings. Heidegger classifies it as authentic when someone pays attention to that influence and decides independently whether to go along with it or not. Living entirely without such influence, however, is not an option in the Heideggerian view.

Care (or concern) edit

(German: Sorge)

A fundamental basis of being-in-the-world is, for Heidegger, not matter or spirit but care:

Dasein's facticity is such that its Being-in-the-world has always dispersed itself or even split itself up into definite ways of Being-in. The multiplicity of these is indicated by the following examples: having to do with something, producing something, attending to something and looking after it, making use of something, giving something up and letting it go, undertaking, accomplishing, evincing, interrogating, considering, discussing, determining....[10]

All these ways of Being-in have concern (Sorge, care) as their kind of Being. Just as the scientist might investigate or search, and presume neutrality, it can be seen that beneath this there is the mood, the concern of the scientist to discover, to reveal new ideas or theories and to attempt to level off temporal aspects.

Clearing edit

(German: Lichtung)

In German, the word Lichtung means a clearing, as in, for example, a clearing in the woods. Since its root is the German word for light (Licht), it is sometimes also translated as "lighting", and in Heidegger's work it refers to the necessity of a clearing in which anything at all can appear, the clearing in which some thing or idea can show itself, or be unconcealed.[11] Note the relation that this has to Aletheia (see the main article or the entry above) and disclosure.

Beings (Seiende, plural: Seienden), but not Being itself (Sein), stand out as if in a clearing, or physically, as if in a space. Thus, Hubert Dreyfus writes, "things show up in the light of our understanding of being."[12] Thus the clearing makes possible the disclosure of beings (Seienden), and also access to Dasein's own being. The clearing is not, itself, an entity that can be known directly, in the sense in which we know about the entities of the world. As Heidegger writes in On the Origin of the Work of Art:

In the midst of being as a whole an open place occurs. There is a clearing, a lighting. Thought of in reference to what is, to beings, this clearing is in a greater degree than are beings. This open center is therefore not surrounded by what is; rather, the lighting center itself encircles all that is, like the Nothing which we scarcely know. That which is can only be, as a being, if it stands within and stands out within what is lighted in this clearing. Only this clearing grants and guarantees to us humans a passage to those beings that we ourselves are not, and access to the being that we ourselves are.[13]

Destruktion edit

Founded in the work of Martin Luther,[14] Heidegger conceptualises philosophy as the task of destroying ontological concepts, including ordinary everyday meanings of words like time, history, being, theory, death, mind, body, matter, logic etc.:

When tradition thus becomes master, it does so in such a way that what it 'transmits' is made so inaccessible, proximally and for the most part, that it rather becomes concealed. Tradition takes what has come down to us and delivers it over to self-evidence; it blocks our access to those primordial 'sources' from which the categories and concepts handed down to us have been in part quite genuinely drawn. Indeed it makes us forget that they have had such an origin, and makes us suppose that the necessity of going back to these sources is something which we need not even understand. (Being and Time, p. 43)

Heidegger considers that tradition can become calcified here and there:

If the question of Being is to have its own history made transparent, then this hardened tradition must be loosened up, and the concealments which it has brought about dissolved. We understand this task as one in which by taking the question of Being as our clue we are to destroy the traditional content of ancient ontology until we arrive at those primordial experiences in which we achieved our first ways of determining the nature of Being—the ways which have guided us ever since. (Being and Time, p. 44)

Heidegger then remarks on the positivity of his project of Destruktion:

...it has nothing to do with a vicious relativizing of ontological standpoints. But this destruction is just as far from having the negative sense of shaking off the ontological tradition. We must, on the contrary, stake out the positive possibilities of that tradition, and this means keeping it within its limits; and these in turn are given factically in the way the question is formulated at the time, and in the way the possible field for investigation is thus bounded off. On its negative side, this destruction does not relate itself toward the past; its criticism is aimed at 'today' and at the prevalent way of treating the history of ontology. .. But to bury the past in nullity (Nichtigkeit) is not the purpose of this destruction; its aim is positive; its negative function remains unexpressed and indirect. (Being and Time, p. 44)

Dasein edit

In his effort to redefine man, Heidegger introduces a statement: 'the ownmost of Dasein consists in its existence'.[15] Heidegger conceptualises existence around the unique qualities of man, which he considers "its own being is an issue for it".[16] In the Heideggerian view, man defines its own being through its actions and choices, and is able to choose amongst possibilities, actualizing at least one of the possibilities available while closing off others in the process. This grasping of only some possibilities defines man as one kind of self rather than another: a dishonest choice defines a person as dishonest, fixing broken windows defines a person as a glazier, and so on. These choices are made continually and on a daily basis, and so man is able to define itself as it moves along. Therefore, living the life of a person is a matter of constantly taking a stand on one's sense of self, and one's sense of self being defined by taking that stand. As no choice is 'once and for always', man has to continually keep on choosing for his sense of self.

Added to this is that the being of everything else on the planet poses an issue for man, as humanity deals with things as what they are and persons as who they are. Only persons, for example, relate to others as meaningful and fitting meaningfully into and with other things and/or activities. Only man, being that is in the manner of existence, can encounter another entity in its instrumental character. Again, 'to be an issue' means to be concerned about something and to care for something. In other words, being of Dasein as existence is so constituted that in its very being it has a caring relationship to its own being. This relationship is not a theoretical or self-reflective one, but rather a pre-theoretical one which Heidegger calls a relation or compartment of understanding. Dasein understands itself in its own being or Dasein is in the manner that its being is always disclosed to it. It is this disclosure of being that differentiates Dasein from all other beings. This manner of being of Dasein to which it relates or comports itself is called 'existence'.[17] Further, it is essential to have a clear understanding of the term 'ownmost'. It is the English rendering of the German wesen translated usually as 'essence' (the 'what'ness). The verbal form of German term wesen comes closer to the Indian root vasati, which means dwelling, living, growing, maturing, moving etc. Thus, this verbal dynamic character implied in the word wesen is to be kept in mind to understand the nuance of the Heideggerian usage of 'existence'. If traditionally wesen had been translated as essence in the sense of 'whatness', for Heidegger such a translation is unfit to understand what is uniquely human. Heidegger takes the form of existence from the Latin word ex-sistere (to stand out of itself) with an indication of the unique characteristic of the being of man in terms of a dynamic 'how' as against the traditional conception in terms of 'whatness'. Hence existence for Heidegger means how Dasein in its very way of being is always outside itself in a relationship of relating, caring as opposed to a relationship of cognitive understanding to other innerworldly beings. Thereby, it is to differentiate strictly, what is ownmost to Dasein from that of other modes of beings that Heidegger uses the term 'existence' for the being of man. For what is ownmost to other modes of beings, he uses the term present-at-hand. The various elements of Existence are called 'existentials' and that of what is present-at-hand are called the 'categories'. According to Heidegger "man alone exists, all other things are (they don't exist)". It is important to understand that this notion of 'existence' as what is ownmost to man is not a static concept to be defined once and for all in terms of a content, but has to be understood in terms of something that is to be enacted that varies from individual to individual and from time to time unlike other beings that have a fixed essence. That being whose ownmost is in the manner of existence is called Dasein. In German, da has a spatial connotation of either being 'there' or 'here'. Dasein thus can mean simply "being there or here". In German, it could also refer to the existence (as opposed to the essence) of something, especially that of man. However, Heidegger invests this term with a new ontological meaning. The German term Dasein consists of two components: Da and sein. In the Heideggerian usage, the suffix -sein stands for the being of man in the manner of existence and Da- stands for a three-fold disclosure. According to Heidegger, the being of man is in the manner of a threefold disclosure. That is, the ontological uniqueness of man consists in the fact that its being becomes the da/sphere, where not only its own being, but the being of other non-human beings as well as the phenomenon of world is disclosed to Dasein because of which it can encounter the innerworldly beings in their worlding character. Hence, for Heidegger the term Dasein is a title for the ontological structure of the ontical human being.

