fbpx
Wikipedia

Porphyrian tree

The Porphyrian tree or Tree of Porphyry is a classic device for illustrating a "scale of being" (scala praedicamentalis), attributed to the 3rd century CE Greek neoplatonist philosopher and logician Porphyry, and revived through the translations of Boethius.[1]

Porphyrian trees by three authors: Purchotius (1730), Boethius (6th century), and Ramon Llull (ca. 1305).

Porphyry suggests the tree in his introduction ("Isagoge") to Aristotle's Categories. Porphyry presented Aristotle's classification of categories in a way that was later adopted into tree-like diagrams of two-way divisions, which indicate that a species is defined by a genus and a differentia and that this logical process continues until the lowest species is reached, which can no longer be so defined. No illustrations or diagrams occur in editions of Porphyry's original work; diagrams were eventually made, and became associated with the scheme that Porphyry describes, following Aristotle.

Porphyry's Isagoge was originally written in Greek, but was translated into Latin in the early 6th century CE by Boethius. Translations by Boethius became the standard philosophical logic textbook in the Middle Ages,[2] and theories of categories based on Porphyry's work were still being taught to students of logic until the late 19th century.

History edit

Philosopher James Franklin offers some history of the Porphyrian tree:

In medieval education, the standard introduction to Aristotle's works was via Porphyry's Isagoge, and division entered the educated consciousness in the form of 'Porphyry's Tree'. It is not clear that Porphyry himself, in the relevant passage,[3] went any further than Aristotle in recommending division. But his brief comment was developed into the Tree by medieval logicians. It appears in William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic and is given the name Arbor Porphyrii in the most popular medieval logic, Peter of Spain's Summulae Logicales.[4] Linnaeus's system of static and discrete species was simply the result of filling in the abstract Tree with the names of actual species.[5]

Thus, the notion of the Porphyrian tree as an actual diagram comes later than Porphyry himself. Still, scholars do speak of Porphyry's tree as in the Isagoge and they mean by this only that the idea of dividing genera into species via differentiae is found in the Isagoge. But, of course, Porphyry was only following what was already in Aristotle, and Aristotle was following what was already in his teacher, Plato.[6]

Example edit

The following Porphyrian tree consists of three columns of words; the middlemost (in boldface) contains the series of genera and species, and we can take it as analogous to the trunk of a tree. The extremes (the terms that jut out to the left and right), containing the differentiae, we can take as analogous to the branches of a tree:

 
This image is an illustration of the notion of a Porphyrian Tree as it comes down to us today through the European philosophical and logical tradition.

The diagram shows the highest genus to be substance. (Whether substance is a highest genus, really, is not in question here: right now we are only going to discuss what the diagram shows, not whether what it shows is true or false.) The technical term for a highest substance is summum genus. So, substance is the summum genus as far as this diagram goes. The diagram shows that the genus substance has two differentia, namely, "thinking" and "extended." This indicates that there are two species of the genus substance, thinking substance and extended substance. The diagram does not give a term for the species of thinking substance (this would be "mind"), but it does give the term for the species of extended substance, namely, body. That is, body is a species of the genus substance; body is that species of the genus substance that is extended.

Now that we have seen body as a species of substance, we treat body as a genus itself. As a genus, it has two differentia of its own, inanimate and animate. So, there are two species of body, inanimate body and animate body. The diagram does not tell us what the term for inanimate body is, but it indicates a term for animate body, namely, animal. Animal is an animate species of the genus body.

And, again, now that we have looked at animal as a species of the genus body, we look at animal now as a genus and consider its differentia, which are shown on the diagram to be irrational and rational. Thus, according to the diagram there are two species of the genus animal, irrational animal and rational animal. We are not told by the diagram what a term for irrational animal is, but the diagram indicates that a rational animal is a human. Thus, human is a rational species of the genus animal.