Disclosure edit

(German: Erschlossenheit)

Hubert Dreyfus and Charles Spinosa write that: "According to Heidegger our nature is to be world disclosers. That is, by means of our equipment and coordinated practices we human beings open coherent, distinct contexts or worlds in which we perceive, feel, act, and think."[18]

Heidegger scholar Nikolas Kompridis writes: "World disclosure refers, with deliberate ambiguity, to a process which actually occurs at two different levels. At one level, it refers to the disclosure of an already interpreted, symbolically structured world; the world, that is, within which we always already find ourselves. At another level, it refers as much to the disclosure of new horizons of meaning as to the disclosure of previously hidden or unthematized dimensions of meaning."[19]

Discourse edit

(German: Rede) The ontological-existential structure of Dasein consists of "thrownness" (Geworfenheit), "projection" (Entwurf), and "being-along-with"/"engagement" (Sein-bei). These three basic features of existence are inseparably bound to "discourse" (Rede), understood as the deepest unfolding of language.[20]

Equipment edit

(German: das Zeug) Das Zeug refers to an object in the world with which one has meaningful dealings. A nearly un-translatable term, Heidegger's equipment can be thought of as a collective noun, so that it is never appropriate to call something 'an equipment'. Instead, its use often reflects it to mean a tool, or as an "in-order-to" for Dasein. Tools, in this collective sense, and in being ready-to-hand, always exist in a network of other tools and organizations, e.g., the paper is on a desk in a room at a university. It is inappropriate usually to see such equipment on its own or as something present-at-hand.

Another, less prosaic, way of thinking of 'equipment' is as 'stuff one can work with' around us, along with its context. "The paper one can do things with, from the desk, in the university, in the city, on the world, in the universe." 'Equipment' refers to the thing, and its usefulness possibilities, and its context.

Ereignis edit

Ereignis is translated often as "an event", but is better understood in terms of something "coming into view". It comes from the German prefix, er-, comparable to 're-' in English, and äugen, to look.[21][22] It is a noun coming from a reflexive verb. Note that the German prefix er- also can connote an end or a fatality. A recent translation of the word by Kenneth Maly and Parvis Emad renders the word as "enowning"; that in connection with things that arise and appear, that they are arising 'into their own'. Hubert Dreyfus defined the term as "things coming into themselves by belonging together".

Ereignis appears in Heidegger's later works and is not easily summarized. The most sustained treatment of the theme occurs in the cryptic and difficult Contributions to Philosophy. In the following quotation he associates it with the fundamental idea of concern from Being and Time, the English etymology of con-cern is similar to that of the German:

...we must return to what we call a concern. The word Ereignis (concern) has been lifted from organically developing language. Er-eignen (to concern) means, originally, to distinguish or discern which one's eyes see, and in seeing calling to oneself, ap-propriate. The word con-cern we shall now harness as a theme word in the service of thought.[23]

Existence edit

(German: Existenz)

Existentiell edit

(German: Existenziell)

Fundamental ontology edit

Traditional ontology asks "Why is there anything?", whereas Heidegger's fundamental ontology asks "What does it mean for something to be?". Taylor Carman writes (2003) that Heidegger's "fundamental ontology" is fundamental relative to traditional ontology in that it concerns "what any understanding of entities necessarily presupposes, namely, our understanding of that in virtue of which entities are entities."[24]

Gelassenheit edit

Often translated as "releasement",[25] Heidegger's concept of Gelassenheit has been explained as "the spirit of disponibilité [availability] before What-Is which permits us simply to let things be in whatever may be their uncertainty and their mystery."[26] Heidegger elaborated the idea of Gelassenheit in 1959, with a homonymous volume which includes two texts: a 1955 talk entitled simply Gelassenheit,[27] and a 'conversation' (Gespräch) entitled Zur Erörterung der Gelassenheit: Aus einem Feldweggespräch über das Denken[28] ("Towards an Explication of Gelassenheit: From a Conversation on a Country Path about Thinking",[29] or "Toward an Emplacing Discussion [Erörterung] of Releasement [Gelassenheit]: From a Country Path Conversation about Thinking").[30] An English translation of this text was published in 1966 as "Conversation on a Country Path about Thinking".[30][31] Heidegger borrowed the term from the Christian mystical tradition, proximately from Meister Eckhart.[29][32][33]

Geworfenheit edit

Geworfenheit describes man's individual existences as "being thrown" (geworfen) into the world. For William J. Richardson, Heidegger used this single term, "thrown-ness", to "describe [the] two elements of the original situation, There-being's non-mastery of its own origin and its referential dependence on other beings".[34]

 
The hotel Bühlerhöhe [de] Castle ("the Bühl Height")

Kehre edit

Kehre, or "the turn" (die Kehre) is a term rarely used by Heidegger but employed by commentators who refer to a change in his writings as early as 1930 that became clearly established by the 1940s. Recurring themes that characterize much of the Kehre include poetry and technology.[35] Commentators (e.g. William J. Richardson)[36] describe, variously, a shift of focus, or a major change in outlook.[37]

The 1935 Introduction to Metaphysics "clearly shows the shift" to language from a previous emphasis on Dasein in Being and Time eight years earlier, according to Brian Bard's 1993 essay titled "Heidegger's Reading of Heraclitus".[38] In a 1950 lecture, Heidegger formulated the famous saying "Language speaks", later published in the 1959 essays collection Unterwegs zur Sprache, and collected in the 1971 English book Poetry, Language, Thought.[39][40][41]

This supposed shift—applied here to cover about thirty years of Heidegger's 40-year writing career—has been described by commentators from widely varied viewpoints; including as a shift in priority from Being and Time to Time and Being—namely, from dwelling (being) in the world to doing (time) in the world.[35][42][43] (This aspect, in particular the 1951 essay "Building, Dwelling Thinking", influenced several notable architectural theorists, including Christian Norberg-Schulz, Dalibor Vesely, Joseph Rykwert, and Daniel Libeskind.

Other interpreters believe "the Kehre" does not exist or is overstated in its significance. Thomas Sheehan (2001) believes this supposed change is "far less dramatic than usually suggested", and entailed a change in focus and method.[44] Sheehan contends that throughout his career, Heidegger never focused on "being", but rather tried to define "[that which] brings about being as a givenness of entities".[44][45] Mark Wrathall[46] argued (2011) that the Kehre is not found in Heidegger's writings but is simply a misconception. As evidence for this view, Wrathall sees a consistency of purpose in Heidegger's life-long pursuit and refinement of his notion of "unconcealment".

Among the notable works dating after 1930 are On the Essence of Truth (1930), Contributions to Philosophy (From Enowning), composed in the years 1936–38 but not published until 1989, Building Dwelling Thinking (1951), The Origin of the Work of Art (1950), What Is Called Thinking? (1954) and The Question Concerning Technology (1954). Also during this period, Heidegger wrote extensively on Nietzsche and the poet Hölderlin.

Metontology edit

Metontology is a neologism Heidegger introduced in his 1928 lecture course "Metaphysical Foundations of Logic." The term refers to the ontic sphere of human experience.[47] [48] While ontology deals with the entire world in broad and abstract terms, metontology concerns concrete topics; Heidegger offers the examples of sexual differences and ethics.

Ontic edit

(German: ontisch)

Heidegger uses the term ontic, often in contrast to the term ontological, when he gives descriptive characteristics of a particular thing and the "plain facts" of its existence. What is ontic is what makes something what it is.

For an individual discussing the nature of "being", one's ontic could refer to the physical, factual elements that produce and/or underlie one's own reality - the physical brain and its substructures. Moralists raise the question of a moral ontic when discussing whether there exists an external, objective, independent source or wellspring for morality that transcends culture and time.

Ontological edit

(German: ontologisch)

As opposed to "ontic" (ontisch), ontological is used when the nature, or meaningful structure of existence is at issue. Ontology, a discipline of philosophy, focuses on the formal study of Being. Thus, something that is ontological is concerned with understanding and investigating Being, the ground of Being, or the concept of Being itself.

For an individual discussing the nature of "being", the ontological could refer to one's own first-person, subjective, phenomenological experience of being.

Ontological difference edit

Central to Heidegger's philosophy is the difference between being as such and specific entities.[49][50] He calls this the "ontological difference", and accuses the Western tradition in philosophy of being forgetful of this distinction, which has led to misunderstanding "being as such" as a distinct entity.[49][51][52] (See reification)

Possibility edit

(German: Möglichkeit)

Möglichkeit is a term used only once in a particular edition of Being and Time. In the text, the term appears to denote "the possibility whose probability it is solely to be possible". At least, if it were used in context, this is the only plausible definition.

Present-at-hand edit

(German: vorhanden, Vorhandenheit)

With the present-at-hand one has (in contrast to "ready-to-hand") an attitude like that of a scientist or theorist, of merely looking at or observing something. In seeing an entity as present-at-hand, the beholder is concerned only with the bare facts of a thing or a concept, as they are present and in order to theorize about it. This way of seeing is disinterested in the concern it may hold for Dasein, its history or usefulness. This attitude is often described as existing in neutral space without any particular mood or subjectivity. However, for Heidegger, it is not completely disinterested or neutral. It has a mood, and is part of the metaphysics of presence that tends to level all things down. Through his writings, Heidegger sets out to accomplish the Destruktion (see above) of this metaphysics of presence.

Present-at-hand is not the way things in the world are usually encountered, and it is only revealed as a deficient or secondary mode, e.g., when a hammer breaks it loses its usefulness and appears as merely there, present-at-hand. When a thing is revealed as present-at-hand, it stands apart from any useful set of equipment but soon loses this mode of being present-at-hand and becomes something, for example, that must be repaired or replaced.

Ready-to-hand edit

(German: Griffbereit, zuhanden, zuhandenheit)

In almost all cases humanity is involved in the world in an ordinary, and more involved, way, undertaking tasks with a view to achieving something. Take for example, a hammer: it is ready-to-hand; we use it without theorizing. In fact, if we were to look at it as present-at-hand, we might easily make a mistake. Only when it breaks or something goes wrong might we see the hammer as present-at-hand, just lying there. Even then however, it may be not fully present-at-hand, as it is now showing itself as something to be repaired or disposed, and therefore a part of the totality of our involvements. In this case its Being may be seen as unreadiness-to-hand. Heidegger outlines three manners of unreadiness-to-hand: Conspicuous (damaged; e.g., a lamp's wiring has broken), Obtrusive (a part is missing which is required for the entity to function; e.g., we find the bulb is missing), Obstinate (when the entity is a hindrance to us in pursuing a project; e.g., the lamp blocks my view of the computer screen).

Importantly, the ready-to-hand only emerges from the prior attitude in which we care about what is going on and we see the hammer in a context or world of equipment that is handy or remote, and that is there "in order to" do something. In this sense the ready-to-hand is primordial compared to that of the present-at-hand. The term primordial here does not imply something Primitive, but rather refers to Heidegger's idea that Being can only be understood through what is everyday and "close" to us. Our everyday understanding of the world is necessarily a part of any kind of scientific or theoretical studies of entities—the present-at-hand—might be. Only by studying our "average-everyday" understanding of the world, as it is expressed in the totality of our relationships to the ready-to-hand entities of the world, can we lay appropriate bases for specific scientific investigations into specific entities within the world.

For Heidegger in Being and Time this illustrates, in a very practical way, the way the present-at-hand, as a present in a "now" or a present eternally (as, for example, a scientific law or a Platonic Form), has come to dominate intellectual thought, especially since the Enlightenment. To understand the question of being one must be careful not to fall into this leveling off, or forgetfulness of being, that has come to assail Western thought since Socrates, see the metaphysics of presence.

Resoluteness edit

(German: Entschlossenheit)

Resoluteness refers to one's ability to "unclose" one's framework of intelligibility (i.e., to make sense of one's words and actions in terms of one's life as a whole), and the ability to be receptive to the "call of conscience".

Seinsvergessenheit edit

This is translated variously as "forgetting of being" or "oblivion of being". A closely related term is "Seinsverlassenheit", translated as "abandonment of being". Heidegger believed that a pervasive nihilism in the modern world stems from Seinsverlassenheit.[53] The "ontological difference," the distinction between being (Sein) and beings (das Seiende), is fundamental for Heidegger. The forgetfulness of being that, according to him, occurs in the course of Western philosophy amounts to the oblivion of this distinction.[54]

The One / the They edit

(German: Das Man, meaning "they-self")

One of the most interesting and important 'concepts' in Being and Time is that of Das Man, for which there is no exact English translation; different translations and commentators use different conventions. It is often translated as "the They" or "People" or "Anyone" but is more accurately translated as "One" (as in "'one' should always arrive on time"). Jan Patočka denoted for the concept Das Man a synonymous designation "public anonymous". Das Man derives from the impersonal singular pronoun man ('one', as distinct from 'I', or 'you', or 'he', or 'she', or 'they'). Both the German man and the English 'one' are neutral or indeterminate in respect of gender and, even, in a sense, of number, though both words suggest an unspecified, unspecifiable, indeterminate plurality. The semantic role of the word man in German is nearly identical to that of the word one in English.

Heidegger refers to this concept of the One in explaining inauthentic modes of existence, in which Dasein, instead of truly choosing to do something, does it only because "That is what one does" or "That is what people do". Thus, das Man is not a proper or measurable entity, but rather an amorphous part of social reality that functions effectively in the manner that it does through this intangibility.

Das Man constitutes a possibility of Dasein's Being, and so das Man cannot be said to be any particular someone. Rather, the existence of 'the They' is known to us through, for example, linguistic conventions and social norms. Heidegger states that, "The "they" prescribes one's state-of-mind, and determines what and how one 'sees'".

To give examples: when one makes an appeal to what is commonly known, one says "one does not do such a thing"; When one sits in a car or bus or reads a newspaper, one is participating in the world of 'the They'. This is a feature of 'the They' as it functions in society, an authority that has no particular source. In a non-moral sense Heidegger contrasts "the authentic self" ("my owned self") with "the they self" ("my un-owned self").

A related concept to this is that of the apophantic assertion.

World edit

(German: Welt)

Heidegger gives us four ways of using the term world:

1. "World" is used as an ontical concept, and signifies the totality or aggregate (Inwood) of things (entities) which can be present-at-hand within the world.
2. "World" functions as an ontological term, and signifies the Being of those things we have just mentioned. And indeed 'world' can become a term for any realm which encompasses a multiplicity of entities: for instance, when one talks of the 'world' of a mathematician, 'world' signifies the realm of possible objects of mathematics.
3. "World" can be understood in another ontical sense—not, however, as those entities which Dasein essentially is not and which can be encountered within-the-world, but rather as the wherein a factical Dasein as such can be said to 'live'. "World" has here a pre-ontological existentiell signification. Here again there are different possibilities: "world" may stand for the 'public' we-world, or one's 'own' closest (domestic) environment.
4. Finally, "world" designates the ontologico-existential concept of worldhood (Weltheit). Worldhood itself may have as its modes whatever structural wholes any special 'worlds' may have at the time; but it embraces in itself the a priori character of worldhood in general.[55]

Note, it is the third definition that Heidegger normally uses.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ By "always already" Heidegger means that every phenomenological inspection of the human being finds this characteristic. It is not founded on something else.