Beneath human, however, there are no further species. "This" and "that" if they are considered differentiae, are of a special kind that map the species human not onto a new species but onto particular humans.[7] The particular human Plato is named in the diagram. Plato is not a species (that is why his name is not in bold, unlike the species above). So, human is the lowest species in this diagram. The technical name for the lowest species in such a scheme is the infima species. So, for this diagram, human is the infima species.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ James Franklin, "Aristotle on Species Variation", Philosophy, 61:236 (April 1986), pp. 245-252.
  2. ^ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy - Medieval Theories of the Categories
  3. ^ Franklin's note: "Porphyry, Isagoge, trans. E. W. Warren (Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1975), 34."
  4. ^ Franklin's note: "N. Kretzmann, William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966), 54; Peter of Spain, Summulae Logicales, I. M. Bocheński (ed.) (Turin: Marietti, 1947), 17-18."
  5. ^ James Franklin, "Aristotle on Species Variation", Philosophy, 61:236 (April 1986), pp. 245-252. The passage quoted here is from pp. 251-252.
  6. ^ A number of Plato's dialogs contain the idea of division in them: see Sophist, Philebus, Statesman, Republic (book VII), and Parmenides.
  7. ^ For a discussion of "this" and "that" as universals/differentia, see G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit, "A. Consciousness", "I. Sense-Certainty: or the 'this' and 'meaning' [Meinen]", translated by A. V. Miller, Oxford University Press, pp. 58-66.

References edit

  This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChambers, Ephraim, ed. (1728). "Arbor Porphyriana". Cyclopædia, or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences (1st ed.). James and John Knapton, et al. p. 128.

Further reading edit

Sources
  • Porphyry, Isagoge (Porphyry's Introduction to Aristotle's 'Categories'.)
  • Porphyry's Introduction, translation and commentary by Jonathan Barnes, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2003.
Studies
  • Asztalos, Monika. (1993). "Boethius as a Transmitter of Greek Logic to the Latin West: The Categories". Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, 95 (1993), pp. 367–407.
  • Blum, Paul Richard. (1999). Dio e gli individui: L' Arbor Porphyriana nei secoli XVII e XVIII. Rivista di filosofia neo-scolastica 91: 18-49.
  • Franklin, James. (1986). "Aristotle on Species Variation". Philosophy, 61:236 (April 1986), pp. 245–252.
  • Kretzmann, Norman. (1966). William of Sherwood's Introduction to Logic (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1966).
  • Martin, John N. (2001). "Proclus and the Neoplatonic Syllogistic". Journal of Philosophical Logic, 30:3 (June 2001), pp. 187–240.
  • Peter of Spain. (1947). Summulae Logicales, I. M. Bocheński (ed.) (Turin: Marietti, 1947).