References edit

  1. ^ Rodney R. Coltman, The Language of Hermeneutics: Gadamer and Heidegger in Dialogue, SUNY Press, 1998, p. 38.
  2. ^ See Hubert Dreyfus's monograph Being-in-the-World for a detailed discussion
  3. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.247.
  4. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.255.
  5. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.253-4.
  6. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.260–74.
  7. ^ Haidt, Jonathan. The Happiness Hypothesis: Finding Modern Truth in Ancient Wisdom. New York: Basic Books, 2006, pp. 47 ff.
  8. ^ de Waal, Frans. Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006, p. 4.
  9. ^ Heidegger 1962, p. 156, H.125.
  10. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.56
  11. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.133
  12. ^ Hubert Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1995. p. 163
  13. ^ Heidegger, M. 2001, On the Origin of the Work of Art. In Poetry, language, thought. (A. Hofstadter, Trans.) (1st ed.). New York: Perennical Classics. (Original work published 1971)
  14. ^ Crowe, Benjamin (2006). Heidegger's Religious Origins: Destruction and Authenticity (Hardcover ed.). Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. p. 2; also see 7. ISBN 0253347068. Heidegger... chose a name for it which itself reflects the importance of Luther to his thinking: Destruktion, a Germanized version of the term destructio used quite frequently in Luther's early writings.
  15. ^ BT, 68
  16. ^ BT, 33
  17. ^ BT, 32
  18. ^ Hubert Dreyfus and Charles Spinosa, "Further Reflections on Heidegger, Technology and the Everyday," in Nikolas Kompridis, ed. Philosophical Romanticism, New York: Routledge, 2006, 265.
  19. ^ Nikolas Kompridis, "On World Disclosure: Heidegger, Habermas and Dewey," Thesis Eleven 1994; 37; 29-45.
  20. ^ Parvis Emad, On the Way to Heidegger’s Contributions to Philosophy, University of Wisconsin Press, 2007, p. 189.
  21. ^ Richard F. H. Polt, The Emergency of Being: On Heidegger's Contributions to Philosophy, Richard F. H. Polt, p. 73.
  22. ^ Giorgio Agamben, Potentialities: Collected Essays, Stanford University Press, 1999, p. 117.
  23. ^ …einzukehren in das, was wir das Ereignis nennen. Das Wort Ereignis ist der gewachsenen Sprache entnommen. Er-eignen heißt ursprünglich: er-äugen, d.h. erblicken, im Blicken zu sich rufen, an-eignen. Das Wort Ereignis soll jetzt, aus der gewiesenen Sache her Gedacht, als Leitwort im Dienst des Denkens sprechen". Martin Heidegger, Identität und Differenz. Pfullingen: Günther Neske, 1957, Seventh Edition 1982, pp. 24–25. English trans. by Joan Stambaugh Identity and Difference. New York: Harper & Row, 1969.
  24. ^ Information Heidegger's Analytic Interpretation, Discourse and Authenticity in Being and Time, pp. 8 - 52
  25. ^ Heidegger, Martin (2010). Country Path Conversations. Translated by Bret W. Davis. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press. p. xi. ISBN 978-0-253-00439-0. I have followed the established consensus in translating this term as 'releasement.' However, it should be kept in mind that the traditional and still commonly used German word conveys a sense of 'calm composure,' especially and originally that which accompanies an existential or religious experience of letting-go, being-let, and letting-be.
  26. ^ Scott, Nathan A. (1969). Negative Capability. Studies in the New Literature and the Religious Situation. New Haven, Connecticut: Yale University Press. p. xiii. Cited in Dente, Carla; Soncini, Sara, eds. (2013). Shakespeare and Conflict. A European Perspective. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Note 5. ISBN 978-1-137-14430-0.
  27. ^ Heidegger, Martin (1959). Gelassenheit. Pfullingen: Neske. 13th Edition: Klett-Cotta (Stuttgart), 2004. ISBN 3-608-91059-X; ISBN 978-36-0891-059-9.
  28. ^ Heidegger, Martin (2002). Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens: 1910-1976. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann. p. 37. ISBN 3-465-03201-2.
  29. ^ a b Hackett, Jeremiah, ed. (2012). A Companion to Meister Eckhart. Leiden: BRILL. p. 689. ISBN 978-9-004-18347-6.
  30. ^ a b Heidegger, Martin (14 June 2010). Country Path Conversations. Translated by Bret W. Davis. p. x. ISBN 9780253004390.
  31. ^ Dente, Carla; Soncini, Sara, eds. (2013). Shakespeare and Conflict. A European Perspective. ISBN 9781137311344.
  32. ^ Heidegger, Martin (14 June 2010). Country Path Conversations. Translated by Bret W. Davis. p. xi. ISBN 9780253004390. The word Gelassenheit [...] has a long history in German thought. It was coined by Meister Eckhart in the thirteenth century and subsequently used by a number of other mystics, theologians, and philosophers.
  33. ^ (in Italian) See Carlo Angelino, Il religioso nel pensiero di Martin Heidegger, in Martin Heidegger, L'abbandono, tr. Adriano Fabris (Genova: Il Melangolo, 1986), p. 19.
  34. ^ Richardson, William J. (1963). Heidegger. Through Phenomenology to Thought. Preface by Martin Heidegger. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. 4th Edition (2003). New York: Fordham University Press. ISBN 0-823-22255-1; ISBN 978-08-2322-255-1. P. 37.
  35. ^ a b Wheeler, Michael (October 12, 2011). "Martin Heidegger – 3.1 The Turn and the Contributions to Philosophy". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2013-05-22. In a 1947 piece, in which Heidegger distances his views from Sartre's existentialism, he links the turn to his own failure to produce the missing divisions of Being and Time [i.e., "Time and Being"]. ... At root Heidegger's later philosophy shares the deep concerns of Being and Time, in that it is driven by the same preoccupation with Being and our relationship with it that propelled the earlier work. ... [T]he later Heidegger does seem to think that his earlier focus on Dasein bears the stain of a subjectivity that ultimately blocks the path to an understanding of Being. This is not to say that the later thinking turns away altogether from the project of transcendental hermeneutic phenomenology. The project of illuminating the a priori conditions on the basis of which entities show up as intelligible to us is still at the heart of things.
  36. ^ Richardson, William J. (1963). Heidegger. Through Phenomenology to Thought. Preface by Martin Heidegger. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers. 4th Edition (2003). The Bronx: Fordham University Press. ISBN 0-823-22255-1; ISBN 978-08-2322-255-1.
  37. ^ Korab-Karpowicz, W. J. (December 21, 2009). "Martin Heidegger (1889—1976) – 1. Life and Works". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2013-05-22.
  38. ^ Brian Bard, 1993, essay, see sections one and three https://sites.google.com/site/heideggerheraclitus/
  39. ^ Lyon, James K. Paul Celan and Martin Heidegger: an unresolved conversation, 1951–1970, pp. 128–9
  40. ^ Philipse, Herman (1998) Heidegger's philosophy of being: a critical interpretation, p. 205
  41. ^ Heidegger (1971) Poetry, Language, Thought, translation and introduction by Albert Hofstadter, pp. xxv and 187ff
  42. ^ Heidegger, Martin (2002). "Time and Being". On Time and Being. Translated by Joan Stambaugh. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. ISBN 0-226-32375-7.
  43. ^ Naess, Jr., Arne D. "Martin Heidegger's Later philosophy". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 2013-06-28.
  44. ^ a b Thomas Sheehan, "Kehre and Ereignis, a proglenoma to Introduction to Metaphysics" in "A companion to Heidegger's Introduction to Metaphysics" page 15, 2001,
  45. ^ Dee also, Sheehan, "Making sense of Heidegger. A paradigm shift." New Heidegger Research. London (England) 2015.
  46. ^ Wrathall, Mark: Heidegger and Unconcealment: Truth, Language, and History, Cambridge University Press, 2011
  47. ^ McNeill, William (1992). "Metaphysics, Fundamental Ontology, Metontology 1925—1935". Heidegger Studies. 8: 63–79. JSTOR 45010876.
  48. ^ Overgaard, Søren (2006). ""Incarnality" and Metontology: A Reply to Frank Schalow". Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology. 37: 92–94. doi:10.1080/00071773.2006.11006566. S2CID 170396387.
  49. ^ a b Wheeler, Michael (2020). "Martin Heidegger". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
  50. ^ Schalow, Frank (2010). "Ontological difference". Historical Dictionary of Heidegger's Philosophy. Scarecrow Press.
  51. ^ Dahlstrom, D. O. (2004). "Ontology". New Catholic Encyclopedia. Gale.
  52. ^ Korab-Karpowicz, W. J. "Heidegger, Martin". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  53. ^ S.L. Bartky (1967) Seinsverlassenheit in the later philosophy of Heidegger, Inquiry, 10:1-4, 74-88, DOI: 10.1080/00201746708601483
  54. ^ "Heidegger, Martin | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  55. ^ Heidegger 1962, H.64

External links edit

  • Dahlstrom, Daniel O. (7 February 2013). The Heidegger Dictionary. London: A & C Black. ISBN 978-1-847-06514-8.
  • Munday, Roderick (March 2009). "Glossary of Terms in Being and Time".

heideggerian, terminology, being, world, redirects, here, documentary, film, ruspoli, being, world, martin, heidegger, 20th, century, german, philosopher, produced, large, body, work, that, intended, profound, change, direction, philosophy, such, depth, change. Being in the world redirects here For the documentary film by Ruspoli see Being in the World Martin Heidegger the 20th century German philosopher produced a large body of work that intended a profound change of direction for philosophy Such was the depth of change that he found it necessary to introduce many neologisms often connected to idiomatic words and phrases in the German language Contents 1 Terms 1 1 Aletheia 1 2 Apophantic 1 3 Being in the world 1 4 Being toward death 1 5 Being with 1 6 Care or concern 1 7 Clearing 1 8 Destruktion 1 9 Dasein 1 10 Disclosure 1 11 Discourse 1 12 Equipment 1 13 Ereignis 1 14 Existence 1 15 Existentiell 1 16 Fundamental ontology 1 17 Gelassenheit 1 18 Geworfenheit 1 19 Kehre 1 20 Metontology 1 21 Ontic 1 22 Ontological 1 23 Ontological difference 1 24 Possibility 1 25 Present at hand 1 26 Ready to hand 1 27 Resoluteness 1 28 Seinsvergessenheit 1 29 The One the They 1 30 World 2 See also 3 Notes 4 References 5 External linksTerms editAletheia edit Main article Aletheia Ancient Greek ἀlh8eia Heidegger s idea of aletheia or disclosure Erschlossenheit was an attempt to make sense of how things in the world appear to human beings as part of an opening in intelligibility as unclosedness or unconcealedness This is Heidegger s usual reading of aletheia as Unverborgenheit unconcealment 1 It is closely related to the notion of world disclosure the way in which things get their sense as part of a holistically structured pre interpreted background of meaning Initially Heidegger wanted aletheia to stand for a re interpreted definition of truth However he later corrected the association of aletheia with truth Apophantic edit German apophantisch An assertion as opposed to a question a doubt or a more expressive sense is apophantic It is a statement that covers up meaning and instead gives something present at hand For instance The President is on vacation and Salt is Sodium Chloride are sentences that because of their apophantic character can easily be picked up and repeated in news and gossip by The They However the real ready to hand meaning and context may be lost Being in the world edit German In der Welt sein Being in the world is Heidegger s replacement for terms such as subject object consciousness and world For him the split of things into subject object as is found in the Western tradition and even in language must be overcome as is indicated by the root structure of Husserl and Brentano s concept of intentionality i e that all consciousness is consciousness of something that there is no consciousness as such cut off from an object be it the matter of a thought or of a perception Nor are there objects without some consciousness beholding or being involved with them At the most basic level of being in the world Heidegger notes that there is always a mood a mood that assails us in humanity s unreflecting devotion to the world A mood comes neither from the outside nor from the inside but arises from being in the world A person may turn away from a mood but that is only to another mood as part of facticity Only with a mood is someone permitted to encounter things in the world Dasein a co term for being in the world has an openness to the world that is constituted by the attunement of a mood or state of mind As such Dasein is a thrown projection geworfener Entwurf projecting itself onto the possibilities that lie before it or may be hidden and interpreting and understanding the world in terms of possibilities Such projecting has nothing to do with comporting oneself toward a plan that has been thought out It is not a plan since Dasein has as Dasein already projected itself Dasein always understands itself in terms of possibilities As projecting the understanding of Dasein is its possibilities as possibilities One can take up the possibilities of The They self and merely follow along or make some more authentic understanding 2 Being toward death edit German Sein zum Tode Being toward death is not an orientation that brings Dasein closer to its end in terms of clinical death but is rather a way of being 3 Being toward death refers to a process of growing through the world where a certain foresight guides the Dasein towards gaining an authentic perspective It is provided by dread of death In the analysis of time it is revealed as a threefold condition of Being Time the present and the notion of the eternal are modes of temporality which is the way humanity views time For Heidegger it is very different from the mistaken view of time as being a linear series of past present and future Instead he sees it as being an ecstasy an outside of itself of futural projections possibilities and one s place in history as a part of one s generation Possibilities then are integral to understanding of time projects or thrown projection in the world are what absorb and direct people Futurity as a direction toward the future that always contains the past the has been is a primary mode of Dasein s temporality Death is that possibility which is the absolute impossibility of Dasein As such it cannot be compared to any other kind of ending or running out of something For example one s death is not an empirical event For Heidegger death is Dasein s ownmost it is what illuminates Dasein in its individuality it is non relational nobody can take one s death away from one or die in one s place and we can not understand our own death through the death of other Dasein and it is not to be outstripped The not yet of life is always already a part of Dasein as soon as man comes to life he is at once old enough to die The threefold condition of death is thus simultaneously one s ownmost potentiality for being non relational and not to be out stripped Death is determinate in its inevitability but an authentic Being toward death understands the indeterminate nature of one s own inevitable death one never knows when or how it is going to come However this indeterminacy does not put death in some distant futural not yet authentic Being toward death understands one s individual death as always already a part of one 4 With average everyday normal discussion of death all this is concealed The they self talks about it in a fugitive manner passes it off as something that occurs at some time but is not yet present at hand as an actuality and hides its character as one s ownmost possibility presenting it as belonging to no one in particular It becomes devalued redefined as a neutral and mundane aspect of existence that merits no authentic consideration One dies is interpreted as a fact and comes to mean nobody dies 5 On the other hand authenticity takes Dasein out of the They in part by revealing its place as a part of the They Heidegger states that Authentic being toward death calls Dasein s individual self out of its they self and frees it to re evaluate life from the standpoint of finitude In so doing Dasein opens itself up for angst translated alternately as dread or as anxiety Angst as opposed to fear does not have any distinct object for its dread it is rather anxious in the face of Being in the world in general that is it is anxious in the face of Dasein s own self Angst is a shocking individuation of Dasein when it realizes that it is not at home in the world or when it comes face to face with its own uncanny German Unheimlich not homelike In Dasein s individuation it is open to hearing the call of conscience German Gewissensruf which comes from Dasein s own Self when it wants to be its Self This Self is then open to truth understood as unconcealment Greek aletheia In this moment of vision Dasein understands what is hidden as well as hiddenness itself indicating Heidegger s regular uniting of opposites in this case truth and untruth 6 Being with edit German Mitsein The term Being with refers to an ontological characteristic of the human being that it is always already a with others of its kind This assertion is to be understood not as a factual statement about an individual that they are at the moment in spatial proximity to one or more other individuals but rather a statement about the being of every human that in the structures of its being in the world one finds an implicit reference to other humans as one could not live without others Humans have been called by others not by Heidegger ultrasocial 7 and obligatorily gregarious 8 Heidegger from his phenomenological perspective calls this feature of human life Being with Mitsein and says it is essential to being human 9 classifying it as inauthentic when a person fails to recognize how much and in what ways someone thinks of themself and how they habitually behave as influenced by our social surroundings Heidegger classifies it as authentic when someone pays attention to that influence and decides independently whether to go along with it or not Living entirely without such influence however is not an option in the Heideggerian view Care or concern edit German Sorge A fundamental basis of being in the world is for Heidegger not matter or spirit but care Dasein s facticity is such that its Being in the world has always dispersed itself or even split itself up into definite ways of Being in The multiplicity of these is indicated by the following examples having to do with something producing something attending to something and looking after it making use of something giving something up and letting it go undertaking accomplishing evincing interrogating considering discussing determining 10 All these ways of Being in have concern Sorge care as their kind of Being Just as the scientist might investigate or search and presume neutrality it can be seen that beneath this there is the mood the concern of the scientist to discover to reveal new ideas or theories and to attempt to level off temporal aspects Clearing edit German Lichtung In German the word Lichtung means a clearing as in for example a clearing in the woods Since its root is the German word for light Licht it is sometimes also translated as lighting and in Heidegger s work it refers to the necessity of a clearing in which anything at all can appear the clearing in which some thing or idea can show itself or be unconcealed 11 Note the relation that this has to Aletheia see the main article or the entry above and disclosure Beings Seiende plural Seienden but not Being itself Sein stand out as if in a clearing or physically as if in a space Thus Hubert Dreyfus writes things show up in the light of our understanding of being 12 Thus the clearing makes possible the disclosure of beings Seienden and also access to Dasein s own being The clearing is not itself an entity that can be known directly in the sense in which we know about the entities of the world As Heidegger writes in On the Origin of the Work of Art In the midst of being as a whole an open place occurs There is a clearing a lighting Thought of in reference to what is to beings this clearing is in a greater degree than are beings This open center is therefore not surrounded by what is rather the lighting center itself encircles all that is like the Nothing which we