External links edit

  •   Media related to Porphyrian tree at Wikimedia Commons

porphyrian, tree, tree, porphyry, classic, device, illustrating, scale, being, scala, praedicamentalis, attributed, century, greek, neoplatonist, philosopher, logician, porphyry, revived, through, translations, boethius, three, authors, purchotius, 1730, boeth. The Porphyrian tree or Tree of Porphyry is a classic device for illustrating a scale of being scala praedicamentalis attributed to the 3rd century CE Greek neoplatonist philosopher and logician Porphyry and revived through the translations of Boethius 1 Porphyrian trees by three authors Purchotius 1730 Boethius 6th century and Ramon Llull ca 1305 Porphyry suggests the tree in his introduction Isagoge to Aristotle s Categories Porphyry presented Aristotle s classification of categories in a way that was later adopted into tree like diagrams of two way divisions which indicate that a species is defined by a genus and a differentia and that this logical process continues until the lowest species is reached which can no longer be so defined No illustrations or diagrams occur in editions of Porphyry s original work diagrams were eventually made and became associated with the scheme that Porphyry describes following Aristotle Porphyry s Isagoge was originally written in Greek but was translated into Latin in the early 6th century CE by Boethius Translations by Boethius became the standard philosophical logic textbook in the Middle Ages 2 and theories of categories based on Porphyry s work were still being taught to students of logic until the late 19th century Contents 1 History 2 Example 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External linksHistory editPhilosopher James Franklin offers some history of the Porphyrian tree In medieval education the standard introduction to Aristotle s works was via Porphyry s Isagoge and division entered the educated consciousness in the form of Porphyry s Tree It is not clear that Porphyry himself in the relevant passage 3 went any further than Aristotle in recommending division But his brief comment was developed into the Tree by medieval logicians It appears in William of Sherwood s Introduction to Logic and is given the name Arbor Porphyrii in the most popular medieval logic Peter of Spain s Summulae Logicales 4 Linnaeus s system of static and discrete species was simply the result of filling in the abstract Tree with the names of actual species 5 Thus the notion of the Porphyrian tree as an actual diagram comes later than Porphyry himself Still scholars do speak of Porphyry s tree as in the Isagoge and they mean by this only that the idea of dividing genera into species via differentiae is found in the Isagoge But of course Porphyry was only following what was already in Aristotle and Aristotle was following what was already in his teacher Plato 6 Example editThe following Porphyrian tree consists of three columns of words the middlemost in boldface contains the series of genera and species and we can take it as analogous to the trunk of a tree The extremes the terms that jut out to the left and right containing the differentiae we can take as analogous to the branches of a tree nbsp This image is an illustration of the notion of a Porphyrian Tree as it comes down to us today through the European philosophical and logical tradition The diagram shows the highest genus to be substance Whether substance is a highest genus really is not in question here right now we are only going to discuss what the diagram shows not whether what it shows is true or false The technical term for a highest substance is summum genus So substance is the summum genus as far as this diagram goes The diagram shows that the genus substance has two differentia namely thinking and extended This indicates that there are two species of the genus substance thinking substance and extended substance The diagram does not give a term for the species of thinking substance this would be mind but it does give the term for the species of extended substance namely body That is body is a species of the genus substance body is that species of the genus substance that is extended Now that we have seen body as a species of substance we treat body as a genus itself As a genus it has two differentia of its own inanimate and animate So there are two species of body inanimate body and animate body The diagram does not tell us what the term for inanimate body is but it indicates a term for animate body namely animal Animal is an animate species of the genus body And again now that we have looked at animal as a species of the genus body we look at animal now as a genus and consider its differentia which are shown on the diagram to be irrational and rational Thus according to the diagram there are two species of the genus animal irrational animal and rational animal We are not told by the diagram what a term for irrational animal is but the diagram indicates that a rational animal is a human Thus human is a rational species of the genus animal Beneath human however there are no further species This and that if they are considered differentiae are of a special kind that map the species human not onto a new species but onto particular humans 7 The particular human Plato is named in the diagram Plato is not a species that is why his name is not in bold unlike the species above So human is the lowest species in this diagram The technical name for the lowest species in such a scheme is the infima species So for this diagram human is the infima species See also editHegelian Dialectic Hierarchy Ontology Sefer HaIkkarim Level of analysis Tree of lifeNotes edit James Franklin Aristotle on Species Variation Philosophy 61 236 April 1986 pp 245 252 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Medieval Theories of the Categories Franklin s note Porphyry Isagoge trans E W Warren Toronto Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies 1975 34 Franklin s note N Kretzmann William of Sherwood s Introduction to Logic Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press 1966 54 Peter of Spain Summulae Logicales I M Bochenski ed Turin Marietti 1947 17 18 James Franklin Aristotle on Species Variation Philosophy 61 236 April 1986 pp 245 252 The passage quoted here is from pp 251 252 A number of Plato s dialogs contain the idea of division in them see Sophist Philebus Statesman Republic book VII and Parmenides For a discussion of this and that as universals differentia see G W F Hegel Phenomenology of Spirit A Consciousness I Sense Certainty or the this and meaning Meinen translated by A V Miller Oxford University Press pp 58 66 References edit nbsp This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chambers Ephraim ed 1728 Arbor Porphyriana Cyclopaedia or an Universal Dictionary of Arts and Sciences 1st ed James and John Knapton et al p 128 Further reading editSources Porphyry Isagoge Porphyry s Introduction to Aristotle s Categories Porphyry s Introduction translation and commentary by Jonathan Barnes Oxford Oxford University Press 2003 Studies Asztalos Monika 1993 Boethius as a Transmitter of Greek Logic to the Latin West The Categories Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 95 1993 pp 367 407 Blum Paul Richard 1999 Dio e gli individui L Arbor Porphyriana nei secoli XVII e XVIII Rivista di filosofia neo scolastica 91 18 49 Franklin James 1986 Aristotle on Species Variation Philosophy 61 236 April 1986 pp 245 252 Kretzmann Norman 1966 William of Sherwood s Introduction to Logic Minneapolis University of Minnesota Press 1966 Martin John N 2001 Proclus and the Neoplatonic Syllogistic Journal of Philosophical Logic 30 3 June 2001 pp 187 240 Peter of Spain 1947 Summulae Logicales I M Bochenski ed Turin Marietti 1947 External links edit nbsp Media related to Porphyrian tree at Wikimedia Commons Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Porphyrian tree amp oldid 1219102047, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.