scarcely know That which is can only be as a being if it stands within and stands out within what is lighted in this clearing Only this clearing grants and guarantees to us humans a passage to those beings that we ourselves are not and access to the being that we ourselves are 13 Destruktion editFounded in the work of Martin Luther 14 Heidegger conceptualises philosophy as the task of destroying ontological concepts including ordinary everyday meanings of words like time history being theory death mind body matter logic etc When tradition thus becomes master it does so in such a way that what it transmits is made so inaccessible proximally and for the most part that it rather becomes concealed Tradition takes what has come down to us and delivers it over to self evidence it blocks our access to those primordial sources from which the categories and concepts handed down to us have been in part quite genuinely drawn Indeed it makes us forget that they have had such an origin and makes us suppose that the necessity of going back to these sources is something which we need not even understand Being and Time p 43 Heidegger considers that tradition can become calcified here and there If the question of Being is to have its own history made transparent then this hardened tradition must be loosened up and the concealments which it has brought about dissolved We understand this task as one in which by taking the question of Being as our clue we are to destroy the traditional content of ancient ontology until we arrive at those primordial experiences in which we achieved our first ways of determining the nature of Being the ways which have guided us ever since Being and Time p 44 Heidegger then remarks on the positivity of his project of Destruktion it has nothing to do with a vicious relativizing of ontological standpoints But this destruction is just as far from having the negative sense of shaking off the ontological tradition We must on the contrary stake out the positive possibilities of that tradition and this means keeping it within its limits and these in turn are given factically in the way the question is formulated at the time and in the way the possible field for investigation is thus bounded off On its negative side this destruction does not relate itself toward the past its criticism is aimed at today and at the prevalent way of treating the history of ontology But to bury the past in nullity Nichtigkeit is not the purpose of this destruction its aim is positive its negative function remains unexpressed and indirect Being and Time p 44 Dasein edit This section possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed June 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Main article Dasein In his effort to redefine man Heidegger introduces a statement the ownmost of Dasein consists in its existence 15 Heidegger conceptualises existence around the unique qualities of man which he considers its own being is an issue for it 16 In the Heideggerian view man defines its own being through its actions and choices and is able to choose amongst possibilities actualizing at least one of the possibilities available while closing off others in the process This grasping of only some possibilities defines man as one kind of self rather than another a dishonest choice defines a person as dishonest fixing broken windows defines a person as a glazier and so on These choices are made continually and on a daily basis and so man is able to define itself as it moves along Therefore living the life of a person is a matter of constantly taking a stand on one s sense of self and one s sense of self being defined by taking that stand As no choice is once and for always man has to continually keep on choosing for his sense of self Added to this is that the being of everything else on the planet poses an issue for man as humanity deals with things as what they are and persons as who they are Only persons for example relate to others as meaningful and fitting meaningfully into and with other things and or activities Only man being that is in the manner of existence can encounter another entity in its instrumental character Again to be an issue means to be concerned about something and to care for something In other words being of Dasein as existence is so constituted that in its very being it has a caring relationship to its own being This relationship is not a theoretical or self reflective one but rather a pre theoretical one which Heidegger calls a relation or compartment of understanding Dasein understands itself in its own being or Dasein is in the manner that its being is always disclosed to it It is this disclosure of being that differentiates Dasein from all other beings This manner of being of Dasein to which it relates or comports itself is called existence 17 Further it is essential to have a clear understanding of the term ownmost It is the English rendering of the German wesen translated usually as essence the what ness The verbal form of German term wesen comes closer to the Indian root vasati which means dwelling living growing maturing moving etc Thus this verbal dynamic character implied in the word wesen is to be kept in mind to understand the nuance of the Heideggerian usage of existence If traditionally wesen had been translated as essence in the sense of whatness for Heidegger such a translation is unfit to understand what is uniquely human Heidegger takes the form of existence from the Latin word ex sistere to stand out of itself with an indication of the unique characteristic of the being of man in terms of a dynamic how as against the traditional conception in terms of whatness Hence existence for Heidegger means how Dasein in its very way of being is always outside itself in a relationship of relating caring as opposed to a relationship of cognitive understanding to other innerworldly beings Thereby it is to differentiate strictly what is ownmost to Dasein from that of other modes of beings that Heidegger uses the term existence for the being of man For what is ownmost to other modes of beings he uses the term present at hand The various elements of Existence are called existentials and that of what is present at hand are called the categories According to Heidegger man alone exists all other things are they don t exist It is important to understand that this notion of existence as what is ownmost to man is not a static concept to be defined once and for all in terms of a content but has to be understood in terms of something that is to be enacted that varies from individual to individual and from time to time unlike other beings that have a fixed essence That being whose ownmost is in the manner of existence is called Dasein In German da has a spatial connotation of either being there or here Dasein thus can mean simply being there or here In German it could also refer to the existence as opposed to the essence of something especially that of man However Heidegger invests this term with a new ontological meaning The German term Dasein consists of two components Da and sein In the Heideggerian usage the suffix sein stands for the being of man in the manner of existence and Da stands for a three fold disclosure According to Heidegger the being of man is in the manner of a threefold disclosure That is the ontological uniqueness of man consists in the fact that its being becomes the da sphere where not only its own being but the being of other non human beings as well as the phenomenon of world is disclosed to Dasein because of which it can encounter the innerworldly beings in their worlding character Hence for Heidegger the term Dasein is a title for the ontological structure of the ontical human being Disclosure edit Main article World disclosure Further information Reflective disclosure German Erschlossenheit Hubert Dreyfus and Charles Spinosa write that According to Heidegger our nature is to be world disclosers That is by means of our equipment and coordinated practices we human beings open coherent distinct contexts or worlds in which we perceive feel act and think 18 Heidegger scholar Nikolas Kompridis writes World disclosure refers with deliberate ambiguity to a process which actually occurs at two different levels At one level it refers to the disclosure of an already interpreted symbolically structured world the world that is within which we always already find ourselves At another level it refers as much to the disclosure of new horizons of meaning as to the disclosure of previously hidden or unthematized dimensions of meaning 19 Discourse edit German Rede The ontological existential structure of Dasein consists of thrownness Geworfenheit projection Entwurf and being along with engagement Sein bei These three basic features of existence are inseparably bound to discourse Rede understood as the deepest unfolding of language 20 Equipment edit This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message German das Zeug Das Zeug refers to an object in the world with which one has meaningful dealings A nearly un translatable term Heidegger s equipment can be thought of as a collective noun so that it is never appropriate to call something an equipment Instead its use often reflects it to mean a tool or as an in order to for Dasein Tools in this collective sense and in being ready to hand always exist in a network of other tools and organizations e g the paper is on a desk in a room at a university It is inappropriate usually to see such equipment on its own or as something present at hand Another less prosaic way of thinking of equipment is as stuff one can work with around us along with its context The paper one can do things with from the desk in the university in the city on the world in the universe Equipment refers to the thing and its usefulness possibilities and its context Ereignis edit Ereignis is translated often as an event but is better understood in terms of something coming into view It comes from the German prefix er comparable to re in English and augen to look 21 22 It is a noun coming from a reflexive verb Note that the German prefix er also can connote an end or a fatality A recent translation of the word by Kenneth Maly and Parvis Emad renders the word as enowning that in connection with things that arise and appear that they are arising into their own Hubert Dreyfus defined the term as things coming into themselves by belonging together Ereignis appears in Heidegger s later works and is not easily summarized The most sustained treatment of the theme occurs in the cryptic and difficult Contributions to Philosophy In the following quotation he associates it with the fundamental idea of concern from Being and Time the English etymology of con cern is similar to that of the German we must return to what we call a concern The word Ereignis concern has been lifted from organically developing language Er eignen to concern means originally to distinguish or discern which one s eyes see and in seeing calling to oneself ap propriate The word con cern we shall now harness as a theme word in the service of thought 23 Existence edit Main article Dasein German Existenz Existentiell edit Main article Existentiell German Existenziell Fundamental ontology edit Traditional ontology asks Why is there anything whereas Heidegger s fundamental ontology asks What does it mean for something to be Taylor Carman writes 2003 that Heidegger s fundamental ontology is fundamental relative to traditional ontology in that it concerns what any understanding of entities necessarily presupposes namely our understanding of that in virtue of which entities are entities 24 Gelassenheit edit For the understanding of Gelassenheit in the Anabaptist tradition see Ordnung Gelassenheit Often translated as releasement 25 Heidegger s concept of Gelassenheit has been explained as the spirit of disponibilite availability before What Is which permits us simply to let things be in whatever may be their uncertainty and their mystery 26 Heidegger elaborated the idea of Gelassenheit in 1959 with a homonymous volume which includes two texts a 1955 talk entitled simply Gelassenheit 27 and a conversation Gesprach entitled Zur Erorterung der Gelassenheit Aus einem Feldweggesprach uber das Denken 28 Towards an Explication of Gelassenheit From a Conversation on a Country Path about Thinking 29 or Toward an Emplacing Discussion Erorterung of Releasement Gelassenheit From a Country Path Conversation about Thinking 30 An English translation of this text was published in 1966 as Conversation on a Country Path about Thinking 30 31 Heidegger borrowed the term from the Christian mystical tradition proximately from Meister Eckhart 29 32 33 Geworfenheit edit Main article Thrownness Geworfenheit describes man s individual existences as being thrown geworfen into the world For William J Richardson Heidegger used this single term thrown ness to describe the two elements of the original situation There being s non mastery of its own origin and its referential dependence on other beings 34 nbsp The hotel Buhlerhohe de Castle the Buhl Height Kehre edit Kehre or the turn die Kehre is a term rarely used by Heidegger but employed by commentators who refer to a change in his writings as early as 1930 that became clearly established by the 1940s Recurring themes that characterize much of the Kehre include poetry and technology 35 Commentators e g William J Richardson 36 describe variously a shift of focus or a major change in outlook 37 The 1935 Introduction to Metaphysics clearly shows the shift to language from a previous emphasis on Dasein in Being and Time eight years earlier according to Brian Bard s 1993 essay titled Heidegger s Reading of Heraclitus 38 In a 1950 lecture Heidegger formulated the famous saying Language speaks later published in the 1959 essays collection Unterwegs zur Sprache and collected in the 1971 English book Poetry Language Thought 39 40 41 This supposed shift applied here to cover about thirty years of Heidegger s 40 year writing career has been described by commentators from widely varied viewpoints including as a shift in priority from Being and Time to Time and Being namely from dwelling being in the world to doing time in the world 35 42 43 This aspect in particular the 1951 essay Building Dwelling Thinking influenced several notable architectural theorists including Christian Norberg Schulz Dalibor Vesely Joseph Rykwert and Daniel Libeskind Other interpreters believe the Kehre does not exist or is overstated in its significance Thomas Sheehan 2001 believes this supposed change is far less dramatic than usually suggested and entailed a change in focus and method 44 Sheehan contends that throughout his career Heidegger never focused on being but rather tried to define that which brings about being as a givenness of entities 44 45 Mark Wrathall 46 argued 2011 that the Kehre is not found in Heidegger s writings but is simply a misconception As evidence for this view Wrathall sees a consistency of purpose in Heidegger s life long pursuit and refinement of his notion of unconcealment Among the notable works dating after 1930 are On the Essence of Truth 1930 Contributions to Philosophy From Enowning composed in the years 1936 38 but not published until 1989 Building Dwelling Thinking 1951 The Origin of the Work of Art 1950 What Is Called Thinking 1954 and The Question Concerning Technology 1954 Also during this period Heidegger wrote extensively on Nietzsche and the poet Holderlin Metontology edit Metontology is a neologism Heidegger introduced in his 1928 lecture course Metaphysical Foundations of Logic The term refers to the ontic sphere of human experience 47 48 While ontology deals with the entire world in broad and abstract terms metontology concerns concrete topics Heidegger offers the examples of sexual differences and ethics Ontic edit Main article Ontic German ontisch Heidegger uses the term ontic often in contrast to the term ontological when he gives descriptive characteristics of a particular thing and the plain facts of its existence What is ontic is what makes something what it is For an individual discussing the nature of being one s ontic could refer to the physical factual elements that produce and or underlie one s own reality the physical brain and its substructures Moralists raise the question of a moral ontic when discussing whether there exists an external objective independent source or wellspring for morality that transcends culture and time Ontological edit German ontologisch As opposed to ontic ontisch ontological is used when the nature or meaningful structure of existence is at issue Ontology a discipline of philosophy focuses on the formal study of Being Thus something that is ontological is concerned with understanding and investigating Being the ground of Being or the concept of Being itself For an individual discussing the nature of being the ontological could refer to one s own first person subjective phenomenological experience of being Ontological difference edit Central to Heidegger s philosophy is the difference between being as such and specific entities 49 50 He calls this the ontological difference and accuses the Western tradition in philosophy of being forgetful of this distinction which has led to misunderstanding being as such as a distinct entity 49 51 52 See reification Possibility edit German Moglichkeit Moglichkeit is a term used only once in a particular edition of Being and Time In the text the term appears to denote the possibility whose probability it is solely to be possible At least if it were used in context this is the only plausible definition Present at hand edit German vorhanden Vorhandenheit With the present at hand one has in contrast to ready to hand an attitude like that of a scientist or theorist of merely looking at or observing something In seeing an entity as present at hand the beholder is concerned only with the bare facts of a thing or a concept as they are present and in order to theorize about it This way of seeing is disinterested in the concern it may hold for Dasein its history or usefulness This attitude is often described as existing in neutral space without any particular mood or subjectivity However for Heidegger it is not completely disinterested or neutral It has a mood and is part of the metaphysics of presence that tends to level all things down Through his writings Heidegger sets out to accomplish the Destruktion see above of this metaphysics of presence Present at hand is not the way things in the world are usually encountered and it is only revealed as a deficient or secondary mode e g when a hammer breaks it loses its usefulness and appears as merely there present at hand When a thing is revealed as present at hand it stands apart from any useful set of equipment but soon loses this mode of being present at hand and becomes something for example that must be repaired or replaced Ready to hand edit This section is written like a personal reflection personal essay or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor s personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style December 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message German Griffbereit zuhanden zuhandenheit In almost all cases humanity is involved in the world in an ordinary and more involved way undertaking tasks with a view to achieving something Take for example a hammer it is ready to hand we use it without theorizing In fact if we were to look at it as present at hand we might easily make a mistake Only when it breaks or something goes wrong might we see the hammer as present at hand just lying there Even then however it may be not fully present at hand as it is now showing itself as something to be repaired or disposed and therefore a part of the totality of our involvements In this case its Being may be seen as unreadiness to hand Heidegger outlines three manners of unreadiness to hand Conspicuous damaged e g a lamp s wiring has broken Obtrusive a part is missing which is required for the entity to function e g we find the bulb is missing Obstinate when the entity is a hindrance to us in pursuing a project e g the lamp blocks my view of the computer screen Importantly the ready to hand only emerges from the prior attitude in which we care about what is going on and we see the hammer in a context or world of equipment that is handy or remote and that is there in order to do something In this sense the ready to hand is primordial compared to that of the present at hand The term primordial here does not imply something Primitive but rather refers to Heidegger s idea that Being can only be understood through what is everyday and close to us Our everyday understanding of the world is necessarily a part of any kind of scientific or theoretical studies of entities the present at hand might be Only by studying our average everyday understanding of the world as it is expressed in the totality of our relationships to the ready to hand entities of the world can we lay appropriate bases for specific scientific investigations into specific entities within the world For Heidegger in Being and Time this illustrates in a very practical way the way the present at hand as a present in a now or a present eternally as for example a scientific law or a Platonic Form has come to dominate intellectual thought especially since the Enlightenment To understand the question of being one must be careful not to fall into this leveling off or forgetfulness of being that has come to assail Western thought since Socrates see the metaphysics of presence Resoluteness edit German Entschlossenheit Resoluteness refers to one s ability to unclose one s framework of intelligibility i e to make sense of one s words and actions in terms of one s life as a whole and the ability to be receptive to the call of conscience Seinsvergessenheit edit This is translated variously as forgetting of being or oblivion of being A closely related term is Seinsverlassenheit translated as abandonment of being Heidegger believed that a pervasive nihilism in the modern world stems from Seinsverlassenheit 53 The ontological difference the distinction between being Sein and beings das Seiende is fundamental for Heidegger The forgetfulness of being that according to him occurs in the course of Western philosophy amounts to the oblivion of this distinction 54 The One the They edit German Das Man meaning they self See also Problem of universals One of the most interesting and important concepts in Being and Time is that of Das Man for which there is no exact English translation different translations and commentators use different conventions It is often translated as the They or People or Anyone but is more accurately translated as One as in one should always arrive on time Jan Patocka denoted for the concept Das Man a synonymous designation public anonymous Das Man derives from the impersonal singular pronoun man one as distinct from I or you or he or she or they Both the German man and the English one are neutral or indeterminate in respect of gender and even in a sense of number though both words suggest an unspecified unspecifiable indeterminate plurality The semantic role of the word man in German is nearly identical to that of the word one in English Heidegger refers to this concept of the One in explaining inauthentic modes of existence in which Dasein instead of truly choosing to do something does it only because That is what one does or That is what people do Thus das Man is not a proper or measurable entity but rather an amorphous part of social reality that functions effectively in the manner that it does through this intangibility Das Man constitutes a possibility of Dasein s Being and so das Man cannot be said to be any particular someone Rather the existence of the They is known to us through for example linguistic conventions and social norms Heidegger states that The they prescribes one s state of mind and determines what and how one sees To give examples when one makes an appeal to what is commonly known one says one does not do such a thing When one sits in a car or bus or reads a newspaper one is participating in the world of the They This is a feature of the They as it functions in society an authority that has no particular source In a non moral sense Heidegger contrasts the authentic self my owned self with the they self my un owned self A related concept to this is that of the apophantic assertion World edit German Welt Further information World disclosure Heidegger gives us four ways of using the term world 1 World is used as an ontical concept and signifies the totality or aggregate Inwood of things entities which can be present at hand within the world dd 2 World functions as an ontological term and signifies the Being of those things we have just mentioned And indeed world can become a term for any realm which encompasses a multiplicity of entities for instance when one talks of the world of a mathematician world signifies the realm of possible objects of mathematics dd 3 World can be understood in another ontical sense not however as those entities which Dasein essentially is not and which can be encountered within the world but rather as the wherein a factical Dasein as such can be said to live World has here a pre ontological existentiell signification Here again there are different possibilities world may stand for the public we world or one s own closest domestic environment dd 4 Finally world designates the ontologico existential concept of worldhood Weltheit Worldhood itself may have as its modes whatever structural wholes any special worlds may have at the time but it embraces in itself the a priori character of worldhood in general 55 dd Note it is the third definition that Heidegger normally uses See also editMartin Heidegger and Nazism Hermeneutics Existentialism 20th century philosophy Continental philosophyNotes edit By always already Heidegger means that every phenomenological inspection of the human being finds this characteristic It is not founded on something else References edit Rodney R Coltman The Language of Hermeneutics Gadamer and Heidegger in Dialogue SUNY Press 1998 p 38 See Hubert Dreyfus s monograph Being in the World for a detailed discussion Heidegger 1962 H 247 Heidegger 1962 H 255 Heidegger 1962 H 253 4 Heidegger 1962 H 260 74 Haidt Jonathan The Happiness Hypothesis Finding Modern Truth in Ancient Wisdom New York Basic Books 2006 pp 47 ff de Waal Frans Primates and Philosophers How Morality Evolved Princeton Princeton University Press 2006 p 4 Heidegger 1962 p 156 H 125 Heidegger 1962 H 56 Heidegger 1962 H 133 Hubert Dreyfus Being in the World Cambridge MIT Press 1995 p 163 Heidegger M 2001 On the Origin of the Work of Art In Poetry language thought A Hofstadter Trans 1st ed New York Perennical Classics Original work published 1971 Crowe Benjamin 2006 Heidegger s Religious Origins Destruction and Authenticity Hardcover ed Bloomington IN Indiana University Press p 2 also see 7 ISBN 0253347068 Heidegger chose a name for it which itself reflects the importance of Luther to his thinking Destruktion a Germanized version of the term destructio used quite frequently in Luther s early writings BT 68 BT 33 BT 32 Hubert Dreyfus and Charles Spinosa Further Reflections on Heidegger Technology and the Everyday in Nikolas Kompridis ed Philosophical Romanticism New York Routledge 2006 265 Nikolas Kompridis On World Disclosure Heidegger Habermas and Dewey Thesis Eleven 1994 37 29 45 Parvis Emad On the Way to Heidegger s Contributions to Philosophy University of Wisconsin Press 2007 p 189 Richard F H Polt The Emergency of Being On Heidegger s Contributions to Philosophy Richard F H Polt p 73 Giorgio Agamben Potentialities Collected Essays Stanford University Press 1999 p 117 einzukehren in das was wir das Ereignis nennen Das Wort Ereignis ist der gewachsenen Sprache entnommen Er eignen heisst ursprunglich er augen d h erblicken im Blicken zu sich rufen an eignen Das Wort Ereignis soll jetzt aus der gewiesenen Sache her Gedacht als Leitwort im Dienst des Denkens sprechen Martin Heidegger Identitat und Differenz Pfullingen Gunther Neske 1957 Seventh Edition 1982 pp 24 25 English trans by Joan Stambaugh Identity and Difference New York Harper amp Row 1969 Information Heidegger s Analytic Interpretation Discourse and Authenticity in Being and Time pp 8 52 Heidegger Martin 2010 Country Path Conversations Translated by Bret W Davis Bloomington Indiana Indiana University Press p xi ISBN 978 0 253 00439 0 I have followed the established consensus in translating this term as releasement However it should be kept in mind that the traditional and still commonly used German word conveys a sense of calm composure especially and originally that which accompanies an existential or religious experience of letting go being let and letting be Scott Nathan A 1969 Negative Capability Studies in the New Literature and the Religious Situation New Haven Connecticut Yale University Press p xiii Cited in Dente Carla Soncini Sara eds 2013 Shakespeare and Conflict A European Perspective Basingstoke Palgrave Macmillan Note 5 ISBN 978 1 137 14430 0 Heidegger Martin 1959 Gelassenheit Pfullingen Neske 13th Edition Klett Cotta Stuttgart 2004 ISBN 3 608 91059 X ISBN 978 36 0891 059 9 Heidegger Martin 2002 Aus der Erfahrung des Denkens 1910 1976 Frankfurt Vittorio Klostermann p 37 ISBN 3 465 03201 2 a b Hackett Jeremiah ed 2012 A Companion to Meister Eckhart Leiden BRILL p 689 ISBN 978 9 004 18347 6 a b Heidegger Martin 14 June 2010 Country Path Conversations Translated by Bret W Davis p x ISBN 9780253004390 Dente Carla Soncini Sara eds 2013 Shakespeare and Conflict A European Perspective ISBN 9781137311344 Heidegger Martin 14 June 2010 Country Path Conversations Translated by Bret W Davis p xi ISBN 9780253004390 The word Gelassenheit has a long history in German thought It was coined by Meister Eckhart in the thirteenth century and subsequently used by a number of other mystics theologians and philosophers in Italian See Carlo Angelino Il religioso nel pensiero di Martin Heidegger in Martin Heidegger L abbandono tr Adriano Fabris Genova Il Melangolo 1986 p 19 Richardson William J 1963 Heidegger Through Phenomenology to Thought Preface by Martin Heidegger The Hague Martinus Nijhoff Publishers 4th Edition 2003 New York Fordham University Press ISBN 0 823 22255 1 ISBN 978 08 2322 255 1 P 37 a b Wheeler Michael October 12 2011 Martin Heidegger 3 1 The Turn and the Contributions to Philosophy Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2013 05 22 In a 1947 piece in which Heidegger distances his views from Sartre s existentialism he links the turn to his own failure to produce the missing divisions of Being and Time i e Time and Being At root Heidegger s later philosophy shares the deep concerns of Being and Time in that it is driven by the same preoccupation with Being and our relationship with it that propelled the earlier work T he later Heidegger does seem to think that his earlier focus on Dasein bears the stain of a subjectivity that ultimately blocks the path to an understanding of Being This is not to say that the later thinking turns away altogether from the project of transcendental hermeneutic phenomenology The project of illuminating the a priori conditions on the basis of which entities show up as intelligible to us is still at the heart of things Richardson William J 1963 Heidegger Through Phenomenology to Thought Preface by Martin Heidegger The Hague Martinus Nijhoff Publishers 4th Edition 2003 The Bronx Fordham University Press ISBN 0 823 22255 1 ISBN 978 08 2322 255 1 Korab Karpowicz W J December 21 2009 Martin Heidegger 1889 1976 1 Life and Works Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2013 05 22 Brian Bard 1993 essay see sections one and three https sites google com site heideggerheraclitus Lyon James K Paul Celan and Martin Heidegger an unresolved conversation 1951 1970 pp 128 9 Philipse Herman 1998 Heidegger s philosophy of being a critical interpretation p 205 Heidegger 1971 Poetry Language Thought translation and introduction by Albert Hofstadter pp xxv and 187ff Heidegger Martin 2002 Time and Being On Time and Being Translated by Joan Stambaugh Chicago University of Chicago Press ISBN 0 226 32375 7 Naess Jr Arne D Martin Heidegger s Later philosophy Encyclopaedia Britannica Retrieved 2013 06 28 a b Thomas Sheehan Kehre and Ereignis a proglenoma to Introduction to Metaphysics in A companion to Heidegger s Introduction to Metaphysics page 15 2001 Dee also Sheehan Making sense of Heidegger A paradigm shift New Heidegger Research London England 2015 Wrathall Mark Heidegger and Unconcealment Truth Language and History Cambridge University Press 2011 McNeill William 1992 Metaphysics Fundamental Ontology Metontology 1925 1935 Heidegger Studies 8 63 79 JSTOR 45010876 Overgaard Soren 2006 Incarnality and Metontology A Reply to Frank Schalow Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 37 92 94 doi 10 1080 00071773 2006 11006566 S2CID 170396387 a b Wheeler Michael 2020 Martin Heidegger The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University Schalow Frank 2010 Ontological difference Historical Dictionary of Heidegger s Philosophy Scarecrow Press Dahlstrom D O 2004 Ontology New Catholic Encyclopedia Gale Korab Karpowicz W J Heidegger Martin Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy S L Bartky 1967 Seinsverlassenheit in the later philosophy of Heidegger Inquiry 10 1 4 74 88 DOI 10 1080 00201746708601483 Heidegger Martin Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Heidegger 1962 H 64External links editDahlstrom Daniel O 7 February 2013 The Heidegger Dictionary London A amp C Black ISBN 978 1 847 06514 8 Munday Roderick March 2009 Glossary of Terms in Being and Time Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Heideggerian terminology amp oldid 1210669413 Being in the world, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.